You are on page 1of 11

"--- --

'

Chapter 5
Seeing, Believing, and Knowing
Fred Dretske
r
A~ T" '"' -k,.f ~,,,frv{ S:c1JJv,(
1 ;_ --h
V~( -2
O.st.ç~10.._ 1 t 0'cf)
MtT p,1s5 )
/99 n

Epislernology is a branch of philosophy devoted to the study of knowledge


and topics~·-such as truth, memory, perception-relai'ing to knowledge.
Epistcmo!ogy is a philosopher's version of cognitive studies.
Truth is an important part of this study because a central conception of
knowledgc is knowledge of flie fruJI!. Though you can know that something
isn't so-that, say, the cat isu'f undcr the sofa-you can't know something
-that the catis under the sofa-that isn't so. To know the whereabouts
of the cat rcquires one to be in possession of the truth about the cat' s
location. This being so, the idea of truth, as a necessary condition
for knowledge, has figured prominently in philosophical discus~ions of
cognihon.
Memory and perception also occupy a prominent place in epistemology.
Much of our knowledge (some would say ail of our knowledge) îs acquircd

Th;, chi!pler was pr<?pared whilf' 1 was a Fel!ow al the Ccnter for Advancf'd Study in the
Behavioral Science'. St,1nford. California. 1 am grateful for the financial support of the
Cenler. the National Endowrnent for !hl' Hurnanihes grant FC-20060-85. and the Andrew
W. Mellon l'oundahun.
130 Dretskc Seeing, Believing, and Knowing 1.31

by perceptual means: we corne to know where the cat is by seeing it on the facts, or something else. After ail, we normally speak oF seeing abjects (like
sofa. We might also hear, smell, and feel the cat. These are some of the cats and sofas), the properties of abjects (the color of a cat, the size of the
ways we have of findîng out, ways of coming Io know, the content and sofa), events (the cat's jumping onto the sofa), states of affairs (the cat's
character of our world. The gencral term for such ways of finding out. being on the sofa), and facts (fhat the cat is on the sofa). If these are ail to
ways of coming ta know, is perceptiori. Memory is the narne wc give to the be counted as instances of visual perception, as they appear to be in
ways we have for retaining (through time) the acquired knowledge. Power- ordinary language, then care must be taken in a scientific study of visual
ful mechanisms for acquiring knowledge (keen eyesight, for example) are of perception to specify whaf is being perceived: an object, a propcrty, an
httle value to animais that cannot remember, if even for a fcw seconds, event, a statc of affairs, or a fact. For it is not at all clear that the same
anything they leam. A large storage capacity, on the other hand, is wastcd · processes and mechanisms are, or need be, involved in the perception of
on systems with no way of getting information to be stored. these different things. Quite the contrary.
As earher chapters reveal, there has bcen a dramatic increase in our Consider, for exarnple, a small child glancing at the sofa and mistakîng a
scientîfic understanding of how we know some of the things we know. sleeping cat for an old sweater. Does the child see an object7 Yes, of course.
Nevertheless, despite this progress, certain classical philosophical prob- Besicles the sofa thcre is an object, the black cat on the sofa, that the chi\d
!ems, problems concerning the nature, scope, and !imits of visual cognition, m1stakenly bclievcs to be a black sweater. Though the child does not
remain unanswered-or, better, remain wîthout answers that command recognize the cat (as a cat), she must, in some sense, see the cal in order to
widespread assent. As we learn more about the way things actually work, mistake it for a sweater. Nevertheless, though the child sees a black cat on
these problems tend to be cxpressed in somewhat different ways. !n the the sofa, sees an abject fitting this description, she does not realize that this
past forty years, for instance, computer terminology, a terminology that is is a correct description of what she sees. She thereby fails lo sec the
embodied in information-processing mode!s of perception and cognition, corrcsponding fact: fhaf there is a black cat on the sofa. She sees an abject
has become popular. Nomenclature aside, though, the problems arc still the {the black cat on the sofa) but not the fact (that there is a black cat on the
o!d problems, the ones philosophcrs have pondcred and debated for cen- sofa) corresponding to it. Shall we say, then, that the child perceives the
turies. John Locke, the famous scventeenth-century philosopher, would black cat on the sofa? The answer to this question will obvîously depend
have little trouble understanding the issues discussed here. Jndeed, he had on whether one is thinking of abjects (black cats) or facts (that they are
well-developed views on most of these topics. black cats).
Although some find it fruslrating, this continuing Jack of agreement We can, of course, mercly stipulate that visual perception is a way of
about the right answers to certain puzzhng questions-the so-called phi!o- seeing objects that involves, in some esscntial way, a knowledge of the
sophical questions-is nol unexpected. Problcms tend to be classified 11s object. So when a child-or, indeed, any other kind of animal (an unsus-
philosophical whcn they eludc established methods, including scientific pectîng mouse, for instance)-sees a cat on the sofa without realizing what
methods, of solution. But this is no reason to belittle the prob!ems or to it is, without leaming or coming ta know that it is a cat, then thîs way of
despair of thcir eventual solution. Solutions may lie in finding bettcr seeing the cat will not count as perceiving the cat. To pcrceive a cal is,
methods. This chapter is an attempt to survey some of the more intractable accordîng lo this way of using words, to corne to know, by visual means,
of these problems, to indicatc options for dealing with them, and to by the use of one's eyes, that it is a cat. Perception is restricted to seeing
introducc, when it seems useful, appropriate distinctions and clarifications. facts-to seeing thai" a catis a cat.
Wc arc frcc to use words as we please. There is nothing to prevcnt our
restricting visual perception to visual cognition, to a coming-to-know-by-
5.1 Sceing Objects and Seeing Facts
visual-means. lt would scem that this particular restriction is, in fact, rather
Whcn cognitive scienhsts speak of visual perception, it seems reasonablc to widesprcad in cognitive psychology. lnterested, as they are, in what sub-
suppose that they are referring to something that we normally describe 1ects learn in their perceptual encountcrs with abjects, cognitive psycho-
using the verb Io see. Seeing the cat on the sofa is to visually perceive the logists tend to focus on a subject's recognition or identification of abjects,
ways of sceing (hearing, smellîng) things that require some knowledge of
cat on the sofa.
To avoid misunderstanding, though. one should ask, at the very begin- what is seen (heard, smelled). So, for instance, recognizing a geometric
ning, whether visual perception (or seeing) is to be reserved for abjects, figure as a triangle requires the subject to realize, to corne to know, upon
secing it, that il is a triangle. If he, upon seeing it, doesn't know what kind
132 Dretske Seeing, Believing, and Knowing 133

of figure it is, doesn't at least distinguish it from other sorts of figures, then can be given sharper focus by distinguîshing between the kind of percep-
he doesn't recognize îl:-not, at least, as a triangle. Recognizing triangles is tion the debatc is a debatc about. Discussions or perceptual learning and
a way of seeing a fact-the fact, namely, that they are triangles. developn1ent will also benefit by a close observance of the difference
We are indeed free to use words as we please. But this proposed between cognitive and sensory forms of perception.
restriction of vîsual perception to the perception of facts, to recognition, lo for these reasons we will adopt in this chapter the device of speaking of
a way of seeing things that requires a knowledge of the thing seen, has sensory and cognitive perception. The first is a way of seeing (or perceiv-
unfortunate consequences. For we now have no natura\ way of describing ing) cats (or triangles) that does not require (though it may in fact be
the child who misl:akes the cal: for a sweater. Since the child does not know accornpanîed by) knowledge that it is a cat (or a triangle) that is seen. This
il: is a cal:, she does not. on this way of using words, perceive the cat. What, is what we have been calling abject perception. Cognifive perception of a cat
then, is the relation that exists between the child and the cal:? The child is (or triangle) will be reserved for that way of seeing the cat (triangle) that
not blind. Light rays, reflected from the cat. are enterîng the child' s eyes necessarily involves a 1.:oming to know, a cognition (in fact, a recognition),
and, in some perfectly normal way, causing within her a visual experience that it is a cat (a triangle). If one, as we ordînari\y describe things, sees a cat
that would be quite different if the cat were not there. This being so, it (a triangle) and recognizes it only as an animal (a figure) of some sort, fails
seems most natural to say, from a commonsense standpoint, that the chi!d (for whatever reason) to know or realize thal it is a cat (a triangle), then one
sees the cat but does not realize that this is what she sees. If, because of the has sen~ory, but not cognitive, perception of a cat (triangle). Cognitively
way we have decided to use the word perception, this does not count as one perceives only an animal (figure) of some (unspecified) sort. 1 leave
perceiving the cat. it must surely count as seeing the cat. Using the word open the question (but see question 5.1) of whether it is possible to have
perception in this restricted way, then, would not let us count, as visual sensory perception of an obiect without any cognitive perception of it~
perception, a person's seeing a catin perfectly normal circumstances. whether, for instance, one rnight see a cat without recognizing it as any-
lt seems preferable, therefore, to distinguish between seeing abjects and thing whatsoever (not even as an animal of some sort).'
seeing facts, not (as above) by artificially reserving the word perception for
one way of seeing, the way of seeing that requires knowledge of the thing
5.2 Pcrceptual Objects
seen (that is, seeing facts), but rather by distinguishing two forms of
perception, two ways of seeing. We are then free to speak of seeing a black
Many, perhaps most, of our cognitive perceptions, the facts we corne to
cat without necessarîly realizing (knowing or believing) that it is a black cat
know by visual rneans, are mediatcd in some way. Our visual knowledge
(or, indeed, an animal at ail) as, say, sense perception (of a black cal), and
of A depends on, and derives from, our visual knowledge of B. We see that
another, recognitional. way of seeing the cat as, say, cognitive perception
we need gas (corne to know, by visual means, that we need gas) by seeing
(that it is a black cat). This brings our use of the term visual perception
lhat our fuel gauge registers "empty.'' We see one fact (that our gas tank
(including as it now does both cognitive and sense perception) into closer
is nearly emply) by seeing another fac!- (that our gauge registers "ernply").
harmony with the ordinary verb fo see and at the same time aliows us to
We see /Jy the neu1spapers that there has been a lragic plane crash, by fhe
preserve the important distinction between seeîng a cat on the sofa and
seeing what it is that is on the sofa.
1. The tapie of see1'nx "-~-atone timf.' a fashio11ab!e \opic in the philosophy of perceplion-
Given this way of using words, we are then free to describe the efforts 1s a hybnd form of perception, a way of >eeing that goes beyond sensory perception
of cognitive scientists as investigating the processes underlying these (requiring a fairly >pecific cognitive or judgmental athtude or lendency on ihe part of the
forms of perception, examining theîr differences and commonalities. Per- perceiver) bu! fal!ing short of full cognitive perception (know!edge not being required}. One
haps it will tum out, for instance, that processes described as early vision see; a stick as a snake. The stkk obviously doe; not have to b~ a snake for one to sec it as
are rnerely the processes involved in sense perception, the seeing of abjects, a snake. Hcnn·. this cannoi be cognitive perception, at least not cognitive perception of a
Snake (for this would rcquire one to rccognize it as a snake, something one cannai do of
and later vision comprises whatever additional conceptual or cognitive sorn{'thing, like a stll"k that is not a snake). Nonetht:>!ess, one secs (srnsury perception) the
processes are essential to the perception of facts (cognitive perception) 'ti<k and takes or judges it Io be a Snake. The knowledge requ1red of cognitive perception
relating to these abjects. Perhaps, also, debates about whether perceptual (knowing that the X is an X) i; replaced by some variant of belief: one believes, or is
processes are top-clown or bottom-up, about the inferenlial or constructive ind1ned to believe. or would believe if one did not know better, of the objcct (it 1nay or rnay
nol be an X) lhat it i" an X.
character of perceptua! processes, about whether these processes are mas-
sively parallel or sequential, and about their modularity are all debates that
134 Dretske Seeing, Bclicving, and Knowing 135

fracks that the animal went this way, by her frown that she is displeascd, and fact about sensory perception, from the fact, namely, that you see the
/Jy the thermomefer that the patient has a fever. gauge but not the tank.
Given this dependence of some visually known facts on other visually Even when we speak of perceiving one objcct by, through, or in perceiv-
known facts, the question naturally arises whether so1ne facts are basic in ing another-in the way we speak, for instance, of seeing the game on TV
the scnse of bcing known directly and without this kind of dependence on or seeing someone in a movic (or photograph)-our knowledge of the
other visua!ly known facts. If my knowledge of the plane crash derives, or game or persan will be secondary relative to our knowledge of the elec-
is somehow inferred, from my knowledge of what is printed in the news- tronic or photographie image. Insofar as we regard the image appearing on
papers, if my knowledge of what other people are thinking and feeling is our television or movie screen as the primary, or real, abject of perception,
somehow inferred from what 1 can see of their observable behavior and we regard facts about these images as cognitively primary. Facts about the
expression, are the latter pieces of knowledge themselvcs derivcd from people and events being represented are secondary. For instance, we leam
some more fundamental, even more basic, kind of knowledge-possibly a (see) that a player kicked a field goal by observing the behavior of the
knowledge of how the light (retlected from a newspaper page or a person's e!ectronically produced images of the player, the ball and the goalposts
face) is structured, how this light is affecting my eyes, or how my brain is appearing on our television screen.
reactîng to al\ these extemal events? Might it tum out. as some philosophers Hence, a question about the structure of cognitive perception-whether
have argued, that ail our knowledge of exl:ernal, objective, facts-that in fact there is a fundamental level of visual knowledge, and if so, whether
there was a plane crash, that the newspaper reports a plane crash, that lhis is knowledge of objective or subjective facts-awaits the answer to a
Susan is displeased, that she is frowning-derive, ultimately, from our prior question: What is the structure of sense perception? What abjects do
knowledge of subjective facts, facts about the current state of our own we see? The answer to this question will constrain, if not determine, the
mind (how things look)? Jnswer to the questions about cognitive perception. If we do not see
This is a question about cognitive perception, about the structure of our physical objects, if we are (in sense perception) always aware of mental
knowledge. Are there some facts we know that are fundamental-fo11nda· irnages (representations) of extemal objects (as some philosophers and
honal, as philosophcrs like to put it-in the scnse that ail other things we psychologists seem to believe), then our knowledge of objective rcality (if,
know are derived from them? Is our knowledge of the way the wor!d is indced, we have such know!edge) wîll necessarily be derivative from and
derived from, and ultimately dependent upon, our knowledge of the way secondary to our knowledge of our own mental states.
the wor!d appears? Discussions of these issues are often clouded by failure to appreciate the
l'he answer to this question depends on the answer to a son1ewhat difference between cognitive perception and sense perception. lt is some-
different question, a question about sense perception. What abjects do we limes argued, for instance, that we do not perceive ordinary physical
see7 Do we see cats, sofas, newspapers, and people? If not, thcn it would abjects because, for whatever reason (the reason is usually skeptical in
seem that our knowledge of these things (the fact, for instance, that the character), we do not know, or cannot be absolutely certain, that there arr
newspapers say there was a plane crash and the fact that Susan is frowning) physical abjects. For al! we know, ail experience, even the experience we
must derive from our factual knowledge about other things (whatever take to be of a real extemal world, may be illusory. It could ail be a dream.
abjects we do see). My knowledge of the plane crash derives from n1y This argument, though it has a distinguished history, is a fairly obvious
knowledge of the newspapers because l did not see the plane crash. 1 see conllation of cognitive perception and sense perception. One does not
only the newspaper. l"lence, whatever facts l learn about the plane crash, have to know, let alone know for certain (whatever that might mean), that
including the fact that there was a plane crash, must derive from facts 1 there are physical objects in order to sec (sense perception) physical obiects.
learn about the newspaper. Such knowledgc is only required for cognitive perception. Just as the child
What facts we see, and which of these facts are fundamentaL therefore described abovc saw a cat on the sofa without knowing what it was, it may
depends on what abjects we see. If you don't see the gas tank, then your turn out that wc see ordinary physical abjects (including cats and sofas)
visual knowledge of the gas tank, that it still contains gas, must derive from every moment of our waking life without ever being able to know (if the
your visual knowledge about whatever objects you do sec-in this case, philosophîcal skeptic is right) that this is what we are seeing. Questions
typically, facts about your fuel gauge. You see that you have some gas left about what abjects we see are quite different from questions about what
by seeing what your gauge registers, and this dcpendence among cognitive facts wc know.
perceptions (your knowledge of the gauge being primary) derives fron1 a
136 Dretske Sceing, Believing, and Knowing 137

Failure to keep the distinction between sense and cognitive perception in front of us by seeing, or somehow being aware of, its internai. mental
clearly in mind also tempts students into mistakenly supposing that if our representalion. When wc are watching a game on television, then, our
knowledge of physical abjects is somehow derivaHve from the way they knowledge of the actual game is doubly indirect: we know about a game
appear tous, from the way they look, then what we really perceive when (as occurring 1,000 miles away by knowing what is happening on a television
we ordinarily say) we see a catis an internai mental image of the cat. We screen a few fecl away. and we corne to know what is happening a few feet
see (as it were) the look or appearance of the cat. Such an inference would be away by becoming aware of what is happening (presumably no distance
fallacious because even if our cognitive perceptions rest on subjective away) in our own minds. In the last analysis, then, ail our knowledge of
foundations (on the way things look tous), our sense perceptions need n9t objective (physical) fact rests on a knowledge of subjective (mental) fact
rest on similar foundations. We may know that there are physical abjects because the only objects perceived (dîrectly) are mental abjects-the way
by the way they appear to us (sa that cognitive perception has, in this things appear.
sense, a subjective basis), but our sense perception of abjects is itself direct Coing beyond these fonns of realism are various forms of idealism
and unmediated. ln other words, we may corne to know (see) it is a cai: (a (somehmes ca!Jed phenomenalism), theories that deny an objective physical
fact) by the way it appears, but what we see (the abject) is the cat itself, not reality altogether. Everything that exists depends for its existence (like a
its appearance. headachc or an afterimage) on someone's awareness of it; hence, every-
Aside from these possible confusions, though, there are a varicty of thing is in the nature of a mental entîty like an idea (hence, idealism). Since
positions that have been, and continue to be, taken on the nature of bol'h these extremc views have few, if any, serious advocates within the philo-
cognitive and sense perception-on what facts and abjects are most sophical {not to mention cognitive science) community today, we will
immediately and directly seen. Though these theories, in both their classical leave them without further comment.
and their modem form, are often hard to classify because of their failure !:o As indicated ear\ier, one might be a Direct Realist on sense perception
be clear about whether it is cognitive perception or sense perception they but an Indirect Realist on cognitive perception. The abjects we see are
are talking about, they can be roughly characterized as follows. physical abjects, but we know about them via their effect on us (the way
Direct (Naive) Realism (sometimes said to be the view of the person-on- they appear ta us) in sense perception. The problem with this mixed
the-street) holds (1) that there is a real physical world, abjects and facts position îs the problem of saying just how one might corne to know how
whose existence is independent of our perception of them (this makes the objects look-which, according to some theorists, is a knowledge of how,
view a form of physical rea/ism) and (2) that under normal conditions we in sense perception, we intemally represent them-without thereby be-
are, in a direct and unmediated way, perceptually aware of these abjects coming aware of. and hcnce perceiving, the internai representations them-
and facts (hence, direct and therefore, according to its detractors, naive selves (thereby bccoming an Indirect Realist on scnse perception also). T o
realism). ln other words, what we are directly aware of in sense perception put it crudely, how can one know how things look wîthout perceiving, or
is, unlike a headache or an afterimage, something physical that continues to somehow being aware of, their look?
exist when we are no longer aware of il. The debate bctween Direct and Indirect Realists becomes very technical
Representative Rea/ism {also called the Causal Theory of Perception) shares at this point. Indirect Realists maintain that we are directly aware of mental
with Direct Realîsm (and common sense) the firs!: of these two doctrines. Jt abjects-images-in hallucinations and dreams. Aside from the cause of
disagrees, though, about the second. According to Representative f{ealism, the experience, though, there is no reason to distinguîsh between these
our perception of physical abjects is indirect, mediated by a more direct illusory cxperiences and our ordinary veridical perception of (physical)
apprehension of something mental, some internai representation (hence the objccls. ln both cases we are directly aware of the internai mental represen.
name represenfalive realism) of externat physical reality. These mental repre· talion. When wc speak, as we commonly do, of seeing an ordinary abject
sentations have been given various names: sensations, ideas, impressions, (iike a cat), wc are, if we speak truly, being caused to experience some
percepts, sense-data, experiences, and so on. But the idea is almost always ca\like image by a real cat (a real cat that we do not directly perceive).
the same. Just as we see what is happening on the playing field by seeing Whcn wc hallucinate or drearn of a cat, there is no such extemal cause-
what is happening on our television screen (so that our know!edge of the hence, wc speak of thcse experiences as illusory. ln ail cases, though, it is
game, when viewed on te!evisîon, is indirect), so knowledge of even the the image that we direc\'ly expcrience. Only the cause of the experiencc is
most obvious physical fact-the fact, say, that thcre is a table (or. indeed, different. Direct Realists try to counter this, and related, arguments by
a television set) in front of us-is îtself indirect. We see that there is a table insisting that although scnsory perception of real abjects requires the
Seeing. Believing, and Knowing 139
IJB Drelske

they view the processing of visual information as a form of problem


having (and thereby the existence) of internai represcntations, and though
solving and hence as a form of reasoning that, though unconscîous, exhib-
such representations in fact determine the way these abjects look or appear
its enough of the essential properties of fully rational thought and judg-
l'o us, there is no reason to suppose we perceive these representations
mcnt to make it, in a fairly literai sense, an instance of problem solving
themselves. We perceive a cat by (inlemally) representing a cat, not by
itself. The light reaching the receptors (sometimes called the proximal
perceiving an internai representation of a cat.
sflrnulus) carries information-fragmentaiy and impoverished (and thereby
ambiguous) information to be sure. but information nonetheless-about
5.3 Perceptual Processes distant situations (the distal stimuli). The visual system's function îs to take
these data and to construct, as best it can, a reasonable conjecture (hypoth-
The debate about the abjects of perception is related to a debate {not esis, judgment) about the distal source of this stimulation. It begins with
always clearly disHnguished from it) about the kind of processes underly- premises describing receptor activîty, data conceming the distribution and
ing perception. Do perceptual processes, those culminating in our seeing intensity of energy reaching the receptor surface, and is charged with the
something, exhibit the qualities of reason and intelligence? Do they, despite task of arriving at usefu! conclusions about the distal source of this stimu-
being unconscious, have an inferential or computational character, moving lalîon. l'he conclusion it reaches (for instance, it must be a cat out there
from premise to conclusion (deductive reasoning), or from data to explana- causing this pattern of retinal activity) constitutes the subject's perception
tory hypothesis (inductive reasoning), in something like the way human of a caL If the visual system reaches a different conclusion-that, for
agents conscîously solve problems7 When I see a cat on the sofa, or that instance, it is probably an old black sweater-the subject sees an old black
there is a cat on the sofa, does my visual system do something similar to ~weater instead of a Auffy black cat. If the perceptual system can't make up
what clever detectives do when they infer, on the basis of certain clues and its mind, or keeps changing its mind (it's a cat; no, on second thought, it's
signs, that a certain state of affairs not directly apprehended rnusl be the probably a sweater; no, that can't be right, ifs probably a cat), the subject
case? sees first a cat. then a sweater, then a cat again. Though such Aip-Aoppîng
We can, of course, metaphorically describe the operations of anything, seldom occurs when we are lookîng at real cats (because, in normal cir-
even the simplest machine, in thoughtlike, semicognitive terms. We are cumstances, light from real cals is generally richer in information-hence,
especially fond of doing this with computers. We say they know, that they less ambiguous-about the kind of abject that has structured the light), it
remember, recognize, infer, and conclude. If one counts arithmetical opera- sometimes happens with specially constructed figures viewed under re-
tîons as forms of comput<ition, even dime store calculators perform (or are shicted (say, monocular) conditions-Necker cubes, for instance. Since so
described as perforrning) 1mpressive feats of reasoning-multiplying, taking much emphasîs is placed on the visual system's efforts at constructing a
square roots, and calculating percentage~ in fractions of a second. We even reasonable interpretation or hypothesis (about the distal stimulus) from
speak of such comparatively humble devices as thermostats and electric information reaching the receptor surfaces, this approach to perceptual
eyes in quasi-perceptual terms-as, for example, "sensing" a drop in room processing is often described as a Conslruchvist or Compufalional approach
temperature or the approach of a persan and responding by tuming the to visual perception.
furnace on or opening a door. The question, then, is not whether we can Since Constructivists regard sensory stimulation, even in the best of
speak this way, not even whether it is sometimes useful to talk this way (to viewing conditions, as inherently ambiguous (there are always a variety of
adopt what Dennett (1987) calls the inlentional stance), but whether this is distal arrangements that could have produced that pattern of proximal
anything more than a metaphorical crutch-a figure of speech that con- stimulation), thcy view pcrceptua! processing as primarily a malter of
ceals or masks our ignorance about underlying causal processes and rnech- adding information to the stimulus (or supplernenling the information avail-
anisms. Do visual systems ever literally solve problems, infer that some- able in the stin1ulus) to reach a perceptual outcome: seeing a cat. Since the
thing is so, formulate (on the basîs of sensory input) hypotheses about the proxin1al stimulation does not unequivocally specify the distant abject as a
distant source of stimulation in the way that rational agents do this at the cat, and sinl'e we nonetheless (under optimal viewing conditions) see a cat
conscious level7 (the visual system reachcs this conclusion), the perceptual system must
Hermann von Helmholtz, the great nineteenth-century physiologist, exploit some other source of information to reach this judgment-adding
thought so, and many investigators today (see, for example, Gregoiy or supplementing (via some inductive inference) the information contained
1974a, 1978; Rock 1977, 1983; Ullman 1980) are inclined to agree. At least in the stimulus.
Seeing, Bchcving. and Knowing 141
140 Dretske

There has been a vigorous challenge to this (more or less) orthoJox solvcrs about the bcsl intcrpretJtion of informationally ambiguous stimuli.
Thcrc is no point in supposing that a process of reasoning is occurring in
position in the last forty years. Gibson, in a series of influential books
(1950, 1966, 1979) and articles (1960, 1972) has argued that the stimulus,
modular systems when the process, being modular, is not allowed to use
properly undersfood, contains ail the information needed to specify the dislal
information (othcr thJn whJt is in the stimulus itself) to generate percep-
state of affairs. If the proximal stimulus is understood, not as a static lual conclusions. Modu!ar systerns are not intelligent. They don'\- have to
distribution of energy occurrîng on the receptor surfaces al a tirne, but as be. l"hcy have no problems to solve. l'hey just do what the stimulus tells
the total dynamic pattern of stimulation reaching a mobile observer over then1 to do.
lt is by no means obvious that these two approaches to the analysis of
fime, there is no need for inference, reasoning, and problem solving. 1'here
is sufficient information in the stimulus (thus broadly conceived) ta specify perceptual processcs are incompatible. lt may tum out, for example, that
although the stimulus, properly understood, is rich in information about
(unambiguously determine) the character of the distal objecL Why reason
about what is out there when the stimulus tells you what is out there7 Why distal abjects. rich enough (Jet us suppose) to unambiguously determine
suppose, as Constructivists do, that perceptual systems are smart de\-ec- what distal objects produced it, it nonetheless requires înferential (reason-
tives when ail they really have to be (given reliable informants-that is, like) processes to decode the signal, to extract this information from the
information-rich stimuli) is good listeners, good extractors of the informa- stimulus. Fingerprints, being unique to their bearers, may unambiguously
tion in the signais reaching the receptors? Since this approach tends to dc!:cnninc or spccify (in an informa!:ion-theoretic sense) who held the gun.
eliminate ail intervening cognitive (indeed, ail intervening psychological) Il nevertheless takcs a good deal of problem solving, after one has dis-
mechanisms from the processes resulting in our perception of abjects, it is covered the incriminating prints, to figure out who held the gun. One has
\-o know which people go with which prints, and this may take memory,
often referred to as a Direct Theory of perceptual processing.
Relevant to the question of whether perceptual systems are more like inference, and prior learning (the sort of cognitive work that organizations
good detectives doing their best with ambiguous data (Constructivism) or like the FBI invest into the creation of a fingerprint file). As Ullman (1980,
380--381) puts it, the ro!e of processing may no\- be to create information,
more like good \isteners faithfully registering stimulus information (Direct
'fheory) is what Fodor (1983) describes as the modularrfy of information- but to extract it, integrate it, make it explicit and usable.
processing systems. A system is (comparatively) modular when it is (corn- There are, then, a variety of ways of expressing questions about the
paratively) insulated from information available to other parts of the total nature of those processes underlying our perception of the world. But these
system. If I am told (and thereby know) that it is a cat on the sofa, for questions should not be confused, as they often are, with questions about
instance, does this, can this, affect my visual perception of the cat? If not. the abjects of perception, the questions discussed in section 5.2. Gibson's
my visual system exhîbits modularity with respect to this kind of informa- views have bcen Jescribed (by both Gîbson and others) as a theory of direct
tion (information available to the central processor from auditory sources). perception. This can be misleading. U cer\-ainly is confusing. The sense (if
If this collateral information is capable of affecHng what I see, then the any) in which this theory is direct is rnuch different from the sense in which
Direct Rea!ism is direct. Direct Realism is a theory about the abjects of
visual system (understood as that subsystem responsible for my seeing
perception, about ll'hul we sec. The kind of direct realism we are now
what l see) is not modu\ar in relation to this kind of information.
If the visual system is modular, its operation (and therefore presumably talking about. the kind ,1ssociated with Gibson's work, is a theory about the
processes underlying perception, about l1ow we see what we see. One can
what the subject perceives) is unaffected by what other information may be
be a Direct Realist about the objecls of perception, holding that we directly
available to other parts of the system (or what the subject may know as a
result of information received from these other parts). Modular systems are apprehend physical objects (not sensations or mental intermediaries}, and
be a Constructivist about the proce~ses underlying our (direct} perception
therefore described as stimu/us-driven (the processing is bottom-up rather
of these objects_ ()ne can <;upposc that intelligence, some kind of thought-
than top-clown): it is the stimulus itself {information at the bottom, as it
were), no\- the system's (possibly variable) hypotheses about that stin1ulus like process, is invo!ved 111 lhe construction of internai representations
(information available at the top) that guides the processing of incoming without supposing that one thereby sees (or in any way perceives) the
repre~entations ~o construc!ed_ l)ne can, in other words, be a Direct Realist
signais and thereby determines what the subject perceives. Modular sys-
tems are therefore most naturally thought of in the second of the lwo ways .Ülout the objects of pt'rception and an Indirect Realist. a Constructivist,
described above-as good extractors of preexistent information, infor- about the processes underlying this direct relationship.
mation that is already in the stimuli, not as good detectives or problem
142 Drctske Sceing. Believing. and Knowing J 43

Once again, though, controversy about the intelligence, or lack of it, of of the abject. What we want to know is what kind of representation a
perceptual processes is often muddled by fai!ure to be clear about exactly sensory representation is. If cognitive perception of a cat occurs when the
which processes are in question. It should be obvious that cognitive per- system constructs a cognitive representation of the cat, an internai judg-
ception-our perception of facts, our seeing that (and hence coming lo ment or belief that it is a cat (some kind of internai description of the cat as
know that) there is a cat on the sofa-is the result of a process that is a cat), what is a sensory representation of the cat, the kind of internai
strongly inAuenced by higher-level cognitive factors, Cognitive perception representation whose occurrence constitutes a sensory perception of the
is clearly not modular. A subject who docs not alrcady know whal a cat is, cat? ls it something like what philosophers and psychologîsts used to call a
or does not already know what they look like-a small child or an in- sensation? Oris it more like what they (or some of them) now call a percept?
experienced animal, say-will be unable to see (recognize) wl1al is O[j_ the Or, to use even more fashionable jargon, is it more like what Marr (1982)
sofa, unable to see fhat there is a cat there (to be carefully distinguished and his associatcs cal! a 2 J-0 sketch?
from an ability to see the cat there). For cognitive perception of the cat on Un!il thcse questions are answered, we can expect little progress on
the sofa, in contrast to sense perception of the cal, requires not only the quesHons about the nature of perception itself. How can we tell whether
appropriate concepts (for cat and sofa) but some intelligence in the applica- sensory pert·eption is best thought of in tcrms of a clever detective or a
tion of these concepts to the objects being perccived {the cat and the sofa}. good listener if we cannot say, in any clear way, what final product, what
The upshot of cognitive perception is some known fucf (say, that there is a kind of internai representation, this kind of perception îs supposed to
cat on the sofa) and such facts are not leamed without the cooperation produce?
of the entire cognitive system. By changing a subject's cognitive set-
changing what the subject knows or believes about the way things look,
5.4 Perceptual Change
for instance-one easily changes what the subject learns, cornes to know,
hence perceives in a cognitive way, about the abjects it secs (in a sensory
way). Sorne form of Constructivism or Computabonalism is therefore Do we !earn to see things7 Does prolonged experience of the world change
inevitable for seeing facls. what we perceive or the way we perceive it? Do people with radically
The real question is, or should be, whether that part of the visual system different languages, radically different ways of describing their surround-
given over to sense perception, to seeing abjects (like cats and sofas), is also ings, see th~ir surroundings differently? Do completely different world
intelligent. Does il exhibit some (any7 al\7) of the marks of reasoned judg- views-what Kuhn (1962), for instance, calls incommensurable scientific
ment7 Is if modular7 lheories-generate differences in what people can observe and, hence, in
The answer to this question will depend on just what one takes to be the data on which their theoretical differences rest?
involved in the perception of objects, in seeing, say, a cat on the sofa or a Such questions have fascinated philosophers and psychologists, linguists
persan in the room. If the upshot or outcome of cognitive perception is and anthropologists. for centuries. The answers to these questions are not
some known fact-that there is a cat on the sofa or a person in the easy. Nevertheless, some things seem reasonably clear-if not the final
room-what is the upshot or culmination of sense perception? When, at answers themse!ves, thcn at least the sorts of consideratîons that must
exactly what stage in the processing of incomlng information, do we see inform the search for final answers.
the cat on the sofa and the persan in the room? If recognizîng the abject as The first point, a point that has been made repeatedly in this chapter, is
a cat or as a persan is not necessary to the sensory perception of these that before rushing in with answers to any of these questions, one should
objects (as it îs to their cognitive perception), what is necessary? Since we first be very c!ear about the question. What kind of perception is the
question a question about?
can sec a cal: at a distance, in bad lighting, or in unusual conditions
(circumstances in which it does not even look like a cat), we cannot As a case in point, the question about whether we learn to sec things has
suppose, following Gibson, that to see a cat is to have infonn.ition in the a reasonably straightforward answer if it is a question about cognitive
stimulus that specifies the cat as a cat. For in such cases there may be no perception. about the facts we corne to know by visual means. The first
information in the stimulus about' what it is we see. That dues not prevent tirne (as a very small child presumably) 1 saw a maple tree 1 probably dîdn't
our seeing it. know what kind of tree it was. Having no experience or knowledge of
lt is true, but unilluminating, to be told thal the sensory perception of an inaple trees, being ignorant of what maple trees lookcd like (or, indeed, of
abject occurs when the visual system constructs a sensory representation what map!e trees were). 1 didn't recognize what 1 saw as a maple tree. 1
144 Dretske S('cing, Bclicving, and Knowing 145

didn't see what kind of tree it was. Now, however, [ am quite expert in this at least a much better, understanding of the nature of sensory representa-
kind of identification. 1 can look at maples, at least the more common hon, of what kind of internai response to an external abject constitutes our
varieties, and quickly recognize them as maples. 1 can see, by their general seeing the abject.
shape, their bark and leaf structure, whaf kind of tree they are, that they are Similar remarks can be made about various forms of perceptual relativify.
maple trees. There has been a change, therefore, in my ability ta cogni- ls perception relative? Well, cognitive perception is certainly relative to
tively perceive abjects around me, a change that can1e about by experience, many things-everything, in fact, capable of influencing what one cornes
leaming, and (in this case) diligent study and practice. Leaming of this kind to be!ieve. If not having a word for X or a theory about X rneans 1 cannot
is a pervasive and familiar phenomenon. corne to have certain beliefs about X, then nat having a word (or a theory)
But if the question about perceptual leamîng is a question about sensory for X will prevent me from cognitively perceiving X. Without an appro-
perception, about the abjects we see, about whether we learn to see maple priate language for talking about oxygen, without some know!edge (how-
trees themselves (and not just the fact that they are maple trees), the ever crudc) of chemical theory, 1 can hardly be expected to see when
answer appears to be quite different. 1 did not leam to See maple trees. 1 oxidatian is occurring (sec that it is occurring) even when il: happens under
could do that when 1 was a very young child-before l leamed to recog- my nase. 1 just will not recognize it-certainly not as oxidation. So the
nlze them. What l leamed is how to identify the things 1 saw, things 1 cognitive perception of oxidation is relative to thos.e factors-factors like
therefore saw before I leamed to identify them. Sensory perception of possession of the right concepts and knowledge of the appropriate scien-
abjects normally cornes before the cognitive perception of these same tific theories-that are essential to a knowledge that oxidatîon is occur-
abjects. If it did not, there would be no way to learn what abjects look like. ring. For the same reason, people who have badly mistaken astronomica]
How can you leam what abjects look lîke if you cannot see them7 Humans views will not be able to see what others see when a lunar eclipse occurs-
do not see thtngs at the moment of bîrth, of course. Certain physiological thal the moon is moving into the earth's shadow. They wi\l not see that a
changes must first occur before we can, for instance, focus on abjects and lunar eclipse is occurring because, with mistaken views about what is
coherently process information contained in light. But these maturational happening (they think the gods are showing dîspleasure by exhnguishing
processes are not to be classified as /earning in any ordinary sense. We no the moon), they will not learn what everyonc else learns when they see the
more leam to see solid abjects than we leam to digest solid food. same thing: that the earth is casting a shadow on the moon.
This is not to say that some changes in our perception, our sensory But though cognitive perception is obviously relative in this way, therc
perception, of abjects may not occur after prolonged experience. Perhaps is no reason to think-in fact, there is a lot of reason not to think-that
abjects start looking different after they become familiar or after we know sensory perception is similarly relative. Though the astronomically ignorant
certain things about them. Daes a familiar face-the face of a loved one, may not see that an eclipse is occurring, they certainly sec lhe eclipse ( = the
say-look different after it has become familiar from the way it looked the earth"s shadow moving across the face of the moon). That, in fact. is what
first time you saw it? Do coins look larger to poor children than they do to frightens them. And though the chemically ignorant can hardly be expected
rich children? Do lines in an optical illusion that look to be of different Io see that oxidation is occurring, they can, given normal eyesight, witncss
lengths start \ooking the same after you learn (by measuring them) that the oxidation, the blazing fire, as well as everyone else.
they are the same length7 These questions are questions about the way To say that perception is relative to a certain factor is to say that our
things look, about the character of our vîsual experience. about something perception of thîngs depends on that factor. Change that factor (enough)
we earlier dubbed (without really knowîng or explaining what it was) the and we change wha\' îs perceived or, possibly, whether anythîng at ail is
sensory representahon of objects. They are not questions about the way we perceived. T o suggest, then, that sense perception is not relative to a
cognitively represcnt abjects, about our perceptual beliefs or judgments. variety of factors affecting our perception of facts is a way of suggesting
Changes and differences in cognitive representations are an obviaus and that sense perception is comparatîvely modular. lt is nof sensitive ta the
familiar fact of life. That such changes exist is not worth arguing about cognitive influences {a subject's language, conceptual scheme, or scientific
(though the changes themse\ves are certainly worth studyîng). Changes, if world view) that determine one's perception of facts. The issue of percep-
any, in our sensory representations are not so obvious. Quite the contrary. tual relativity. and more generally of perceptual change and learning, then,
To document such changes one has to be very clear about what sensory is merely another way of approaching questions raised in earlier sections of
representations are and wha!" constitutes a change in them. To answer this chapter about perceptual processes in general. lt seems, therefore, that
questions about whether we learn to see in this sense, then, requires a clear, the answers to a variety of questions, both philosophica\ (raised in this
J46 Dretske
Secing, Believing, and Knowing 147
chapter) and scientific (addrcssed in earlier chapters), depends on a deeper
5.4 Are ob1ed> and facls seen in dr('ams and hallucination~? Or does one merely dream (or
understanding of perceptual processes and the different outcomes, sensory
h.lliucinatd lhat one 1.'> scdng an objeet or a fact7 (ls this difference. the difference
versus cognitive, that they support. Achieving deeper understanding of bdween ;ceing an abject in one's dream and dreaming one >l"<:> an abject. a rea/
this sort will require the combined efforts of investigators from many fields. dilfen•ncc?) Are these colored lh1ngs (of which one is aware in dreams and hallucina-
tions) in the inind7 Arc therc round rcd things in the brmn when one dreams of
;on1cthing red and round?
Suggestions for Further Reading
5.S If a ~rar explodes and disappears when rhe light from it is still on its way to earlh. does
For more detailed treatments of the distinction bl.'tween the perception of obied; dlld lhe one nonetheless stiU sce the star when the light reaches the earth many years latcr? If
perception of facts, and for a defense of lhe idea that seuse perception does not rcqtnrl' so. does this mcan that one can sec things that do not exist {any longer}? [f noi. what
cognitive perception. that seeing is not (or at least no\ necessarily) bt-beving. sel' Dretske (if ;iny lhing) does one sec when the light from the star enters one's eyes and gives Tise
1969, 1978, 19Sl. Sibley 1971. and Wamock 19.55. For opposing viewpoints (dcfend1ng the to an "experience" of a twinkling spot of !ight?
idea that ail perception invo!ves, if not knowledgc, lhcn a kind of judgment or bdief). read 5.6 Are experts in a given field-auto mechanics (on cars). cooks (on food), and tailors (on
Armstrong 1961, Ham\yn 1957, Heil 1983. and Pitcher 1971 fabrics). for instance-able to se;o things that the nonexpert, the !ayperson, cannot see7
For discussion of the issues surrounding the controversy betwl.'en Dire.;:t (Naivc) and How is one to intcrpret au!o mechanics' daims that they can htar things that laypeople
Rcpresentative Realis\s about the abjects of perception (whcther we directly sce physiral can't hear-that, for example, a car's valves need adjusting or that it needs a tune-up7
abjects or some mental sunogate). sec Drelske 1969. 1981, Goldman 1977. Sanford 1976, What kind of pl'rception is this?
and Chisholm 1957 for direct theories and Jackson 1977. Aycr 1956. 1962, and Pricc 1932
for indirect lht...:iries. A {by now) classic article on causal lheories of perception is Grice 196 L Refercnces
Concerning the question of whether perceptual processcs are ("Onstru("tive or not. dn
exchange that brings out most of the issues can be found in Ullman 198D, an article in the Arn1strong. D, M. (1961) Perceplwn and lhe phys1ca/ wor/d. London: Routledge and Kcgan
Constructivisl vein, and the comments on it (many of which defend a direct theory). For Paul.
vigorous exposition and defense of Construdivism, see Gregory l 974a,b. 1978. Rod; 1977, Ayer. A. ]. ( 1956). 11ie pr<J/1/ems of k1wwledge. London: Penguin Books.
1983, and Fodor and Pylyshyn 1981. Works generally supporlive of a direct theory of Ayer. A. J. ( 1962). flie Jo1<ndtilions of empirict1/ know/edge. London: Macmillan.
perceptual proceosing (and therefore sympathetic Io many of Gibson's ideas) includt• Turvey Brown. H. ( 1':1117). Obsenmlion and <Jbjec/101/y. ()xford: Oxford University Press.
1977. Mace 1977. Michaels and Care\lo 1981, and many of the contribution; to Shaw and (hisholm. R. (!957). Perceiurng: A plu/osophica/ sludy. lthaca. NY: Cornell University Press.
Bransford 1977 and Macleod and Pick 1974. For further discussion, induding cvaluation; of Churchland, P. (1979). Snenli~·c rea/1sn1 and the plasliûly of 1111"nd. Cambridge: Cambridge
th.,. emp1ri<Al sial us of these two approachcs. see 1-!ay('s-Roth 1977, )ohansson, von !iof;ten, University Press.
and Janss(>n 1980, and Epstein 1973. Churchland, P. (1988). Percep!ual plasticily and theorchea] neutralily: A reply fo Jerry
For perceptual leaming, change. and devdopment, consult the rcferences in chapter 4. For Fodor. f'lu/o,;ophy of Science 55, 167- IS7.
perceptual re\ativity, see Churchland 1979, 1988. chapter .5 of Drctskc 1969. Han>on 1958. Dennett, D. (1987). The i'1/enlionul sfa'1ft. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Kuhn 1962, Brown 1987, and Shapere 1982. D1elske, F. {!969) 5et1t\'1' and k1wwi11g. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Drelske, F. (1978). The role of the percept tn visual cognition. ln C. Wade Savage, ed,
Questions l'erceplw'1 and ct>&nilwn. {Minnesota Studies in the Phi!osophy of Science 9.) Minneapo-
li,, MN: University of Minnesota Press.
5.1 !s sen~ory perception possible withoul cognitive perception? Can one sec an obiec\-· Drelske, F. {1981) Knowledge and the flow vf 111fvrmalion. Cambridge. MA: MIT Press.
like a cat-without thereby coming to know someilrmg (not necessarily thal it is a cati Epstein. W. (1973). The proces,; of "taking-inlo-accounf' in v1sual perception. Perception l,
aboutit? !f nol, docs this mean thal some kind of conceplual abi!1ly (whalrver is needt•d 267-285
lo know) is necessary for vis1on--the abi!ily lo sec things7 Fodor. ). ([98J). Tl1r n1vd•J/urily of niind. Cambridge. MA: MIT Press.
Do animais see the ;ame things wc do? Do they have beliefs? 1f so. do thcy have the fod<>r, )., and Z. Pylyshyn (1981). How direct is visual per("eption7: Sorne renections on
same kind of beliefs we have? Does every aniinal with eyes (and therefor<·. presurnably, Gib;on's "'c("ological appr{)açh." Cogmlion 9, 139-196.
vision-the ability tu see things) have thoughh? Gib;on, J. J. ( 1950) Tlic ptnl'plron vj lire t'isuu/ world. Boston. Houghton MifAin
5.2 \sil poosible lo sec facts whi!c seeing no obJects-lo h,1ve cognitive perception without C,bson,). J. (1960). "lht· concept of the stimulus in psychology. Amrncan Psycho/ogisl 15,
sensc perception? What is the best way to describe whal happens when one ddccb a 694·-70J.
change in overa!I illumination {lhat the hgh\s went oui, say) w1th one'~ eyes closed7 b C1bson, ). J. ( 1966). The .'1'1!5'> con>idered as percepfuu/ sy.>/ems. Boston: Houghton MifAin.
thi~ a case of seeing a facl (that the \ights wt·nt out) w1thout see1ng an object7 G1b,on. 1 J. (1972). A theory of direct vi~ual perception. ln J. R. Royce and W. W.
5.3 ls secing an event {the cat's jumping on th(' sofa) and a slatc of affoir' (lhe çat'~ be1ng Rozcboorn. <"ds. Tlie r.syclr.>loxy of knowi"!(. New Yorko Gordon and Breach.
on the oofa) more hke sceing objeds (the ("at on lhe S()fa) or more like sceinf-\ fad> (lhJl C1boon. J. /. ( 1979). Tl1e eu1/ox!<'u/ t1pproarh Io oisut1/ perreplio11. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.
the cat is on the sofa)? Whal is required to sce the propcrlies of ob1ech--,ay, lh<' '"e Coldman. A. ( l 977). Perceplual obiecls. Synlhese 35. 257- 2t\4
or color of a cat7 Does one see the color of a black cat when one sees anolher (diffcrenll Gregory. R. ( 1974a). Choosing a paradigm for perception. ln E. C. Carteret te and M. P.
object of the same rolor (say, a black ba!l)7 Friedman, eds .. H1md/~\>k "f perceplio11. Vol. 1: //isloncul t1nd philosophica/ roofs of' perct/!lion.
New York: Academic Prc~s
148 Dretske

Gregory. R. ( l 974b). p,,.rçeptions as hypotheses. ln S. C. Brown. eJ_, Philosophy of psyclwloxy.


London, Macmillan_
Gregory, R. (1978)_ Eyr 11nd brmn, Thr psyclw/ogy of sering. Jrd ... d_ New York· McCraw-llill.
Gricc. P_ (1961) The causal theory of perception. Proceedmgs of the Ar1;/olelia11 Soody, Action
5Hppleme11/ary Volume 35.
Hamlyn, D. W. (1957). The psycholosy of perception. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Hansun, N R_ (1958). Pa/lems of discovery. London: Cambridge University Press.
Hayes-Roth, F. (1977). Critique of Turvey's "Conhasting orientations to the theory of v1sual
information processing." Psycho/ogica/ Review 84, 5Jl-535.
Heil, J. (1983). Perceplion and cognilron. Berkeley, CA· University of Ca!ifomia Press.
Jackson, F. (1977). Perceplion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Johansson, G., C. von Hofsten. and C. Jansson (1980). Event pen.:eption_ A11111«1/ Review of
Psychology 31. 27-63.
Kuhn. T. S. (1962). The struclure of scienlific revoluiions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press_
Mace, W. M. (1977). James Gibson's strategy for perceiv1ng: Ask nul whafs in your head.
but what your head i~ inside of_ ln ShJw and Bransford 1977.
Macleod. R. B., and H. L. Pick, /r. eds. (1974)_ l'erceplion: Lssays in lwnor of Janus J. G1b.1tm.
lthaca. NY: ComE>ll University Press.
Marr. D_ ( 1982)_ V1s1on: A cornpula/10mi/ mvesl1!{alion inlo lhe human represenla/10" and pnJCr.>s-
mg of visua/ infomuifion. San Francisco' W. H. Freeman.
Michaels, C. F., and C. Carello (1981)_ f>ired perception. Englewood Cliffs. N/: Prcnticc-HalL
Pitchcr, G. (1971 ). A lheory of perceplwn. Princeton, NJ: Pnnceton Univcr;ily Prcs~-
Price, H. H_ (1932). Perreplron. London: Melhuen.
Rock, L (1977). ln defense of unconsciou5 infcrence_ ln W_ Epstein, ed., 5/abilily and ronshmry
in visual perception. New York: Wiley.
Rock, L (I 983). Tite logic of perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Sanford, D. ( 1976). The prim.iry objects of perct"ption. M111J 85, 189-208.
Shapere, D. (1982). The concept of observation in science and philosophy_ Philosoplry of
Sâence 49. 485-525.
Shaw, R.. and ]. Bransford, eds. (1977)_ Perceiving. acting tlnd knowing_ Hillsda!e. NJ:
L Erlbaum Associales.
Sibley, F. N. (1971). Analyzing seeing. ln F_ N_ Sibley. ed .. Prrcrplron. London: Methuen.
Turvey, M. T. (1977). Contra5hng orientahons to the lheory of visual infonnahon process-
ing. Psycholog1ca/ Review 84, 67-88.
Ullman. S. (1980). Against direct perception. &lun>wral imd Bram Sâenres 3, 37J-4 15_
Wamock, J_ (1955)_ Seeing. Arisloielian Soriely Proceedings 55.

You might also like