You are on page 1of 53

Discrete Structures & Algorithms

Propositional Logic

EECE 320 : UBC : Spring 2009

1
Summary so far
• Pancake sorting
• A problem with many applications
• Bracketing (bounding a function)
• Proving bounds for pancake sorting
• You can make money solving such problems (Bill Gates!)
• Illustrated many concepts that we will learn in this course
• Proofs

• Sets

• Counting

• Performance of algorithms

2
Propositional logic

• Logic of compound statements built from simpler


statements using Boolean connectives.
• Building block for mathematics and computing.
• Direct applications
• Design of digital circuits

• Expressing conditions in programs

• Database queries

3
A sandwich is better than God

• Nothing is better than God.


• A sandwich is better than nothing.
• Thus, a sandwich is better than God.

4
What is propositional logic?

• The simplest form of mathematical logic.


• Develops a symbolic language to treat compound and
complex propositions and their logical relationship in an
abstract manner.

• And, before we get ahead of ourselves... what is a


proposition?
• A declarative statement that is either true or false (but not
both!).
5
Examples of propositions
• September 6 2007 is a Thursday.
• September 6 2007 is a Friday.
• 3+2 equals 7.
• There is no gravity.
The following are not propositions.
• Do your homework.
• What is the time?
• 3+4.
6
Propositions and their negations
Suppose p is a proposition, then the
negation of p is written as ¬p.

The negation of proposition p implies that “It is


not the case that p.”

Examples
p: It is raining. ¬p: It is not raining.
p: 3+2=5. ¬p: 3+2≠5.

Notice that ¬p is a proposition too.


7
Conjunctions and disjunctions

• Elaborate ways of saying “and” and “or”


• Consider two propositions, p and q
• Conjunction (“and”): p Λ q
• It is a bright and windy day.

• The day has to be both bright and windy.

• Disjunction (“or”): p V q
• To ride the bus you must have a ticket or hold a pass.

• One of the two conditions (“have a ticket” or “hold a pass”)


suffices. (Though both could be true.)
8
“Exclusive or”

• In day-to-day speech, sometimes we use “or” as an


“exclusive or”.
• “I will take a taxi or a bus from the airport.”
• Only one of “taxi” or “bus” is implied.
• To be precise, one would need to say “I will take either a
taxi or a bus from the airport.”

• “Exclusive or” XOR is denoted by the symbol.

9
Truth tables
•Truth tables can be used to evaluate statements. A
simple proposition can either be “true” or “false”.

Negation Conjunction (“and”) Disjunction (“or”)


p q pΛq p q pVq
p ¬p
F F F F F F
T F
F T F F T T
F T
T F F T F T
T T T T T T
Notice that the conjunction and disjunction of two propositions
are also propositions (and, along with negation, are called
compound propositions).

10
Logical equivalence

Two statements are logically equivalent if and only


if they have identical truth tables.

The simplest example is ¬(¬p) ≡ p.

11
Implication

• Another important logical construct is implication


• This is akin to saying “If ... then ...”
• When proposition p holds then q holds.
• Notation: p → q.

• Example: If I am on campus, I study.


• p: I am on campus.

• q: I study.

12
Truth table for implication
• p → q: If p, then q.
• If p is true, q must be true for the implication to hold.
• p is the assumption/premise/antecedent.
• q is the conclusion/consequent.
Implication
p q p→q
T F F
T T T
F F T
F T T
13
An equivalent for implication
Is there an expression that is equivalent to p → q but uses
only the operators ¬, Λ, V?
Implication
p q p→q
F F T
Consider the F T T
proposition ¬p V q T F F
T T T

p q ¬p ¬p V q
F F T T
F T T T
T F F F
T T F T
14
Proving other equivalences

• Easy to use truth tables and show logical equivalence.


• Example: distributivity
• p Λ (q V r) ≡ (p V q) Λ (p V r)

• Do this as an exercise.

• You would have seen these forms in earlier courses on


digital logic design.

15
Logical equivalences
• The basic laws Propositions that are logically equivalent. You

• Identity
will need to know them, although we will not
elaborate on them in lecture.
• Domination
In the text (Rosen): Chapter 1, Section 2.
• Idempotence

• Negation and double negation

• Commutation

• Association

• Distribution

• Absorption

• De Morgan’s laws
16
Variations on a proposition

• Given a proposition p → q, there are other propositions


that can be stated.
• Example: If a function is not Of the three (contrapositive,
continuous, converse, inverse),
it is not differentiable.
which is not like the other two?

• Contrapositive: ¬q → ¬p
• Example: If a function is differentiable, then it is continuous.

• Converse: q → p Hint: One is a logical equivalent of the original


proposition.

• Example: If a function is not differentiable, then it is not continuous.

• Inverse: ¬p → ¬q The “contrapositive” is equivalent to the original


proposition.
• Example: If a function is continuous, then it is differentiable.
17
Tautology & Contradiction

• A proposition that is always true is called a tautology.


• Example: p V ¬p

• A proposition that is always false is called a


contradiction.
• Example: p Λ ¬p

18
Bi-conditionals (“if and only if”)
• If p and q are two propositions, then p ↔ q is a bi-
conditional proposition.
• p if and only if q. (p iff q)

• p is necessary and sufficient for q.

• If p then q, and conversely.

• Example: The Thunderbirds win if and only if it is


raining.

• p ↔ q is the same as (p → q) Λ (q → p).


• Are there other other equivalent statements?
19
What is an argument?

• A sequence of statements the ends with a conclusion.


• (Not the common language usage of a debate or dispute.)

Structure of an argument

Statement 1 (p1)
premises
Statement 2 (p2)
or
...
antecedents
Statement n (pn)

Statement n+1 (conclusion)


20
Example

• Premises
• “If you have a current password, you can log onto the
computer network.”

• “You have a current password.”

• Conclusion
• “Therefore, you can log onto the computer network.”

21
Representing an argument
An argument is sometimes written as follows:

premises

conclusion

22
Valid arguments

• An argument is valid if and only if it is impossible for


all the premises to be true and the conclusion to be
false.
• How do we show that an argument is valid?
• We can use a truth table, or

• We can show that (p1 Λ p2 Λ ... Λ pn → pn+1) is a


tautology using some rules of inference.

23
Why use rules of inference?
• Constructing a truth table is time consuming!
• If we have n propositions, what is the size of the truth
table? 2n, which means that the table doubles in size
with every proposition.

Implication
p→q
p q
Two propositions are involved in an implication,
F F theT truth table has 22 = 4 rows.
therefore
F T T
T F F
T T T

24
Rules of inference

modus ponens
“method of affirming”

25
Rules of inference

modus tollens
“method of denying”

26
Rules of inference

generalization specialization

27
Rules of Inference
More rules of inference listed in the text. Try
proving them as an exercise.
Chapter 1, Section 5 (Rosen).

• pq Rule of hypothetical


qr syllogism
pr
•pq Rule of disjunctive
p syllogism
q

28
Inference Rules for Quantifiers
More rules of inference listed in the text. Try
proving them as an exercise.
Chapter 1, Section 5 (Rosen).

• x P(x)
P(o) (substitute any specific object o)

• P(g) (for g a general element.)


x P(x)

• x P(x)
P(c) (substitute a new constant c)

• P(o) (substitute any extant object o)


x P(x)
29
Formal Proofs

• A formal proof of a conclusion C, given premises p ,1


p2,…,pn consists of a sequence of steps, each of which
applies some inference rule to premises or previously-
proven statements to yield a new true statement (the
conclusion).
• A proof demonstrates that if the premises are true, then
the conclusion is true.

30
Formal Proof Example

• Suppose we have the following premises:


“It is not sunny and it is cold.”
“We will swim only if it is sunny.”
“If we do not swim, then we will canoe.”
“If we canoe, then we will be home early.”
• Given these premises, prove the theorem
“We will be home early” using inference rules.

31
Proof Example cont.

• Let us adopt the following abbreviations:


• sunny = “It is sunny”; cold = “It is cold”;
swim = “We will swim”; canoe = “We will canoe”;
early = “We will be home early”.

• Then, the premises can be written as:


(1) sunny  cold (2) swim  sunny
(3) swim  canoe (4) canoe  early

32
Proof Example cont.

• Step Proved by
1. sunny  cold Premise #1.
2. sunny Simplification of 1.
3. swimsunny Premise #2.
4. swim Modus tollens on 2,3.
5. swimcanoe Premise #3.
6. canoe Modus ponens on 4,5.
7. canoeearly Premise #4.
8. early Modus ponens on 6,7.

33
Proofs and theorems
A theorem is a statement that can be shown to be
true. A proof is the means of doing so.

Axioms,
postulates,
hypotheses and
previously proven
theorems Rules of inference

Proof

34
Common Fallacies
• A fallacy is an inference rule or other proof
method that is not logically valid.
• A fallacy may yield a false conclusion!

• Fallacy of affirming the conclusion:


• “pq is true, and q is true, so p must be true.” (No, because
FT is true.)

• Example:
• If you do every problem in the book, then you will learn
mathematics. You learned mathematics.

• Therefore you did every problem in the book (incorrect!).


35
Common Fallacies

• Fallacy of denying the hypothesis:


• “pq is true, and p is false, so q must be false.”
(No, again because FT is true.)

• Example
• If you do every problem in the book, then you
will learn mathematics. You did not do every
problem in the book.
• Therefore you did not learn mathematics
(incorrect!).
36
Common fallacies:
Circular Reasoning
• The fallacy of (explicitly or implicitly) assuming the
very statement you are trying to prove in the course
of its proof. Example:
• Prove that an integer n is even, if n 2
is even.

• Attempted proof: “Assume n is even. Then n2=2k


2

for some integer k. Dividing both sides by n gives n =


(2k)/n = 2(k/n). So there is an integer j (namely k/n)
such that n=2j. ThereforeBegs
n is the
even.”
question: How do
• you in
Circular reasoning is used show that j=k/n=n/2
this proof. Where? is an integer,
without
37 first assuming that n is even?
A Correct Proof

• Prove that an integer n is even, if n2 is even.

38
Proof Methods for Implications

• For proving implications pq, we have:


• Direct proof: Assume p is true, and prove q.
• Indirect proof: Assume q, and prove p.
• Vacuous proof: Prove p by itself.
• Trivial proof: Prove q by itself.
• Proof by cases:
Show p(a  b), and (aq) and (bq).

39
Direct Proof Example
• Definition: An integer n is called odd iff n=2k+1 for
some integer k; n is even iff n=2k for some k.

• Theorem: (For all numbers n) If n is an odd integer,


then n2 is an odd integer.

• Proof: If n is odd, then n = 2k+1 for some integer k.


Thus, n2 = (2k+1)2 = 4k2 + 4k + 1 = 2(2k2 + 2k) + 1.
Therefore n2 is of the form 2j + 1 (with j the integer
2k2 + 2k), thus n2 is odd. □
40
Indirect Proof Example

• Theorem: (For all integers n)


If 3n+2 is odd, then n is odd.
• Proof: Suppose that the conclusion is false, i.e., that n
is even. Then n=2k for some integer k. Then 3n+2 =
3(2k)+2 = 6k+2 = 2(3k+1). Thus 3n+2 is even,
because it equals 2j for integer j = 3k+1. So 3n+2 is
not odd. We have shown that ¬(n is odd)→¬(3n+2 is
odd), thus its contra-positive (3n+2 is odd) → (n is
odd) is also true. □

41
Vacuous Proof Example

• Theorem: (For all n) If n is both odd and even, then n2


= n + n.
• Proof: The statement “n is both odd and even” is
necessarily false, since no number can be both odd and
even. So, the theorem is vacuously true. □

42
Trivial Proof Example

• Theorem: (For integers n) If n is the sum of two


prime numbers, then either n is odd or n is even.
• Proof: Any integer n is either odd or even. So the
conclusion of the implication is true regardless of the
truth of the antecedent. Thus the implication is true
trivially. □

43
Proof by Contradiction

• A method for proving p.


• Assume p, and prove both q and q for some proposition q. (Can
be anything!)

• Why does it work?


• Thus p (q  q)
• (q  q) is a trivial contradiction, equal to F
• Thus pF, which is only true if p=F
• Thus p is true.
44
Proof by Contradiction Example
• Theorem: sqrt(2) is irrational.
2• Proof:
• Assume 21/2 were rational. This means there are integers
i,j with no common divisors such that 21/2 = i /j.
• Squaring both sides, 2 = i2/j2, so 2j2 = i2. So i2 is even;
thus i is even.
• Let i =2k. So 2j2 = (2k)2 = 4k2. Dividing both sides by 2,
j2 = 2k2.
• Thus j2 is even, so j is even.
• But then i and j have a common divisor, namely 2, so we
have a contradiction. □ 45
Review: Proof Methods So Far

• Direct, indirect, vacuous, and trivial proofs of


statements of the form pq.
• Proof by contradiction of any statements.
• Next: Constructive and nonconstructive existence
proofs.

46
Proving Existence

• A proof of a statement of the form x P(x) is called an


existence proof.
• If the proof demonstrates how to actually find or
construct a specific element a such that P(a) is true,
then it is a constructive proof.
• Otherwise, it is nonconstructive.

47
Constructive Existence Proof

• Theorem: There exists a positive integer n that is the


sum of two perfect cubes in two different ways:
• equal to j3 + k3 and l3 + m3 where j, k, l, m are positive
integers, and {j,k} ≠ {l,m}

• Proof: Consider n = 1729, j = 9, k = 10,


l = 1, m = 12. Now just check that the equalities hold.

48
Nonconstructive Existence Proof

• Theorem:
“There are infinitely many prime numbers.”
• Any finite set of numbers must contain a maximal
element, so we can prove the theorem if we can just
show that there is no largest prime number.
• I.e., show that for any prime number, there is a larger
number that is also prime.
• More generally: For any number,  a larger prime.
• Formally: Show n p>n : p is prime.
49
The proof, using proof by cases...

• Given n>0, prove there is a prime p>n.


• Consider x = n!+1. Since x>1, we know
(x is prime)(x is composite).
• Case 1: x is prime. Obviously x>n, so let p=x and
we’re done.
• Case 2: x has a prime factor p. But if pn, then p mod
x = 1. So p>n, and we’re done.

50
Pancake numbers

• How did we prove the bounds on P ?


n

• n  P  2n – 3
n

• What are the propositions involved?

51
Wrap up

•Propositional logic
• Or propositional calculus
• Truth tables
• Logical equivalence
• Basic laws
•Rules of inference
• Arguments
• Premises and conclusions
•Proofs

52
53

You might also like