You are on page 1of 45

Engaging Bioethics An Introduction

With Case Studies 1st Edition Seay


Visit to download the full and correct content document:
https://textbookfull.com/product/engaging-bioethics-an-introduction-with-case-studies-
1st-edition-seay/
More products digital (pdf, epub, mobi) instant
download maybe you interests ...

Case Studies in Society Religion and Bioethics Sana


Loue

https://textbookfull.com/product/case-studies-in-society-
religion-and-bioethics-sana-loue/

Engaging Archaeology 25 Case Studies in Research


Practice First Edition Silliman

https://textbookfull.com/product/engaging-archaeology-25-case-
studies-in-research-practice-first-edition-silliman/

Exploring Mathematics An Engaging Introduction to Proof


John Meier

https://textbookfull.com/product/exploring-mathematics-an-
engaging-introduction-to-proof-john-meier/

Introduction to Management Science A Modeling and Case


Studies Approach with Spreadsheets 6th Edition Hillier

https://textbookfull.com/product/introduction-to-management-
science-a-modeling-and-case-studies-approach-with-
spreadsheets-6th-edition-hillier/
Film Studies An Introduction Teach Yourself 1st
Edition Warren Buckland

https://textbookfull.com/product/film-studies-an-introduction-
teach-yourself-1st-edition-warren-buckland/

Space Engineering Modeling and Optimization with Case


Studies 1st Edition Giorgio Fasano

https://textbookfull.com/product/space-engineering-modeling-and-
optimization-with-case-studies-1st-edition-giorgio-fasano/

Psychoanalytic Case Studies from an Interpersonal


Relational Perspective 1st Edition Rebecca Coleman
Curtis

https://textbookfull.com/product/psychoanalytic-case-studies-
from-an-interpersonal-relational-perspective-1st-edition-rebecca-
coleman-curtis/

Stochastic Finance An Introduction with Examples 1st


Edition Turner

https://textbookfull.com/product/stochastic-finance-an-
introduction-with-examples-1st-edition-turner/

Comprehensive Electromyography With Clinical


Correlations and Case Studies Mark A. Ferrante

https://textbookfull.com/product/comprehensive-electromyography-
with-clinical-correlations-and-case-studies-mark-a-ferrante/
Engaging Bioethics

Engaging Bioethics: An Introduction with Case Studies draws students into this rapidly changing field, helping
them to actively untangle the many issues at the intersection of medicine and moral concern. Presuming
readers start with no background in philosophy, it offers balanced, philosophically based, and rigorous inquiry
for undergraduates throughout the humanities and social sciences as well as for health care professionals-in-
training, including students in medical school, pre-medicine, nursing, public health, and those studying to
assist physicians in various capacities. Written by an author team with more than three decades of combined
experience teaching bioethics, this book offers

Flexibility to the instructor, with chapters that can be read independently and in an order that fits the
course structure
Up-to-date coverage of current controversies on topics such as vaccination, access to health care, new
reproductive technologies, genetics, biomedical research on human and animal subjects, medically
assisted death, abortion, medical confidentiality, and disclosure
Attention to issues of gender, race, cultural diversity, and justice in health care
Integration with case studies and primary sources
Pedagogical features to help instructors and students, including
Chapter learning objectives
Text boxes and figures to explain important terms, concepts, and cases
End-of-chapter summaries, key words, and annotated further readings
Discussion cases and questions
Appendices on moral reasoning and the history of ethical issues at the end and beginning of
life
An index of cases discussed in the book and extensive glossary/index
A companion website (www.routledge.com/cw/seay) with a virtual anthology linking to key primary
sources, a test bank, topics for papers, and PowerPoints for lectures and class discussion.

Gary Seay is professor of philosophy at Medgar Evers College of the City University of New York.

Susana Nuccetelli is professor of philosophy at St. Cloud State University in Minnesota.

2
Praise for this edition

“Seay and Nuccetelli have done an admirable job of distilling and making accessible a large body of medical
information, complex case law, and philosophical ethics. Their text makes the project of developing
competence and understanding in bioethics a lot less daunting, without simplifying the philosophical and
scientific issues. The book is organized so that instructors can easily design a course around a subset of the
topics covered, and its teaching and learning resources are outstanding. This is the best bioethics textbook I am
aware of, for students and teachers alike.”
Brandon Cooke, Professor and Chair (Philosophy),
Minnesota State University, Mankato

“This is a concise introduction to bioethics that covers a lot of ground. The chapters are sufficiently self-
contained so that the text can be adapted to different course designs, and the boxes and figures throughout are
helpful learning aids. Important cases are discussed but don’t dominate the discussion, so the emphasis remains
on the philosophical arguments and issues.”
William A. Bauer, Teaching Assistant Professor,
North Carolina State University

“Seay and Nuccetelli offer a refreshing and bold approach to bioethics that confronts readers directly, requiring
them to wrestle intimately with the most pressing issues through numerous case studies and a nuanced
analysis of the core concepts and principles. The authors strike a delicate balance between accessibility and
depth, with the results being a text that is eminently readable. This is not easy material, but the authors have
created a text open to readers with little or no philosophical background without sacrificing the complexity
found in these important discussions. They also offer an expansive and up-to-date sourcebook to find primary
sources online in the companion website.”
Scott O’Leary, Assistant Professor, University of Saint Mary

3
Engaging Bioethics
An Introduction with Case Studies

Gary Seay and Susana Nuccetelli

4
First published 2017
by Routledge
711 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10017
and by Routledge
2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN
Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business
© 2017 Taylor & Francis
The right of Gary Seay and Susana Nuccetelli to be identified as the authors of this work has been asserted by
them in accordance with sections 77 and 78 of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988.
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilized in any form or by any
electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and
recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers.
Trademark notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered trademarks, and are used only
for identification and explanation without intent to infringe.
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Names: Seay, Gary, author. | Nuccetelli, Susana, author.
Title: Engaging bioethics : an introduction with case studies / by Gary Seay and Susana Nuccetelli.
Description: New York, NY : Routledge, 2017. | Includes bibliographical references and index.
Identifiers: LCCN 2016028430 | ISBN 9780415837958 (pbk : alk. paper) | ISBN 9780415837941
(hbk : alk. paper) | ISBN 9780203788707 (ebk)
Subjects: LCSH: Medical ethics. Medical ethics—Case studies.
Classification: LCC R724 .S397 2017 | DDC 174.2—dc23
LC record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2016028430
ISBN: 9780415837941 (hbk)
ISBN: 9780415837958 (pbk)
ISBN: 9780203788707 (ebk)
Typeset in Minion Pro
by Apex CoVantage, LLC

5
Contents

About the Authors


Preface
Abbreviations

Part I Bioethics and Moral Theory


Chapter 1 The Study of Morality

Chapter 2 Philosophical Accounts of Morality

Part II Theoretical and Methodological Issues in Bioethics


Chapter 3 Principle-Oriented and Case-Oriented Bioethics

Chapter 4 Managing Patient Information

Chapter 5 Consent with Competence and Without

Part III Moral Issues at the End of Life

Chapter 6 Death and Dying

Chapter 7 When Life Supports Are Futile or Refused

Chapter 8 Medically Assisted Death

Chapter 9 End-of-Life Measures for Severely Compromised Newborns

Part IV Moral Issues at the Beginning of Life

Chapter 10 Personhood in the Abortion Debate

Chapter 11 Abortion in the Typical Case

Chapter 12 Abortion in the Hard Cases

Chapter 13 Conflicts of Rights at Life’s Beginning

Part V The Biotechnological Revolution


Chapter 14 New Reproductive Technologies

6
Chapter 15 Human Genetic Engineering

Part VI Medicine and Society

Chapter 16 Biomedical Research on Animals

Chapter 17 Biomedical Research on Humans

Chapter 18 Justice in Health Care

Appendix A: The Tools of Ethical Inquiry


Appendix B: Evolving Attitudes toward Ending or Preventing Human Life
Glossary/Index
Index of Cases
Additional References

7
Detailed Contents

About the Authors


Preface
Abbreviations

Part I Bioethics and Moral Theory


Chapter 1 The Study of Morality
1.1 Rev. Jacobson’s Refusal of Vaccination
1.2 The Evolution of Bioethics from Professional Ethics
The Hippocratic Tradition
Medieval Developments
Later Developments
Contemporary Bioethics
1.3 Bioethics in the Context of Ethics
Descriptive and Normative Senses of ‘Morality’
The Philosophical Study of Morality
Normative Ethics
1.4 Chapter Summary
1.5 Study Aids
Key Words
Questions and Cases for Further Consideration
Suggested Readings

Chapter 2 Philosophical Accounts of Morality


2.1 Baby Theresa and the Problem of Anencephalic Organ Sources
2.2 Authority Is the Source of Normativity
Culture as Moral Authority
God as Moral Authority
2.3 Authority Is Not the Source of Normativity
Natural Law Theory
Consequentialism
Kantian Ethics
Virtue Ethics
Care Ethics
Rossian Ethics
Particularism
2.4 Chapter Summary
2.5 Study Aids
Key Words
Questions and Cases for Further Consideration
Suggested Readings

8
Part II Theoretical and Methodological Issues in Bioethics

Chapter 3 Principle-Oriented and Case-Oriented Bioethics


3.1 Dax’s Case
3.2 Principlism
Autonomy
Nonmaleficence
Beneficence and Paternalism
3.3 Casuistry
How Casuistry Works
The Top-Down/Bottom-Up Dichotomy
3.4 Chapter Summary
3.5 Study Aids
Key Words
Questions and Cases for Further Consideration
Suggested Readings

Chapter 4 Managing Patient Information


4.1 The Tarasoff Decision
4.2 Medical Confidentiality
Philosophical Grounds
Absolutism, Universalism, and Skepticism
4.3 Must Health Care Professionals Always Tell the Truth?
Disclosure and Deception Defined
Evolving Attitudes toward Disclosure
Moral Grounds for Disclosure
The Problem of Culture
4.4 Genetic Information
Genetic Knowledge
Genetic Pseudo-Knowledge
Nondirective Genetic Counseling
Is There a Right to Genetic Ignorance?
4.5 Chapter Summary
4.6 Study Aids
Key Words
Questions and Cases for Further Consideration
Suggested Readings

Chapter 5 Consent with Competence and Without


5.1 Natanson v Kline: The Limits of Paternalistic Beneficence
5.2 The Elements of Informed Consent
Consent
Information
Understanding and Voluntariness
Competence
5.3 Exceptions and Doubts
Exceptions to Informed Consent
Skepticism about Informed Consent
5.4 Consent in the Absence of Competence
Decisionmaking for Previously Competent Adults
Decisionmaking for Never Competent Adults

9
Decisionmaking for Children
Decisionmaking in Ashley X
5.5 Chapter Summary
5.6 Study Aids
Key Words
Questions and Cases for Further Consideration
Suggested Readings

Part III Moral Issues at the End of Life

Chapter 6 Death and Dying


6.1 Was Jahi McMath Dead?
6.2 Accounting for Human Death
Western Thought on Human Death
The Standard Account of Death
6.3 Cardiopulmonary Death
The Cardiopulmonary Criterion
Donation after Cardiac Death
6.4 Brain Death
Disorders of Consciousness versus Brain Death
Whole-Brain versus Brainstem Death
Higher-Brain Death
6.5 Chapter Summary
6.6 Study Aids
Key Words
Questions and Cases for Further Consideration
Suggested Readings

Chapter 7 When Life Supports Are Futile or Refused


7.1 Was Continued Life in Tony Bland’s Best Interests?
7.2 Forgoing Life Supports
Karen Quinlan
Nancy Cruzan
Nancy B
7.3 Medical Futility at the End of Life
What Is Medical Futility?
Types of Futility
The Moral Grounds of Medical Futility
Disagreements about Futility Judgments
7.4 Objections and Alternatives to Medical Futility
The Sanctity-of-Life Doctrine
Ordinary versus Extraordinary Means
7.5 Chapter Summary
7.6 Study Aids
Key Words
Questions and Cases for Further Consideration
Suggested Readings

Chapter 8 Medically Assisted Death


8.1 Dr. Coxs Use of Euthanasia

10
8.2 Medical Euthanasia
Euthanasia and Other End-of-Life Measures
Types of Euthanasia
Passive versus Active Euthanasia
8.3 Physician-Assisted Suicide
Physician-Assisted Suicide and Voluntary Active Euthanasia
Oregons Death with Dignity Act
Suicide Tourism
8.4 Physician-Assisted Dying: For and Against
Physician-Assisted Dying Is Morally Permissible
Physician-Assisted Dying Is Morally Forbidden
The Dutch Experience
8.5 Chapter Summary
8.6 Study Aids
Key Words
Questions and Cases for Further Consideration
Suggested Readings

Chapter 9 End-of-Life Measures for Severely Compromised Newborns


9.1 Baby Jane Doe: Parental Choice and State Duties
9.2 Decisionmaking Standards for Compromised Newborns
The Baby Doe Regulations
From the Baby Doe Regulations to HCA v Miller
9.3 Prematurity and Low Birthweight
Prematurity
Low Birthweight
The Ethical Issues
9.4 Critical Care for Severely Compromised Newborns
For Providing Critical Care
Against Providing Critical Care
Neonatal Euthanasia
9.5 Chapter Summary
9.6 Study Aids
Key Words
Questions and Cases for Further Consideration
Suggested Readings

Part IV Moral Issues at the Beginning of Life


Chapter 10 Personhood in the Abortion Debate
10.1 Marlise Muñoz: Pregnant but Dead
10.2 Personhood
The Ambiguity of ‘Person’
Criteria of Personhood
Over-Inclusiveness, Under-Inclusiveness, and Speciesism
10.3 The Abortion Debate
Does the Debate Matter?
How to Move Ahead
Personhood in the Abortion Debate
10.4 Chapter Summary

11
10.5 Study Aids
Key Words
Questions and Cases for Further Consideration
Suggested Readings

Chapter 11 Abortion in the Typical Case


11.1 Roe v Wade: A Compromise on Abortion
11.2 Abortion: Some Facts
What Is Abortion?
The Practice of Abortion
11.3 Against the Moral Permissibility of Abortion
The Sanctity of Life
Developmental Continuity
Kind Essentialism
Potentiality
The Loss of a Valuable Future
11.4 For the Moral Permissibility of Abortion
Skepticism about Fetal Personhood
The Good Samaritan Argument
11.5 Intermediate Views
Early Brain Activity
Organized Cortical Activity
Fetal Interests
11.6 Chapter Summary
11.7 Study Aids
Key Words
Questions and Cases for Further Consideration
Suggested Readings

Chapter 12 Abortion in the Hard Cases


12.1 Sherri Finkbine’s Choices
12.2 Two Hard Cases for Abortion Critics
Abortion to Save the Mother’s Life or Health
Abortion for Fetal Defects
12.3 Two Hard Cases for Abortion Defenders
Abortion for Sex Selection
Late-Term Abortion
12.4 Chapter Summary
12.5 Study Aids
Key Words
Questions and Cases for Further Consideration
Suggested Readings

Chapter 13 Conflicts of Rights at Life’s Beginning


13.1 Deborah Zimmerman: Alcohol Abuse During Pregnancy
13.2 Maternal-Fetal Conflicts
Some Facts about Fetal Harm
Maternal Obligations and Rights
A Dilemma for Public Policy
13.3 Maternal Rights and the State’s Obligations
Abortion Policy in the UK

12
Abortion Policy in the US
Banning ‘Partial-Birth Abortion’
Restricting Public Funding for Abortion
13.4 Maternal Rights and Conscientious Objectors
Women/Health Care Providers Conflicts
The Duties of Conscientious Objectors
The Referral Problem
13.5 Chapter Summary
13.6 Study Aids
Key Words
Questions and Cases for Further Consideration
Suggested Readings

Part V The Biotechnological Revolution


Chapter 14 New Reproductive Technologies
14.1 Nadya Suleman’s Octuplets
14.2 The Simple Cases
The Simple Case of In-Vitro Fertilization
Fertility Therapy
The Problem of Multiples
14.3 The Complex Cases
Egg Donation, Gestational Surrogacy, and Postmenopausal Motherhood
Some Facts about Egg Donors and Gestational Carriers
Moral Controversies
14.4 Chapter Summary
14.5 Study Aids
Key Words
Questions and Cases for Further Consideration
Suggested Readings

Chapter 15 Human Genetic Engineering


15.1 Designing Deaf Baby
15.2 Some Moral Controversies in Reprogenetics
Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis
Human Reproductive Cloning
Early Eugenics
15.3 Human Genetic Enhancement
The Posthuman Scenario
Defining ‘Enhancement’
Designer Babies
15.4 Chapter Summary
15.5 Study Aids
Key Words
Questions and Cases for Further Consideration
Suggested Readings

Part VI Medicine and Society

13
Chapter 16 Biomedical Research on Animals
16.1 Dr. Gennarelli’s Head-Injury Study
16.2 The Animal Experimentation Debate
Abolitionism and Its Rivals
The Benefits Argument
Doubts about the Benefits of Animal Research
16.3 Animal Moral Standing
For the Moral Standing of Animals
Speciesism versus Humanism
Skepticism about Animals’ Moral Standing
Animal Law
16.4 Chapter Summary
16.5 Study Aids
Key Words
Questions and Cases for Further Consideration
Suggested Readings

Chapter 17 Biomedical Research on Humans


17.1 The Tuskegee Untreated-Syphilis Study
17.2 Ethical Issues in Research on Human Subjects
Early Ethical Guidelines
What Researchers Owe to Subjects
17.3 Research Using Human Biological Material
The Case of Henrietta Lacks
Ms. Lacks’s Descendants
17.4 Epidemiological and Clinical Research
Epidemiological Research
Randomized Clinical Trials
17.5 Gene Therapy
Therapy or Research?
The Jesse Gelsinger Case
17.6 Research in Developing Countries
The AZT Trials in Sub-Saharan Africa
Cultural Imperialism versus Relativism
Moral Lessons from the AZT Trials
17.7 Chapter Summary
17.8 Study Aids
Key Words
Questions and Cases for Further Consideration
Suggested Readings

Chapter 18 Justice in Health Care


18.1 Shortland v Northland Health: Rationing Is Not Futility
18.2 Allocation of Health Care Resources
Distributive Justice
Priority Setting
Distributive Justice in Organ Transplants
18.3 Access to Health Care
Health Inequalities and Inequities
The Right to Health Care
Universal Coverage

14
18.4 Chapter Summary
18.5 Study Aids
Key Words
Questions and Cases for Further Consideration
Suggested Readings

Appendix A: The Tools of Ethical Inquiry


Moral Judgment
Normative versus Descriptive Judgment
Moral Judgment Characterized
Moral Argument
Deductive and Inductive Reasoning
Concepts and Facts
Moral Principles, Commonsense Morality, and Reflective Equilibrium
Missing Premises and Extended Arguments
Check Your Understanding
Appendix B: Evolving Attitudes toward Ending or Preventing Human Life
Abortion, Infanticide, and Contraception
Euthanasia and Suicide
Glossary/Index
Index of Cases
Additional References

15
About the Authors

Gary Seay is professor of philosophy at Medgar Evers College of the City University of New York. With
Susana Nuccetelli, he is co-editor of Ethical Naturalism: Current Debates (Cambridge University Press, 2012)
and Themes from G. E. Moore: New Essays in Epistemology and Ethics (Oxford University Press, 2007). He has
served on the American Philosophical Associations Committee on Philosophy and Medicine and was
consulting bioethicist on the Ethics Committee of the New York Hospital Medical Center of Queens.

Susana Nuccetelli is professor of philosophy at St. Cloud State University in Minnesota. Her articles in ethics,
philosophy of language, and Latin American philosophy have appeared in many edited volumes and journals.
She is the author of Latin American Thought: Philosophical Problems and Arguments (Westview Press, 2002).
With Gary Seay, she is the author of How to Think Logically (2e, Pearson, 2012).

16
Preface

Our view in writing this book represents a departure from the prevailing wisdom about how bioethics should
be taught. For most of the subjects brief history, questions about pedagogy have been mostly cast in terms of
two governing assumptions: first, that it is chiefly medical school students in training to be physicians, along
with some undergraduate pre-med majors, who take courses in bioethics, and, second, that the best way for
these students to understand the central issues of the discipline is through using an anthology of original
sources. But neither of these assumptions any longer applies. Students enrolled in bioethics today are as likely
to be undergraduates in nursing programs or training to be physician-assistants, or physical therapists, as med
school students. And there are better ways to teach these diverse kinds of students than to throw at them a
massive, often expensive, collection of primary sources, culled from various journals in medicine, philosophy,
and law. This textbook borrows whats best of the traditional approachusing case studies and providing
references for original sources onlineand combines it with a clear, student-friendly introduction to the complex
subjects and arguments, including the major moral controversies of 21st-century medicine. The book should
therefore be valuable to students with different backgrounds and who are approaching the ethics of medicine
from numerous angles. There are, of course, already other bioethics textbooks, but, we think, none that cover
so thoroughly and lucidly the major moral controversies of contemporary bioethics as this book does.
Engaging Bioethics offers flexibility to the instructor. It can be used as either a stand-alone textbook or in
combination with one of the major anthologies, as its eighteen chapters, grouped in six parts, unfold in a way
that allows instructors to supplement each topic with readings of original sources. A virtual anthology on the
companion website links to key original sources, further allowing for seamless integration of primary sources.
At the same time, chapters are generally self-contained units, and the topics are presented in a way that
permits instructors to assign them in different sequences according to their needs. For example, instructors
wishing to spend less time on theoretical issues could skip Chapters 1 and 2, and fill in the gaps on moral
theory and methodology as the course unfolds. Instructors who want to devote more time to moral reasoning
may assign Appendix A, while those wishing to cover some of the history of end- and beginning-of-life issues
may assign Appendix B. Throughout, we have aimed at even-handedness in reconstructing facts and
arguments, leaving alternative evaluations for further discussion in the classroom.
Intended for students of introductory courses in bioethics or biomedical ethics, this book assumes no
background in those subjects, or in moral philosophy. Weve tried to make the writing style simple and direct,
with jargon kept to a minimum. Scattered throughout are special-emphasis boxes and figures in which
important points are summarized to help students focus on crucial distinctions and fundamental ideas. Each
chapter opens with a set of learning objectives to frame the chapters goals and a case study to get students
immediately engaged. At the end of each chapter are summaries, key words (bolded throughout on first use,
and defined in a glossary at the end of the book), brief annotated lists of suggested readings, and some
questions and cases for further consideration. Among these, in each chapter, is a case raising a cultural, racial,
or gender issue in medicine, always listed at the end for easy reference. Pedagogical aids at the back of the
book include an index of all cases, a list of major abbreviations, additional bibliographical references, and a
glossary. More tools can be found at the books companion website, with open-access resources for students and
password-protected instructors resources. Instructors resources include a test bank of multiple-choice questions
with answers, topics for papers, and PowerPoint presentations. For students and instructors alike, we have
created a unique virtual anthology, listing original sources that are available electronically through most
university libraries subscriptions to databases. This feature includes links to most of the Suggested Readings
found at the end of each chapter (marked with an asterisk in the chapter and online), as well as additional links
selected from a variety of sources, including professional associations, news items, legislation, blogs,
interviews, podcasts, and videos relevant to the chapter topics. Wherever possible, links are provided via
multiple sources, with stable URLs and/or DOIs. This unique approach allows instructors to teach from a

17
textbook while also supplementing with original sources without the burden of an expensive print anthology,
whether they assign additional readings or use them for research papers or homework assignments.
Finally, two notes about terminology are in order. One concerns the absence of a universally accepted
collective noun for all members of the medical team. For brevity, when possible we have used health care
provider with this comprehensive sense. The other issue concerns our eclectic way to avoid sexist language
throughout. Rather than always including all pronouns (e.g., he/her, his or hers), which can become messy to
read, we simply tried to balance our use of masculine and feminine pronouns or use they/their.
We wish to acknowledge some contributions that have made this a much better textbook, especially those of
our very patient and unfailingly helpful editors at Routledge, Andrew Beck and Alison Daltroy. Special thanks
are due also to Natasha Meed and Josiah Enninga for their technical assistance and to anonymous reviewers
who provided insightful guidance. There are several persons to whom we owe thanks for comments and
assistance with details that helped to shape our views on various topics: Stefan Baumrin, Tony Cunningham,
Jordan Curnutt, Rosamond Rhodes, Alan Seay, and Mark Timmons. Our thanks go also to our students at
Medgar Evers College of the City University of New York and at St. Cloud State University, on whom we tried
earlier drafts of the chapters.

18
Abbreviations

AMA American Medical Association


ANH Artificial Nutrition and Hydration
AWA Animal Welfare Act
D&X Intact Dilation and Extraction
DCD Donation after Cardiac Death
FLOA Future-Like-Ours Argument
EoL End-of-life Measure
ER Emergency Room
FDA Food and Drug Administration
GP Groningen Protocol
GSA Good Samaritan Argument
HGP Human Genome Project
ICU Intensive Care Unit
QALY Quality-Adjusted Life Years
IRB Institutional Review Board
IVF In-Vitro Fertilization
LST Life-Sustaining Treatment
NICU Neonatal Intensive Care Unit
NRT New Reproductive Technology
PAD Physician-Assisted Dying
PAS Physician-Assisted Suicide
PGD Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis
PPACA Patient Protection and Affordable Care Act
PVS Permanent Vegetative State
RCT Randomized Clinical Trials
SSA Sex-Selective Abortion
SSS Sliding-Scale Standard
STD Sexually Transmitted Disease
UDD Unified Determination of Death Act
HRC Human Reproductive Cloning
VAE Voluntary Active Euthanasia
VLBW Very Low Birthweight
WHO World Health Organization

19
Part I

Bioethics and Moral Theory

20
1 The Study of Morality

Learning Objectives

In reading this chapter you will

► Identify the historical roots of contemporary bioethics in the development of Western


medicine and its professional ethics.
► Recognize descriptive and normative senses of morality.
► Distinguish philosophical studies of morality from those of the sciences.
► Place bioethics in the landscape of ethics.

This chapter introduces bioethics as a practice and an area of ethics of interest to several disciplines. It does so
by first looking at an early landmark case where protecting public health infringed on an individual liberty to
refuse vaccination. Until the 1970s, such conflicts were resolved by appeal to accepted practice and professional
codes. After briefly reviewing the history of these, the chapter looks closely at bioethics today, outlining its
main branches and relations to other areas of ethics.

21
■ 1.1 Rev. Jacobson’s Refusal of Vaccination
The advantages of vaccination policies to prevent outbreaks of infectious disease are now widely
acknowledged. Yet vaccination has not always been smooth sledding. In 1758 the American Calvinist
theologian Jonathan Edwards died of a smallpox inoculation shortly after his inauguration as president of what
is today Princeton University. Such casualties were not uncommon when vaccinations were first introduced.
The eventual eradication of smallpox and the significant progress that has been made in reducing the threat of
other serious diseases, such as polio and measles, are however among the global, public-health successes of
vaccination. In the US, the moral and legal grounds of vaccination mandates by the state came to be questioned
most forcefully when a smallpox epidemic spread through the Northeast in 1901, causing 773 documented
cases and 97 deaths. The following year Cambridge, Massachusetts reported 2,314 infected individuals, of
whom 284 died. Citing an existing statute, the city’s board of health decided to enforce vaccination against
smallpox for all residents, and stipulated a five-dollar fine for those who failed to comply. Among the
delinquents was the Reverend Henning Jacobson, who refused the vaccine for himself and his son. He had a
previous adverse reaction to it and, more important, thought the ordinance violated his right to care for his
own body in the way he thought best.
The city responded by requesting payment of the fine, which prompted Jacobson to initiate legal action. The
court decided that, under the police power of the state, the city’s ordinance did not violate any liberty rights
guaranteed by the Fourteenth Amendment. Jacobson then appealed to the US Supreme Court, which in 1905
found for the state, emphasizing the Commonwealth’s power to enact and enforce laws aimed at protecting the
public from communicable diseases.

■■■
This was the first ruling by the US Supreme Court concerning the scope of state power in public health law.
More than a century later, vaccination continues to present moral and legal challenges worldwide. In 2009, 5-
year-old Edgar Hernandez, soon to be known as ‘patient zero,’ returned from school one day with symptoms
consistent with ‘swine flu’ (the H1N1-virus infection). The virus was not to remain in his remote Mexican
village. A month later, it afflicted some 1,000 individuals in all parts of the United States. By June, there were
18,000 reported cases. Five months later, the Food and Drug Administration approved the use of H1N1
vaccines, and roughly 61 million Americans were vaccinated within the first three months. Faced with a short
supply of the new vaccine, the State of New York’s Department of Public Health sought to protect hospital
patients, who generally have greater vulnerability to infectious disease, by imposing vaccination mandates for
health care providers. It considered the mandate justified by precedent from state court rulings in previous
cases of mandatory rubella vaccination and annual tuberculosis testing of health care providers. The New York
Times reported that three nurses obtained the mandate’s suspension by questioning the vaccine’s proven
effectiveness.1
They thus won a legal battle but not the moral war. For as health care providers, they faced a moral conflict:
on the one hand, they had the duty to promote their patients’ health; on the other, the exercise of that duty
interfered with their individual liberty interest to refuse vaccination or any other medical treatment. In
Jacobson v Massachusetts, the Supreme Court emphasized that many liberty interests must be limited in
pursuit of the common good because “a community has the right to protect itself against an epidemic of disease
which threatens the safety of its members.”
Controversies over vaccination mandates may result from differing beliefs about the facts, the law, religion,
or morality. Rev. Jacobson questioned the facts—namely, whether

Unvaccinated individuals put the public at an increased risk of contracting smallpox.


The state had the power to enforce vaccination ordinances.
The epidemic would spread according to natural, rather than, Divine plans.

22
But his deepest disagreement with the court concerned the right thing to do, from the moral perspective, when
protecting public health infringes on a person’s liberties. Questions of this sort pertain to bioethics, a practice
and a field of academic inquiry with roots in the development of Western medicine and the professional codes
of health providers.

Image 1.1
©iStockPhoto/Steve Debenport

23
■ 1.2 The Evolution of Bioethics from Professional Ethics
The Hippocratic Tradition
The patient’s right to refuse medical treatment, including vaccination, was generally ignored until the rise of
contemporary bioethics in the 1960s and 1970s. But long before that there were concerns in medicine about
other matters of moral right and wrong, especially in connection with patient welfare. From the very
beginnings of Western medicine in 5th-century Greece, physicians sought to regulate their practice by moral
rules. Those who embraced the teachings of Hippocrates of Kos (ca. 460–370 BCE) hoped their rules would be
adopted by other physicians. In this way, persons of defective character—including quacks and dishonest
schemers of all kinds—might find the calling of medicine too morally rigorous for their taste and be driven
away. The rules of Hippocratic medicine became background assumptions that persisted through more than
20 centuries until the rise of contemporary bioethics. They chiefly concern duties and decorum. Among other
things, Hippocratic doctors pledged to avoid harming their patients, to keep confidential the things revealed to
them in the course of treatment, and to ask as a fee no more than what the patient could reasonably afford to
pay. But they were also expected to cultivate certain traits of character or virtues. Physicians should have a
demeanor of seriousness, scholarliness, dignity, and reserve. They were to be scrupulously honest and polite
with their patients, striving always to bring credit to their profession and to put the patient at ease. In addition,
they were to regard the practice of medicine as a ‘holy’ calling, and hold their mentors in great reverence.
It is striking how many of these ideals persist even today in the mystique of medicine that undoubtedly
contributes to its high social status. And although some Hippocratic duties such as what appears to be a strict
prohibition of both abortion and euthanasia are controversial today, others continue to carry weight in
contemporary bioethics. These include that patients have an obligation to cooperate with their health care
providers, and that physicians have a duty to relieve suffering and should neither try to apply curative
treatment where no cure is possible nor attempt to save from death a patient who cannot be saved.

Medieval Developments
The Influence of Christianity and Maimonides
Over the centuries, a number of other ethical rules have taken hold in the practice of medicine. Some of these
originated in the late Roman period and early Middle Ages owing in part to the influence of Christianity, such
as the duty of medical professionals not to abandon their patients. St. Basil of Cappadocia, probably inspired by
Jesus’ teaching that one must care for the sick, founded the first hospital at Caesarea in 372, where nuns and
monks served as health care providers. Hospitals on this model soon began to spring up all over Christendom.
At the same time, the Hippocratic tradition took on a new moral imperative for physicians: the duty to care for
the sick, putting the patient’s interest first, even when they risked exposure to deadly disease. Later, during the
high Middle Ages, this duty came to be interpreted in Italian commercial cities as a duty of health care
providers not to abandon patients, even in a time of plague, without regard to risk to themselves. Not
surprisingly, the compliance with this new medical duty was uneven. Some were able to muster the courage to
act on it, but many did not. For nurses, such a stringent duty of care had long been taken for granted, a fact
evident later in Florence Nightingale’s criticism of medical professionals who care more about themselves than
about their patients.
In the medieval period, however, the moral influences on Western medical ethics came not only from
Christianity. Jewish scholars also made substantial contributions. Chief among them was the physician and
philosopher Maimonides (1135–1204). His voluminous writings as a Talmudic scholar touch occasionally on
ethics in medicine such as the duties to care for the sick and wounded and to preserve human life whenever
possible. So important was the latter duty, Maimonides thought, that religious duties—even Sabbath
observance—could be suspended, if necessary, to comply with it.

Thomist Ethics

24
Another medieval thinker with influential views on the ethics of medicine was Thomas Aquinas (1225–1274),
the Italian Catholic theologian and philosopher whose writings are the foundations of what’s now called
‘Thomism.’ Thomism sanctions an iron-clad duty of health care professionals to protect and extend human life
whenever possible. In reasoning about this weightiest of moral matters, Thomists think that the intention with
which an action is taken is important in assessing whether the action is morally right or wrong—something
consistent with the common intuition that, for instance, an amputation, normally forbidden on moral grounds
as mutilation, would be right when necessary to remove a gangrenous limb, thereby saving a life.
Thomism also refined casuistry, a method for deciding what to do or believe, morally, about any given case
that’s now preferred by some bioethicists over an alternative method that invokes general principles. Casuist
decisionmaking begins by identifying the morally relevant facts of a case, drawing moral conclusions by
comparing it with similar cases that have been already decided. We consider both methods in Chapter 3. For
now, note that Thomist bioethics continues to be a force today.

Later Developments
Percival’s Medical Ethics
Some new developments occurred at the very beginning of the 19th century. In 1803 an English doctor, Thomas
Percival (1740–1804) of Manchester, introduced the expression ‘medical ethics’ in an influential book with that
title. It was a large-scale treatise dealing with doctors’ duties in four areas: hospitals, the law, the professional
conduct of physicians in private practice, and relations with pharmacists. Physicians have those duties because
they are trusted to act in the best interests of the patient. Their good reputation depends on such public trust,
which must never be betrayed. It is earned through an uncompromising devotion to the patient’s welfare, high
scientific standards, and the benefit physicians bring to society. Doctors must also respect their patients, the
poor and obscure no less than the wealthy and prominent. But they are also paternalistic toward them: the
physician determines what’s in the patients’ best interests, and makes treatment decisions accordingly. We
return to paternalism in Chapter 3.
Percival followed the Hippocratic tradition, not only in assuming paternalism, but also in rejecting strict
veracity as a duty of physicians toward patients. A physician may deceive patients whenever she thinks that
not to know the truth is in their best interest. But his contemporary, John Gregory (1724–1773), a respected
Scottish physician and professor at Edinburgh, took just the opposite view, and over the next century and a
half he was joined by three eminent American medical school professors who wrote on ethical questions in
medicine, Benjamin Rush (1746–1813), Worthington Hooker (1806–1867), and Richard Clarke Cabot (1868–
1939). All argued that doctors have a duty to tell the truth to their patients.
In contemporary bioethics, the trend to favor a strict duty of veracity has grown parallel to the rise of
awareness about respect for patient autonomy, a medical duty also to be considered at some length in Chapter
3. Here, let’s note that this duty correlates with

A patient’s right to make self-regarding decisions about medical treatment freely, without any coercive
interference.

In the English-speaking world, owing partly to the human-rights movements of the 1960s and 70s, and partly
to the efforts of 20th-century bioethicists, respect for patient autonomy now prevails over paternalism.
Protestant theologians Joseph Fletcher (1905–1991) and Paul Ramsey (1914–1988), two especially noteworthy
pioneers of bioethics, were among those who offered influential arguments for this change. The increasing
acceptance of those arguments led to acceptance of the now familiar right of patients to refuse treatment,
including life-saving treatment.

Image 1.2
©iStockPhoto/ericsphotography

25
The 1847 AMA Code
This overview of professional ethics in the history of medicine would be incomplete without mentioning two
more milestones, both in connection with the appearance in 1847 of the first Code of Ethics of the American
Medical Association (AMA). One concerns the Code’s recognition of some significant obligations that patients
owe their doctors, in addition to a long list of duties of physicians—some from the Hippocratic tradition and
Percival’s Medical Ethics, others breaking new ground. The other concerns the Code’s article IV, which
excludes from the profession all who practice nonstandard forms of medicine outside allopathic medicine, the
strictly science-based mainstream of Western medicine. Thus it became a firm rule of medical ethics that
respectable doctors were to have nothing to do with folk ‘healers’ who practiced homeopathic and
naturopathic remedies of various kinds.
This position was defended enthusiastically by Hooker, who thought that physicians therefore had a
professional duty to be scientifically educated in ways appropriate to their specialties. Hooker’s idea was in fact
not really an innovation in bioethics, but acquired new urgency in the 20th century because of the rapid
development of new technologies. It implies that health care professionals have a firm obligation to keep
abreast of the most recent scholarly literature in their specialties and to know about the latest technologies for
treatment. In the early 20th century, Cabot added another dimension to the needed clinical competencies:
health care professionals must be not only highly proficient in the most up-to-date science of their specialties
but also careful to cultivate communication with patients and cooperation of health care teams in the hospital
environment so as to maximize the patient’s chances of recovery.

Contemporary Bioethics
The Emergence of Biomedical Ethics
Bioethics became an independent field in the 1960s and 70s, with medical ethics as one of its main areas of
concern. Among the factors contributing to this development were

Radical changes in the deliverance of health care as hospitals became ‘medical centers’ and health-
insurance-funded medicine became ‘managed care.’
Rapid developments in medical technology that brought unexpected ethical problems. Vastly increased
technical proficiency had in many cases only created new moral quandaries.

26
Box 1.1 Ethical Rules for Health Care Providers from the History of
Professional Ethics in Medicine

In the decades after World War II, medicine made spectacular advances in scientific knowledge and developed
powerful new technologies for healing. With progress came increasing uncertainty about whether medicine
should always do for a patient all it could do. Did the application of sophisticated technology and invasive
surgery always serve the patient’s best interests? Health care providers began to realize that the use of
medicine’s full armament in the service of healing might actually make some patients worse off—something
scarcely imaginable before.
Philosophers, theologians, and legal scholars interested in such questions joined efforts with physicians,
nurses, and other health care providers in seeking adequate answers. This in turn led to the birth of bioethics as
an interdisciplinary field of inquiry and area of concern within which medical ethics figures prominently.
Hospitals began to set up their own ethics committees to advise health care professionals and administrators
wrestling with moral dilemmas. At the same time, centers of scholarship in the new field of bioethics began to
appear. In the US, notable institutions arose at the Hastings Center in New York, at the University of
Pennsylvania, at the University of Minnesota, and at Georgetown University’s Kennedy Institute of Ethics,
among other locations. In the late 1970s, the Kennedy Institute published an influential work in contemporary
bioethics, Warren Reich’s Encyclopedia of Bioethics. Meanwhile, Georgetown’s Tom Beauchamp and the
University of Virginia’s James Childress brought out their path-breaking book, Principles of Biomedical Ethics.

Bioethics Today

27
While the long history of ethics in the medical profession and the newly crafted professional codes provide us
with some guideposts in the bewildering forest of contemporary bioethics, they do not really explain how
we’re justified in taking one path rather than another when we face a moral quandary. Moral codes, whether
ancient and revered or the most up-to-date, have no power to obligate us unless their rules are well supported
by independent moral reasons. This is where bioethics comes in.
Bioethics is an interdisciplinary area of concern about moral issues that arise in (1) the practice of medicine
and biomedical research, (2) public health policy, and (3) our relationships with nonhuman animals and the
environment. (1) and (2) constitute the parts of bioethics known as biomedical ethics, which focuses on moral
issues in medicine and clinical ethics, biomedical research ethics, and public health ethics.
Among other things, biomedical ethicists advocate for the rights of patients, offer guidance to the health care
community about what interventions are morally obligatory, forbidden, or optional in specific moral dilemmas,
and counsel health care officials on morally sound public health policies. They also grapple with theoretical
questions concerning the moral reasons for and against certain medical interventions at the end of life, or at its
beginning, such as euthanasia and abortion, professional duties in medicine such as truth-telling and
confidentiality, and policies for the allocation of scarce medical resources such as organs and access to
intensive care.
Note that, although biomedical ethics is only one part of bioethics, here we’ll follow the common practice of
using ‘bioethics’ and ‘biomedical ethics’ interchangeably. Either way, bioethics as a field of inquiry is
interdisciplinary, because it includes elements of philosophy, medicine, theology, the social sciences, and the
law. Its main tools are

Reasoned argument and conceptual analysis (from philosophy).


Scientifically rooted information about the facts of human physiology and the healing arts (from
medicine).
Knowledge of cultural and religious traditions (from theology and the social sciences).
Careful consideration of legal decisions in landmark cases involving bioethical questions (from the
law).

The issues and arguments of bioethics have roots of two kinds: some have emerged in the history of medicine,
others as a result of contemporary reflection about moral right and wrong in the practice of medicine. The
chapters to follow will take up each of these foundations in turn.

Figure 1.1 Bioethics as a Field of Inquiry

28
29
Another random document with
no related content on Scribd:
Years later, when the New York dentist replaced Gabriel's old steel
fillings, he explained to him about the music. Gabriel had been
receiving radio signals in the bits of metal in his head, he said. He
was very scientific about it, even drawing a little diagram to show him
how the radiator had helped ground him. Gabriel listened politely and
smiled but said nothing. To him it was still a miracle.

THE END
*** END OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK SMALL VOICE,
BIG MAN ***

Updated editions will replace the previous one—the old editions will
be renamed.

Creating the works from print editions not protected by U.S.


copyright law means that no one owns a United States copyright in
these works, so the Foundation (and you!) can copy and distribute it
in the United States without permission and without paying copyright
royalties. Special rules, set forth in the General Terms of Use part of
this license, apply to copying and distributing Project Gutenberg™
electronic works to protect the PROJECT GUTENBERG™ concept
and trademark. Project Gutenberg is a registered trademark, and
may not be used if you charge for an eBook, except by following the
terms of the trademark license, including paying royalties for use of
the Project Gutenberg trademark. If you do not charge anything for
copies of this eBook, complying with the trademark license is very
easy. You may use this eBook for nearly any purpose such as
creation of derivative works, reports, performances and research.
Project Gutenberg eBooks may be modified and printed and given
away—you may do practically ANYTHING in the United States with
eBooks not protected by U.S. copyright law. Redistribution is subject
to the trademark license, especially commercial redistribution.

START: FULL LICENSE


THE FULL PROJECT GUTENBERG LICENSE
PLEASE READ THIS BEFORE YOU DISTRIBUTE OR USE THIS WORK

To protect the Project Gutenberg™ mission of promoting the free


distribution of electronic works, by using or distributing this work (or
any other work associated in any way with the phrase “Project
Gutenberg”), you agree to comply with all the terms of the Full
Project Gutenberg™ License available with this file or online at
www.gutenberg.org/license.

Section 1. General Terms of Use and


Redistributing Project Gutenberg™
electronic works
1.A. By reading or using any part of this Project Gutenberg™
electronic work, you indicate that you have read, understand, agree
to and accept all the terms of this license and intellectual property
(trademark/copyright) agreement. If you do not agree to abide by all
the terms of this agreement, you must cease using and return or
destroy all copies of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works in your
possession. If you paid a fee for obtaining a copy of or access to a
Project Gutenberg™ electronic work and you do not agree to be
bound by the terms of this agreement, you may obtain a refund from
the person or entity to whom you paid the fee as set forth in
paragraph 1.E.8.

1.B. “Project Gutenberg” is a registered trademark. It may only be


used on or associated in any way with an electronic work by people
who agree to be bound by the terms of this agreement. There are a
few things that you can do with most Project Gutenberg™ electronic
works even without complying with the full terms of this agreement.
See paragraph 1.C below. There are a lot of things you can do with
Project Gutenberg™ electronic works if you follow the terms of this
agreement and help preserve free future access to Project
Gutenberg™ electronic works. See paragraph 1.E below.
1.C. The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation (“the
Foundation” or PGLAF), owns a compilation copyright in the
collection of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works. Nearly all the
individual works in the collection are in the public domain in the
United States. If an individual work is unprotected by copyright law in
the United States and you are located in the United States, we do
not claim a right to prevent you from copying, distributing,
performing, displaying or creating derivative works based on the
work as long as all references to Project Gutenberg are removed. Of
course, we hope that you will support the Project Gutenberg™
mission of promoting free access to electronic works by freely
sharing Project Gutenberg™ works in compliance with the terms of
this agreement for keeping the Project Gutenberg™ name
associated with the work. You can easily comply with the terms of
this agreement by keeping this work in the same format with its
attached full Project Gutenberg™ License when you share it without
charge with others.

1.D. The copyright laws of the place where you are located also
govern what you can do with this work. Copyright laws in most
countries are in a constant state of change. If you are outside the
United States, check the laws of your country in addition to the terms
of this agreement before downloading, copying, displaying,
performing, distributing or creating derivative works based on this
work or any other Project Gutenberg™ work. The Foundation makes
no representations concerning the copyright status of any work in
any country other than the United States.

1.E. Unless you have removed all references to Project Gutenberg:

1.E.1. The following sentence, with active links to, or other


immediate access to, the full Project Gutenberg™ License must
appear prominently whenever any copy of a Project Gutenberg™
work (any work on which the phrase “Project Gutenberg” appears, or
with which the phrase “Project Gutenberg” is associated) is
accessed, displayed, performed, viewed, copied or distributed:
This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere in the United
States and most other parts of the world at no cost and with
almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away
or re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License
included with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.org. If you
are not located in the United States, you will have to check the
laws of the country where you are located before using this
eBook.

1.E.2. If an individual Project Gutenberg™ electronic work is derived


from texts not protected by U.S. copyright law (does not contain a
notice indicating that it is posted with permission of the copyright
holder), the work can be copied and distributed to anyone in the
United States without paying any fees or charges. If you are
redistributing or providing access to a work with the phrase “Project
Gutenberg” associated with or appearing on the work, you must
comply either with the requirements of paragraphs 1.E.1 through
1.E.7 or obtain permission for the use of the work and the Project
Gutenberg™ trademark as set forth in paragraphs 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.

1.E.3. If an individual Project Gutenberg™ electronic work is posted


with the permission of the copyright holder, your use and distribution
must comply with both paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 and any
additional terms imposed by the copyright holder. Additional terms
will be linked to the Project Gutenberg™ License for all works posted
with the permission of the copyright holder found at the beginning of
this work.

1.E.4. Do not unlink or detach or remove the full Project


Gutenberg™ License terms from this work, or any files containing a
part of this work or any other work associated with Project
Gutenberg™.

1.E.5. Do not copy, display, perform, distribute or redistribute this


electronic work, or any part of this electronic work, without
prominently displaying the sentence set forth in paragraph 1.E.1 with
active links or immediate access to the full terms of the Project
Gutenberg™ License.
1.E.6. You may convert to and distribute this work in any binary,
compressed, marked up, nonproprietary or proprietary form,
including any word processing or hypertext form. However, if you
provide access to or distribute copies of a Project Gutenberg™ work
in a format other than “Plain Vanilla ASCII” or other format used in
the official version posted on the official Project Gutenberg™ website
(www.gutenberg.org), you must, at no additional cost, fee or expense
to the user, provide a copy, a means of exporting a copy, or a means
of obtaining a copy upon request, of the work in its original “Plain
Vanilla ASCII” or other form. Any alternate format must include the
full Project Gutenberg™ License as specified in paragraph 1.E.1.

1.E.7. Do not charge a fee for access to, viewing, displaying,


performing, copying or distributing any Project Gutenberg™ works
unless you comply with paragraph 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.

1.E.8. You may charge a reasonable fee for copies of or providing


access to or distributing Project Gutenberg™ electronic works
provided that:

• You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive from
the use of Project Gutenberg™ works calculated using the
method you already use to calculate your applicable taxes. The
fee is owed to the owner of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark,
but he has agreed to donate royalties under this paragraph to
the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation. Royalty
payments must be paid within 60 days following each date on
which you prepare (or are legally required to prepare) your
periodic tax returns. Royalty payments should be clearly marked
as such and sent to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation at the address specified in Section 4, “Information
about donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation.”

• You provide a full refund of any money paid by a user who


notifies you in writing (or by e-mail) within 30 days of receipt that
s/he does not agree to the terms of the full Project Gutenberg™
License. You must require such a user to return or destroy all
copies of the works possessed in a physical medium and
discontinue all use of and all access to other copies of Project
Gutenberg™ works.

• You provide, in accordance with paragraph 1.F.3, a full refund of


any money paid for a work or a replacement copy, if a defect in
the electronic work is discovered and reported to you within 90
days of receipt of the work.

• You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free
distribution of Project Gutenberg™ works.

1.E.9. If you wish to charge a fee or distribute a Project Gutenberg™


electronic work or group of works on different terms than are set
forth in this agreement, you must obtain permission in writing from
the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the manager of
the Project Gutenberg™ trademark. Contact the Foundation as set
forth in Section 3 below.

1.F.

1.F.1. Project Gutenberg volunteers and employees expend


considerable effort to identify, do copyright research on, transcribe
and proofread works not protected by U.S. copyright law in creating
the Project Gutenberg™ collection. Despite these efforts, Project
Gutenberg™ electronic works, and the medium on which they may
be stored, may contain “Defects,” such as, but not limited to,
incomplete, inaccurate or corrupt data, transcription errors, a
copyright or other intellectual property infringement, a defective or
damaged disk or other medium, a computer virus, or computer
codes that damage or cannot be read by your equipment.

1.F.2. LIMITED WARRANTY, DISCLAIMER OF DAMAGES - Except


for the “Right of Replacement or Refund” described in paragraph
1.F.3, the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the owner
of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark, and any other party
distributing a Project Gutenberg™ electronic work under this
agreement, disclaim all liability to you for damages, costs and
expenses, including legal fees. YOU AGREE THAT YOU HAVE NO
REMEDIES FOR NEGLIGENCE, STRICT LIABILITY, BREACH OF
WARRANTY OR BREACH OF CONTRACT EXCEPT THOSE
PROVIDED IN PARAGRAPH 1.F.3. YOU AGREE THAT THE
FOUNDATION, THE TRADEMARK OWNER, AND ANY
DISTRIBUTOR UNDER THIS AGREEMENT WILL NOT BE LIABLE
TO YOU FOR ACTUAL, DIRECT, INDIRECT, CONSEQUENTIAL,
PUNITIVE OR INCIDENTAL DAMAGES EVEN IF YOU GIVE
NOTICE OF THE POSSIBILITY OF SUCH DAMAGE.

1.F.3. LIMITED RIGHT OF REPLACEMENT OR REFUND - If you


discover a defect in this electronic work within 90 days of receiving it,
you can receive a refund of the money (if any) you paid for it by
sending a written explanation to the person you received the work
from. If you received the work on a physical medium, you must
return the medium with your written explanation. The person or entity
that provided you with the defective work may elect to provide a
replacement copy in lieu of a refund. If you received the work
electronically, the person or entity providing it to you may choose to
give you a second opportunity to receive the work electronically in
lieu of a refund. If the second copy is also defective, you may
demand a refund in writing without further opportunities to fix the
problem.

1.F.4. Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set forth in
paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you ‘AS-IS’, WITH NO
OTHER WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS OR IMPLIED,
INCLUDING BUT NOT LIMITED TO WARRANTIES OF
MERCHANTABILITY OR FITNESS FOR ANY PURPOSE.

1.F.5. Some states do not allow disclaimers of certain implied


warranties or the exclusion or limitation of certain types of damages.
If any disclaimer or limitation set forth in this agreement violates the
law of the state applicable to this agreement, the agreement shall be
interpreted to make the maximum disclaimer or limitation permitted
by the applicable state law. The invalidity or unenforceability of any
provision of this agreement shall not void the remaining provisions.
1.F.6. INDEMNITY - You agree to indemnify and hold the
Foundation, the trademark owner, any agent or employee of the
Foundation, anyone providing copies of Project Gutenberg™
electronic works in accordance with this agreement, and any
volunteers associated with the production, promotion and distribution
of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works, harmless from all liability,
costs and expenses, including legal fees, that arise directly or
indirectly from any of the following which you do or cause to occur:
(a) distribution of this or any Project Gutenberg™ work, (b)
alteration, modification, or additions or deletions to any Project
Gutenberg™ work, and (c) any Defect you cause.

Section 2. Information about the Mission of


Project Gutenberg™
Project Gutenberg™ is synonymous with the free distribution of
electronic works in formats readable by the widest variety of
computers including obsolete, old, middle-aged and new computers.
It exists because of the efforts of hundreds of volunteers and
donations from people in all walks of life.

Volunteers and financial support to provide volunteers with the


assistance they need are critical to reaching Project Gutenberg™’s
goals and ensuring that the Project Gutenberg™ collection will
remain freely available for generations to come. In 2001, the Project
Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation was created to provide a
secure and permanent future for Project Gutenberg™ and future
generations. To learn more about the Project Gutenberg Literary
Archive Foundation and how your efforts and donations can help,
see Sections 3 and 4 and the Foundation information page at
www.gutenberg.org.

Section 3. Information about the Project


Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation
The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation is a non-profit
501(c)(3) educational corporation organized under the laws of the
state of Mississippi and granted tax exempt status by the Internal
Revenue Service. The Foundation’s EIN or federal tax identification
number is 64-6221541. Contributions to the Project Gutenberg
Literary Archive Foundation are tax deductible to the full extent
permitted by U.S. federal laws and your state’s laws.

The Foundation’s business office is located at 809 North 1500 West,


Salt Lake City, UT 84116, (801) 596-1887. Email contact links and up
to date contact information can be found at the Foundation’s website
and official page at www.gutenberg.org/contact

Section 4. Information about Donations to


the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation
Project Gutenberg™ depends upon and cannot survive without
widespread public support and donations to carry out its mission of
increasing the number of public domain and licensed works that can
be freely distributed in machine-readable form accessible by the
widest array of equipment including outdated equipment. Many small
donations ($1 to $5,000) are particularly important to maintaining tax
exempt status with the IRS.

The Foundation is committed to complying with the laws regulating


charities and charitable donations in all 50 states of the United
States. Compliance requirements are not uniform and it takes a
considerable effort, much paperwork and many fees to meet and
keep up with these requirements. We do not solicit donations in
locations where we have not received written confirmation of
compliance. To SEND DONATIONS or determine the status of
compliance for any particular state visit www.gutenberg.org/donate.

While we cannot and do not solicit contributions from states where


we have not met the solicitation requirements, we know of no
prohibition against accepting unsolicited donations from donors in
such states who approach us with offers to donate.

International donations are gratefully accepted, but we cannot make


any statements concerning tax treatment of donations received from
outside the United States. U.S. laws alone swamp our small staff.

Please check the Project Gutenberg web pages for current donation
methods and addresses. Donations are accepted in a number of
other ways including checks, online payments and credit card
donations. To donate, please visit: www.gutenberg.org/donate.

Section 5. General Information About Project


Gutenberg™ electronic works
Professor Michael S. Hart was the originator of the Project
Gutenberg™ concept of a library of electronic works that could be
freely shared with anyone. For forty years, he produced and
distributed Project Gutenberg™ eBooks with only a loose network of
volunteer support.

Project Gutenberg™ eBooks are often created from several printed


editions, all of which are confirmed as not protected by copyright in
the U.S. unless a copyright notice is included. Thus, we do not
necessarily keep eBooks in compliance with any particular paper
edition.

Most people start at our website which has the main PG search
facility: www.gutenberg.org.

This website includes information about Project Gutenberg™,


including how to make donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary
Archive Foundation, how to help produce our new eBooks, and how
to subscribe to our email newsletter to hear about new eBooks.

You might also like