You are on page 1of 9

Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 43 (2012) 284-292

jind Philosophy
Contents lists available at SciVerse ScienceDirect

Studies in History and Philosophy of Science


j o u r n a l h o m e p a g e : www.elsevier.com/locate/shpsa

Two literary encyclopaedias from Late Antiquity *


Paula Olmos
Instituto de Estudios Clásicos ‘Lucio Anneo Séneca', Universidad Carlos III de Madrid, Spain

A R T I C L E A B S T R A C
I N F O T
Article history: This paper aims to offer a new perspective on two fifth-century texts: Martianus Capella’s De nuptiis Phil-
Available online 9 January 2012
ologiae et Mercurii and Macrobius’ Saturnalia. Both were transmitted and received throughout the Middle
Ages as methodical sources containing an account of the ancient sciences and disciplines, and highly criticised
Keywords: in modern times for their supposedly poor level of scientific knowledge. Setting aside the recent focus on the
Encyclopaedia Late Neoplatonic ascription of some of their content, I claim that these texts still contribute to a traditional
Antiquity educational ideal. They put forward a kind of amateur, dilettantish encyclopaedic lore as the appropriate
Macrobius
'further education’ for young Latin men of the higher class that would allow them to acquire material for
Martianus Capella
excellence in discourse within the framework of a basically rhetorical education. With their literary
Rhetoric
Roman education
sophistication and informal approach, they also illustrate the means of acquiring this broader knowledge in
a non-professional way, by individual reading/listening and excerpting, as something distinct from the
formal schooling available in grammar and rhetoric. Such an approach could help us to avoid the still rather
widespread and sometimes undeservedly excessive criticism of the level of their 'science’ and, especially,
blaming this dubious characteristic on the prejudiced assumption of the decline of science in the 'obscure
times’ of Late Antiquity.
© 2011 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.

When citing this paper, please use the full journal title Studies in History and Philosophy of Science

been somewhat rehabilitated by modern criticism, at least in some Plato, particularly the Timaeus).2 Macrobius’
respects. The works of these two authors have many things in common1
2 although they are rather different in their final format and presentation.

In fact, they shared a common fate during the Middle Ages as maître-
livres, i.e. books that were used as intermediate sources that could make
other purportedly worthier ones more understandable (e.g. the works of

* It was just after finishing this paper that I had access to two, most recently published, works that will surely be of considerable importance for future Macrobian scholarship, namely:
R. A. Raster's new edition and translation of the Saturnalia in the Loeb Collection (3 vols., 2011) and A. Cameron's comprehensive study of the social and intellectual context of its
composition in his monumental The Last Pagans of Rome (2011), both of which show a rather similar approach to the figure of Macrobius and to the interpretation of his works. Even
though I've been able to add these works to the reference list and insert a few footnotes highlighting points of contact with their stances, it was impossible for me, at such a stage in the
edition process, to go over the whole paper again. In any case, even if at some point I may seem to abide with some of the traditional assumptions they so effectively attack (e.g.
Macrobius' paganism), these are in no way essential for my arguments, being even explicitly minimized as keys for Macrobius' interpretation. On the contrary, I would say that my
reading of Macrobius is fairly compatible with the general approach offered in these two works, which has likewise so much in common with the spirit of L. Cracco Ruggini's studies
on Late Antiquity, extensively used in this paper.
E-mail address: polmos@inst.uc3m.es
1 Although there is still some debate about the identity and chronological position of these two authors, the most widely accepted hypotheses place both of them in the first half of
the 5th century and their works as follows: Macrobius' Saturnalia and Commentarii in Somnium Scipionis, Rome, 430-440 AD; Martianus Capella's De nuptiis Philologiae et Mercurii,
Carthage, 410-439 AD. Capella is widely believed to have been born and resident in Carthage and he made his living, according to his own testimony, as an advocate. Macrobius,
probably also of African (or Hispanic) origin, lived and wrote in Rome and became part of the senatorial elite, his family being connected with the Symmachi.
2 Cf. Barkhouche, 1997, p. 17. In his edition of Macrobius' Commentarii, L. Scarpa ([ed.], 1981, p. 50) also talks about this combined reception of a group of Late Antique texts, including
the works of Calcidius and Boethius together with those of Macrobius and Martianus Capella within the context of the medieval interest in Platonism.

0039-3681/$ - see front matter © 2011 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.
doi:10.1016/j.shpsa.2011.12.018

1 Introduction Martianus Capella. Traditionally undervalued as mere compilers of an


Recent studies have showed a renewed interest in the intriguing allegedly already degraded scientific legacy and choice victims of the
works of encyclopaedic authors of Late Antiquity such as Macrobius or excesses of Quellenforschung, they have both
P. Olmos / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 43 (2012) 284-292 285

Commentaries on the Dream of Scipio is actually a work that could easily be technical interest) of these authors’ scientific knowledge—an attitude
framed within the tradition of Platonic interpretation, via Cicero. But the that dominated traditional accounts of Capella’s work by authors such as
way in which Martianus Capella’s only extant work, the allegorical Stahl, Johnson, and Burge (1971)7 and is also found in so recent an editor
narrative in nine books On the Marriage of Philology and Mercury (Ramelli as B. Ferré ([ed.], 2007)—is beginning to give way in the face of careful
[ed.], 2001) (in which the seven liberal arts expound their doctrines), or study of many intriguing passages (Schievenin, 2009; Suárez Martínez,
Macrobius’ other major work,3 the convivial dialogue called Saturnalia 2006).8 It should not, in any case, act as an anachronistic hindrance to the
(Marinone [ed.], 1967; Raster [ed.], 2011) (in which twelve guests discuss understanding of Martianus’ or Macrobius’ true intentions and interests.
various erudite issues), would contribute to such an endeavour is not at Although we are dealing here with very complex and multilay-
all clear. ered 9 —and at least in the case of the Saturnalia, fragmentary—works,
However, among the most significant interpretations of Capella’s there is really no reason but our own surprise at their particular literary
contribution is the recent assessment by Guillaumin (2007), Guillaumin choices (highly conspicuous writing strategies, which include myth,
(2008), based on Hadot’s theory of a late, specifically Neoplatonic fixing fiction and their paraphernalia, self-irony and even grotesque and
of the cycle of the seven liberal arts (Hadot, 1984, 2nd ed. 2005),4 i.e. the humorous standpoints) 10 not to take their common reference to their
seven personified disciplines featured in the Marriage. Moreover, the educational aims and cultural agenda seriously. Both the Saturnalia and
mythical allegory within which Mar- tianus offers his closed cycle of the Marriage were dedicated to their respective authors’ sons—Martianus
disciplines has also been meticulously described as related to (Jr.) and Plotinus Eustathius. These would be receiving from their own
mysteriosophical rituals (Lenaz, [ed.], 1975) and connected with a fathers a ready-made compilation of established lore for their personal
Neoplatonic sensibility through the doctrines of lamblichus and the Bildung. In Macrobius’ own words in the ‘Prooemium’ to the Saturnalia:
Chaldean Oracles. This allegory—i.e. the myth of Philology selected as a [s]o that all that I have worked out from different volumes [written]
bride for Mercury and ascending to immortality through divine science, in either Greek or the Roman language, since you have been in this
with the help of the seven disci- plines/maidens, the marriage gift world and even before you were born, all this may be for you like a
offered by Mercury—is particularly developed in his first and second trousseau of knowledge, a kind of storeroom of writings, so that
books, although it is present throughout the whole work. when you need to remember either the stories that are buried in a
In the case of Macrobius’ Saturnalia, some emphasis has also been put heap of books, hidden from regular people, or memorable sayings or
on its allegedly Neoplatonic lineage5 (Neri & Ramelli, [eds.], 2007, p. 124). deeds, may it be easy for you to find and extract them.11
Here, however, l am not so much interested in the presence of these
Martianus’ son, for his part, appears as an interlocutor both at the
philosophical and theosophical references (taking into account,
beginning and the end of the Marriage in programmatic sections that
moreover, that the different trends of the various schools of
reveal, according to L. Crisante, ‘l’impegno didascalico-peda- gogico di
Neoplatonism to a certain extent pervade most of the literary production
Marziano’ (Crisante, [ed.], 1987, p. 19). However, as Hadot’s (1984)
of Late Antiquity), as l am in taking a serious look at these works as
corrections to Marrou’s (1948) probably too naive account of ancient
honest attempts to compile, expound and transmit a certain store of
education show, there is a certain lack of connection between such
knowledge for educational and cultural purposes.
endeavours as Martianus’ and Macrobius’ ency- clopaedism and any
lt has been acknowledged, even by the most conspicuous supporters
properly recorded institutionalized educational practice. Hadot
of Martianus’ Neoplatonic ascription, that unlike Augustine, who in his
mentions, for example, the variety of sources used by Martianus as
De musica—and allegedly in his De grammatica— adapted and interpreted
evidence of the innovative nature of his endeavour and the lack of similar
the precise content of these two disciplines to better serve the
textbooks intended for such an educational syllabus (1984, p. 155).
Neoplatonic purpose of the ‘return of the soul’, Martianus does not
However, Martianus’ subtle homage to Varro as a presiding fig-
undertake such an endeavour. He instead offers a much more traditional
ure—albeit probably not so much as a source in the proper sense
and standard account of the arts, based on a wide variety of sources.3 4 5 6
(Schiavenin, 2009, pp. 31-45)—or Macrobius’ close imitation of Au- lus
Furthermore, the conventional suspicion of the soundness (and thus,
Gellius’ Noctes Atticae12 could testify to their being conscious of working

3 We have only a third extant, but very fragmentary, work by Macrobius, pure science, which they vulgarized with a superficial and presumptuous encyclopaedic
which is believed to be prior to the two major ones (420-425 AD), a grammatical essay erudition destitute of creativity)’ (p. 192).
called De verborum Graeci etLatini differentiis vel societatibus. In addition, the relative 8 ln his brief article, Suarez Martinez clarifies a confusing paragraph regarding
chronology of the Commentarii and the Saturnalia is still controversial (Cf. Navarro Antolin, certain topological characteristics of the number three mentioned by Capella, previously
[ed.], 2010, pp. 7-9). deemed faulty or incomprehensible. For his part, Schievenin, in his collection of essays on
4 The first source for such a cycle would have been Augustine’s De ordine, supposedly Martianus Capella, resolves a number of traditional misreadings and reveals the overall
based on the suggestions made by Porphyry in his De regressu animae. Hadot’s ‘late accuracy (relative to the knowledge of the times) of his views and reported theories on,
fixation’ theory partially conflicts with Marrou’s (1971 [1948], 1969) account of a long- for example, Eratosthenes’ measurement of the Earth’s circumference (pp. 75-88) or the
running but gradual and coherent evolution of encyclopaedic concerns, from the climatic characteristics of the lands of the antipodes (pp. 89-109).
purportedly old Greek education in the liberal arts to the medieval cycles. 9 Cracco Ruggini describes Late-Antiquity’s ‘endless proliferation, intersecting and

5 This is said to be particularly present in the solar theology expounded in Sat. stratification of different traditions and mentalities’ (1997, p. 193).
117-23 where, for example, Plotinus (l 17, 3) and Porphyry (l 17, 70) are mentioned. The 10 Humour is present throughout Martianus’ Marriage and Macrobius’
solar theology is expounded by one of the most respected figures in the dialogue, Vettius Saturnalia. ln the first case, Satire, the inspiring muse, is responsible for many humorous
Agorius Praetextatus, who starts his redefinition and reinterpretation of the characters passages, although her explicit presence and involvement is not always necessary. The
and roles of the Olympic gods with the following assertion: ‘That most gods, at least those presentation of Dialectic in Book lV (§328-334) is, for example, particularly ridiculous. ln
placed under supreme heaven, are related to the Sun, is not an estimation born out of vain the case of the Saturnalia, there is a long section dedicated to jokes and humorous dicta
superstition, but of divine reason’ (‘Nam quod omnes paene deos, dumtaxat qui sub caelo (Sat. ll 1-ll 7) and Evangelus, the uninvited guest, is also responsible for some politically
sunt, ad solem referunt, non vana superstitio sed ratio divina commendat’, Sat. 117, 2). An incorrect remarks that, while denoting his own negative characteristics, give some nice
extensive commentary on the possible alternative interpretations of this fragment is to be variation to the tone of the dialogue.
found in Cameron (2011, pp. 264-268). 11 ‘et quidquid mihi vel te jam in lucem edito vel antequam nasceris, in diversis
6 ln Hadot’s own words: 'Si l’arrière-plan de l’allégorie elle-même (livres l et Graecae seu Romanae linguae voluminibus elaboratum est, id totum sit tibi scientia
ll) et de l’introduction des sept disciplines au début des livres lV, V, Vl, Vll, Vlll et lX est supellex, et quasi de quodam litterarum peno, siquando usus venerit aut historiae quae in
essentiellement néoplatonicien, le contenu des disciplines ne s’y rapporte librorum strue latens clam vulgo est, aut dicti factive memorabilis reminiscendi, facile id
qu’occasionnellement’ (Hadot, 1984, pp. 155). tibi inventu atque depromptu sit’, Proo. 2. The verbs invenire and depromere, which we
7 Stahl’s pioneering yet also rather prejudiced work on Late Antiquity science have translated as ‘find’ and ‘extract’, belong to the rhetorical vocabulary of invention, the
was criticized by L. Cracco Ruggini in her programmatic 1997 paper, ‘From Fourth to Sixth oratorical task of excogitating and selecting material (particularly arguments) for a
Century: A No-Man’s Land in the History of Sciences’. Referring to Stahl’s Roman Science discourse.
(1962), she says: ‘however, the author proceeds from premises which are highly debatable 12 Cf. among other cross-references: Sat. Proo. 2-3/NA, Proo. 2-3; Sat. 111,41-

and which today may be regarded as obsolete (for example the Romans were incapable of 44/NAII18; Sat. II2,15-17/NA XIX11,1-4; Sat. II 8,4-9/NA XV 2,3-8. For a
286 P. Olmos/Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 43 (2012) 284-292

within a certain tradition, favouring a specific kind of cultural ideal or education. We will look at some aspects of this tradition in the following
agenda. However, this agenda could more easily be linked to the section.
continuous further education of cultivated young adults than to any kind
of formal schooling. This is probably the main reason these works, even
though they make use of sources of this kind for their technical details, 2. Classical education: grammar and rhetoric
look like anything but textbooks (regardless of their use as such in the
Flamant (1977, p. 253) summarized the classical education of Roman
very different context of medieval monastic schools). This is also
young men as follows: ‘Sortant de la classe du grammaticus, le jeune
probably one of the reasons each of them is so unique and so different in
Romain entrait dans la classe du rhetor; il n’en sortait d’ailleurs jamais...
genre and literary choice, both being two particular samples, diverse and
’. The last remark is not to be taken literally, however, but refers to the
disconnected, of individual approaches to amateur and non-professional
rhetorical standards that dominated the continuous evaluation of young
reading/listening and excerpting, a kind of cultural practice or task
men who were active in Roman social life and its discursive practices. It
which was nowhere formally established. In my opinion, their stunning
is widely acknowledged that formal education (with the effective
literary sophistication would thus be both due to and part of their educa-
presence of professional teachers) was in most cases limited to the two
tional informality and amateur cultural ideal.
areas of grammar and rhetoric, and provided complete training in these
In what follows, I will explore various aspects of the significance of
discursive skills. This curriculum was meant to prepare young elite
these two works as samples of an informal proposal for the cultural
Romans to act as agents, or alternatively, as an attentive and expert
enhancement of elite adults within the context of the fifth- century Latin
audience, for any discourse, particularly public, legal, and political
world. This was a world in which different cultural trends, Christian and
discourse. Other fields of knowledge such as specialized philosophy
pagan, competed for ascendancy, even during the most peaceful periods
(physical, metaphysical or ethical) or the mathematical and descriptive
of coexistence. My stance in no way disputes the presence of Neoplatonic
sciences and arts, were deemed a suitable undertaking for a more
topics or the possibility of ascribing a philosophical/religious faith to
restricted group of particularly interested pupils.21 And although many
both authors, but it does not seem so clear that the concrete aim of these
decided to pursue such subjects, attending certain schools and joining the
two works was such a particularized proselytism. 13 The educational
circle of specific masters, knowledge of such areas was not particularly
proposal they present is, in both cases, fairly wide-ranging and could
required for public office or to take part in the social life of the senatorial
serve high society in general, as well as addressing a composite audience
elite, at least in principle.
of pagan (both classical and orientalizing pagans) and Christian elites.14
But of course the arts of discourse are meta-linguistic in nature, and
On the other hand, Macrobius and Martianus were most probably both
discourse itself must be about something. Concerns about the quality
pagan15 and favoured traditional Classical lore and erudition, probably
(epistemic and ethical) of the content of discourse had pervaded and
in a context of relative defeat for their position.16 It is also clear that they
complicated discussions about the very essence of such arts as grammar
objected to certain Christian attitudes, 17 but they do not write in an
and rhetoric from the very beginning. If it were supposed that someone
openly anti-Christian frame of mind. Whether this be self-censorship,18
like Plato had opposed the sophistic masters of words he confronted
fearful prudence or smart disguise 19 is another question. Beyond the
because they were not interested in attaining truth, any sensible response
alleged winks to their coreligionists, in the later all-Christian context, the
to such a stance would need, from then on, to combine two elements: (a)
cultural/educational proposal they offered could be and was easily
the conscious assumption of the meta-discursive character of the art
accepted and preserved as something valuable.20
involved (usually identified with rhetoric), which is in principle
Finally, it should also be taken into account that, although situated in
indifferent to certain aspects of the content (or may at least have room for
their own contexts, these works issue from a long tradition: the
certain strategies and devices that are indifferent to the epistemic status
Ciceronian ideal of a cultivated Roman youth whose excellence in public
of the contents), and consequently, (b) the requirement for the speaker to
office would be supported by an in-depth philosophical (and scientific)

contemporary approach to Aulus Gellius, see Keulen (2009). 19 Schievenin (2009, pp. 1-17) finds traces of Martianus’ use of Lucretius and

13 In Cameron’s wording, either pagans or Christians, these authors wouldn’t Porphyry in his Prologue and interprets these references as subtle indications of a
count among the ‘committed’ or ‘rigorist’ ones (Cameron, 2011, pp. 206-230). general pagan cultural framework that would easily be noticed by attentive readers:
Marinone ([ed.], 1967), Italian editor and translator of the Saturnalia, while ‘La omogeneita di proemio e intermezzo rende chiari gli elementi del prologo del De
considering Macrobius a pagan, already talked about this lack of commitment: ‘Nel nuptiis: presenza di autori incompatibili con la cultura cristiana; contrasto dell’autore
nostro scrittore la fede religiosa e cosi poco combattiva, direi quasi cositepida, che con la cultura dominante (cristiana, mai nominata), ma sopratutto rivendicazione e
trova spiegazione soltanto in un deliberato silenzio nei confront! degli avversari.’ funzione del sapere della tradizione classica. A questo punto il De nuptiis puo
(1967: 24). procedere: gli elementi proemiali attesi sono suficienti per il lettore attento.’
14 Against excessively dichotomous views of Late Antiquity religious Schievenin thus assumes a certain anti-Christian stance in Martianus, which is
confrontations, L. Scarpa, in his own edition of Macrobius’ Commentarii (1981, p. nevertheless subsumed under a more general and relevant argument in favour of the
26), states: ‘C’era invece un largo spazio di indagine e di dibattito non knowledge pertaining to traditional lore.
necessariamente polarizzato nell’antitesi tra Cristianesimo e paganesimo.’ 20 According to Cracco Ruggini (1985, pp. 298-299): ‘the tradition of ancient culture

15 Both Kaster and Cameron assume, though, that the most sensible hypothesis, actually did survive thanks to this gradual detachment from the mores, in which all
taking in account his dates and high office, is that Macrobius was, after all, a its values were shifted to grammar. This facilitated its Christianization and allowed
Christian, as were, by then, the descendants of the personages taking part in his the great aristocratic libraries of the fourth and fifth centuries to be transformed into
Saturnalia dialogues. ecclesiastical and monastic libraries.’ A. Cameron’s conclusive words also relate to
16 See L. Cracco Cracco Ruggini (1985, p. 298): ‘Macrobius wrote at a time when this long-term endurance of ancient Classical culture: ‘This is one area in which
the pliant self-confidence which many proceres of Symmachus’ generation had still paganism (defined as the Roman tradition, Rome’s glorious past) continued to
manifested with regard to their social and cultural status was beginning to weaken.’ exercise real power and influence on men’s minds. Despite the best attempts of
17 See, for example, Martianus complaining about the prohibitions regarding the Augustine and other rigorists, the Roman literary tradition played a vital and
divination arts in Book IX (§898), where he states that they have been ‘indecently continuing role in shaping the thought-world of Christians, both at the time and in
chased from Earth’ (‘terris indecenter expulsas’), a fragment mentioned by Shanzer centuries to come’ (2011: 801).
(1986, p. 21) as evidence of the anti-Christian polemic supposedly contained in the 21 The reasons for such individual interest could be many indeed, ranging from the

work. Macrobius is conspicuously silent regarding Christianity, but in the Saturnalia, intellectual disposition of some particularly gifted elite youngsters to the educational
his character Evangelus, the bad character of the dialogue, garrulous, uninvited and needs of people who would be employed all around the Empire in the many
ignorant (although not always wrong), has been interpreted as a Christian professions that made use of mathematical knowledge. See especially Cuomo (2000,
stereotype, particularly because of his name. Ramelli, for example, favours this Ch. 1): ‘Land-surveyors, architects, mechanicians, ‘technicians’ of various sorts were
interpretation (Neri & Ramelli, 2007, p. 7 ff), although it is rather contested by other all pretty visible in the scenario of late antiquity’ (p. 16). Incidentally, Cuomo’s
scholars (Flamant, 1977; Scarpa, [ed.], 1981) and has been finally rejected by both contextual study reveals the inadequacy of Hadot’s restrictive view of mathematics
Kaster ([ed.], 2011) and Cameron (2011). as a field almost exclusively concerned with philosophical (Platonist) propaedeutics
18 Or ‘Roman etiquette’, in Stewart’s words, according to Stahl ([ed.], 1952, p. 8). (Hadot, 1984, Ch. 2, pp. 25 ff).
P. Olmos / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 43 (2012) 284-292 287

find his ‘good’ content elsewhere, and so the need for the praiseworthy The relationship between all of these traditional concerns and our fifth-
orator of, at least, a general-purpose broad education in other fields of century authors is, of course, not straightforward. What we do have to
knowledge.22 take into account is that both of them refer, in some way, if not to such
In Quintilian (¡nst. Orat. 2.17) we find what is probably one of the remote instances, at least to a traditionally understood idealized situation
bravest statements regarding (a): a courageous and indeed rather lucid which they try to reconstruct. In Macrobius’ case, this is very obvious, as
recognition of the indifference of the art of rhetoric towards pure he situates his dialogue more or less a generation before his own
epistemic goals: (following Ciceronian models). According to what we know of the real
I admit that in rhetorical discourse sometimes false things are persons portrayed as characters in the Saturnalia (especially the three
presented as true, but I do not concede that, for that reason, rhetoric main ones, Quintus Aurelius Symma- chus, Vettius Agorius Praetextatus
itself is based on false opinions, because it is a very different thing to and Nicomachus Flavianus), the dramatic date of the dialogue could be
have a certain viewpoint oneself than to make others embrace it.23 placed around 382-383. Around this period and due, in part, to the extant
works and testimonies of these same people, historians have traditionally
But Quintilian himself must have accordingly favoured education in a
identified a certain ‘pagan/classical renaissance’ as taking place. Today
broader sense, 24 following the Isocratean 25 ideal of a general political
the status of this as a genuine historical fact is somewhat contested, but
Bildung: one based on rhetoric, but including a wider cultural training.
it is more or less portrayed as such by Macrobius.29 In the Saturnalia, these
However, it is Cicero who makes his viewpoint about aspect (b) most
three erudite aristocrats share their wisdom with other characters in the
clear in his rhetorical works—the orator’s need for positive knowl-
dialogue, including professional specialists (all foreigners: the
edge/erudition and thus the demand for further extra-rhetorical
philosopher Eustathius, the rhetorician Eusebius and the doctor Disarius,
education:
who were Greeks, and the Cynic boxer Horus, an Egyptian), lesser and
some younger but equally erudite Romans (the brothers Rufius and
It is my opinion that no-one can be a praiseworthy orator if he has Caecina Albinus, the young grammarian Servius and Avie- nus) and a
not attained knowledge of all the great issues and arts: because it is twelfth rather intriguing character (Evangelus), the self-invited banquet
necessary that discourse should flourish from and be full of the spoiler, a bad-mannered and poorly educated aristocrat who acts as a
recognition of realities for, if these are not well known and contrasting and ironic figure. 30 Based in part on Macro- bius’ images,
understood by the orator, his words [his elocution] will be useless Cracco Ruggini has talked about the way these kinds of aristocrats and
and mostly childish. De oratore, I 20.26 other people belonging to their circle (particularly the ‘usually Greek’
Let him be not only instructed in dialectical skills, but also familiar professional ‘scholars’ admitted to it) 31 employed their leisure time
with all the subjects indicated and treated by philosophy. Orator, (otium) in the kind of erudite and cultural activities which were ideally
XXXIII 118.27 socially connected with their civic positions
This Ciceronian ideal of the perfect orator (and, thus, the perfect elite (negotia).32
Roman citizen) as someone well versed in almost everything remained In the case of Martianus, his choice of a non-realistic scenario— the
an important stereotype alternatively embodied or referred to by mythical assembly of the Gods in heaven to celebrate the marriage of
different authors. However, it did not, to our knowledge, give rise to any Philology and Mercury—makes this kind of reference much more
institutional programme in response. Cicero himself offers testimony to difficult. However, there is a significant, albeit rather ironic, allusion to
a certain resistance to such a thing even within his own circle. Thus, in the ignorance of his own times, in contrast to a putative past.33 Moreover,
the dialogue De oratore, for example, he has the character of Antonius Schievenin has also worked on a particularly difficult section of the
reply to such proposals of a broad education, which he deems excessively Prologue (§1-2). The proposed interpretation, connected with certain
ambitious, with the following remark: Egyptian rituals, implies that the work as such would be intended for the
let him [the orator] restrict himself to those issues useful in the forum ‘awakening’ of a certain cultural renaissance.34 On the other hand, what
and civil life and leave aside other disciplines, important and is clear in Martianus is not so much the way this kind of broad erudition
clarifying as they might be, and urge him to pursue this single task, should be put to use in social gatherings (Macrobius’ chosen scenario),
night and day, as they say.28 but the way it should be acquired in maturity and outside the context of
formal schooling, by dedicating some leisure time (paradigmatically, ‘the

22 The dual perspective on discourse as good in a rhetorical sense (persuasive, (conceited, scornful and more inclined to social and tricky discursive success than true
well-argued, well presented, well pronounced) and good because of its proper content is knowledge), he is not always wrong. In Sat. I 7,12, he quotes Varro’s Menippean Satires and
also behind the tension found in traditional associations such as Hippias’ polymathia or Praetextatus accepts his quotation; in Sat. II 2,10, he makes his contribution to the
Gorgias’ claim to be able to talk about ‘every possible issue’ (Gorgias 448a, De Oratore discussion on funny dicta and immediately afterwards (Sat. II 2,12) his opinion on Servius’
III129). These feats could alternatively be interpreted as genuine, and thus a desirable goal, modesty is deemed somewhat impertinent but mostly right; in Sat. III10-11, it is his
or as evidence of the sophists’ blameworthy epistemic indifference. protestations that help develop the dialogue, etc.
23 ‘ego rhetoricen nonnunquam dicere falsa pro veris confitebor, sed non ideo in falsa 31 Kaster (1980), Kaster (1988) comments on the very relative acceptance and recognition
quoque esse opinione concedam, quia longe diversum est, ipsi quid videri et, ut alii (within certain limits) of these professional sages and teachers in the context of aristocratic
videatur, efficere’. dilettantism.
24 Cf.: ¡nst. Orat. 1.10, especially regarding music, geometry and astronomy; 32 See L. Cracco Ruggini (1986): ‘Alle attivita culturali l’aristocrazia senatoria si

10.1, about readings in history and philosophy; 12.2-4, about education in practical dedicava allora soprattutto nei periodi di otia che si alternavano ai negotia, vale a dire
philosophy, civil law, customs, exempla. all’esercizio di funzioni e di cariche pubbliche’ (p. 98); ‘II tipo di otium che Simmaco
25 Cf. J.-Y. Guillaumin (2003, [ed.], p. XLVIII). sembra auspicare e preferire e pertanto quello litteratum, che nulla ha a che vedere
26 ‘Ac mea quidem sententia nemo poterit esse omni laude cumulatus orator, con la iners desuetudo da ogni impegno che offusca l’intelligenza come acqua fangosa,
nisi erit omnium rerum magnarum atque artium scientiam consecutus: etenim ex rerum con gli otia muta che isolano dal contatto sociale e politico, con la quies piacevole ma
cognitione efflorescat et redundet oportet oratio. Quae, nisi res est ab oratore percepta et inoperosa e quindi virtuti infructuosa’ (p. 99). Cameron examines as well this idea of
cognita, inanem quandam habet elocutionem et paene puerilem.’ the learned activities of the elite (2011, Ch.10. ‘The real circle of Symmachus’: 353-
27 ‘Nec vero dialecticis modo sit instructus sed habeat omnis philosophiae notos et 398) finally finding a high degree of idealism in Macrobius’ view and the supposedly
tractatos locos.’ See, also, Orator III12-13, IV 14-16 and most especially XXXI112-XL 139. historical accounts based on his portrait.
28 ‘is autem concludatur in ea, quae sunt in usu civitatum vulgari ac forensi, 33 ‘Felicis, inquit, sed Capellae flamine, indocta rabidum quem videre saecula’
remotisque ceteris studiis, quamvis ea sint ampla atque praeclara, in hoc uno opere, ut (§999). L. Crisante (1987, pp. 19ff.) comments on this final section of Capella’s work
ita dicam, noctes et dies urgeatur’, De oratore, I 260. in which the author confronts his muse Satire, the personified genre which he is
29 Cracco Ruggini (1986, pp. 97-98). Cameron’s book (2011) is mainly devoted to allegedly using and in which he is also innovating.
rejecting the historical authenticity of such a neat, jointly pagan, anti-Christian, Classical 34 ‘in Marziano la similitudine tra l’inno proemiale della sua opera e quello del rito
and learned renaissance. di risveglio della divinita diventa metafora di quel risveglio culturale che egli conta
30 Although he is, in general terms, a negative character with morally corrupt attitudes di perseguire con il progetto di una grande opera’ (Schievenin, 2009, p. 24).
288 P. Olmos/Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 43 (2012) 284-292

languishing eves of winter’)35 either to doing the kind of job he did—i.e. to address a situation of uncertainty (§6, §8, §21-22) or persuasion as
compiling basic wisdom and information about every field of knowledge depending on a variety of factors (§25), for example—betrays a very
from erudite and well-informed old established books—or, alternatively, specific interest in and familiarity with rhetorical themes that has so far
to taking advantage of his own efforts and reading his book. If his been fairly neglected by the critics. Martianus’ profession as a lawyer in
encyclopaedic Marriage is the result of what a certain muse (Satire, in this Carthage has been mentioned as the source of his familiarity with legal
case) kept telling him for some time about the adequate use of leisure vocabulary (Stahl et al., 1971, pp. 19-20) and the generally well-informed
time for his own learning, it may easily become the best instrument for nature of the book dedicated to Rhetoric (Book V) has been duly
the learning of others—as Scheherazade’s tales kept the sultan emphasized.41 But, apart from older works by Hinks (1935) and Fisher
entertained for many nights, they likewise become the source of our own (1936) on its sources and its separate edition as part of Halm’s collection
entertainment, night after night. of Latin rhetorical texts (1863), the specific content of Martianus’ Book V
However, it should not be assumed that Martianus’ interest in has not received much attention.42
learning is less ‘socially oriented’ (less pragmatic) than that of Macrobius, There we find a particular paragraph, supposedly containing an
who offers us so vivid an image of erudite conversation and learning ‘in informal list of the parts (or officia) of Rhetoric, which is particularly
use’ (meaning discursive use). He has chosen a format in which the significant for our point. Although at the appropriate stage of Rhetoric’s
positive exposition of learned matters is clearly more systematic than in didactic discourse (§442), we find five parts of the art explicitly
Macrobius’ Saturnalia—the particular issues and themes addressed are mentioned, the five traditional ones, in the traditional order (inven- tio,
also different and somewhat more ‘scientific’. However, there are many dispositio, elocutio, memoria and pronuntiatio), previously there is a kind of
clues throughout the work to the context of interpersonal communication informal presentation of rhetoric’s acknowledged officia in paragraph
in which such lore matters. We know from his own testimony (§577, 428:
§999) that Martianus worked as an advocate in Carthage and his it was really worthwhile, even for the gods, to listen to such an
rhetorical background can be glimpsed in many passages. By way of ingenious choice of arguments [invention], such rich and eloquent
example, let us turn to two successive poetical sections: the conclusion of expression [elocution], such capable memory and treasure of
Book II (§219-220) and the beginning of Book III (§221-222).36 In the first, recollections; such an order in disposition, such nice modula-
the author announces the start of the technical portion of his work (the tion in pronunciation and the gestures in motion, such deep
exposition of the disciplines: ‘Now that the myth is over, the books begin conceptions!43 44 45
that expound the following arts’, 37 §220.1-2) after the more narrative Bovey (2003, chap. 5) has commented on this paragraph, emphasizing the
section had concluded (‘Now that the main part of the fable is past’,38 peculiar mention of that final ‘deep conceptions’ (‘profund- itas in
§219.1) in the holding of the divine assembly into which the seven conceptu’), which, unlike the rest of the discursive characteristics
maidens will subsequently make their entrances. In the second, the mentioned, is not related to any previously recognized rhetorical officium.
author starts a playful dispute/dialogue with a secondary muse, She concludes, rather convincingly, that it cannot be identified with
Camena, regarding the proper way of expounding the arts, either as Augustine’s or Sulpicius Victor’s intellec- tio,44 which is conceived as a
‘naked truths’ or dressed in a fictional/literary discourse. 39 These two preliminary duty of the orator, undertaking the analysis and
consecutive sections of the work reveal to us an author who is highly characterization of the particular case or issue at stake. Martianus himself
conscious of the subtle difficulties of a language which supposedly moreover states, at the above-mentioned §442, that other authors allow
expresses truthful knowledge, but also aims to make such knowledge for a sixth part of rhetoric which they call iudicatio, but he explicitly rejects
comprehensible, visible, teachable and even, hopefully, amusing. There this ‘judgement’ as a separable part because it should preside over every
is a methodological concern here with the proper exposition and duty (‘partibus cunctis adscribitur’), being best understood as the
transmission of artistic and technical lore. However, the solution offered orator’s capacity to discriminate in every aspect of discourse. As Bovey
is still rather paradoxical. There will be poetic ornament in it, represented concludes, it does not seem very promising either to identify the pro-
by muse Camena’s attribute (a bejewelled booklet, §221.1), but also, funditas of §428 with such iudicatio.
purportedly, technical accuracy. Meanwhile, an all-pervading satirical There is not much we can say, however, about Martianus’ addition
genius will now and then continue to make fun of some aspects of the in technical terms, as there is no connected subsequent technical
disciplines themselves.40 development in the work. In fact, it does not seem to be an explicitly
This attitude could be characterized as extremely literary and technical addition or correction. It may be just the opposite: a way of
rhetorical, revealing a skilled analyst of the characteristics of human expressing Martianus’ concern with the failure of the technical precepts
discourse, someone interested in how linguistic representation operates of Rhetoric to ensure good speech, mentioning, albeit in an informal way,
and how human communication (as something distinct from the sage’s the need to be ‘profound’ in terms of content. Such a concern envisages
or philosopher’s solitary attainment of truth) works. His taste for the kind of wide-ranging intelligence, erudition and communicative
dialectical and yet playful disputes like the one represented by his capacity socially acknowledged as belonging to renowned orators or
dialogue with Camena and other particular passages—those in Book I sophists beyond their implementation of the skills acquired in rhetorical
regarding the nature of deliberation and consultation as the proper way school. There would be no easy precepts attached to such a requirement.

35 ‘hiemali pervigilio marcescentes’ (§2). facundae ubertatis eloquium, tam capacis memoriae recordationisque thesaurum;
36 Martianus’ work is written in a mixed prose and poetry style, becoming a qualis dísponendí ordo, quam pronuntiandi congruens modulatio, qui gestus in motu,
comprehensive example of prosimetrum. quae profunditas in conceptu!'
37 ‘Nunc ergo mythos terminatur; infiunt/artes libelli qui sequentes asserent.’ 44 Bovey just mentions Augustine in her discussion, but in his Institutiones Oratoriae, the
38 ‘Transcursa, lector, parte magna fabulae.’ 4th-century rhetorician Sulpicius Victor also acknowledged such intellectio as one of the
39 ‘the arts are dressed. Or would you rather send the flock of sisters nude to join orator's duties (Lopetegui, Muñoz García, & Redondo, 2007, p. 180, n. 13). Augustine and
the heavenly senate and thus plead to the Thunderer?’ (‘et vestiantur Artes. An tu Sulpicius Victor follow an alternative tradition, enumerating just three parts of rhetoric:
gregem sororum nudum dabis iugandis, et sic petent Tonantis, et caelitum intellectio, inventio and iudicatio (Halm, 1863). In Marius Victorinus' Explanationum in
senatum?’ §222. 9-13). rhetoricam M. Tullii Ciceronis libri duo, a recognized source of Capella's work, we can also
40 ‘and [the books] will illustrate serious disciplines for the most part without read about such discrepancies between the number of parts of rhetoric: ‘Alii enim partes
hindering pleasure’ (‘et disciplinas annotabunt sobrias/pro parte multa nec septem, multi quattuor, sed plerique quinque esse dixerunt. Eorum et sententiam Cicero
vetabunt ludicra’, §220.4-5). secutus quinque partes esse confirmat' (Lopetegui et al., 2007, pp. 270, 478).
41 Johnson (Stahl et al., 1971) mentions the fact that it is the book with the widest 45 Macrobius mentions Cicero's dialogues (Sat. 11, 4) and particularly Plato's
variety of sources. Symposium (Sat. 11, 3) in his Prologue, but the tradition of the symposium genre had
42 Olmos (2011) is an attempt to overcome this situation. grown and expanded considerably since Plato, with both Greek and Latin authors. See
43 ‘audire operae pretium etiam superis fuit tantae inventionis ingenium, tam Navarro Antolín (2010, pp. 14-22).
P. Olmos / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 43 (2012) 284-292 289

Such a profunditas could come instead from a thorough education in the also involved. The extant 52 content of the discussions included in
recognized arts and sciences and would represent the traditional Macrobius’ Saturnalia can be summarized thus:
aspiration of the masters of rhetoric to ensure that their pupils were Eve of the 1st day: origins of the Saturnalia festivities; ways of dividing
capable of speaking properly and reasonably on any issue, ideally in a the day, according to legal, religious and literary sources;
well-informed way. Such aspiration to encyclo- paedism driven by
discursive and rhetorical concerns is precisely the interpretative key I am
seeking to explore here.

3. Compiling as systematizing: literary unity as unification of


knowledge

In the previous section, I have tried to provide evidence for what I


think is one common aim behind such encyclopaedic endeavours as
those undertaken by Martianus and Macrobius (with all their
differences): to offer a broad and accurate, yet somehow informal, store
of knowledge suitable for the cultural enhancement of citizens (young
and mature men) who would be taking part in public social life through
discursive practices. Now
I will focus on the very different literary strategies selected by the two to
serve this goal.
In both cases, a literary form that takes us away from the classroom
context is chosen. Macrobius’ erudite dialogue, following the Ciceronian
tradition, but also taking after the more concrete genre of the symposia,45
provides a dramatic setting in which literary and philosophical issues
seem to emerge within polite society in a rather spontaneous way. It is
not so spontaneous in the text, however, because the plot has been
planned twice over. The author begins his plan with the ‘Prooemium’,
speaking about his own method for creating a unified work based on the
many sources he would be using, as bees make their honey from different
flowers:
We should imitate the bees in their ways, that wander about and pick
flowers and then sort what they have gathered and divide it into
honeycomb’s cells, and from a varied juice they make a mix of a single
flavour, changing the properties of their fragrance.46
He then makes his own literary ambition explicit: ‘I would like my work
to be like this: there are many disciplines in it, many precepts and
examples 47 from many periods, but composed into a single whole.’ 48
Such unity is attained by means of the dramatic setting itself, the choice
of characters, the justification given to the gathering and the literary logic
of the plot. Yet in any case, the author feels it should be justified on
another level and the characters themselves make a second plan for their
own meeting explicit, mentioning, once and again, their interest in
conducting a culturally enhancing dialogue: ‘May we have here literate
enjoyment and erudite musing.’ 49 Moreover, before the three-day
banquet begins, there is a previous gathering on the eve of the festival at
which an erudite issue is already discussed (the origins of the Saturnalia
festivities), initiated by the assertion made by Rufius Albinus that
‘nothing could be more agreeable for either us [Rufius, Praetextatus and
Avienus] and these other gentlemen [the newly arrived Symmachus,
Caecina and Servi- us] to talk about than learned issues’,50 after which
they decide to ‘arrange’ the main meetings, mentioning the proposed
guests and their suitability for such an aim.
The issues ultimately discussed throughout the work are varied,
although knowledge about traditions and religious rituals as contained
in the literary works of the Latin writers, especially Virgil, is central. As
will be mentioned later, the specific domain of the grammarian’s
concerns makes up the backbone of Macrobius’ interests in this work.51
But as the following outline reveals, many other fields of knowledge are

46 ‘Apes enim quodam modo debemus imitari, quae vagantur et flores carpunt, 48 ‘Tale hoc praesens opus volo: multae in illo artes, multa praecepta sint, multarum
deinde quicquid attulere disponunt ac per favos dividunt, et sucum varium in unum aetatum exempla, sed in unum conspirata' (Sat. Proo. 10).
saporem mixtura quadam et proprietate spiritus sui mutant' (Sat. Proo. 5). 49 ‘Haec nobis sit litterata laetitia et docta cavillatio', Sat. II1, 8.

47 This distinction between technical, theoretical precepts and historically situated case 50 ‘nec enim ulla alia de re quam doctis quaestionibus colloqui aut nobis aut his potest

studies (exempla) relates to the distinction between knowledge/study/discussion of esse iucundius', Sat. I 2,17.
general principles vs. particularities, a divide always present in rhetorical discussions 51 See Kaster, 1980.

about the themes (quaestiones) involved in discourse (either general thesis or particular 52 There are various lacunae throughout the work.

hypothesis).
290 P. Olmos/Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 43 (2012) 284-292

justification of the use of archaic expressions; praise of the philosopher for Mercury in Book I, shows certain initial resistance to being divinized
Eustathius, to be present the next day, for his familiarity with the three and undergoing the rites of purification and ascent to the heavens that is
schools of philosophy (Academic, Stoic, Peripatetic). not exactly justified by the possible difficulties and pains involved in
Morning of the 1st day: origins and anecdotes regarding various such a process (presented in §134-143). Before all of that comes, she
official garments (especially the praetexta gown); ritual traditions claims that she does not want to lose ‘the myths and the Milesian delights
involving Saturn, the identification of Saturn with Serapis; Roman and the stories of the mortals, in all their poetic diversity’,53 54 a captivat-
religion in its literary and physical aspects (‘quid mythici, quid physici ing longing for human ‘multiplicity’ explicitly opposed to the divine
aestiment’, i.e. excluding profound theology); true religious vs. folk ‘oneness’ and based on its particularly enjoyable and varied literary
traditions; slaves and their role; fixing and calculating the calendar in expressions.
Rome and Egypt; solar theology, identification of all the gods with the This nostalgic lament (the author’s own?) will not be satisfied in the
sun; the religious/philosophical authority of the poets (Virgil); Virgil’s following narrative, as Philology must submit to the rituals of her
expertise in many fields (each guest will develop a different aspect apotheosis (occupying Book II), literally throw up her human doctrines
tomorrow). (§135-6) and acquire the divine wisdom provided by her bridegroom’s
Afternoon/evening of the 1st day: afternoon discussions will be lighter; gift, thus performing the appropriate purification that is obviously
the proper balance between funny and serious subjects; a round of funny praised as a good thing throughout the text. But Martianus has already
and erudite dicta (sayings); comments on Cicero’s mordacitas (sharpness); voiced an alternative, rather ironical and slightly negative view of such a
other public figures (theatrical ambience); wine and desserts (secunda process that places him in a very particular position regarding the
mensa), proper vocabulary and traditions about them; praise and doctrines and disciplines to be subsequently set out. This ironic stance
criticism of drink, food and sex. will reappear at particular points in the text, not really threatening the
Morning of the 2nd day: Virgil as a source of ‘pontifical law’ (ius sincere appraisal of the good disciplines, but embodying the constant
pontificium);53 sacred terms, places, and rituals; Evangelus mentions supervision of a somewhat mocking Satire over the whole work, both
supposed errors in Virgil (and is contradicted). acting as a source of pedagogical entertainment (by making the useful
Afternoon/evening of the 2nd day: the ancient Roman lifestyle, criticism but possibly dry sciences more pleasurable) and, in my opinion,
of old luxury; laws regarding meals; names and characteristics of nuts embodying a rather mature and human sceptical perspective.
and fruits; traditions about figs, olives and grapes. Books III to IX contain the systematic expositions of the seven liberal
Morning of the 3rd day: Virgil’s rhetorical expertise and eloquence arts (Grammar, Dialectic, Rhetoric, Geometry, Arithmetic, Astronomy
(figures of speech, pathos); Cicero vs. Virgil as the best orator; styles and and Music), presented as long discourses voiced by the personified
genera dicendi (types of speech); Virgil’s knowledge of Greek literature, disciplines themselves. However, the contrast between the
philosophy and science; parallels between Virgil and Homer; Virgil’s use narrative/mythical sections, the ironic meta-discourse (appearing time
of Greek poetry; the importance of Greek culture; Virgil’s use of archaic and again in different significant sections) and the technical expositions
Roman writers. within the work has been a constant source of puzzlement for modern
Afternoon/evening of the 3rd day: philosophy as a proper subject for a scholars, who seek a key to the unity of the text. The scholars that have
symposium; how to arrange a good banquet and philosophy’s role in it; focused on the myth itself and the rituals contained in it (Guillaumin,
appropriate and inappropriate degrees of censure and scorn within a 2007; Guillaumin, 2008; Lenaz 1975) tend to emphasize the religious and
banquet; food, drink and health (medical approach); formal debate Neoplatonic aspects of the work as the leitmotif, while among those who
(disputatio), proposed by guests, between two Greek specialists (Disarius, have tried to make sense of the role of the ‘technical parts’, opinions vary.
a doctor, and Eustathius, a philosopher) on kinds of food and their effects For some critics,55 it is not even clear that these ‘technical parts’ are really
on health; medical and philosophical Greek doctrines and opinions on substantive and they suggest that they could be seen more as a literary
wine, women, and other victuals (their hot/cold character); the brain and characterization of the speech of the plot’s heroines. As we have already
the nervous system; age and ageing (draught/humidity); blushing and seen, this would not be fair, as the ‘instructive’ or ‘theoretical’ parts are
turning pale; geography and climate in food production; physiology in fact better informed than was previously thought. Moreover, they
(thirst and hunger); the ring finger, traditions and beliefs about its occupy too much of the work to be seen as mere literary excursuses. And
meaning; density and other characteristics of different waters; water yet Shanzer (1986), who presents a very open and comprehensive
optics, augmentation of shapes through water, opposition between approach to the text, analyzing its particular genre as belonging within
Atomistic and Platonic theories of sight (opposition between the doctor’s the Menippean tradition, points to the possibility of its not being com-
and the philosopher’s ways of solving problems); chicken/egg priority pletely ‘in earnest’,56 while Stahl, Johnson and Burge (1971), in a more
problem; conservation of meat; final lacuna. critical mood, talk about a possible ‘exhibition piece’, displaying rather
According to our modern categorizations, it seems that the most than transmitting knowledge. Shanzer’s conclusion is not so
‘scientific’ and specialized matters are those addressed in the final discouraging, however. She prefers to talk about a combination of
session, those related to medical and physiological problems, the rest motives. She posits a serious interest in the ‘scientific’ doctrines pre-
falling more or less within the domain of the literary/gram- matical sented, equally sincere philosophical and religious beliefs behind the
antiquitates. But all of these final subjects are explicitly called quaestiones allegorical framework, but also a very remarkable ironic mood (1986, p.
conviviales (Sat. VII 3, 24; VII 4, 1, i.e. questions that are suitable for a 43). This humorous stance is apparently dictated by the adoption of Satire
banquet), and many of them are taken directly from Plutarch’s both as a mythical character, who would have told such a tale to the
homonymous work. So we have here a fine example of a somewhat author during ‘the languishing eves of winter’, and as a literary genre
frivolous yet socially relevant use of scientific knowledge. from which Martianus, still according to Shanzer, would really like to
In the case of Martianus, the literary genre selected for the coherent borrow and innovate within (1986, pp. 29-44). Shanzer’s inclusive
and unified transmission of his compendium of arts is a mythical definition of our text as a ‘philosophical spoudo- geloion’ (1986, p. 41)
narration presided over by Satire as the inspiring muse, in the tradition attempts to summarize both the serious and pleasant (useful and
of Milesian fables and Menippean satire. There is a nice passage at the enjoyable) aspects expressed by the Greek compound and the deeper
beginning of Book II (§100) in which Philology, already chosen as a bride ideological basis for its allegorical form.

53 Virgil’s philosophical lore and Virgil’s expertise in ‘augural law’ (the stated opinatione formidat.’
themes of Eustathius and Flavianus) are missing (lacuna). It is Praetextatus who is 55 Stahl, Johnson and Burge (1971).

speaking at the beginning of the extant text. 56 ‘If asked what it was, one might equally well respond, ‘a philosophical polemical

54 ‘nam certe mythos, poeticae etiam diversitatis delicias Milesias historiasque allegory’ or ‘an only partially successful literary joke’ (Shanzer, 1986, pp. 43-4).
mortalium, postquam supera conscenderit, se pellitus amissuram non cassa
P. Olmos / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 43 (2012) 284-292 291

Other studies, such as those by Crisante (1987) and Schievenin (2009), much further. The common context is that of sought-after social promi-
focus on certain meta-discursive and particularly significant sections of nence based on discursive excellence that could derive from slightly
the work to try to make sense of it: the prologue, the ending, 57 the different backgrounds and personal inclinations, and we do not have
previously mentioned dialogue with the muse Camena, certain enough encyclopaedic works to create such a division.
interruptions of the action by side remarks, etc. Both scholars comment In his influential study, Flamant provided a somewhat cursory
on one of these supposedly significant moments, at the beginning of Book diagnosis of the Latin rhetorical tradition after the major figures of the
VI (Crisante, 1987, pp. 18-25; Schievenin, 2009, pp. 47-59), where Satire classical period:
ridicules Martianus because he has not recognized certain characters, two Ce que les rhéteurs latins ont retenu de Cicéron et de Quintilien, ce
additional maids, who appear at the introduction of Geometry (the first ne sont pas les innovations, le désir d’élargir l’art oratoire aux
of the mathematical Greek arts). These are Philosophy and Paedia, two dimensions d’un véritable humanisme, mais au contraire ce qu’il y a
‘comprehensive’ disciplines (disciplines of disciplines) who, together de plus impersonnel, de plus banal, en un mot le simple héritage de
with Philology itself, represent ideals of learning. Although things are la tradition grecque. A l’ambitieux programme du De oratore, on
not completely clear, here it would seem that Philosophy is an old, préfera tout de suite la sécheresse scolaire du De inventione. (Flamant,
already abandoned ideal and path to wisdom. Paedia would represent a 1977, pp. 253-254)
more practical and ‘scientific’ approach (particularly concerned with
This assessment could easily be contradicted by mentioning the
incorporating the mathematical sciences or arts) and explicitly of
proposals of our two authors, writing three centuries after Quintilian
Varronian lineage. And finally, it would be expected of Philology, after
with the confidence that they would be understood and most likely
her assimilation of her bridegroom’s gift, that she would represent
followed by a cultured set.
Martianus’ own proposed comprehensive standard ofbroad culture and
education.
For her part, M. Bovey (2003) has pointed out the need to ‘trail’ the References
myth and the allegory into the technical books (III-IX) and analyze, in
Barkhouche, B. (1997). La transmission du Timée dans le monde latin. In D. Jacquart
particular, the physical presentation, short narratives and poetic (Ed.), Les voies de la science grecque (pp. 1-31). Genève: Droz.
fragments introducing and dismissing the seven maidens. Bovey thus Bovey, M. (2003). Disciplinae cyclicae. L'organisation du savoir dans l'oeuvre de Martianus
arrives at a closer view of the seven disciplines that makes more sense of Capella. Trieste: Edizioni Université di Trieste.
Cameron, A. (2011). The last Pagans of Rome. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Cracco
the whole work and its encyclopaedic ambitions. Finally, as I have tried Ruggini, L. (1985). Conservatism and innovation in the culture of the fourth/ fifth
to indicate in my own analysis of certain parts of Book V (Rhetoric)58 and century. Quaderni ticinesi di Numismatica e Antichità classiche, XIV, 287-303. Cracco
as Schievenin’s (2009, pp. 75-103) studies on certain passages of Book VI Ruggini, L. (1986). Simmaco: otia et negotia di classe, fra conservazione e rinnovamento.
In F. Paschoud et al. (Eds.), Colloque Genevois sur Symmaque (pp. 97-118). Paris: Les Belles
(Geometry) reveal, there is still much to be gleaned as characteristic of Lettres.
Martianus’ method and interests from his supposedly standard Cracco Ruggini, L. (1997). From fourth to sixth century: A No-Man’s Land in the history
‘compilations’, that is, from the supposedly dullest and most technical of sciences. Scripta Classica Israelica, XVI, 191-198.
Crisante, L (Ed.). (1987). Martiani Capellae, De nuptiis Philologiae et Mercurii Liber IX.
parts of the work. A careful study of the artistic content and precepts of Padua: Editrice Antenore.
Book V, for example, reveals our author’s rather practice-related and Coumo, S. (2000). Pappus of Alexandria and the mathematics of late antiquity. Cambridge:
somewhat realistic approach to the art of speech in its civic context. CUP.

Moreover, if there is a ‘personal touch’ in his apparently merely Ferré, B. (Ed.). (2007). Martianus Capella, Les noces de Philologies et de Mercure, Livre VI, La
Géométrie. Paris: Les Belles Lettres.
traditional exposition of Rhetoric’s precepts, it does not seem to have Fischer, H. -W. (1936). Untersuchungen uber die Quellen der Rhetorik des Martianus Capella
much to do with a Neoplatonic orientation of its lore towards the proper (Inaugural-Dissertation). Breslau: Hermann Eschenhagen.
purification and return of the soul to a divine sphere. Flamant, J. (1977). Macrobe et le Néo-Platonisme latin, à la fin du IVe siècle. Leiden: Brill
(Études préliminaires aux religions orientales dans l’Empire Romain, 58). Guillaumin, J.-
To sum up, if Macrobius’ work represents a literary unit emerging Y. (Ed.). (2003). Martianus Capella. Les noces de Philologies et de Mercure, Livre VII,
from a complicated framework of interests and a creative use of highly L'Arithmétique. Paris: Les Belles Lettres.
varied sources and traditions, the same could be said about Martianus’ Guillaumin, J.-B. (2007). L’encyclopédisme de Martianus Capella: héritage d’une forme
traditionnelle ou nouveauté radicale? Schedae prépublication, 4(1), 45-68. Guillaumin, J.-B.
book. Their most conspicuous common characteristic is the literary (2008). Néoplatonisme et encyclopédisme dans l’oeuvre de Martianus Capella. R.É.L.,
sophistication (LeMoine, 1972) chosen and carefully developed to do the 86,167-190.
job for them: that of offering a guide to selfenhancement directed at an Hadot, I. (1984). Arts libéraux et philosophie dans la pensée antique. Paris: Études
Augustiniennes.
audience of already cultured people59 who would probably need such a
Halm, K. (1863). Rhetores Latini Minores. Leipzig: Teubner.
strategy to be duly encouraged. Hinks, D. A. G. (1935). Martianus Capella on Rhetoric, PhD Theses, Trinity College,
4. Conclusion: grammatical and rhetorical encyclopaedism Cambridge.
Kaster, R. A. (1980). Macrobius and Servius: Verecundia and the Grammarian's function.
We have seen how the encyclopaedic endeavours of Macrobius’ Harvard Studies in Classical Philology, 84, 219-262.
Saturnalia and Martianus’ De nuptiis could be related to their authors’ Kaster, R. A. (1988). Guardians of language: The grammarian and society in Late Antiquity.
Berkeley: University of California Press.
interest in proposing and disseminating certain recipes and strategies for Kaster, R. A. (Ed.). (2011). Macrobius. Saturnalia (Vol. 3 vols.). Cambridge, Mass./
more substantive learning in the context of a culture in which what was London: Harvard University Press.
more or less guaranteed (for the elite, at least) was a grammatical and Keulen, W. (2009). Gellius the Satirist. Roman Cultural Authority in Attic Nights.
Leiden/Boston MS: Brill.
rhetorical education. Macrobius’ obvious fondness for specifically LeMoine, F. (1972). Martianus Capella, A Literary Re-evaluation. Munich: Arbeo-
grammatical and literary issues and Martianus’ known background and Gesellschaft.
proven expertise in rhetorical practice could lead us to initially establish Lenaz, L. (Ed.). (1975). Martiani Capellae. De nuptiis Philologiae et Mercurii liber secundus.
Padua: Liviana Editrice.
a distinction between a grammar-driven and a rhetoric-driven Lopetegui, G., Muñoz García, M., & Redondo, E. (2007). Antología de textos sobre retórica
encyclopaedism, but I really do not think such a distinction could take us (ss. IV-IX). Bilbao: Universidad del País Vasco.
Marinone, N. (Ed.). (1967). Macrobio. I Saturnali Torino: UTET.

57 ‘Questi interventi metaletterari hanno, come si é detto, la spiegazione Martianus' work as a ‘teacher's book' as opposed to a ‘student's book': ‘perché il De nuptiis
definitiva e il loro suggello nella chiusa e precisamente nella violenta replica di Satyra non é per l'allievo, ma per il maestro: basti pensare ai ricorrenti topoi dello studio, alle arti
alie accuse di Marziano' (Crisante, 1987, p. 25). che espongono solo i loro principi fondamentali, agli strumenti stessi di Grammatica: il
58 See Olmos (2011). I find particularly significant certain details of his profilo dell'opera vuole essere elevato, rivolto non ai principianti ma ai dotti, ai sapientes,
doctrines on the parts of Rhetoric (§428, §442), the genres and audiences of Rhetoric e con questi trova perfetta e cordiale intesa, segno di orientamento, programma di
(§428, §447-448), the matter of Rhetoric (§439-40), the questions properly addressed by conoscenza'. I would instead say that, in any case, the kind of maestro that Martianus is
Rhetoric (§441) and his particular exposition of the stasis theory (§443-472). embodying is not at all a teacher in such a professional sense and that the context of the
59 Schievenin (2009, p. 57) expresses a somewhat similar idea by talking about learning contained in his work is definitely outside that of the formal classroom.
292 P. Olmos /Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 43 (2012) 284-292

Marrou, H.-I. (1948). Histoire de l'éducation dans l'antiquité. Paris: Seuil.


Marrou, H. I. (1969). Les Arts Libéraux dans l'Antiquité Classique. In Arts Libéraux et
Philosophie au Moyen Âge. Actes du Quatrième Congrès International de
Philosophie Médiévale (pp. 5-27). Montréal; Paris: Institut d'Études Médiévales;
J.Vrin.
Navarro Antolín, F. (Ed.). (2010). Macrobio. Saturnales. Madrid: Gredos.
Neri, M., & Ramelli, i. (Eds.). (2007). Macrobio Commento al Sogno di Scipione. Milán:
Bompiani.
Olmos, P. (2011). Rhetoric, Satire and Encyclopaedia in Martianus Capella. in D.
Hernández de la Fuente (Ed.), New perspectives on Late Antiquity (pp. 327-351).
Newcastle: Cambridge Scholars Publishing.
Ramelli, i. (Ed.). (2001). Marziano Capella, Le nozze di Filologia e Mercurio. Milano: Bompiani.
Scarpa, L (Ed.). (1981). Macrobii Ambrosii Theodosii. Commentariorum in somnium Scipionis
libri duo. Padua: Liviana Editrice.
Schievenin, R. (2009). Nugis ignosce lectitans. Studi su Marziano Capella. Trieste: Edizioni
Universita di Trieste.
Shanzer, D. (1986). A philosophical and literary commentary on Martianus Capella’s De Nuptiis
Philologiae et Mercurii. Book 1 (Vol. 32). Berkeley: University of California Press
(Classical Studies).
Stahl, W. H. (Ed.). (1952). Macrobius. Comentary on the Dream of Scipio. New York: Columbia
University Press.
Stahl, W. H., Johnson, R., & Burge, y. E. L. (1971). Martianus Capella and the seven liberal
arts. Vol. I. The quadrivium of Martianus Capella. Latin traditions in mathematical sciences.
50 B.C.-A.D. 1250, with a study of the allegory and the verbal disciplines. New York;
London: Columbia University Press.
Suárez Martínez, P. (2006). in Martianum Capellam i: Un problema en torno al 3.
Exemplaria Classica, 10, 253-262.

You might also like