You are on page 1of 11

Valentí Simpson / U156100

WHY DEMOCRACY DOESN’T WORK

INTRODUCTION

“Democracy is the worst form of government, except for all the others”, said Winston
Churchill in 1947. His quote indicates our reality: a not nearly perfect political system,
but the best we could possibly have at the moment. Sure, “power to the people” sounds
great, but is this actually good? Another quote from Churchill suggests a negative
answer, “The best argument against democracy is a five-minute conversation with the
average voter.” Democracy might be the best system out there, among our current
alternatives, but that doesn’t entail that it’s a good, desirable system. I intend to show
why.

It’s interesting to note that some theories of justice are bound to some concrete forms of
government. Therefore, we can see how Rawls’ first principle of justice, the Equal
Liberty principle, binds him to Democracy. By this principle, society is so structured
that all persons hold the same political liberties: everyone has the right to hold public
office and to affect the outcome of national elections. Then, it’s difficult to see how
Rawls’ sense of justice could be upheld in a non-democratic society, where some people
would be stripped of their political liberties.

But we needn’t be bound to the pursuit of democracy. In Anarchy, State and Utopia
(ASU, for short), the libertarian Robert Nozick chases after the minimal state, a “night-
watchman state” whose only function is the protection of its citizens’ rights against
violence and theft. In addition to an explicit critique of democracy in the chapter
“Demoktesis”, Nozick’s idea of the minimal state implicitly carries an incompatibility
with a democratic system, as there is no public law, and no actual body politic that
participates in decision and policy making. Anything more than this minimal state
would actually be coercive and unjust, all our democratic states too.

Furthermore, democracy is deeply flawed. In his recent book Against Democracy, Jason
Brennan, also a libertarian, argues that democracy should be judged by its results, and
these don’t look promising. As an instrumentalist, Brennan is more than ready to
abandon democracy for any other alternative that works better.

For the purposes of showing democracy’s failure, I will first turn to Brennan and his
profound argument against it. The next step is seeing Brennan’s own proposal:
epistocracy, democracy’s substitute.

Next, I will follow Nozick’s reflection on Utopia. In the third and final part of ASU,
Nozick argues that Utopia, the imagined community any of us would want to inhabit,
actually consists in a framework for building utopias, experimental communities that

1
we could build and structure conjointly, in an effort to create societies its inhabitants
would truly want to occupy. This philosophical digression is an abstract, albeit
interesting tool by which Brennan’s proposal for epistocracy gains new force and
justification.

Finally, as Nozick proposes, I shall experiment with Brennan’s epistocratic government,


seeing how it can be carried further, in an attempt to rearrange politics in its search for
justice.

1. AGAINST DEMOCRACY

In a new preface to his book, Against Democracy, Brennan says the following:

“Democracy is a tool, nothing more. If we can find a better tool, we should feel free
to use it. Indeed, […] we have a duty to use it. Justice is justice. Bad decisions are
not rendered just simply by political fiat. Political decisions are high stakes. How
dare anyone make such decisions incompetently?” (Brennan, 2017, p. xiv).

In this short quote lay the key elements of Brennan’s argument against democracy:

1) Democracy as a tool.

As I mentioned, Brennan is an instrumentalist; he thinks that if we can find an


alternative to democracy that produces better results, we should implement it. In
chapters 4 (“Politics Doesn’t Empower You or Me”) and 5 (Politics Is Not a Poem”),
Brennan systematically debunks strong deontological arguments for democracy; we
can’t value democracy for what it is, it doesn’t carry with it some intrinsic justice.
Given this scenario, and because epistocracy seems a more efficient alternative to
democracy, we should experiment with it. This can be contested by a conservatist
argument, such as Burkean Conservativism. As we will see, this needs solving.

His instrumentalist approach serves as the bridging premise by which to finally


conclude against democracy and in favour of epistocracy. Next, I present the main
argument against democracy.

2) Political competence.

The core of Brennan’s argument against democracy is founded on what he calls the
“competence principle”, which states that “every individual high-stakes political
decision ought to be made competently and in good faith by what is generally a
competent decision-making body” (Ibid, p. 160). We have a right to a competent
government, as he argues in chapter 6 (“The Right to a Competent Government”).
Therefore, if it’s the case that political decisions made through democracy are not

2
competent decisions we must reject democracy on the whole. Similarly, he makes his
case for epistocracy, basing it upon an “antiauthority tenet”:

“When some citizens are morally unreasonable, ignorant, or incompetent about


politics, this justifies not permitting them to exercise political authority over others.
It justifies either forbidding them from holding power or reducing the power they
have in order to protect innocent people from their incompetence” (Ibid, p. 17).

In chapter 2 (“Ignorant, Irrational, Misinformed Nationalists”), Brennan does an


exhaustive analysis of much empirical work on voter behaviour. All this empirical data
allows him to theorise about the flawed workings of democracy. He divides democratic
citizens into three archetypes: Hobbits, who are mostly apathetic and ignorant about
politics, with no social scientific and historical knowledge (in the US, the average non-
voter is a hobbit); Hooligans, the “rabid sports fans of politics”, with strong political
opinions and a big, biased consumption of political information (most regular voters
and politicians are hooligans); and Vulcans, the ideal type, who think scientifically and
rationally about politics and have opinions strongly grounded in social science and
philosophy (Ibid, p. 4-5). No one is ever a true vulcan, everyone is at least minimally
biased.

Furthermore, Brennan notices in his third chapter (“Political Participation Corrupts”)


that the education argument, first advanced by Mill, fails. This is, participating in
politics (as many deliberative democracy advocates would have it) does not educate or
ennoble us; au contraire, “[…] most common forms of political engagement are more
likely to corrupt and stultify” (Ibid, p. 55). Using Brennan’s terminology, political
participation turns hobbits into hooligans and hooligans into even worse hooligans, not
into vulcans.

It appears that, at its base, democracy is deeply flawed. It is sustained by individuals


that are biased and misinformed, and are therefore too incompetent to be trusted for
decision-making. Moreover, as a result of democracy, their ill-made decisions are
imposed on the rest of us, no matter how little we agree with them. Democracy is,
therefore, incompetently coercive.

As a final step, in chapter 7 (“Is Democracy Competent?”), Brennan discusses two


possible objections that claim that democracy is really a competent system.

First, Brennan goes on to counter the “epistemic” defence of democracy. This defence
tries to show how competence is an emergent feature of democratic decision-making;
the electorate tends to produce smart decisions as a collective, overriding individual
incompetence. This defence is possible through three mathematical theorems: the
“miracle of aggregation theorem”, “Condorcet’s jury theorem” and the “Horn-Page
theorem”. This a priori defence of democracy fails, as Brennan responds to each
possibility, showing that these theorems do not apply to real-life democracy and that the

3
empirical evidence mentioned above gives us more than good reasons to doubt
democracy.

The second objection Brennan faces rests on empirical grounds, arguing that, while
individual voters are incompetent, democratic governments are not. This would explain
why democracies have typically performed better than other regimes. Such an objection
can have many different forms, which Brennan faces.

 One possibility is that party systems “reduce the epistemic burdens of voting” (Ibid,
p. 195); voters have a “cognitive shortcut”, they can treat all candidates of a party
as a homogenous group, and thus can act as if they appeared to be well-informed.
Brennan gives four reasons why this isn’t enough. First, studies indicate that many
voters don’t even know what policies different political parties defend. Second, to
vote competently “requires tremendous social scientific knowledge” (Ibid, p. 196),
such as the possible consequences, good or bad, of their policies; it’s not enough to
know the candidate’s preferences. Third, as we saw, voters tend to be hooligans,
consuming information in highly biased ways. Fourth, as Both Ilya Somin and
Brennan argue, “the quality of the candidates […] depends in large part on the
quality of the electorate”, and as voters are extremely ignorant and misinformed,
the quality of the candidates is consequently low.

 Another possibility is that, as Gilens claims, the median voter theorem is wrong,
and politicians aren’t representing the position of the median voter, but are actually
responding to the preferences of richer voters. There might be an upside to this,
given that empirical data shows that higher income voters are also high-information
voters. Brennan happily accepts this as it only goes to show that “democracy works
better than it otherwise would, because it doesn’t exactly work” (Ibid, p. 198). In
fact, this might even constitute a point in favour of epistocracy; it shows that
governments work best when responding to the preferences of the best informed.

 A final possibility is that, while the voting public is largely irrational and
misinformed, it actually doesn’t get what it wants. According to Brennan, there
might be “a wide range of political bodies and administrative procedures that
mediate between what the majority of the moment appears to want during the
election and what laws and rules actually get passed” (Ibid, p. 199). This could
mean that there are sufficient checks in place in democracy so as to make electoral
decisions low-stakes political decisions. If this were the case, the competence
principle would not apply, as voting wouldn’t be sufficiently high-stakes and
government itself is competent. Brennan doesn’t buy this possibility. Major
elections “remain high stakes” (Ibid, p. 202). While elections don’t directly
determine what policies get passed, they do have a major influence in the
probabilities regarding which will eventually get implemented.

4
3) Conclusion: epistocracy

In light of everything said so far, we have reasons to reject democracy. At its base, the
voters, democratic decision-making is not handled competently. There is enough
empirical evidence that points to the conclusion that voters are irrational, misinformed
and biased beings that are not sufficiently prudent nor wise and therefore should not be
trusted with deciding political matters. Their incompetent decisions are then imposed on
innocent people, left to suffer the consequences. By the competence principle, we have
a right to be protected from this incompetence. And while the government itself might
act competently, at least most of the time, this doesn’t justify keeping democracy alive.
Less so when, thinking instrumentally along with Brennan, we appear to have a better
alternative: epistocracy.

Epistocracy, at its roots, means “rule of the knowledgeable”, much like what Plato
espoused with the rule of the philosopher-king. An epistocratic political system, then,
formally distributes power “according to competence, skill, and the good faith to act on
that skill” (Ibid, p. 14). Brennan’s proposal of epistocracy is a modest one, as he himself
admits that “Realistically, epistocracies will still feature the rule of hooligans rather than
vulcans, although epistocratic hooligans may be more vulcan-like than in democracy”
(Ibid, p. 207).

Epistocracies will generally share the same institutions as democracy. The main
difference is that not everyone has, by default, an equal right to vote or run for office.

Out of many possible forms of epistocracy (some propose unequally distributing votes,
others leaving voting rights/restrictions to chance) Brennan favours one: government by
simulated oracle. Drawing on the character of Pythia the Oracle, who is wiser than all of
us put together, and to whom we should always defer to for decision-making, Brennan
points to the possibility of simulating such an oracle. In chapters 2 and 7, Brennan had
drawn on social scientist Althaus’ empirical work on the relation between citizens’ level
of information and their policy preferences. Althaus had shown that low-information
voters “have systematically different preferences from well-informed ones, even after
correcting for the influence of demographic factors such as race, income and gender”
(Ibid, p. 34). Through this “enlightened preferences method”, we can estimate the
electorate’s policy preferences if they were better informed. This can ultimately be
applied to elections, as Brennan shows:

“Suppose there is a range of candidates from various political parties. We can ask
citizens to provide their anonymously coded demographic information and then take
a test of basic objective political knowledge. Then they rank the candidates from
most to least favored. Using these data, we can determine how the public would rank
the candidates if the public were fully informed. Whatever candidates ranks the
highest, wins” (Ibid, p. 222).

5
2. NOZICK ON UTOPIA

In an effort to shed light on the possible shortcomings of his minimal state, Nozick
takes up the investigation of utopia, as his minimal state might not invoke inspiration
like the idealisations of utopia do. While I have no interest in the minimal state itself,
Nozick’s inquiry into utopia provides me with a philosophical tool with which to further
Brennan’s criticism of democracy and his proposal for epistocracy.

Admitting that it is impossible to simultaneously fulfil all conditions by which


something would qualify as a utopia, Nozick sets out to investigate “the best of all
possible worlds” (Nozick, 1974, p. 298). This quickly leads to the fact that someone’s
best possible world will not be everyone’s. Still, utopia must be, in some way, the best
for all. Nozick then asks us to imagine a possible world in which to live. Every rational
creature inhabiting your imagined world can emigrate to a world of their own
imagining. Nozick calls these worlds, “associations”. Searching for utopia, then, means
to search for stable worlds, associations that are set up in a way so that its inhabitants
cannot imagine an alternative association in which they’d rather live (this excludes such
possibilities as absolute monarchies, where some citizens are exploited, given that they
would simply emigrate to some other, non-exploiting, association). It is interesting to
note that, in thinking along these lines, Nozick has shifted the idea of utopia as a
possible world to the idea of possible worlds.

At this point, the model for utopia consists in imagined possible worlds (with some
constraints that Nozick introduces, which don’t interest me at present). How do we
project this model to our world? In actuality, possible worlds correspond to a “diverse
range of communities, which people can enter if they are admitted, leave if they wish to,
shape accordingly to their wishes” (Ibid, p. 307). Given the divergence between real life
and imagined possible worlds, many of the conditions we could satisfy in the latter
can’t actually be satisfied, such as the limited number of possible communities, or the
impossibility of finding your every value satisfied in any one community. Nevertheless,
Nozick remains optimistic and states that we can “satisfy many of them”.

“Utopia”, therefore, “is a framework for utopias, a place where people are at liberty to
join together voluntarily to pursue and attempt to realize their own vision of the good
life in the ideal community but where no one can impose his own utopian vision upon
others” (Ibid, p. 312). Because people are different and complex, plurality is the
condition of utopia. Finally, utopia is “the environment in which utopian experiments
may be tried out” (Idem).

How is any of this relevant for Brennan’s substitution of democracy with epistocracy?
As Brennan himself notes, “Whether we should prefer epistocracy to democracy is in
part an empirical question, which I am not fully able to answer. […] There are good
reasons to think epistocracy would produce better results than democracy with universal

6
suffrage, yet there are reasons to worry it will not” (Brennan, 2017, p. 228). He then
explains how the English politician Edmund Burke, reflecting on the disasters brought
on by the French Revolution, wrote that humans are not smart enough to rebuild society
through revolution, beginning anew. The French Revolution showed that institutions
“that seem unjust on philosophical reflection turn out to serve useful purpose” (Ibid, p.
229). This all led to “Burkean conservativism”, the idea that “we must be extremely
cautious when making radical changes to existing institutions. […] Experimentation
with new forms of government is dangerous” (Idem).

Nevertheless, Brennan warns, “Burkean conservativism tells us to be careful, but we


also have to be careful with Burkean conservativism” (Ibid, p. 230). In effect, Burkean
conservativism is reason for stagnation; applied too much, and no changes can be
brought about. At this point, Nozick reappears. We must defeat Burkean conservativism
if we are ever to have a chance at utopia. Experimentation might be dangerous, but
stagnation more so. Any true political activity is a step towards utopia, an attempt at
building upon utopian framework. Burkean conservativism takes this framework away
from us.

If all this is true, Brennan might find in Nozick a justification for epistocracy. In
philosophising about utopia, Nozick paves the way for new, innovative proposals (such
as Brennan’s) that might bring us closer to a community which all would want to
inhabit. Democracy, as Brennan has effortfully shown, is unjust; epistocracy might
relieve us from these injustices. How dare anyone deny us our right to strive for utopia?

3. EXPERIMENTING WITH EPISTOCRACY

By inquiring into the nature of utopia through Nozick, epistocracy is justified. It


constitutes an attempt to experiment, with the final objective of building communities
worth living in.

It is then time to experiment. I shall try to see how far epistocracy can take us, if we
commit ourselves to the effort of trying to arrange our institutions so as to achieve
justice.

Brennan devises epistocracy, government through simulated oracle, as a means to solve


the problem of incompetence at the moment of elections. By studying the degree of
knowledge of citizens, as well as their candidate preferences, we can arguably reach the
conclusion of what candidate would be elected by an all-knowledgeable electorate.
Instituting this might cause outrage amongst the electorate, and other problems
regarding how to manage these empirical studies (Brennan points to the possibility that
politicians might tamper with them to favour themselves).

This is not the type of epistocracy I wish to experiment with. I want to take Brennan’s
government through simulated oracle to the next step, over and beyond elections. I think

7
simulated oracle can work, not just for choosing the best-suited political candidate, but
also for choosing and implementing actual policies, actual laws. If by enlightened
preference method we can cross-reference citizen’s degree of knowledge with their
political inclinations to figure out what policies would be preferred in a situation of high
information, why not use it to actually choose and implement these policies? Through
such empirical study, we can skip political representation altogether. Why choose to
have parties struggling for our support in an electoral feud, which might then not fully
represent us in parliament when choosing what laws to pass, when we can discover the
actual political decisions citizens with an ideal degree of knowledge would make?

Brennan has made sure that knowledge is correlated with good decision-making in
politics. He has given ample evidence that the political preferences of high-information
voters seem to be good preferences. He says, for instance, that high-degree voters all
tend to prefer economic policies which economists themselves tend to agree over, such
as less government intervention and control over the economy. They are also
systematically more liberal when it comes to social issues: more pro-choice, less
punitive crime measures, less military intervention, more affirmative action, etc. If the
people know what they want, and we now know that some wants are better than others,
and that we can actually determine these better wants, I don’t see where the mystery is.

Let’s suppose, for the sake of argument, that government by simulated oracle as I have
construed it, post-elections, can be implemented. Where does this leave politics, as we
now understand it?

Let’s take a basic political institution, parliament or congress, for instance. In most
democratic governments (parliamentary governments), there is such an institution
where policies and laws are discussed by deputies, and finally passed (or discarded). In
such places, elected representatives exercise the legislative power of government. Laws
are voted for by these political characters, who act in name of their political party and,
ultimately, for the people. Nevertheless, this is mere representation. Citizens don’t
really get a vote in what laws are to be passed. They merely get to choose what parties
can have a greater influence in this process.

Through epistocracy, as I propose it, there is no need for such a discussion regarding
laws. Parliament is no longer the home of representatives who choose policies after
“deliberation” and discussion. With simulated oracle, parliament would be “occupied”
by social and political scientists, who use their methods (such as the enlightened
preferences method) and devise newer, better ones, to figure out what policies would be
preferred in ideal knowledge conditions. Such an epistocracy closely resembles a
technocracy. It seems that this is truly the rule of the knowledgeable. No longer would
we depend on contingent discussions, by characters that, as Brennan argues, are of low
quality, incompetent, biased, and corrupted, in our search for justice.

8
4. CONCLUSIONS

I set out to show the faults of democracy, a system that is deeply rooted in our society,
but deeply flawed.

Brennan’s book, Against Democracy is a devastating attempt at that. In this work, he


goes over much empirical evidence showing that democracy functions in a highly
incompetent way, which results in the imposition of bad policies on an innocent few.
Democracy is, thus, incompetent, coercive and unjust. Because he is an instrumentalist,
Brennan argues that if we have a better alternative to democracy (and because
democracy has no intrinsic good) we should implement it.

Epistocracy is this alternative. Instead of giving everyone a right to vote by default, we


should make it so the knowledgeable rule, given that knowledge is positively correlated
with good politics. Brennan’s epistocracy is not a standard one; he doesn’t simply
advocate for vetoing people form voting. He proposes what he calls government by
simulated oracle, a system by which we can determine the decisions that would be made
with an ideal degree of knowledge.

To justify any attempt of implementing epistocracy, I shifted from Brennan to Nozick,


and his philosophical investigation into utopia. Utopia, Nozick elaborates, is a
framework for building utopias. It is the realization, in real life, of an environment in
which to build communities where people can experiment with different ways of living,
in an effort to live according to everyone’s will. Epistocracy, as an experiment in
politics, is justified under this framework for utopia.

Finally, I wished to experiment with Brennan’s idea of epistocracy. But, while he


focused it on electoral decision-making, I took it one step further, for actual policy
decision-making. If we can determine what preferences would be advocated for if
citizens were ideally knowledgeable, why not base politics on this? If we trust Brennan,
and think that decisions made in ideal knowledge conditions are the best possible
decisions, why require the intermediate of political representation? Why not just go with
those decisions? It’s the “rule of the knowledgeable” taken at its word.

A further line of analysis, now, would take up the question of how to implement such a
system. I truly think the social sciences should shift their attention to these questions.
This kind of experimentation really is, as Nozick said, the way to utopia. And what can
be more important than giving our all to the pursuit of justice, to building a community
for all?

9
BIBLIOGRAPHY

BRENNAN, Jason. Against Democracy. Princeton, Princeton University Press (2017).

NOZICK, Robert. Anarchy, State, and Utopia. New York, Basic Books Inc (1974)

10
CONTENTS

INTRODUCTION 1

AGAINST DEMOCRACY 2

NOZICK ON UTOPIA 6

EXPERIMENTING WITH EPISTOCRACY 7

CONCLUSIONS 9

BIBLIOGRAPHY 10

11

You might also like