You are on page 1of 18

A Redescription of "Romantic Art"

Author(s): Niklas Luhmann


Source: MLN, Vol. 111, No. 3, German Issue (Apr., 1996), pp. 506-522
Published by: The Johns Hopkins University Press
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3251025
Accessed: 16/01/2009 17:23

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless
you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you
may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.

Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at
http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=jhup.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
page of such transmission.

JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We work with the
scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that
promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

The Johns Hopkins University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
MLN.

http://www.jstor.org
A Redescriptionof "RomanticArt"

Niklas Luhmann

A sociologist taking up a theme like "romantic art" should endeavor


to add nothing new to the subject matter itself. Faithfulness to the ob-
ject is called for-even if only in the ordinary sense of "empirical." In
what follows it is therefore not a matter of competing with literary or
aesthetic inquiry or of offering new interpretations of Romantic texts
or other contemporary works of art. Nor shall I intervene in the broad
discussion bearing on the relationship of Romanticism, and above all
early German Romanticism (Fruhromantik), to modern society and its
self-description as "modern";1 this discussion is too dependent on
crude evaluations (for example, "irrationalism") and will necessarily
remain controversial as long as the concept of modernity itself remains
controversial. It is, then, not a question of hermeneutics, not a matter
of 'knowing better' in the domain of the critical analysis of art; in fact
it is not even, at least not directly, a question here of a more adequate
understanding of key Romantic concepts such as poetry (Poesie), irony,
arabesque, fragment, criticism. Such may emerge as a byproduct of
our investigation. But disciplinary discourses operate in their own spe-
cific recursive networks, with their own intertextualities, their own self-
fabricated pasts, which, for instance, determine what one has to do in
order to assume the standpoint of second-order observation and to re-
main intelligible-regardless of whether one continues the discursive
tradition or suggests particular changes. And, as is well-known, it is dif-

1 See Karl Heinz Bohrer, Die KritikderRomantik,Frankfurt 1989.

MLN, 111 (1996): 506-522 ? 1996 by The Johns Hopkins University Press
MLN 507

ficult (if not impossible, at least dependent on coincidences hard to


foresee) to intervene in disciplines from the outside in the name of in-
terdisciplinarity.2
This should be emphasized in advance when, as here, it is a matter
of redescribing with systems-theoretical instruments what happened
when Romanticism discovered its own autonomy and realized and
worked through what had already taken place historically, namely the
social differentiation of a functional system specifically related to
art.3There is a considerable literature bearing on this development, a
literature that takes as its point of departure the notion that the spe-
cific character of Romanticism as well as subsequent reflections of art
is conditioned by the reorganization of society along the lines of func-
tional differentiation.4 If Romanticism was modern and still is, then
not because it preferred the "hovering" (das "Schwebende') or the "ir-
rational" or the "fantastic," but because it attempts to endure system
autonomy. Up till now, however, there have not been any investigations
that seek to make clear, at the level of abstraction of general systems
theory, what is to be expected when functional systems are differenti-
ated as self-referential, operationally closed systems. This process can-
not be grasped according to the schema-still predominant at the
time of Romanticism-of part and whole. The same goes for general
concepts of the advantageous division of labor or, negatively formu-
lated, of the eternal conflict of apriori binding values; phrased in
terms of proper names: the point holds for Emile Durkheim and Max
Weber. For neither can one assume that an "organic" solidarity corre-
sponding to the division of labor emerges on its own, nor is itjustified
to conceive of values as fixed points on the horizon of action orienta-
tion. Today entirely different theoretical instruments are available for
a discussion of these foundational issues.

2 On these difficulties, but also on


possible parallelisms among developments in the
natural sciences, cybernetics, and literary studies, see the book by the English scholar
trained in chemistry: N. Katherine Hayles, ChaosBound: OrderlyDisorderin Contemporary
Literatureand Science,Ithaca 1990, esp. p. 37.
3 The concept of "redescription" is here employed in the sense of Mary Hesse, Mod-
els and Analogiesin Science,Notre Dame 1966, p. 157ff. One should, however, speak of
"metaphorical redescription" only if one accepts that no theory can do without
metaphors and furthermore that the concept of metaphor is itself a metaphor that uses
"metapherein" in a figural, extended, or translated sense.
4 See, for example, SiegfriedJ. Schmidt, Die Selbstorganisation
desSozialsystems
Literatur
im 18. Jahrhundert,Frankfurt 1989; Niels Werber, Literaturals System:Zur Ausdifferen-
zierungliterarischerKommunikation,Opladen 1992. Cf. also Gerhard Plumpe, Asthetische
KommunikationderModerne,Vol. I: VonKant bisHegel,Opladen 1993.
508 NIKLAS ITIIHMANN

II

Important changes in the conceptual repertoire of systems theory re-


sult when one substitutes "essential definitions" ( Wesensdefinitionen),but
also so-called analytic system concepts, with the theoretical notion of
the operative closureof systems. Essential definitions rested on a hetero-
referential (fremdreferentiell)orientation, analytic definitions on a self-
referential orientation of the observer. The notion of operative closure
and, related to it, the theory of autopoietic systems presuppose that self-
referential systems must be observed. They are just that which they
make out of themselves. An observation is therefore only then appro-
priate if it takes the self-reference of the system and, in the case of sys-
tems operating with meaning (sinnhaft operierend), the self-observation
of the system into account. The "paradigm shift" that is thereby ac-
complished displaces systems theoryfrom the level of first-order obser-
vation (systems as objects) to the level of second-order observation (sys-
tems as subobjects or obsubjects, to employ formulations of Jean Paul) .5
With this turn, the distinction between self-reference and hetero-
reference is relocated within the observed observing system. Not only
the scientific observer must be able to distinguish between him/herself
and others (that is, between concepts and objects); this verba/res dis-
tinction is valid for all observing systems, even when they are occupied
with sense perceptions and have to rely on the external world without
being able to distinguish between reality and illusion.6 The generaliza-
tion of the concept and the structural problems of observing systems
has far-reaching consequences, which only became apparent through
mathematical analyses. This detour via mathematics frees us at the
same time from the mystifications previously attached to concepts such
as "meaning" (Sinn) or "mind" (Geist). They enable us to see today
more clearly why and how something like "imagination" is required and
in what sense construction/deconstruction/ reconstruction as an on-
going process, an ongoing displacement of distinctions (Derrida's dif-
ferance), is necessary in order to dissolve paradoxes in and as time.7

5 See Clavis Fichteana seu Leibgeberiana,in Jean Paul, Werke,vol. 3, Munich 1961,
pp. 1011-56, or Flegeljahre,eine Biographie,in Werke,vol. 2, Munich 1959, pp. 567-1065,
esp. 641.
6 This special condition of an unavoidable trust in the world that can only be dis-
rupted through critical reflection holds, however, only for psychic systems. For this rea-
son we can leave it out of consideration in what follows.
7 The parallels between deconstruction and second-order cybernetics are treated
more thoroughly in: Niklas Luhmann, "Deconstruction as Second Order Observing,"
New LiteraryHistory24 (1993), pp. 763-82.
M LN 509

In what follows we rely on the calculus of form developed by George


Spencer Brown.8 Similar considerations are to be found in the second-
order cybernetics which Heinz von Foerster has elaborated.9 Here the
consideration as to what happens when the output of a system is im-
mediately reintroduced into the system (that is, when the system forms
reflective loops within itself) leads to the concept of the non-trivial,
and therefore unpredictable, machine. And here too the problem
consists in the fact that the space of possibilities of the system is so
greatly expanded through self-reference that neither internal nor ex-
ternal observations can predict the operations of the system. A further
inference that can be drawn from these mathematical analyses: the sys-
tem requires meaning in order to deal successfully (zurechtzukommen)
with both itself and its world.l?
With reference to this problematic locus Spencer Brown employs
the concept of the "re-entry" of a distinction into itself.Hllere too it is
a question of deploying possibilities of ordering that cannot be
achieved through the normal operations of the arithmetic and alge-
bra and can only be demonstrated as paradoxes. Spencer Brown's
mode of presentation has the advantage of being directly applicable
to a very formal concept of observation. Observation is, in this con-
text, nothing other than the use of a distinction for the indication of
one and not the other side of the distinction, however the system that
performs this might be constituted. For this reason the analysis con-
cludes by referring back to its beginning in the equation of observing
and drawing a distinction: "We see now that the first distinction, the
mark, and the observer are not only interchangeable, but, in the form,
identical. 12
For the analysis of the Romantic world, the consequences of such a
re-entry are of central importance. If it can be accomplished (whether
it is accomplished is then an empirical question), the system reaches
a state of "unresolvable indeterminacy."13 The decisive aspect of this

8 See
George Spencer Brown, LawsofForm,New York 1979. Cf. also Dirk Baecker, ed.,
KalkiilderForm,Frankfurt 1993.
9 Heinz von Foerster, ObservingSystems,Seaside, Cal. 1981. See also the German edi-
tion expanded with several additional contributions: Heinz von Foerster, Wissenund
Gewissen.VersucheinerBriicke,Frankfurt 1993.
10This presupposes, of course, a de-subjectification of the concept of meaning. For a
thorough elaboration of this point see Niklas Luhmann, SozialeSysteme:Grundrifieiner
allgemeinenTheorie,Frankfurt 1984, p. 92ff.
11On this point and on what follows, see Spencer Brown, Laws ofForm,54ff., 69ff.
12 Ibid., p. 76.
13 Ibid., p. 57.
510 NIKLAS LUHMANN

concept is that the indeterminacy is not explained with reference to


dependence on an overpowering, itself indeterminable environment,
but rather is caused by the re-entry within the system itself. It is thus a
matter of self-generateduncertainty with which the system in one way or
another, but in any case selectively, must deal.
In order to do this the system requires:
1. a memoryfunction. Memory must be understood here as the presentation
of the present as the result of the past; or alternatively as the result of an
ongoing discrimination between forgetting and remembering.14 The
memory function is thus a necessary accompaniment to all operations of
observing systems. It is by no means a matter of the occasional calling up
of memories on the time-scale of the past (after the pattern: where did I
put my glasses?).
2. an oscillatorfunction. This can be interpreted-going beyond Spencer
Brown- as the correlate of the use of distinctions. With every deploy-
ment of distinctions in observation the system will also observe (mit-
beobachten)the possibility of crossing the border of the distinction with a
further operation and thus moving from one side to the other-for ex-
ample: from the positive to the negative, from the good to the bad, from
the allowed to the prohibited, from the useful to the non-useful, from the
profane to the sacred, etc., from the realistic to the fantastic and back
again.
With the memory function the system binds itself to its own, now un-
alterable past. In this way it produces a present with a past horizon and
motivates itself to proceed from the present state of the world rather
than presupposing everything as new and unknown at every moment
and thus always starting from the beginning.15 For this reason there is
no "originary" present, no present that would be its own origin. With
the oscillator function the system holds its future open-and not
merely as the freedom of performing this or that action, but with re-
gard to the fact that everything can arrive different; and this not arbi-
trarily, but depending on the distinction being used, which, because it

14 Hence of the
freeing-up and the reimpregnation of the observational capacities of
the system. This according to Heinz F6rster, Das Geddchtnis.Eine quantenmechanische Un-
tersuchung,Vienna 1948. This formulation, by the way, shows how identities emerge,
namely through confirmation (Bewdhrung) in reimpregnation or, in the terms of
Spencer Brown (Laws of Form,p. 10), through condensation and confirmation; in any
case, however, through the ongoing equation (Abgleichung)with new irritations but not
with fixed contents of the environment.
15 In doctrines of wisdom the opposite requirement is occasionally stated: "The wise
perceive every thing as new, in attentive observation if not at first glance." Baltasar
Gracian, CriticonoderUeberdie allgemeinenLasterdesMenschen,Hamburg 1957, p. 15.
MLN 511

includes what it excludes, indicates what in any given case can be oth-
erwise. This too does not require, but rather makes possible a chrono-
metric ordering of future temporal positions.
The differencebetween the simultaneously required memory and oscil-
lator functions makes the construction of time necessary, the distinc-
tion of past and future and the insertion of a present between them in
which alone the system can operate. Via temporal difference modal-
theoretical paradoxes can be dissolved, for example the supramodal
necessity of contingency that was once so important to theology. The
necessary can now be seen as a consequence of its being past, the con-
tingent as a feature of the future. With the distinction of past and fu-
ture the system can, additionally, deal with the requirement that it si-
multaneously (!) generate and hold in store both redundancy and
variety;the requisite redundancy will then be attributed to the past, the
requisite variety to the future. And that still leaves the question open
whether one conceives of the present as constant, as enduring, and
time as flowing through it, or construes the present of the system as
process, as a movement out of the past in the direction of the future.
The system can think of itself as static and as the correlate to the eter-
nity of God, for example as a soul which must endure its temporal ex-
istence; or as dynamic and with the necessity/impossibility of using the
present in order to shape the future. This distinction can then be used
to adapt the temporal structures to socio-cultural configurations. In any
case, however, the constructivist analysis compels one to conclude that
every present is furnished with past and future horizons and for that
reason that the future can never become present.16 The temporal hori-
zons only shift with, indeed by virtue of, the operations of the system so
that from moment to moment new pasts and futures are being selected.
Reformulated in terms of the theory of games, what follows from
this analysis is that the game can only be played within the game and
only with distinctions that identify the individual operations and si-
multaneously the play itself.17 That's why Adam (in Paradise Lost) had to
have the world explained to him by the archangel Raphael; and that's
why Henry Adams can only describe his education as the play of an in-
determinate I against an indeterminate world.18

16 On this point see Niklas Luhmann, "The Future Cannot Begin: Temporal Struc-
tures in Modern Society," SocialResearch43 (1976), pp. 130-52.
17For several mathematical variants of this theme, cf. Louis H. Kauffman, "Waysof
the Game-Play and Position Play,"Cybernetics and Human Knowing2/3 (1994), pp. 17-
34.
18
Henry Adams, TheEducationof HenryAdams,New York 1918.
512 NIKLAS LUHMANN

III
In certain respects, mathematical theories have today overtaken what
in the so-called human sciences (Geisteswissenschaften), but in sociology
as well, had always been intuited and expressed through a rather am-
biguous use of language. This is true above all for chaos theory.19 It is
also true of the catastrophe theory of Ren6 Thom and of the post-
Godelian calculus of forms of Spencer Brown discussed above. Of
course, it is not to be expected that Romanticism anticipated and more
or less intuitively took such a development of formal theory programs
into consideration. However, a close examination of the texts of
Romanticism can disclose so many correspondences that it becomes
unavoidable to ask how they can be explained.
An overhasty conclusion would be to say that Romanticism is nothing
other than the poetic paraphrase of a mathematical problem, a poetic
version of mathematics. We shall leave that view aside and instead make
our way via a sociological theory that can sustain empirical verification.
This intention was already alluded to above. Its point of departure is the
notion that the functional differentiation of modern society can be con-
ceived in terms of autonomous, operatively closed, autopoietic func-
tional systems. That leads to the hypothesis that all functional systems
draw limits or borders and therefore must reproduce the difference
between inside and outside internally as the difference self-reference/
hetero-reference. The transition from hierarchically fixed positional
orders describable as nature to the primacy of the distinction between
self- and hetero-reference is considered a characteristic, if not the deci-
sive feature of Romantic literature20 (and, one can add, Romantic art in
general). That encourages us to be on the lookout for the above de-
scribed consequences of re-entry. For in the final analysis the distinction
between self- and hetero-reference is nothing other than the re-entry of
the distinction system/environment into the system itself.

IV

With the differentiation of the art system and its disconnection from
external compulsions, an excess of communicative possibilities

19 On this point see Hayles, ChaosBound (note 2). On the discussions set into motion
by the theory of thermodynamics, see Kenneth D. Bailey, Sociologyand the New Systems
Theory,New York 1994.
20 See esp. Earl R. Wasserman, TheSubtler
Language.CriticalReadingsofNeoclassicaland
RomanticPoems,Baltimore 1959.
M LN 513

emerges internally and must be internally controlled and brought into


form.21 The relationship of redundancy and variety, which for a long
time had accompanied the description of art,22shifts in the direction
of a flood of variational possibilities that can hardly any longer be mas-
tered.23 The "marvelous"is not an invention of Romanticism, but of
the Cinquecento;24 but when its differentiation is fully accomplished, art
can more forcefully distance itself from a pre-given reality.25More and
more, art must generate the requisite redundancies itself, and this
through the restriction of variety. Today one would speak of "self-
organization." For this reason, Romanticism discovers itself as if new
born in an empty space and called on to give itself its own meaning.
How that'ssupposed to happen becomes a question in terms of which
one can gather together diverse themes of Romantic literature.
For example, the call for a new mythology.26With a formulation
coined to describe postmodern architecture but entirely applicable to
Romanticism, one could say: "Whereas mythology was given to the
artist by tradition and by patron, in the postmodern world it is chosen
and invented."27That can happen in an entirely "sentimentalist"fash-
ion by drawing on antiquity and Christianity, through borrowings that
reflect on the fact that they form their observations from a different

21 On this see Peter Fuchs, ModerneKommunikation:Zur Theoriedes


operativenDisplace-
ments,Frankfurt 1993, p. 79ff.
22 For
example, for the Renaissance in the twin concepts unita/moltitudineor, distin-
guished from these, verisimile/meraviglioso. For a representative example, see Torquato
Tasso, Discorsidell'artepoeticae in particularesoprail poemaeroica(1587), in: Prose,Milano
1969, where (p. 366) it is stated that the poet should rely more on the one than the other
("o piu del verisimile o piu del mirabile") in order to produce "magior diletto." The
sphere of the "marvelous,"however, is limited by the fact that means have to be found
"peraccoppiare il meraviglioso co'l verisimile." (p. 367) Beyond this example, one could
of course recall such ancient cosmological distinctions as ordo/varietasor unitas/diversi-
tas.
23At the same time, biology reorients its inquiries from pre-given essential charac-
teristics to "irritability"as that characteristic which enables the evolution of living be-
ings. SeeJean-Baptiste Pierre Antoine de Monet de Lamarck, Philosophiezoologique,Paris
1809, reprint Weinheim 1960, esp. vol. I, p. 82ff.
24 Cf. Baxter Hathaway, Marvels and Commonplaces: RenaissanceLiteraryCriticism,New
York 1968.
25 Of course, that doesn't mean that art can indicate the one-way traffic on Fifth
Avenue incorrectly or claim that Carthage defeated Rome. In this, Tasso is still right
(Discorsi,p. 367), but today that'sno longer the problem.
26 For example, in the sense of the "alteste Systemprogramm des deutschen Idealis-
mus," here cited from G. W. F. Hegel, Werke, vol. I, Frankfurt 1971, pp. 234-36, or in the
sense of Friedrich Schlegel.
27 CharlesJencks, "Postmodern vs. Late-Modern," in Ingeborg Hoesterey, ed., Zeitgeist
in Babel:ThePostmodernistControversy, Bloomington 1991, pp. 9-21; here, p. 9.
514 NIKLAS LUHMANN

temporal position. In contradistinction to the Renaissance, the great


discovery of which was that there had once been perfection in this
world, the directive difference no longer lies in the distinction between
secular and theological descriptions, but in the temporal difference
between present and past.
Or-second example-the accentuation of writing as a form in
which absences (author or content) can appear as present.28 "Die
Schrift hat fur mich," Friedrich Schlegel confesses, "ich weiB nicht
welchen geheimen Zauber, vielleicht durch die Daimmerung von
Ewigkeit, welche sie umschwebt."29 In Ludwig Tieck's William Lovell,
the characters reveal themselves and their opinions only through writ-
ing. What's Romantic in this is not the presentational form of the epis-
tolary novel, but rather the fact that an image of "voruiberfliegenden
Geffihlen, die mit unserer Vernunft (nicht) in eins zu schmelzen
(sind),"30 is fixed in writing. And when that which has been suppos-
edly written down is published, the reader can dissolve the narrative
and accept as his/her own one of the possible points of view. Writing
evidently compensates for the displacement of an enduring present
with process, since it can be reused in the present, but also read dif-
ferently. It fixes itself, as it were, but not the reader.
And above all-third example-criticism (Kritik), conceived as the
ongoing labor in reflection on the never-complete artwork. Romanti-
cism, then, seeks forms with which it can respond to the necessity/
impossibility of transcending the limits of the imagination. The ex-
pressive devices on the literary plane that correspond to this are irony
and the fragment, in music the preference for the piano with its con-
text- and continuation-dependent tonal qualities. The unambiguous
distinctions are no longer sufficient, every frame of observation refers
to a further frame of observation, which it confirms by realizing itself
in it.31
Systemic autonomy, to which Romanticism in this way endeavors to
respond, is just what happened to the art system as a result of the func-
tional differentiation of society. One can no longer expect instruction

28 Here too the


parallel to postmodernism, in this case to Derrida, is astonishing.
29 "Uber
Philosophie," in Friedrich Schlegel, Werke,Berlin 1980, vol. II, pp. 101-29;
here, p. 104.
30 Ludwig Tieck, FriiheErzdhlungenund Romane,Munich 1963, p. 378.
31 In this
regard also the correspondences to postmodernism are not accidental. See
David Roberts, Art and Enlightenment:AestheticTheoryafterAdorno,Lincoln, Neb. 1991;
"Die Paradoxie der Form in der Literatur,"in Dirk Baecker, ed., ProblemederForm,Frank-
furt 1993, pp. 22-44.
M LN 515

from the religious system, the political or economic systems, nor from
the households of the most important families as to how artworks are
to be made. For this reason one could almost say: autonomy becomes
the destiny which is interpreted as a defence against external inter-
vention; or the invisible cage in which the artist is forced to select,
to be original and free. Romanticism thus views and deals with the
problem of autonomy on the level of the artwork and the creative free-
dom of the artist derived from it, but not on the social level of the func-
tional system of art; for only in this way can Romanticism define its po-
sition. The social system of art lets itself be represented through the
idea of art.
All that reads like a commentary on the self-generated "unresolv-
able indeterminacy" that is unavoidable as soon as one reintroduces
the difference between system and environment within the system it-
self. And just as in mathematics imaginary numbers or imaginary
spaces are required in order to absorb paradoxes,32 Romanticism con-
denses the imaginary to the fantastic, and thereby to forms that pre-
cisely do not mean what they show, but are nothing other than mate-
rialized irony.33 But that by no means implies that all forms dissolve,
that no distinction any longer holds, that everything becomes arbi-
trary.On the other hand, it does not suffice to postulate with Kant that
freedom is given for its rational use or that the genius must make a dis-
ciplined and cautious use of his geniality.34 Rather, the artwork re-
ceives the task of demonstrating its own contingency and being its own
program; and that makes very severe demands on both productive and
receptive observation, which therefore cannot happen 'just any way."
Self-generated indeterminacy does not by any means imply that no
meaningful operations, no determinations are possible; merely that
determinations must be recognizable as self-determinations and as
such observable. In other words, communication must be transferred
to the level of second-order observation.
Against this background the reason that the Romantics begin to play

32 See
Spencer Brown, Laws ofForm,p. 58ff, where a tunnel is introduced beneath the
surface on which the system performs its acceptable calculations. Cf. Dirk Baecker, "Im
Tunnel," in Dirk Baecker, ed., ProblemederForm,pp. 14-37.
33 On the further development of this tendency-with ever new outraged oppo-
nents-up to surrealism, see Bohrer, Die KritikderRomantik,p. 39ff.
34 This is, by the way,a longstanding, pre-romantic idea. One encounters it in the dis-
tinction libertas/licentiaof natural law theory or in the disegnodoctrine of the cinquecento
with its distinction between creative imagination and the skilled and practiced execu-
tion of a drawing.
516 NIKLAS LUHMANN

with "reality," doubling identities in the form of Doppelgdnger, twins, ex-


changed names, and mirror images, becomes intelligible: in order to
show that the same can also be otherwise and must be set into relation
with itself. Instead of the ontological guiding difference (Leitunter-
scheidung) between being and non-being-which on the side of being
congeals to substance so that in the reapplication of the distinction to
itself the side of being is confirmed-other guiding distinctions
appear, for example, the distinction finite/infinite (determinate/
indeterminate) or, alternatively, inside and outside.35 Ontological
metaphysics, which took only one possible primary distinction as its
point of departure, now had to be outtrumped by a meta-metaphysics,
which could take shape with the typically Kantian question regarding
conditions of possibility. The localization of reality with respect to the
distinction inside/outside was then as now a hardly solvable problem:36
"Ist das Reale auBer uns: so sind wir ewig geschieden davon; ist es in
uns: so sind wirs selber."37 However, because no adequate, sufficiently
rich, many-valued logic is available, the problem is displaced onto aes-
thetics. Translated into constructivist terminology, that means that the
decision as to what can be treated as reality and what not is made in-
ternal to the system. The reality test of "resistance" doesn't have to be
given up as a result, but it is no longer a matter of a resistance of the
environment to the system, rather of system operations to system op-
erations within the same system-above all the resistance of the self-
produced memory against new impulses or occurent ideas, or the re-
sistance of the already begun artwork or narrative against something
which can no longer be added to it. Viewed in this way, reality is noth-
ing more than the correlate of consistency tests within the system, and
this can occur in such a way that magic, ghosts, the supernatural, etc.
are introduced into a tale so as to acquire narrative plausibility, which
can then be revoked within the tale itself when, at the end, a perfectly
natural explanation for all the strangeness is provided.38 The figure of
the Doppelgdnger thus means nothing more than that in reality there is

35 On the plurality of such "primarydistinctions," see Philip G. Herbst, Alternativesto


Hierarchies,Leiden 1976, p. 88. Herbst's work is, by the way, quite probably the earliest
sociological response to Spencer Brown.
36 On the contemporary version of the problem, see N. Katherine Hayles, "Con-
strained Constructivism: Locating Scientific Inquiry in the Theater of Representation,"
in George Levine, ed., Realismand Representation: Essayson theProblemof Realismin Rela-
tion to Science,Literature,and Culture,Madison, Wisc. 1993, pp. 27-43.
37Jean Paul, VorschulederAsthetik,in Werke,vol. 5, Munich 1963, p. 7-514 (445).
38 This is a well-known narrative technique of Ludwig Tieck's, from WilliamLovellto
Das Zauberschlo/3.
M L N 517

no assymmetry of original and copy; rather, that this is a distinction art


alone requires for itself, an entry on the cost side in the balance of its
autonomy.
All this can be handled with the de-reification (Entding-
lichung) of the concept of world introduced already by Kant. World is
no longer a totality of things, an aggregatio corpororum,a universitas re-
rum, but rather the final, and therewith unobservable, condition of
possibility of observations, that is of every sort of use of distinctions.
To formulate this another way, the world must be invisiblized so that
observations become possible. For every observation requires a "blind
spot,"39 or more precisely: it can only indicate one side of the distinc-
tion being used, employing it as a starting point for subsequent ob-
servations, but not the distinction itself as a unity and above all not the
"unmarked space," precisely the world from which every distinction,
as soon as it is marked as a distinction, must be delimited.
This invisibilization of the nevertheless doubtlessly given and pre-
supposed world had dramatic consequences for Kant, Fichte, and
above all for the Romantics. It leads to an overburdening of the indi-
vidual with expectations regarding the production of meaning and
therewith to the collapse of the communication weighed down with
such expectations. The individual endowed with reflection now re-
ceives the title of "subject." But the higher and more complex the ex-
pectations that subjects direct toward themselves and their others, the
greater is the probablity of a failure of their communications. Texts ex-
emplary of this are Jean Paul's Siebenkds (the marriage scenes) and his
Flegeljahre.40 The forcing of subjectivity as the single answer to the
problem of world makes intersubjectivity difficult, indeed, if one is
conceptually rigorous, actually impossible. Today this necessarily leads
to the question whether the "human being," the "subject," or similar
collective singulars are a possible starting point for social theory at all.
The Romantics used them and couldn't give the matter a second
thought, for they had in any case no chance to develop an adequate
theory of society. For them this position was occupied by the concept
of "spirit" (Geist) and by the French Revolution.

39 On this
point, see Heinz von Foerster, "Das Gleichnis vom blinden Fleck," in Ger-
hard Johann Lischka, ed., Der entfesselteBlick: Symposium,Workshops, Ausstellung,Bern
1992, pp. 15-47.
40 See also
Ludwig Tieck, WilliamLovell,p. 603: "Esist ein Fluch, der auf der Sprache
des Menschen liegt, daB keiner den anderen verstehen kann." Cf. also p. 383 (Balder's
letter to William Lovell).
518 NIKLAS LUHMANN

Nearly contemporaneous with Romanticism a new sort of concept of


"culture"(Kultur) arises, offering itself as a serviceable "memory func-
tion" for modern society. One can see this with respect to the Roman-
tics, but also other "humanistic" (geisteswissenschaftlich) endeavors, in-
cluding religion (Schleiermacher) and philosophy (the late work of
Husserl). From the middle of the eighteenth century, the term "cul-
ture" is employed as an independent expression, that is: it is no longer
related to the care of something else as in "agriculture"or "cultura
animi" (Cicero). Formally, culture is distinguished from nature, but
that is merely an external delimitation and says nothing about the con-
tents that are seen as cultural and, as such, approved or disapproved.
Here too one must distinguish between themes and functions: the
themes of culture and its function with regard to the autopoiesis of a
highly complex societal system. The themes of culture are formulated
with reference to possible comparisons, in particular regional (at first
national) and historical comparisons. Historically, such comparisons
can in principle reach back indefinitely, as far as the "sources"that are
alwaysbeing discovered allow. With respect to content, cultures are re-
lated to ideas (Ideen)or values, for which an "apriori"validity,or at least
a fixed orientation, is presupposed well into the twentieth century. Fol-
lowing the schema laid down in the Kantian critiques or by some other
method, a plurality of validity types can then be posited, the unity of
which either remains unreflected or is described as a tragic conflict
(Weber) or as endless discourse (Habermas).41
Ideas, values, validity claims of all sorts emerge as correlates or, as it
were, as secretions of the comparative construction of culture. In this
way one endeavors to retransform contingency into necessity, with the
result, however, that contingency reappears in daily practice-be it as
the merely approximate realization of ideas, be it as the ever renewed
necessity of deciding in cases of value conflict. This problematic oc-
cupies the thematic horizon of modern society, but still doesn't show
wherein the persuasive force of the comparative method consists. It
seems to be rooted in the fact that extremely diverse states of affairs
can neverthelessbe compared, in the conspicuousness value of the
equality of the diverse, which is to say: in the successful solution of a
paradox. What is similar fascinates and, so to speak, proves itself by

41 One can
speculate that Kant's Kritikder Urteilskraftaimed at such an integration,
but failed to provide it.
MLN 519

virtue of the fact that it is found unexpectedly.


This is called "wit"(Witz)
and is found "interesting."42One can showthat the same is different
and that diverse things allow identities to be known so long as one di-
rects the comparison in terms of this cognitive interest. But why should one
do that? For the reason that it is a cognitive strategy that makes it pos-
sible to deal with extraordinarily complex, in the final analysis world-
societal states of affairs. The semantics of the society is keyed to its
structural complexity and one component of this is that talk of ideas
and values provides a surface description that prevents inquiry from
reaching the paradox of the equivalence of the different and thus
from developing modes of description sufficiently complex to grasp
the complexity of the society.
One could speak in this connection of a cultural symptomology.43
The themes of culture have a symptomatic function. They do not
merely mean themselves, but also something else; and that becomes
especially noticeable when they are formulated as unconditional, tran-
scendental, or absolute, and are introduced into the communicative
process with precisely this import. Thus there arises in the course of
the nineteenth century a second culture, a culture of suspicion that
raises the question of what is being disguised by the themes of culture.
I am referring, of course, to Marx, Nietzsche, Freud, and the sociology
of knowledge that follows in their path.
Poking around in allegedly latent structures is a way of searching out
hidden interests. The appropriate response to such searching is a tu
quoqueargument, namely the question as to the interest behind this in-
terest in latency. The suspicion of veiled motives becomes universal
and therefore trivial; it is then a matter of nothing other than a dou-
ble description of reality with first- and second-order observation.
The considerations set forth in the previous sections allow for a re-
formulation of the question as to the function of cultural themes. So-
ciety requires a memory function that allows it to accept the present
as the result of the past and as the starting point for subsequent oper-
ations. A memory, however, does not merely hold past events in re-
serve; it accomplishes above all a continuous discrimination of for-
getting and remembering. Most everything sinks away and very little
is so condensed and reconfirmed that it can be reused. This sortal

42 For the
subsequent development of this configuration, see Karl Heinz Bohrer,
Plotzlichkeit:ZumAugenblickdes dsthetischenScheins,Frankfurt 1981.
43 This is the formulation of Matei Calinescu, "From the One to the
Many: Pluralism
in Today's Thought," in Hoesterey, ed., PostmodernistControversy,pp. 156-74; here, 157.
520 NIKLAS LUHMANN

function serves the ongoing adaptation of the system to that which it


can construct as repetition. However, as a sortal function it must re-
main latent because otherwise it would also remember what is forgot-
ten. The memory must, to put the matter differently, accomplish a re-
entry of the difference between forgetting and remembering within
forgetting, and the form in which this occurs seems to be the con-
struction of themes-of identities and generalizations that can be
fixed in communicatively available designations.44 Themes, in other
words, make possible a forgetting of forgetting, and at the same time
the way in which themes are constructed serves the ongoing adapta-
tion of the system to itself, the continuing inscription of a consistent
"reality."
To return to Romanticism after this long digression: one can assume
that this systems-theoretical concept will contribute to a socio-histori-
cal understanding of Romanticism. With a peculiar preference for
transitional tones, for paradoxes, for the narratively produced believ-
ability of the unbelievable, for the cognition of what cannot be com-
municated, the Romantics cultivate a symptomology that avoids con-
gealing to theses, which could then be accepted or rejected. The
previously binding, early European tradition has to be forgotten in
order to free up new capacities, and then restaged in a timely form
(zeitgemdfl) with a nostalgia that reflects on itself. In Romantic poetry
and criticism ideas are evoked and simultaneously marked as un-
reachable.
The temporal conceptions of the Romantics also fit with this analy-
sis. Time is still presupposed as a movement in the old sense and there-
with related implicitly to the cognitive possibilities of conscious per-
ception. But the present is experienced as precarious, as a caesura, as
the "Differential der Funktion der Zukunft und Vergangenheit."45
The ambivalence in the evaluation of the French Revolution provides

44 "Themes"-the reference, of course, is to communicating and therefore social sys-


tems. For perceptual (psychic) systems one would have to speak of "objects."
45 Novalis, Werke, ed. Ewald Wasmuth, Heidelberg 1957, vol. I, p. 129 (fragment 417).
Cf. fragment 2225 (vol. II, p. 125): "Alle Erinnerung ist Gegenwart. Im reinen Element
wird alle Erinnerung uns wie notwendige Verdichtung erscheinen." Or Bliithenstaub109:
"Die gewohnliche Gegenwart verknupft Vergangenheit und Zukunft durch
Beschrankung. Es entsteht Kontiguitat, durch Erstarrung, Krystallisation. Es gibt aber
eine geistige Gegenwart, die beyde durch Aufl6sung identifiziert." Werke,Tagebiicherund
BriefeFriedrichvon Hardenbergs,ed. HansJoachim Mahl and Richard Samuel, Darmstadt
1978, vol. 2, p. 283. Cf. also Jean Paul, Titan, in Werke,
ed. Norbert Miller, Munich 1969,
vol. II, p. 478: "Nein, wir haben keine Gegenwart, die Vergangenheit muB ohne sie die
Zukunft gebaren."
MLN 521

a political illustration of the same tendency. And that seems to suffice


as a symptom of the insecurity of the Zeitgeist. One does not find the
way to an adequate theory of time although the idea of a three-phase
passage from the past through the present to the future has already
been refuted by the experience of the precarious character of the pres-
ent, by its de-ontologization.46 The present is valued precisely because
of its undecidablity (but wouldn't one then have to say: because of the
necessity of deciding?) and is projected onto the historical moment of
European society. The past loses itself in history. One can forget or re-
member it47; one has to prophesize it, as Friedrich Schlegel claims.48
And the future becomes the best guarantee for the fact that the world
is indescribable, and will remain so.
Despite this historicization and, if one can put it this way, rendering
precarious of temporal conceptuality, however, the Romantics do not
entirely succeed in detaching the concept of time from the premises
of ontological metaphysics. Their concept of the world is too strongly
oriented in terms of the human being for that. In contradistinction to
many animals,49 for humans a thing remains identical to itself when it
shifts from rest to movement. And that suggests an ontologically
nested concept of time, oriented in terms of the phenomenon of
movement, a concept that presupposes identities that bridge the dis-
tinction movement/non-movement and can sustain not merely move-
ment but also the change from non-movement to movement and vice
versa, that is, the "crossing" of this distinguishing limit. Even Heideg-
ger will still have difficulty with this. From the perspective of a radical
constructivist theory of observation, however, identity is not a time-
independent given, but merely an instrument for binding time when
it is a question of mediating past and future in the present.
Science, including systems theory, cannot afford such cultivated un-
decidabilities in the temporal, material, and social dimensions. It must
aim for refutable theses. That does not, however, exclude attempts to

46 On this
point, see Ingrid Oesterle, "Der 'Ffihrungswechsel der Zeithorizonte' in
der deutschen Literatur,"in Dirk Grathoff, ed., StudienzurAsthetikund Literaturgeschichte
derKunstperiode, Frankfurt 1985, pp. 11-75.
47 A concept of memory based in quantum physics that fits this state of affairs can be
found in Heinz von Foerster, "Wasist Gedachtnis, daB es Rufickschauund Vorschau er-
m6glicht?" in Wissenund Gewissen,pp. 299-336. See also by the same author, Das Geddcht-
nis (note 14).
48 Werke(n. 29), vol. I, p. 199.
49 For example, frogs. SeeJ. Y Lettvin, H. R. Maturana, W. S. McCulloch, and W. H.
Pitts, "Whatthe Frog's Eye Tells the Frog's Brain," Proceedingsof theInstituteof RadioEn-
gineers47 (1959), pp. 1940-59.
522 NIKLASLUHMANN

do justice to Romanticism in a theoretical redescription. The systems-


theoretical instruments of description break with the semantic reper-
toire in terms of which Romanticism sought to understand itself. For
the actual aim of this redescription is a theory of modern society for
which Romanticism can only have-but this in a most revealing way-
symptomatic value.
Universityof Bielefeld

You might also like