You are on page 1of 8

Galley: Article - 00192

Level 2
Philosophy of Science
Pete Mandik, William Paterson College, Wayne, New Jersey, USA
William Bechtel, Washington University in St Louis, St Louis, Missouri, USA

CONTENTS
The logical structure of science The sociohistorical structure of science
Challenges to Logical Positivism

Philosophy of science concerns the principles and laws of learning to characterize how various kinds
processes of scientific explanation, including both of experiences (e.g. reinforcement) would change
processes of confirmation and of discovery. the behaviour of organisms.
Laws, which are central to the D-N model, are 00192003
00192001 Philosophy of science is primarily concerned to taken to specify general relations (as in Newton's
provide accounts of the principles and processes law that force equals mass times acceleration ( f ˆ
of scientific explanation. Early in the twentieth cen- ma) ). To apply these general relations to particular
tury, philosophers of science focused on the logical events, one must specify conditions holding at a
structure of scientific thought, whereas in the later previous time, which are usually called initial con-
part of the century logic was de-emphasized in ditions. Recognizing that multiple laws and initial
favour of other frameworks for conceptualizing conditions may be involved in a given explanation,
scientific reasoning and explanation, and an em- such explanations can then be represented in the
phasis on historical and sociological factors that following canonical form (where L designates a
shape scientific thinking. While tracing through law, C an initial condition, and E the event to be
the landmarks of this history we note many points explained):
of contact between the philosophy of science and
L1, L2, L3, . . .
the cognitive sciences.
C1, C2, C3, . . .
Therefore E
THE LOGICAL STRUCTURE OF
SCIENCE Advocates of the D-N perspective generally as-
sumed that the Cs and Es were sentences whose
truth or falsity could be determined directly
The Deductive-Nomological Model of
through observation. These observation sentences
Explanation and Hypothetico-Deductive also provided the empirical support for the laws.
Model of Theory Development Most advocates of a logical analysis of science dis-
00192002 The appeal to logic to articulate the structure of avowed interest in scientific discovery, restricting
scientific explanation and scientific reasoning was their focus to justification. Their characterization of
the hallmark of the Logical Positivists, a group of the relationship between observations and laws
early twentieth-century philosophers and scien- make it clear why they saw little hope for a logic
tists, working initially in Eastern Europe, who of discovery. (More recently, artificial intelligence
sought to provide an explication of science that (AI) researchers and philosophers sympathetic to
could explain its high epistemic status. They AI have proposed discovery tools to employ within
offered a model of explanation, the Deductive- this framework: Langley et al., 1987; Thagard, 1988;
Nomological (D-N) model, which holds that ex- Darden, 1991.) The challenge in discovery is to
plaining a phenomenon involves deducing its construct new laws to account for more or new
occurrence from laws (Hempel, 1966). Something phenomena. Since laws are to be general, not spe-
like this view is thousands of years old and may be cific, they must go beyond any finite set of data,
discerned in the work of Aristotle. The D-N model and thus there inevitably seems to be a major
was extremely influential in some areas of psych- inductive leap to a new hypothesis. Once a hypoth-
ology earlier in the twentieth century. Many behav- esis was put forward, the process of testing could
iourists, for example, sought to discover general begin by deducing its observational consequences
Galley: Article - 00192
2 Philosophy of Science

in accord with the D-N model. This process of general statement, deductively entails not just the
hypothesizing general laws and testing their de- particular observation statements it was advanced
duced consequences was termed the Hypothetico- to explain, but an indefinite number of others. The
Deductive model of theory development. theory is confirmed by demonstrating the truth of
00192004 Hempel (1966) illustrates H-D with the example some of these additional observation statements.
of Semmelweis' work during the 1840s on childbed
fever. Semmelweis observed cases of `puerperal
fever' or `childbed fever' contracted by women
Intertheoretic Reduction
who delivered children in his hospital. He noted Recognizing that one might want to explain why 00192007

that cases were especially frequent in groups of laws held, the proponents also generalized this
women where deliveries were handled by phys- framework, allowing for the derivation of one or
icians instead of midwives. Semmelweis' key in- more sets of laws (each comprising a theory) from
sight into the cause of childbed fever came when another set of laws (comprising another theory).
he observed that a physician came down with The second set of laws will be more general ones
similar symptoms upon injuring himself with an from which, under specific boundary conditions,
instrument during an autopsy. Semmelweis hy- the first set of laws might be derived. (Thus, the
pothesized that `cadaveric material' on the injuri- boundary conditions replace the initial conditions
ous instrument caused the disease, and that, in the above formalism.) Proponents also suggested
similarly, the physicians associated with outbreaks that this approach might be extended to relations
of childbed fever had cadaveric material on their between laws in one science and those of a
hands prior to delivering babies. Semmelweis more basic science by providing bridge laws relat-
tested this hypothesis by examining its implica- ing the vocabularies of the two sciences (by trans-
tions. One implication of the hypothesis that cada- lating the terms of one into the terms of another),
veric material is the cause of childbed fever is that giving rise to the following schema:
its removal from the hands of physicians would
Laws of the lower-level science
result in a decrease in cases of childbed fever.
Bridge laws
When Semmelweis tested this implication by re-
Boundary conditions
quiring that physicians wash their hands in chlor-
inated lime prior to examining patients (which he Laws of the higher-level science
assumed would remove the cadaveric matter), he These derivations are known as reductions; they
observed that groups of women examined by phys- figure prominently in discussions about the rela-
icians who washed with chlorinated lime had tion between psychology and neuroscience in
lower incidents of childbed fever than groups of which some theorists propose that the theories of
women examined by physicians who did not. psychology ought to reduce to those of neurosci-
00192005 The example of Semmelweis' hypothesis and test ence (Churchland, 1986). Analogously, reductions
conforms to the H-D model in the following way. are posited, or at least hoped for, for any two adja-
Semmelweis' observations could be formulated as cent levels, such as from biology to chemistry and
a series of observation statements, statements of from chemistry to physics.
particular states of affairs such as `Jane Doe was One example of a successful reduction that con- 00192008
exposed to cadaveric material and contracted child- forms to the above account is the derivation of the
bed fever', `Mary Smith was exposed to cadaveric Boyle±Charles Law of classical thermodynamics
material and contracted childbed fever', and so on. (specifications of the temperature and pressure re-
His hypothesis took the form of a law-like general lations in an ideal gas) from statistical mechanics.
statement, `Any woman exposed to cadaveric ma- Boyle±Charles Law terms such as temperature and
terial will contract childbed fever'. And, in accord- pressure are translated into the terms of statistical
ance with D-N, the original observation statements measures of the kinetic properties of molecules in a
may be deductively inferred from the statement of volume. Equating temperature with mean kinetic
law. Thus the relation of observation statements to energy supplies one of the bridge laws enabling
statements of law has a reciprocal structure as translations of the laws of Boyle±Charles into the
depicted by H-D and D-N. (See Figure 1.) laws of statistical mechanics. Boundary conditions
00192006 If the only support for a hypothesis were the include specifications of the kinds of molecules, the
observation sentences it was intended to explain, volume to which their motion is restricted, and the
the reciprocal relationship between proposing hy- range of temperatures and pressures they are sub-
potheses and explanation would be circular. Circu- ject to. With translations of terms and boundary
larity is avoided, though, since a law, being a
Galley: Article - 00192
Philosophy of Science 3

conditions in place, the Boyle±Charles Law is de- applicable to many domains in the life sciences. A
rivable from the laws of statistical mechanics. major reason is that explanation does not tend to
00192009 Just as laws gain their empirical support from the involve showing that a phenomenon follows a law
true observation sentences that are derived from (Cartwright, 1983; Giere, 1999). Instead, explan-
them, so reducing laws gain their support from ation often involves identifying and describing the
the already confirmed laws that can be derived mechanism that generates the phenomenon (Wim-
from them. Reduction, though, can also provide satt, 1972; Machamer et al., 2000). A key component
justification for reduced laws. Insofar as the redu- to the idea of mechanism is that of a set of processes
cing laws are more general, confirmation they re- that generate a phenomenon, with these processes
ceive in some domains can provide indirect being performed by different parts of a system.
support for other laws that can be derived from Thus, an explanation consists of functionally de-
them. composing the process of producing the phenom-
enon into a set of different component processes
and localizing these component processes in actual
CHALLENGES TO LOGICAL physical parts of a system (Bechtel and Richardson,
POSITIVISM 1993). (Often actually identifying the component
physically is not possible, and researchers settle
Popper's Critique of Confirmation for indirect evidence that such a component exists.)
00192010 By making predictions which turn out true, the For example, to explain basic physiological pro-
Logical Positivists thought we could justify laws. cesses such as cellular respiration, biochemists
On this claim, however, they were criticized by had to identify a set of activities (oxidation of sub-
Karl Popper (Popper, 1935/1959), who noted that strates, electron transfer, and phosphorylation of
such arguments had the invalid form of affirming ADP) and determine the components of the cell
the consequence: responsible for them (enzymes, cofactors, and
membranes with restricted permeability).
If L were true, then prediction P would be true An emphasis on mechanisms does not eliminate 00192012
P is true appeal to laws ± sometimes key relations between
L is true parts of a system (e.g. between a substrate and an
This formalism is invalid since it is possible for enzyme) are expressed in laws. But laws play a
both premises to be true, but the conclusion false. subsidiary role. The emphasis is on differentiating
Instead, Popper argued that the only way evidence the operations performed in the system, linking
could bear upon laws was through the use of modus them with physical parts of the system, and then
tollens arguments in which failed predictions could showing how the component parts and processes
be used to falsify a purported law: interact with each other to produce the phenom-
enon. Some of the individual interactions can be
If L were true, then prediction P would be true stated in laws, but the specification of the particular
P is false components involved and the intricacy of their
L is false interactions is generally far too specific to render
into laws. Quite often such explanations are pre-
Accordingly, Popper emphasized that the method
sented in diagrams (these are especially useful
of science was a method of conjectures and refuta-
when the component processes are organized non-
tions in which scientists proposed explanatory laws
linearly with multiple interactions and feedback
and then sought evidence showing that they were
loops), not linguistically (although diagrams are
false. If a proposed law resisted all attempts at
typically accompanied by linguistic commentary).
falsification, Popper would speak of it as corrobor-
Many of the endeavours of the cognitive sciences 00192013
ated, not as true or confirmed, recognizing that
can be interpreted as advancing mechanisms.
future evidence could always reveal it to be false.
Grammars, for example, are often presented as
mechanisms for generating sentences. Psycholin-
Mechanisms instead of Laws guists who investigate the psychological reality of
particular grammars are investigating whether
00192011 Although the D-N model seems to apply well to a
they are actually implemented in language users.
number of scientific domains, especially in physics
Researchers in AI, especially those creating pro-
(for example, to explanations of phenomena that
grams to account for human performance, are de-
appeal to the laws describing ideal gases or prin-
composing an activity into component operations.
ciples of thermodynamics), it does not seem
Implementing the program on a computer
Galley: Article - 00192
4 Philosophy of Science

provides an existence proof that the hypothesized more purely behavioural research, moreover, such
set of operations is sufficient to generate the phe- studies can not only serve to confirm a cognitive
nomenon in question. Behavioural experiments decomposition, but also play a heuristic role in
using such tools as reaction times and error analy- determining the functional decomposition itself
sis are required to demonstrate that the processes (Bechtel et al., 2000).
actually figure in human information processing. Such connections between cognition and neuro- 00192016

00192014 When the explanatory vehicle is assumed to be a science are commonly construed as reductionistic.
description of a mechanism, scientific inquiry is not But since one is not starting with laws at the cogni-
restricted to producing data to be subsumed under tive level, and deriving them from laws of neuro-
a hypothesis or to being used in testing a prediction science, such research does not fit the theory
derived from a hypothesis. Early in the process of reduction model (above). Rather, relating a func-
inquiry, researchers are simply trying to figure out tional decomposition to a structural localization
what are the processes that contribute to a particu- provides an alternative conception of reduction,
lar effect. One strategy is to show that processes are one much closer to Darden and Maull's (1977) con-
actually separable in the system by showing that ception of an interfield theory. Such an account
one process can be impaired while the other is may be much closer to actual scientific practice.
retained, or that an experimental manipulation Moreover, it does not raise the spectre of either
produces a crossover interaction between measures explaining away the higher-level approach (with a
of the two processes. When these manipulations successful reduction) or eliminating it (if reduction
are performed after a mechanism has been pro- fails). Rather, it weaves the two approaches closely
posed, they serve the more traditional role of together; functional decomposition and structural
testing the proposed explanation. In such ways, localization are contributors to the common inquiry
empirical inquiry contributes both to discovery of of understanding the mechanism. Each can provide
models of mechanism and to testing them. not only support for the other, but heuristic
guidance to the other, and the resulting explana-
tory account is an integrated one.
Alternative Conceptions of Reduction
There is a further way in which reduction 00192017

00192015 The application of the model of mechanistic ex- emerges in the context of a mechanistic model of
planation in the previous paragraphs focused on explanation. Once a system has been decomposed
the traditional disciplines of cognitive science: cog- into component functions and these localized
nitive psychology, linguistics, and AI. But a very within the system, a new explanatory task arises ±
natural place to employ this framework is to rela- explaining how each component function is per-
tions between more traditional cognitive explan- formed. Developing this explanation requires
ations and neuroscientific ones. Although interest repeating the process: decomposing the component
in the neural realization of cognitive mechanisms process into its component processes, and localiz-
did not play a critical role in cognitive science until ing these within the subsystem where the process
recently, this was largely due to the paucity of from the first decomposition was localized. Recog-
techniques that could link cognitive and neural nizing that this can be done successively, the model
investigations (Bechtel et al., 1998). But the emer- of mechanistic explanation provides a framework
gence of cognitive neuroscience as a major area of for reduction through multiple levels (Wimsatt,
scientific collaboration in the 1990s reveals that 1976). There is an important point to recognize
cognitive and neural modes of investigation can about this multilevel conception of reduction ± at
be invoked together. Indeed, neuroimaging experi- each level, a different phenomenon is being ex-
ments, whether with positron emission tomo- plained. Moreover, at each level, the explanation
graphy (PET), functional magnetic resonance involves not only the contributing components, but
imaging (fMRI), magnetoencephalography (MEG), the interactions that are specified in the account at
or (ERP), require use of cognitive tasks and meas- that level. A process such as seeing is reductively
ures along with measures of neural activity. In explained in terms of the contributions of the dif-
terms of the model of mechanistic explanation, ferent components of the visual system and their
what these tools are providing is localization of interactions, while it is the activity of a given com-
the functions decomposed in a cognitive analysis ponent which is explained by going into it and
of the task (e.g. by showing where various atten- identifying its subcomponents and their inter-
tional processes are realized in the brain). Like action.
Galley: Article - 00192
Philosophy of Science 5

THE SOCIOHISTORICAL STRUCTURE Normal science, then, just is paradigm-based sci- 00192020

OF SCIENCE ence. Immature science is science studying a


domain recognizably the same as that studied by
Paradigms and Revolutions paradigm-based successors, but without the util-
ization of any paradigms, as in the cases of optics
00192018 While the Logical Positivists were themselves very prior to Newton and of electrical research in the
interested in the science of their time, their account first half of the eighteenth century (pp. 12±14). A
was grounded primarily in logic, not in the details stage of crisis emerges for a science when the
of scientific practice. (A consequence of this is that requisite consensus regarding the applicability of
they viewed it as a normative model characterizing a paradigm begins to unravel. Patterns of problem-
any possible science.) Kuhn's work drew philoso- solving in normal science give way to novel ap-
pher's attention (as well as that of historians and proaches, and where new consensus emerges, a
sociologists of science) to the specific details of the stage of resolution of a new paradigm returns the
process of scientific research. Kuhn (1996) chal- cycle to normal science.
lenged the views that science employed a set of One of Kuhn's views that garners much attention 00192021
general methods that remained constant over time in the philosophy of science is his claim that differ-
and accumulated a body of truths. In their stead, ent paradigms are incommensurable and thus
Kuhn suggested that scientific approaches vary so choice of one over another cannot be subject to
significantly at different eras of a discipline that the rational procedures. One way of thinking of incom-
findings and theories at one time cannot be mean- mensurability of paradigms is by thinking of para-
ingfully related to the findings and theories of other digms as involving different languages, the terms
times. Instead of viewing the historical progression of which cannot be translated into each other. For
of science as the progressive accumulation of example, the term `space' as used within a Newton-
truths, Kuhn offered a cyclic model of the stages ian physical paradigm cannot be translated as the
of scientific activity through history. The cycle term `space' as used within an Einsteinian physical
involves the five stages of (1) immature science, paradigm, and vice versa. Einsteinians differ from
(2) normal mature science, (3) crisis science, (4) Newtonians in holding that space is curved by
revolutionary science, and (5) resolutions, which mass, for example. The meaning of `space' depends
is followed by a return to normal science (see on the theory it is embedded in; where theories
Figure 2). diverge, so do the meaning of their terms. Part of
00192019 The key notion in understanding Kuhnian phil- Kuhn's argument that paradigms are not open to
osophy of science is the notion of a paradigm. The rational choice hinges on the notion that observa-
five stages of the Kuhnian cycle may be unpacked tion statements cannot serve as neutral points of
in terms of this notion, since normal science is arbitration since there is no theory-neutral observa-
paradigm-based science, and four of the stages are tion language. In other words, observation is
understood by way of contrast with normal sci- theory-laden: how one perceives the world
ence. For Kuhn, paradigms are `Universally recog- depends on the theory with which one conceives
nized scientific achievements that for a time the world. For instance, a newborn baby, if shown a
provide model problems and solutions to a com- cathode-ray tube, would not see it as a cathode-ray
munity of practitioners' (1996, p. x). Further, para- tube because the baby would understand an insuf-
digms serve for a time implicitly to define the ficient amount of theory to know what cathode-ray
legitimate problems and methods of a research tubes are.
field for succeeding generations of practitioners. Kuhn's thesis that paradigms are incommensur- 00192022
They do so in virtue of two essential characteristics able leads to another of his theses, namely, that the
(p. 10): first, `Their achievement was sufficiently history of a scientific discipline is noncumulative.
unprecedented to attract an enduring group of ad- Noncumulativity follows from incommensurabil-
herents away from competing modes of scientific ity in the following way. Since the language of
activity.' Second, their achievement `was suffi- one paradigm cannot be translated into the lan-
ciently open-ended to leave all sorts of problems guage of another, the statements held to be true
for the redefined group of practitioners to resolve'. within one paradigm cannot be expressed, let
Examples of paradigms include Ptolemaic astron- alone judged to be true, within another. The
omy, Copernican astronomy, Aristotelian dynam- theory-ladenness of perception guarantees that
ics, Newtonian dynamics, corpuscular optics, and not only can items of theory not be accumulated
wave optics. across paradigms, but neither can observations.
Since not even observations are retained from one
Galley: Article - 00192
6 Philosophy of Science

paradigm to the next, the history of a discipline Nonetheless, no consensus has emerged in contem-
cannot be viewed as the accumulation of truths or porary philosophy of science that is on a par with
as progressing towards a truer account of the the status once accorded the Positivists. For cogni-
world. This challenges the traditional view of sci- tive scientists, one of the attractive features of cur-
ence as an intellectual that progresses over time. rent philosophy of science is the increasing effort to
The history of science, as viewed through the Kuh- employ ideas from cognitive science in the attempt
nian lens, is of a series of paradigms and revolu- to understand science (Giere, 1992; Thagard, 1998).
tions, none bearing any rational relation to any
other.
References
Challenges to Kuhn Bechtel W, Abrahamsen A and Graham G (1998) The life
of cognitive science. In: Bechtel W and Graham G (eds)
00192023 Kuhn's hypothesis of incommensurability has been
A Companion to Cognitive Science, pp. 1±104. Oxford, UK:
challenged on several fronts. One denies that the Blackwell.
meanings of theoretical terms are determined Bechtel W, Mandik P and Mundale J (2000) Philosophy
wholly by factors internal to a paradigm, but meets the neurosciences. In: Bechtel W, Mandik P,
holds instead that they may be determined, at Mundale J and Stufflebeam RS (eds) Philosophy and the
least in part, by causal relations between the term Neurosciences: A Reader. Oxford, UK: Blackwell.
and items in the external world. Putnam (1975) Bechtel W and Richardson RC (1993) Discovering
suggests that the meaning of certain scientific Complexity: Decomposition and Localization as Scientific
terms involves causal relations between the terms Research Strategies. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
and things in the world that they denote. For in- Press.
Cartwright N (1983) How the Laws of Physics Lie. Oxford,
stance, part of the meaning of water is the sub-
UK: Clarendon Press.
stance H2O that was present when the term
Churchland PS (1986) Neurophilosophy. Cambridge, MA:
`water' was first brought into use to denote that MIT Press.
substance. A causal chain leads from current uses Darden L (1991) Theory Change in Science: Strategies from
of `water' to the initial dubbing of H2O as water. Mendelian Genetics. Oxford, UK: Oxford University
These causal chains remain constant regardless of a Press.
scientist's theory. Thus, water discourse need not Darden L and Maull N (1977) Interfield theories.
be incommensurable between adherents of diver- Philosophy of Science 43: 44±64.
gent theories about water. Appealing to causal re- Fodor J (1984) Observation reconsidered. Philosophy of
lations to fix the content of representations is Science 51: 23±43.
mirrored in much cognitive scientific practice, es- Giere R (1992) Cognitive Models of Science. Minneapolis,
MN: University of Minnesota Press.
pecially in the cognitive neurosciences where
Giere R (1999) Science without Laws. Chicago: University
representations are thought of as carrying informa-
of Chicago Press.
tion about their environmental causes. Hempel CG (1966) Philosophy of Natural Science.
00192024 Another challenge to Kuhnian incommensurabil- Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
ity arises from theorists who propose that the mind Howson C and Urbach P (1993) Scientific Reasoning: The
is modular. Fodor (1984), for example, argues that Bayesian Approach. La Salle, IL: Open Court.
many perceptual processes are modular in the Kuhn TS (1996) The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 3rd
sense of being `informationally encapsulated' so edn. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
that their outputs are immune from influence by Lakatos I (1970) Falsification and the methodology of
theoretical and other acquired beliefs. Fodor, there- scientific research programmes. In: Lakatos I and
fore, contends that observational reports can be Musgrave A (eds) Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge.
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press
treated as univocal even when theorists hold differ-
Langley PS, Simon HA, Bradshaw GL and Zytkow JM
ent theories.
(1987) Scientific Discovery: Computational Explorations of
00192025 Though many of the issues raised by Kuhn con- the Creative Process. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
tinue to be debated, the Kuhnian spirit is a perva- Laudan L (1977) Science and Relativism. Berkeley, CA:
sive force in post-Positivist philosophy of science. It University of California Press.
has, for example, led philosophers to focus much Machamer P, Darden L and Craver CF (2000) Thinking
more on the diachronic nature of science as well as about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science 67: 1±25.
the actual research processes of science (see, for Mayo D (1996) Error and the Growth of Experimental
example, Lakatos, 1970; Laudan, 1977) or to apply Knowledge. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Bayes Theorem to model rational theory choice Popper K (1935/1959) The Logic of Discovery. London:
(Howson and Urbach, 1993; Mayo, 1996). Hutchinson.
Galley: Article - 00192
Philosophy of Science 7

Putnam H (1975) The Meaning of `Meaning'. In: Mind, Further Reading


Language, and Reality: Philosophical Papers of Hilary Bechtel W (1988) Philosophy of Science. Hillsdale, NJ:
Putnam. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Lawrence Erlbaum.
Thagard P (1988) Computational Philosophy of Science. Glymour CN (1980) Theory and Evidence. Princeton, NJ:
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Princeton University Press.
Wimsatt WC (1972) Complexity and organization. In: Hacking I (1983) Representing and Intervening. Cambridge,
Schaffner KF and Cohen RS (eds) PSA 1972, pp. 67±86. UK: Cambridge University Press.
Dordrecht: Reidel.
Laudan L (1990) Science and Relativism: Some Key
Wimsatt WC (1976) Reduction, levels of organization, Controversies in the Philosophy of Science. Chicago:
and the mind±body problem. In: Globus G, Maxwell G University of Chicago Press.
and Savodnik I (eds) Consciousness and the Brain: A Simon HS (1996) The Sciences of the Artificial, 3rd edn.
Scientific and Philosophical Inquiry. New York: Plenum Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Press. Thagard P (1992) Conceptual Revolutions. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press.

Keywords: (Check)
Explanation; mechanism; reduction; theory change; scientific discovery

INDUCTIVE SUPPORT

OBSERVATION STATEMENT
STATEMENTS OF LAW

DEDUCTIVE ENTAILMENT

00192f001 Figure 1. The reciprocal relationship between hypothe-


sizing laws from observations and deriving observations
from laws

IMMATURE NORMAL CRISIS REVOLUTION RESOLUTION


SCIENCE SCIENCE

00192f002 Figure 2. The stages in Kuhn's account of scientific change


ECSaq192
Queries for Macmillan, ECS paper no. 192

Title: Philosophy of Science


Author: Bechtel

Can you supply a small glossary defining complex terms for the layperson?

Displayed syllogisms (e.g. L1 etc., C1 etc., Therefore E): in each case, the conclusion
(e.g. Therefore E) is preceded by a box - is this correct? Should it in fact be the
symbol “therefore” (three dots), and was incorrectly rendered in the computer print-
out?

Section “Mechanisms instead of Laws”, 1st para: we’ll need to give ADP in full.

Section “Alternative Conceptions of Reduction”: similarly, we’ll need PET, fMRI,


MEG, ERP in full: are the first three “positron emission tomography”, (functional)
magnetic resonance imaging, and magnetoencephalography? (I just can’t remember
what ERP is, I’m afraid . . .)

Section “Paradigms and Revolutions”, end of last para: “traditional view of science as
an intellectual [? word missing ?] that progresses over time” - ?

End of main text: no reference is given for Thagard 1998.

Giere 1992 ref: is the place of publication Minneapolis, MN?

Wimsatt 1972 ref: what is PSA (title)? Proceedings of - ?

You might also like