You are on page 1of 11

Social Science & Medicine 55 (2002) 743–753

Too many choices? Hospital and community staff reflect on the


future of prenatal screening
Clare Williamsa,*, Priscilla Aldersona, Bobbie Farsidesb
a
Social Science Research Unit, University of London, 18 Woburn Square, London WC1H ONS, UK
b
Centre for Medical Law and Ethics, King’s College London, Strand, London WC2R 2LS, UK

Abstract

Promoting informed choice is commonly recognised as the chief purpose and benefit of prenatal screening, its very
presence being viewed as a key way in which the process can be distanced from eugenics. As the number of conditions
and features which can potentially be screened for rises, dilemmas about how to achieve informed choice can only
increase. Seventy hospital and community staff working in or attached to two English hospitals were interviewed
individually on topics which included their views on genetic developments and moral beliefs and values, and how these
affected their daily work. The majority then took part in small discussion groups led by an ethicist. The research
identified a paradox. On the one hand, participants recognised the centrality of informed choice to prenatal screening,
although they had many doubts about whether it could be achieved. On the other hand, most saw the expansion of
screening, which might further compromise informed choice, as an inevitable and inexorable process over which they
had little, if any, control. This was despite the fact that many of them decided, managed or implemented prenatal
screening policies within their hospitals. The paper explores the factors which staff themselves identified as responsible
for this perceived inevitable expansion. It then discusses more generally how the expansion of medical technologies can
appear as inexorable to those involved. Finally, the paper calls for more inclusive, integrated and collaborative debate
and research around the whole area of prenatal screening. This is to ensure that as far as possible, the wider
consequences and implications of any proposed expansion to prenatal screeningFboth the promises and the potential
side-effectsFare debated ahead of their implementation, and also to help ensure that public policy represents and
serves contemporary society. r 2002 Elsevier Science Ltd. All rights reserved.

Keywords: Prenatal screening; Informed choice; Genetic knowledge; Health technology

Introduction the need to be absolutely clear and explicit about the


risks and limitations of screening. There is a
Promoting informed choice is commonly recognised responsibility to ensure that people who accept an
as the chief purpose and benefit of prenatal screening, as invitation do so on the basis of informed choice.
reflected in many professional guidelines. The centrality
of informed choice is illustrated by the foreword to the The very presence of informed choice in prenatal
Second Report of the UK National Screening Commit- screening is often viewed as a key way in which the
tee (Department of Health, 2000), which states that an process may be distanced from eugenics (Kerr, Cunning-
important general theme is: ham-Burley, & Amos, 1998a). In the area of prenatal
screening the concept of informed choice is a complex
one, although this has not always been acknowledged,
particularly, in the biomedical literature. Instead,
*Corresponding author. Tel.: +44-207-612-6397. recommendations have tended to focus primarily on
E-mail address: clare@williams-forbes.freeserve.co.uk the importance of increasing the knowledge of practi-
(C. Williams). tioners and women, on the assumption that this will

0277-9536/02/$ - see front matter r 2002 Elsevier Science Ltd. All rights reserved.
PII: S 0 2 7 7 - 9 5 3 6 ( 0 1 ) 0 0 2 0 0 - 3
744 C. Williams et al. / Social Science & Medicine 55 (2002) 743–753

enable practitioners to ensure that women make haematologists; paediatricians; neonatologists; scien-
informed choices. One of the implications for practice tists; psychologists; chaplains; legal, audit and primary
noted by The Health Technology Assessment (HTA) care managers. The 11 groups discussed topics raised
Review (Bricker et al., 2000) is that, ‘Rapid changes in during the earlier interviews, which included informed
care may leave maternity staff and women behind. choice. The groups were of mixed disciplines and
Better information is needed for both’ (p. 48). Whilst seniority apart from one which was made up of
this may well be true, other factors such as inadequate practitioners working within haematology. Discussions
resources have previously been recognised as negatively lasted approximately 2 h, and with permission, were
affecting informed choice, even when only one screening taped and transcribed. This paper is based on the group
test was being offered (Green, 1994). As the number of discussions.
conditions and features which can potentially be Transcripts were analysed by content for emergent
screened for rises, dilemmas about how to achieve themes (Weber, 1990) which were then coded (Strauss &
informed choice can only increase. Corbin, 1990). Codes were compared for similarities and
This paper explores the views of hospital and differences across the groups, eventually leading to
community staff involved in prenatal screening and broader themes which made up the overall theoretical
testing. It looks at some of the main factors that they framework (Charmaz, 1983). Informed choice is part of
identified as limiting informed choice, and then goes on the conceptual theme exploring issues of equity in
to explore why, despite their concerns, many felt that the relation to prenatal screening. The research team met
rapid expansion of prenatal screening was inevitable. At frequently to discuss the data and analysis and to
the outset it should be stated that although many people incorporate sociological and philosophical perspectives,
use the term screening in a broad sense to include in order to add to the richness and validity of the
genetics, current prenatal screening is almost entirely analysis.
concentrated on phenotype information (Alderson et al., To protect anonymity, each participant is identified
2001). by a number and the hospitals are not identified,
although a similar range of views was found in each
one. In addition, participant titles have been purposely
The study kept broad, so for example, those described as midwives
range from junior midwives to senior managers, and
The paper reports on one aspect of a larger project in those described as obstetricians range from research
which the key research questions were: How is genetic fellows to consultants, and include those specialising in
knowledge affecting policy and practice in perinatal foetal medicine.
health care services? What challenges and opportunities
does the knowledge present, and how do practitioners Informed choice
address these in their daily work, both individually and
together? What aims and values guide them, and how One of the reasons the hospitals were selected was that
can insights from ethics and social science help? How they offered different antenatal screening programmes.
can these insights be shared in more useful ways with For example, the district general hospital offered the
busy practitioners? Can multidisciplinary group discus- more typical (within the UK) maternal serum screening
sions help staff to discuss and resolve dilemmas? at 16 weeks gestation, which indicates whether there is a
Seventy people working in or linked to two English higher chance of the baby having Down’s syndrome or
hospitals (one teaching hospital and one district general open neural tube defects. The teaching hospital offered
hospital) and in attached community services, were an innovative ultrasound scan at 12–14 weeks gestation,
interviewed individually by the two research sociologists which included within it the option of screening for
(P.A. and C.W.). The semi-structured ‘guided con- Down’s syndrome and major physical anomalies. When
versations’ (Lofland & Lofland, 1984) encouraged discussing the purpose of prenatal screening, group
respondents to give their own accounts and meanings. participants recognised the centrality of informed
The interview themes included interviewees’ views about choice:
genetic developments and moral beliefs and values, and
how these affected their daily work. Midwife, 50: yto give the client more of an opinion
Fifty six interviewees then took part in small (usually as to what the risk factors areyto give them
4–6 people) discussion groups led by a health care more information, to be able to make an informed
ethicist (B.F.), with 12 participants attending twice, at choice.
their request. Their work related directly or indirectly to
perinatal care, and participants included: midwives; Manager, 53: You don’t have to have screening, it’s
health visitors; neonatal nurses; genetic counsellors; there. You choose to have it, it’s not compulsory, so
sonographers; obstetricians; foetal medicine specialists; if you don’t want to know, you don’t need to take up
C. Williams et al. / Social Science & Medicine 55 (2002) 743–753 745

screeningyand it goes back to information and Midwife, 45: It’s very difficult, because if a woman
helping people make the choices, and it would be a now chooses not to have a scan, which is very
different matter if society said, ‘‘and if we found this unusual, but if she does, it’s almost written every-
is the outcome you have to do thisy’’. where, you know, ‘‘difficult womany’’.
However, despite the freedoms implied by the
Ethicist: But that goes back to the question of what is
opportunity to choose, staff identified a number of
screening about, and if it’s about giving choice, one
constraints on women’s choices.
of the choices available is to opt out.
Restrictions on individual choice through the offer of
Manager, 57: I don’t think you are ever given that
screening
choice to be honest.
Many participants felt that women’s choices to opt in
or out of screening might be shaped through the very act Midwife, 45: You aren’t. It’s a very difficult choice,
of screening being offered: and I think you have got to be very strong, because
every time you come to the clinic somebody says
Midwife, 51: Of course antenatally we offer all the something.
different options, because they are there for couples
to choose. It’s their choice as to whether they have Manager, 57: Yes, and you’re labelledFit’s like,
serum screening, Bart’s tests [a type of serum ‘‘Oh, she’s a difficult one’’.
screening] and things like this. We have to offer it
because it’s individual choice and it’s there, but also Midwife 51: You’re deviant.
in a way if you are offering these things, you are in a
way implying that it is better to have the perfect child Some people felt that women had similar difficulties
if you see what I mean. later on, if they decided against the termination of an
affected pregnancy. For example, this health visitor
Manager, 57: I think if it’s [screening] there they will explains how she was notified about the birth of a baby
have it in most cases, won’t they? If it’s offered to with Down’s syndrome on her caseload:
them they will take it, because it gives them that little Health visitor, 62: I’ve had people phoning me up to
bit of added reassurance, that little bit of comfort let me know that I’ve got a new Down’s baby and
sort of thingypeople take what’s offered. it’s, ‘‘they had the test and they knew they were going
to have it [baby with Down’s syndrome]’’. It’s the
judgemental thing, saying any woman in their senses
Difficulties of ‘opting out’ would terminate.
A few participants, however, did not feel that the offer
Many participants felt that screening was commonly of screening might put pressure on women:
perceived to be an integral part of antenatal care which
women might feel a responsibility to have: Obstetrician, 18: Would an English woman ever go
into screening, including diagnosis and termination
Midwife, 31: I think society deems that everything because she feels pressurised by society that she
should be perfect and I think that a lot of women, would be doing something bad if she didn’t? In
when they’re faced with the thought of having England, 1999, for Downs? I don’t feel that.
screening and other invasive procedures, feel that if
they have a handicapped child, if they don’t have the
screening, it’s almost as if to say, ‘‘Well, it’s your
fault because you didn’t have the screening’’. Lack of time to present choices

Manager, 53: It’s about the process of the whole of As noted in previous studies (e.g. Green, 1994),
antenatal care to me, it’s about a process of making almost everyone highlighted the lack of time to explain
sure you have a normal baby at the end of it, and in a the screening process fully to women:
sense you sign up to doing the right thing, so you get
Manager, 42: yI think the dilemma between saying
this ‘perfect’ baby as a result, and that’s [screening]
that people need good information and then saying
just part of the process.
there’s not enough time, that is the dilemma we’re
Most participants felt that it was much harder for grappling with, and personally I think screening has
women to opt out of screening than to opt in, as been introduced without that resource commitment
illustrated by the following sequence from Group 10: being taken on boardyit is very much the physical
746 C. Williams et al. / Social Science & Medicine 55 (2002) 743–753

side of things are dealt with, and nobody says, ‘‘Well, the sorts of things you can now see, and I don’t know
actually we need all this support around it’’. enough about it, but I worry that some people
probably make actually what turn out to be very
foolish decisions....
How screening information is offered

Some practitioners recognised their own potentially Societal attitudes to disability


strong influence on women’s choices:
Midwife, 51: If you offer it in such a way that it may Many staff saw a general lack of support within
not be such a negative thing to have a baby with society for disabled people and the difficulties this could
Down’s, then it may not beyyou may get someone present for women in making informed choices:
else who through past experiences may offer it in a Midwife, 8: One of the most important things is that
different way, so we have got an incredible amount of society here is not set up to cater for these children
power in that relationship. once they’re born, I think that’s the major problem.
Psychologist, 55: If the ethos is to prevent the birth of It’s not that people disagree with you having a
babies who are disabled or who have problems then handicapped child, it’s just that when you do have a
you would expect the screening to be as it isyto say, handicapped child, you are then almost, not without
‘‘Well, there you go, there is a risk or there isn’t’’, and exception, but you’re almost left to deal with it
then the mother or the parents are invited to make completely on your own, and it’s not necessarily a
the decision about whether to go on or not. That’s disapproval thing.
where it stops really, doesn’t it? The emphasis I don’t
think would be on encouraging you in any way that Midwife, 51: I think we have gone down the line
you are going to be able to cope. where if you do have a child with Down’s, obviously
you need extra support, but I think, looking at the
resources we’ve got in society, we may not be able to
Information given about conditions screened for
offer that support.
There was concern about the accuracy of the Thus, although participants recognised the centrality
information given to potential parents about the of informed choice in prenatal screening, for a variety of
conditions being screened for, or diagnosed: reasons, many doubted how achievable this aim was in
practice. Other specific difficulties highlighted, such as
Paediatrician, 58: ybut then sometimes I have had
the increased problems faced by women from ethnic
the feeling that people, I wouldn’t say, are pres-
minority groups and the difficulty of providing non-
surised, but that they are not necessarily given a
directive counselling, are discussed elsewhere (e.g.
realistic idea of what the outlook will be for their
Williams, Alderson, & Farsides, 2001). It is not
unborn child, that too black a picture may be
surprising that informed choice was seen as so important
painted, and maybe by people who don’t actually
amongst staff. Freedom of choice is central to western
know themselves.
biomedical ethics (Beauchamp & Childress, 1989), the
women’s health movement (Lippman, 1999) and to
Haematologist, 28: I think in most genetic diseases,
prenatal screening (Parker, 2000), and Chadwick (1999)
we are becoming less clear about prediction of
points out how questioning the rhetoric of choice risks
outcome, and how the range of interacting environ-
appearing to argue against individual rights.
mental, genetic factors, which ultimately will govern
Many of the practitioners’ reported difficulties in
the medical care in that particular situation, and all
trying to promote informed choice are confirmed by the
the social factors, are still largely unknown, so it
research of others. For example, Kaufert (2000) states
would be intellectually dishonest to predicate a
that although more generally, screening has been
choice based on that knowledge.
recognised as the defining characteristic of late 20th
Complex information presented at a sensitive time century surveillance medicine (Armstrong, 1995), the
posed difficulties for professionals and women: screening of women has to be seen as:

Paediatrician, 58: ...but perhaps you need all this a philosophical and historical construct reflecting a
information before you are actually pregnant because very particular view of health and disease, and a very
I think when you are pregnant or when an particular perspective on women and their bodiesy.
abnormality is found on a scan, that is a really Being screened is a duty; evasion is tagged as
difficult time to try and explain the pros and cons of irresponsible behavior, a moral dereliction (pp.
what a cleft palate means, or what extra digits mean, 166–167).
C. Williams et al. / Social Science & Medicine 55 (2002) 743–753 747

Hallowell’s (1999) study of women attending genetic health practitioners underestimate, or are even unaware
counselling for hereditary breast/ovarian cancer found of structural and social factors which might restrict
the freedom to choose being increasingly challenged by choice. For example, Lippman (1999) states:
the obligation to know. She states that the rhetoric of
There is a tendency in much biomedical literature to
the new genetics constructs individuals as having a
locate (all) influences/constraints on choice internal-
responsibility to obtain genetic knowledge and subse-
lyy. But overwhelming any such influences, and
quently to attempt to modify their risks, and also, to be
generally ignored, are powerful external influences
responsible for the health of others too. However, it
and constraints on women’s choicesy (p. 283).
should be noted that there is a key distinction between
this type of screening with its emphasis on promoting Kerr et al. (1998a) found that in the accounts of the
health and foetal screening, where, because of the scientists and clinicians they interviewed, ‘simplistic
current lack of treatment, one of the main options is assumptions’ about neutrality, applied science and
termination of pregnancy. Lippman (1999) argues that individual choice undermined more sophisticated dis-
not only do constraints such as these set limits on the cussions about genetics. They argue that, in contrast to
opportunities women have for choice and control, but professionals, lay people saw medical, structural and
they also increase the likelihood of blame for those who cultural factors as ‘inextricably linked’ to people’s
make the ‘wrong’ choices. These findings echo the decisions (Kerr, Cunningham-Burley, & Amos, 1998b).
concerns that many participants felt about antenatal Ettorre (1999) also describes how:
screening, that it was a routine that could be difficult for
women to decline without appearing irresponsible and biomedical experts, similar to other scientists, distin-
blameworthy. guish between the ‘social’ (ie behavioural processes)
The concerns expressed by a minority of staff about and the ‘intellectual’ (i.e. objective science)y. As a
the information given on impairments being screened for strategy to maintain professional dominanceythey
are supported by Abramsky, Hall, Levitan, and attempt to ensure the dominance of the intellectual
Marteau (2001), who found that too little, or inaccurate by constantly opposing ‘social’ intrusions’ (pp. 550–
information was often given about foetal sex chromo- 551).
some conditions. The haematologist in particular, high- However, in our discussion groups, many practi-
lights the importanceFand the difficultyFof explaining tioners, both senior and junior, illustrated that they were
the variability of conditions being screened for, and the not only aware of, but were troubled by structural and
need to move away from a genetically deterministic social factors which they perceived as affecting informed
view. The influence on uptake that practitioners may choice in prenatal screening. These included the
have by presenting tests in a positive or a less positive recognition of their own power within negotiations.
way has been shown by Simpson, Johnstone, and Boyd Given their concerns about the achievability of what
(1998), in relation to HIV testing. Negative attitudes they regarded as the chief purpose of prenatal screening,
towards disability which some practitioners felt affected why did participants think that screening services were
prenatal choices were also reported by Kerr et al. expanding so rapidly? During the group discussions, a
(1998a), who state that decisions are made within number of interlinked factors were cited by staff. These
familial, cultural, economic and social experiences and indicated that although the participants were active in
pressures, including the stigmatization and lack of helping to create and implement screening options, they
support given to people with disabilities. They believe did not tend to see themselves as agents.
that in this way, ‘the line between individual, voluntary
choice and socially enforced coercion becomes blurred’ Momentum of new technology
(p. 192). Kerr and Cunningham-Burley (2000) also argue
that reproductive choices are taking place within a Many staff felt that the technology of prenatal
narrowing context of increasing state and economically screening seemed to have taken on a momentum of its
driven surveillance on the one hand, and a declining own:
sense of collective responsibility for those who are sick
or defined as ‘other’. Lippman (1999) goes further, Health visitor, 56: yas long as we’re offering
stating that dominating economic values serve to antenatal screening, how long is it before another
reinforce new conceptions of normality and libertarian test gets added, and another test, and anothery?
self-reliance, without promoting true self-determination
and choice. Midwife, 2: yI’m not convinced thatFperhaps at
Thus, the concerns participants expressed about all, and certainly not on a regular basisFthat those
constraints on prenatal informed choices are not new, of us involved, those of us who provide this service,
but what is perhaps surprising is the fact that they were really ask ourselves why we’re doing it. It may be
voiced by practitioners. Much research concludes that different from place to place, but in my career as a
748 C. Williams et al. / Social Science & Medicine 55 (2002) 743–753

midwife, I’ve never heard a really ‘begin at the Consumerism


beginning’ discussion about the provision of antena-
tal screening in the same way that we have these Participants felt that the consumer driven society
discussions about the provision of other health care affected screening policies and options, with dominant
services. It feels to me like something that’s been sectors of the public expecting to be offered all available
dropped in and evolved, and that we haven’t really, information, services and options:
well, certainly, I haven’t been involved in really
Paediatrician, 59: ythe scientific knowledge is
serious discussions about, ‘what’s this really about?’
leaping away and will carry on advancing over and
A few participants envisaged the possibility of a above our capacity to make sustainable decisions
societal decision being taken to halt the process: about these thingsyand where the decision makers
of the day draw those lines will be partly consumer
Manager, 42: You know, as a society you could go led, because you have such a consumer orientated
backwards, we could decide that we’re not going to society.
provide screening for the entire pregnant population
Fit’s a decision that could be made.
Paediatrician, 58: The whole NHS is, the whole
However, the majority felt that the process was business of costing, genetics, drugs and all sorts of
unstoppable: things, is driven by public demand eventually, isn’t it?

Obstetrician, 11: The problem is how do we goFwe Most felt that consumer demand would continue to
can’t go back now. We’ve got here and we’ve got all drive the further expansion of prenatal screening
this information. programmes, possibly moving it on from selection to
avoid impairments towards the selection of children with
Health visitor, 56: The thing is, you can’t uninvent specific characteristics (Parens, 1998):
things.
Midwife, 46: It depends on their background and
how much they’ve read. You get women who want
A ‘culture of screening’
serum screening, they will want nuchal translucency,
they want every sort of screening test available to
Linked to the momentum of these technologies was
enable them to obviously make a choice and to have
the perceived importance of screening both in antenatal
a ‘perfect’ child.
care and in health care more generally:
Paediatrician, 58: ybecause that’s the road we’re all Obstetrician, 44: I certainly think expectations have
on, that screening is part of life isn’t it, or a certain gone up, they are very high, and they have gone up
amount of screening is part of life, and we just all for whatever they [consumers] envisage to be perfect.
accept it. Now, that may be disease free, it may actually go on
to be other thingsywe have people who actually
Midwife, 2: We’ve got into a situation where, you want to have a certain genderFthat’s their perfect
know, if the average midwife was asked what do they child.
believe, I would be surprised if the majority of
midwives here said, ‘‘let’s abandon the screening’’.
Restricted notions of ‘normality’
They have also been drawn into that culture.
Linked to the perception of growing consumer
Market competition demand were concerns about how changing concepts
of ‘normality’ might serve to expand the screening
Market competition was also expected to lead most process:
hospitals into wanting to adopt the latest screening
Psychologist, 22: I have to voice my worry here,
techniques, partly in order to retain expert staff:
something that troubles me, the issue about growing
Health visitor, 56: yare you going to say, well, at demand. If there is a society in which one can make
this hospital you can only have the basics, and if you an individual informed choice that you don’t want to
want anything more expensive you have got to go to have a baby with a minor abnormality, then over a
X Hospital? You get into a wheel, don’t you, and period of years we will see less and less babies with
everybody wants to be at the forefront of what’s abnormalities born on the wholeythen the social
going on, don’t they?yand then are all the experts pressure on those who are disabled will rise and rise,
going to want to go and work at X Hospital, to your and the stigma that will be attached to them will be
detriment? even greater. We create this world of perfect people
C. Williams et al. / Social Science & Medicine 55 (2002) 743–753 749

where the minor abnormality will be seen as a stigma, screening programme for? In some ways I feel they’re
as a very bad thingy. being led by economics.

Manager, 53: The other thing to think about is, is it


‘Disposable culture’
cheaper actually to invest in screening and therefore
treatingFwhatever you take to be treatingFthan
The recognition, that with the current lack of
actually dealing with something afterwards and the
available treatment for many foetal impairments a key
longterm cost implications?
outcome of prenatal screening is termination of preg-
nancy, led to reflections on a modern ‘disposable Screening for Down’s syndrome was picked out as
culture’: being seen as particularly economically advantageous by
the state:
Health visitor, 56: But we are becoming a society like
that aren’t we? If the washing machine breaks down Obstetrician, 70: I think for Down’s syndrome
it’s cheaper to get a new one than it is to have the old everything started from the government, because if
one repaired, and it’s a continuation of that. you go back, the whole screening for chromosomal
abnormalities was Down’s syndrome, because they
live and they are expensive for the government, so I
Litigation
think the emphasis was given to that, and this was the
only reason, because they are more common than
The threat of litigation if foetal conditions were not
other abnormalities, they can live for 40 years, and
identified was also seen as a powerful factor aiding the
they are expensive for the government so it was more
expansion of prenatal screening:
profitable for the government to terminate those
Midwife, 51: And legally, if you don’t offer it where pregnancies than to support those pregnancies.
do you stand, if those tests and things are available
but you don’t offer it?
Discussion
Haematologist, 28: ..there have been a number of
successful claims for wrongful births arising out of a The research appeared to highlight a paradox. On the
failure to identify genetic riskFthe haemoglobin one hand, many participants doubted that informed
disorders specificallyFand so in a sense that dictates choice could be achieved, although they saw it as both
one aspect of our stance on screening. an essential feature of, and a key reason for prenatal
screening. On the other hand, despite these concerns,
Economic ‘solution’ most saw the expansion of prenatal screening, which
could further compromise informed choice, as an
Some participants felt that prenatal screening could inevitable and uncontrollable process. Kerr et al.
be seen as a convenient economic ‘solution’ to the (1998b) state that ‘a narrow and privileged group’ of
‘problem’ of disability by the state, as a cheaper option individuals are making decisions about genetics, includ-
than providing suppport for disabled people. They felt ing prenatal screening programmes. However, the
that women would have increased options to continue majority of participants in our study, many of whom
with their pregnancy, if they could be assured of such decided, managed or implemented antenatal policies in
support networks: their hospitals, felt that they had little control over
prenatal screening expansions, and that they did not
Midwife, 47: ...screenings have their purpose, but at belong to this ‘narrow group’. The discussion will firstly
the end of the day, what are we really trying to address the factors which staff themselves identified as
sayF‘‘OK, your baby is not normal, not really combining to bring the expansion about. It will then
accepted in this sort of society that we are living in, move on to discuss more generally the ways in which the
we can terminate it’’. I think it goes a bit deeper than expansion of new technologies can appear as inexorable
just saying, ‘‘we are looking after your wellbeing’’. to those involved.
Are we looking after your wellbeing or are we
looking down the line of how much is this going to Factors identified by participants
cost?
Our research indicates that despite the fact that many
Manager, 67: I think if the screening programme is participants recognised their power within individual
really for people then the support networks should be situations, they felt they had limited agency, being
there. So your question comes up again, who is the mainly reactive, rather than proactive. They perceived
750 C. Williams et al. / Social Science & Medicine 55 (2002) 743–753

powerful forces which they felt were combining to discourse (Lippman, 1999; Kerr & Cunningham-Burley,
promote the rapid expansion of screening techniques, 2000). Participants identified factors within this dis-
but perceived many of these forces to be outside their course which they felt were serving to expand prenatal
control. Describing how prenatal screening could be screening. These include market competition between
seen by the state as an economic solution to the hospitals, and, as in the United States, the threat of
‘problem’ of disability, some staff recognised that within litigation was seen to be an increasingly important factor
the centralised British National Health Service system, promoting prenatal screening (Press & Browner, 1997).
options and ‘choices’ could be ruled out from above by Understandably, staff were reluctant to argue against
those within the Department of Health who shape individual consumer choice, as this links so closely with
policy, supporting Kerr et al.’s (1998b) notion of a arguing against individual rights (Chadwick, 1999). It
‘narrow and privileged’, and it seems, unknown (to also goes against the ‘nondirective’ ethos which remains
those on the ground) group of individuals. The idea that a key feature of genetic counselling (Clarke, 1997).
the technology seemed to have a momentum of its own Serious concerns were expressed during the groups
echoes the work of Brown, Rappert, and Webster about what the eventual impact of individual consumer
(2000), who draw attention to the ways in which agency choice might be for wider society, including increased
may be attributed to actual technologies, so that they are stigma for disabled people, and the notion of the
seen to be developing ‘naturally along identifiable lines’, provisional, expendable pregnancy subject to quality
as their ‘‘‘self-evident’ benefits are taken up by users’’ (p. control on the basis of its future potential (Rothman,
9). One powerful consequence is that any questioning 1988). The concerns expressed by participants about the
about whether a particular option should be taken up emphasis on the ‘perfect baby’ have been highlighted by
disappears, to be replaced simply by questions about those who argue that the changes in prenatal screening
when it will come about. They state that in this situation: and testing may be altering the relationship between the
pregnant woman, her foetus, and the social world
human agency becomes reduced to engaging in (Rapp, 1999). Dumit and Davis-Floyd (2000) state that
behaviour to ensure the speedy uptake of particular the combination of technocratic emphasis on the baby-
technological possibilities. The force implied in this as-product and the development of new technologies to
attribution of agency is that one can either ride the assess foetal quality has led to a strong focus on the
wave of advancement or drown in the waves of production of ‘the perfect baby’, with pregnant women
progress (p. 9). being described as ‘genetic gatekeepers’ (Rapp, 1999).
Indeed, the phrase ‘perfect baby’ was used by some
The culture of screening was also identified by participants as if it was an unproblematic term. Some
participants as a force which promotes prenatal screen- staff perceived there to be little sense of collective
ing. Pregnancy is being seen increasingly as an ‘at risk’ responsibility for disabled people within society, which
time, with every pregnant woman being offered a they felt affected the choices of women (Lippman, 1999;
growing number of screening possibilities (Petersen, Kerr & Cunningham-Burley, 2000). As Rose (2000)
1999). As Beck-Gernshein (1995) observes, the over- points out, ‘choice’ must be contextualised, so for
riding principle of ‘informed choice’ means that practi- example, if women live in a society perceived as hostile
tioners are duty bound to point out the options to all to the needs of disabled people, their choices may be
women, so that even women who choose deliberately to constrained. However, it should be pointed out that our
avoid screening cannot do so until they have thought research only explored the views of health care staff, not
through the process. In the antenatal setting, the links those of women, nor the actual local services available.
between being responsible and being a ‘good’ mother
have long been recognised as very powerful, with blame
being attributed to women who fail to act in what is Acceptance and expansion of innovative technologies
deemed an appropriate manner (Ehrenreich & English,
1978; Oakley, 1984). Many practitioners felt that, The discussion will now focus on two key pieces of
particularly in the antenatal setting, the offer of a research which explore the ways in which similar
screening test could be seen as a recommendation which innovative technologies gainedFor are gainingFaccep-
compromised free and informed choice (Press & tance, in an attempt to explain further why, despite their
Browner, 1997). As practitioners recognised, these reservations, practitioners seemed to view further rapid
constraints need to be set within more general trends expansion of screening technologies as inexorable.
in Western society including the current individualised Whilst the first study by Press and Browner (1997),
focus on screening and preventive medicine (Beck, explores in detail how actual patient choices to accept
1992). and use the innovation of maternal serum alpha
The powerful rhetoric of individual choice and foetoprotein test (MSAFP) came about in California,
personal responsibility is set firmly within a consumer the work of Beck-Gernshein (2000) looks more broadly
C. Williams et al. / Social Science & Medicine 55 (2002) 743–753 751

at the factors she considers essential for ‘paving Beck-Gernshein (2000) then focuses on the ways in
the road’ for the acceptance of innovative technologies. which the concept of responsibility has been adapted to
Press and Browner (1997) extended McKinlay’s (1982) the new options of reproductive medicine and prenatal
model of how medical innovations come to be routinised, diagnosis, in that it now refers to prenatal qualitative
arguing that one of the key reasons MSAFP testing selection. The words used, such as prevention, link, ‘to
acceptance was achieved was because the new test was goals which are widely accepted because they serve the
absorbed ‘under the rubric’ of previous, noncontraversial interests of the individual (maintaining health, avoiding
routine prenatal care. Once it had been accepted as a pain) as well as the interests of society (cost saving)’ (p.
routine part of prenatal care, it was seen by women to 131). However, she argues that a change of attitudes is
convey the advantages associated with such care, occurring, posing the question, ‘Do ethics in the age of
including information, reassurance and the prevention genetics mean that avoiding the birth of a handicapped
of maternal and foetal harm. This then led to consumer child becomes the obligation of today’s responsible
demand, reinforcing the ‘need’ for the service. Press and citizen?’ Beck-Gernshein believes that there are signs
Browner (1997) state that although MSAFP was initially that this is the case, with blame being attachedFsome-
introduced specifically to detect neural tube defects, AFP times in subtle waysFto those who do not act
was soon identified as a marker of a much wider range of ‘responsibly’. As she states,
foetal health problems than was anticipated, and these
expanded uses also became rapidly incorporated into the freedom of choice is proclaimed as a basic right, with
screening process. Kerr and Cunningham-Burley (2000) a great deal of goodwill and good intentionsybut on
recognise this normalisation process, stating that, ‘where the other hand, there is the momentum of technol-
new tests fit old paradigms, uptake is higher and ogy, and in gradual stepsFalbeit at first hardly
concerns are more muted’ (p. 289). In addition, the noticeableFthe concept of responsibility changes its
recent HTA Review (Bricker et al., 2000) of ultrasound content; it is being expanded and adapted along with
screening in pregnancy comments how, rather than being the increasing options of technology (p. 132).
strategically introduced, antenatal screening programmes
tend to ‘creep’ in (p. 82). This subtle but rapid process of In adddition, although very few practitioners men-
incorporation, routinisation and consequent consumer tioned it as a factor, the possibility of screening and
demand may be one reason why Midwife 2 claimed that genetics research becoming increasingly influenced by
she had ‘‘never heard a really ‘begin at the beginning’ corporate and commercial interests should not be
discussion about the provision of antenatal screening’’, ignored (Rose, 2000; Kaufert, 2000).
but instead had a sense that it had ‘‘been dropped in and The work of Press and Browner (1997) and Beck-
evolved’’. Gernshein (2000) illustrate many of the subtle factors
In the second study, Beck-Gernshein (2000) argues which may promote the acceptance of innovative
that in relation to genome analysis, two major values of technologies and help to explain why, apart from the
modern society, the concepts of health and responsi- reasons that participants identified as important, the
bility, act as cultural prerequisites, helping to create process might appear as uncontrollable to them, despite
cultural acceptance of the technology. Then, in a spiral their concerns. Lock (1998) believes that perhaps
shaped social process, through the spread of genome because of their focus on the clinical encounter, social
analysis, the very values of health and responsibility are scientists have tended to create an oversimplified picture
altered. She states that the introduction of a new of physician dominance. In relation to prenatal screen-
technology requires a bridgehead in the social system, ing, it appears that a complex pattern of wider cross
as the basis for expansion. In the case of genome currents emerges, involving criss-crossing trends and
analysis, partial acceptance stems from linking it to the counter-trends, both internal and external to medicine
importance of health, and in this way, ‘obstacles are itself (Williams, 2001). Whilst women attending for
pushed aside, doubts are allayed, critics are silenced (or screening might assume that staff have made a deliberate
fall silent of their own accord’ (p. 126). With the growing and expert decision to offer specific screening policies
acceptance and use of gene technology, the concept of within the context of informed choice, and have devised
health itself then changes and expands, ‘gradually, strategies to ensure that this happens, it appears that, for
silently, but nonetheless radical in its results’, leading a variety of reasons, this may not always be the case.
to rising expectations. Beck-Gernshein points out how Within group discussions facilitated by the ethicist,
easily preventive health measures gain legitimacy and participants felt able to express their concerns about
rationality, not by direct compulsion, nor a voluntary prenatal screening, which are similar to those high-
act, but by something in between which she calls lighted by members of the general public (Kerr et al.,
‘voluntary compulsion’. This exerts a subtle pressure 1998b). Unlike the professionals interviewed by Kerr
which is arguably even more powerful than overt et al. (1998a), many of our participants recognised the
compulsion (Lukes, 1974). complex factors mitigating against informed choice. It
752 C. Williams et al. / Social Science & Medicine 55 (2002) 743–753

appears that these technologies are confronting health Alderson, P., Aro, A., Dragonas, T., Ettorre, E., Hemminki, E.,
care staff with dilemmas, but many said that this was Jalonija, P., Santalahti, P., & Tymstra, T. (2001). Prenatal
their first opportunity to discuss these issues in any screening and genetics. European Journal of Public Health,
depth with others (Williams et al., 2001). The impor- 11, 231–233.
tance of debate about medical and scientific innovations Armstrong, D. (1995). The rise of surveillance medicine.
Sociology of Health and Illness, 17, 393–404.
has long been supported. For example, in its 1995
Beauchamp, T., & Childress, J. (1989). Principles of biomedical
report, ‘Human Genetics’, The House of Commons ethics (3rd ed.). New York: Oxford University Press.
Science and Technology Select Committee stated: Beck, U. (1992). Risk society: Towards a new modernity.
London: Sage.
The dilemmas that genetics poses will be resolved by Beck-Gernshein, E. (2000). Health and responsibility: From
the public and parliamentary debate, not by aca- social change to technological change and vice versa. In B.
demics alone. But that debate must be well informed, Adam, U. Beck, & J. Van Loon (Eds.), The risk society and
both about the science itself and about its ethical, beyond (pp. 63–77). London: Sage.
legal and social implications. Beck-Gernshein, E. (1995). The Social Implications of Bioengi-
neering. NJ: Humanities Press.
Although we make no claims for our participants Bricker, L., Garcia, J., Henderson, J., Mugford, M., Neilson, J.,
being ‘representative’, our research took place in two Robers, T., et al. (2000). Ultrasound screening in pregnancy:
very different hospitals, and it seems likely that the lack A systematic review of the clinical effectiveness, cost-
of opportunities for debate is common, even amongst effectiveness and women’s views. Health Technology Assess
staff directly involved in offering and implementing 4 (16).
Brown, N., Rappert, B., & Webster, A. (2000). Introducing
prenatal screening programmes. The importance of
contested futures: From looking into the future to looking
including a full diversity of views in order to achieve
at the future. In N. Brown, B. Rappert, & A. Webster
more accountable and sophisticated policy making has (Eds.), Contested futures: A sociology of prospective techno-
been persistently called for (e.g. Kerr et al., 1998a). science (pp. 3–20). Aldershot: Ashgate.
However, the ongoing lack of inclusive public demo- Chadwick, R. (1999). Genetics, choice and responsibility.
cratic debate has been highlighted (Shakespeare, 1999), Health, Risk and Society, 1, 293–300.
as has the enduring notion that the ‘public’ need only to Charmaz, K. (1983). The grounded theory method: An
be educated about science, rather than their expertise explication and interpretation. In R. Emerson (Ed.),
being drawn on to inform debate about what directions Contemporary field research: A collection of readings (pp.
science should or should not be taking (Rose, 2000). 109–126). Prospect Heights, Ill: Waveland Press.
Clarke, A. (1997). The process of genetic counselling. In P.
Without this inclusive dialogue and debate, even the
Harper, & A. Clarke (Eds.), Genetics, society and clinical
more seemingly straightforward aspects of informed
practice (pp. 179–200). Oxford: BIOS Scientific Publishers.
choice such as the information to be given about Department of Health (2000). Second Report of the UK
screened for conditions will be impossible to address, National Screening Committee. Department of Health,
let alone the complexities of issues such as the advance London.
of DNA diagnostics. In conclusion, this paper adds to Dumit, J., & Davis-Floyd, R. (2000). Children of the third
the calls for inclusive, integrated and collaborative millenium. In R. Davis-Floyd, & J. Dumit (Eds.), Cyborg
debate and research. This is to ensure that as far as babies (pp. 1–20). New York: Routledge.
possible the wider consequences and implications of Ehrenreich, B., & English, D. (1978). For her own good: 150 years
prenatal screening technologiesFboth the promises and of experts’ advice to women. New York: Anchor Books.
Ettorre, E. (1999). Experts as storytellers in reproductive
the potential side-effectsFare debated ahead of their
genetics: Exploring key issues. Sociology of Health and
implementation, and also to help ensure that public
Illness, 21, 539–559.
policy represents and serves contemporary society. Green, J. (1994). Serum screening for Downs syndrome:
Experiences of obstetricians in England and Wales. British
Acknowledgements Medical Journal, 318, 769–772.
Hallowell, N. (1999). Doing the right thing: Genetic risk and
responsibility. Sociology of Health and Illness, 21, 597–621.
We are very grateful to everyone who participated in
Kaufert, P. (2000). Screening the body: The pap smear and the
this research, and to The Wellcome Trust Biomedical mammogram. In M. Lock, A. Young, & A. Cambrosio
Ethics programme for funding the project (No. 056009). (Eds.), Living and Working with the New Medical Technol-
ogies (pp. 165–183). Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
References Kerr, A., & Cunningham-Burley, S. (2000). On ambivalence
and risk: Reflexive modernity and the new human genetics.
Abramsky, L., Hall, S., Levitan, J., & Marteau, T. (2001). What
Sociology, 34, 283–304.
parents are told after prenatal diagnosis of a sex chromo-
Kerr, A., Cunningham-Burley, S., & Amos, A. (1998a).
some abnormality: Interview and questionnaire study.
Eugenics and the new genetics in Britain: Examining
British Medical Journal, 322, 463–466.
C. Williams et al. / Social Science & Medicine 55 (2002) 743–753 753

contemporary professionals’ accounts. Science, Technology Petersen, A. (1999). Counselling the genetically at risk: The
and Human Values, 23, 175–198. poetics and politics of non-directiveness. Health, Risk and
Kerr, A., Cunningham-Burley, S., & Amos, A. (1998b). Society, 1, 253–265.
Drawing the line: An analysis of lay people’s discussions Press, N., & Browner, C. (1997). Why women say yes to
about the new genetics. Public Understanding of Science, 7, prenatal diagnosis. Social Science and Medicine, 45, 979–
113–133. 989.
Lippman, A. (1999). Choice as a risk to women’s health. Rapp, R. (1999). Testing women, testing the fetus. New York:
Health, Risk and Society, 1, 281–292. Routledge.
Lock, M. (1998). Perfecting society: The planned family in Rose, H. (2000). Risk, trust and scepticism in the age of the new
Japan. In M. Lock, & P. Kaufert (Eds.), Pragmatic women genetics. In B. Adam, U. Beck, & J. Van Loon (Eds.), The
and body politics (pp. 206–239). Cambridge: Cambridge risk society and beyond (pp. 63–77). London: Sage.
University Press. Rothman, B. (1988). The tentative pregnancy: Prenatal diagnosis
Lofland, J., & Lofland, L. (1984). Analyzing social settings: A and the future of motherhood. London: Pandora Press.
guide to qualitative observation and analysis. Belmont, CA: Shakespeare, T. (1999). Losing the plot? Medical and activist
Wadsworth. discourses of contemporary genetics and disability. Sociol-
Lukes, S. (1974). Power: A radical view. London: Macmillan ogy of Health and Illness, 21, 669–688.
Press. Simpson, W., Johnstone, F., & Boyd, F., et al. (1998). Uptake
McKinlay, J. (1982). From ‘‘promising report’’ to ‘‘standard and acceptability of antenatal HIV testing: Randomised
procedure’’: Seven stages in the career of a medical controlled trial of different methods of offering the test.
innovation. In J. Milbank, Technology and the future of British Medical Journal, 316, 262–267.
health care, Milbank Reader, Vol. 8 (pp. 233–270). Cam- Strauss, A., & Corbin, J. (1990). Basics of qualitative research.
bridge, MA: MIT Press. London: Sage.
Oakley, A. (1984). The captured womb. Oxford: Blackwell. Weber, R. (1990). Basic content analysis. London: Sage.
Parens, E. (1998). Enhancing human traits: Ethical and social Williams, S. (2001). Sociological imperialism and the profession
implications. Washington, DC: Georgetown University of medicine revisited: Where are we now? Sociology of
Press. Health and Illness, 23, 135–158.
Parker, M. (2000). Public deliberation and private choice in Williams, C., Alderson, P., & Farsides, B. (2001). Is nondirec-
genetics and reproduction. Journal of Medical Ethics, 26, tiveness possible within the context of antenatal screening
160–165. and testing? Social Science and Medicine, in press.

You might also like