You are on page 1of 10

FORUM – PHENOMENOLOGICAL AND NEUROCOGNITIVE PERSPECTIVES ON

DELUSIONS

Phenomenological and neurocognitive perspectives


on delusions: a critical overview
LOUIS SASS, GREG BYROM
Department of Clinical Psychology, Graduate School of Applied and Professional Psychology, Rutgers University, 152 Frelinghuysen Rd., Piscataway, NJ 08854-
8020, USA

There is considerable overlap between phenomenological and neurocognitive perspectives on delusions. In this paper, we first review major
phenomenological accounts of delusions, beginning with Jaspers’ ideas regarding incomprehensibility, delusional mood, and disturbed “cogito”
(basic, minimal, or core self-experience) in what he termed “delusion proper” in schizophrenia. Then we discuss later studies of decon-
textualization and delusional mood by Matussek, changes in self and world in delusion formation according to Conrad’s notions of
“apophany” and “anastrophe”, and the implications of ontological transformations in the felt sense of reality in some delusions. Next we con-
sider consistencies between: a) phenomenological models stressing minimal-self (ipseity) disturbance and hyperreflexivity in schizophrenia, and
b) recent neurocognitive models of delusions emphasizing salience dysregulation and prediction error. We voice reservations about homogeniz-
ing tendencies in neurocognitive explanations of delusions (the “paranoia paradigm”), given experiential variations in states of delusion. In par-
ticular we consider shortcomings of assuming that delusions necessarily or always involve “mistaken beliefs” concerning objective facts about
the world. Finally, we offer some suggestions regarding possible neurocognitive factors. Current models that stress hypersalience (banal stimuli
experienced as strange) might benefit from considering the potential role of hyposalience in delusion formation. Hyposalience – associated with
experiencing the strange as if it were banal, and perhaps with activation of the default mode network – may underlie a kind of delusional dere-
alization and an “anything goes” attitude. Such an attitude would be conducive to delusion formation, yet differs significantly from the hypersa-
lience emphasized in current neurocognitive theories.

Key words: Delusions, schizophrenia, phenomenological psychopathology, neurocognitive models, salience dysregulation, prediction error,
self-disorder, delusional mood

(World Psychiatry 2015;14:164–173)

THE PHENOMENOLOGICAL Phenomenology is acutely sensitive to with semi-structured formats (10) ca-
APPROACH TO DELUSIONS the potential variety of orientations a pable of illuminating how behavioral
“deluded” patient might have. Also, it signs and symptoms are reflective of
The phenomenological approach fo- stresses that delusions may defy ready “alterations of the structures of experi-
cuses on delusion as a phenomenon, comprehension or empathy by normal encing” (11, p. 546).
on its subjective or lived dimension: individuals, since they sometimes involve
what it is like to have a delusion. A cru- radical changes in grounding structures
cial feature of phenomenological psy- and assumptions of human experience. Jaspers and “delusion proper”
chopathology is its emphasis on the Schizophrenia patients are often aware
mode, manner, or form of the experi- of the difficulty of conveying their experi- The formulation of delusions offered
ence in question (1,2). The content of ences and the likelihood of being misun- by K. Jaspers, the father of phenomeno-
an experience, and the supposedly derstood (8). D.P. Schreber, the schizo- logical psychopathology, set the agenda
erroneous nature of beliefs presumably phrenia patient (of a grandiose paranoid for much subsequent psychiatric theory
asserted or assumed by the patient, are sort) who is perhaps the most famous and investigation. Unlike contemporary
less important than how the delusional delusional patient of all time, spoke of uses of the term, in which “delusion”
world seems to be experienced and matters that “lack all analogies in human applies to aberrant beliefs in schizo-
what sort of reality or existence the experience and which I appreciated phrenic, paranoid, manic, psychotically
patient might ascribe to it. directly only in part with my mind’s eye” depressive, and organic conditions, Jas-
Heidegger (3) referred to the latter (9, p. 123). “To make myself at least pers considered “delusion proper” or
dimensions of existence as “ontolo- somewhat comprehensible I shall have “primary delusion” (1, pp. 95,98) (also
gical”, and distinguished them from to speak much in images and similes, known as “true” delusion) to be charac-
object-oriented (what he called “ontic”) which may at times perhaps be only teristic of schizophrenia.
modes of understanding experience. approximately correct” (9, p. 2). “True” delusions could, thought Jas-
Delusions often involve a mutation in Recognizing this diversity and this pers, be distinguished from delusion-
the ontological framework of experience difficulty in communication and com- like ideas, because the latter could be
that can alter the overall sense of ex- prehension suggests the need for in- understood within the context of under-
istence and the world, including changes depth, qualitative exploration of the lying personality or as exaggerations of
in felt reality-status, time, space, and patient’s experiences. This requires normal emotions and affects. True delu-
self-experience (4-7). replacing typical structured interviews sions – which involve conviction, cer-

164 World Psychiatry 14:2 - June 2015


tainty, imperviousness, and impossi- concerns the experienced reality-status patient stared at a swinging cord of a
bility as (merely) associated features – of the delusional beliefs or quasi-beliefs light-switch so intently that, after a
require learning about “the primary (i.e., the degree or kind of reality that time, he came to feel that not the cord
experience traceable to the illness” (1, the delusional world is experienced but the wall and background were mov-
p. 96), of which the apparently incor- as having). ing back and forth; this led, in turn, to
rect judgment is a secondary product. Delusions may help to make a kind the thought that the world was coming
For Jaspers, primary or true delusion of rational sense out of what would oth- to an end (17, p. 93).
involves a direct and unmediated expe- erwise be felt as disturbing, and other- Matussek stresses decontextualiza-
rience that is un-understandable in wise inexplicable, changes in the very tion and framing of isolated features
light of previous experiences or beliefs. foundations of the experiential world – for “apperception of delusional signifi-
It is rooted in some indescribable alter- i.e., out of the torturous sense of things cance” (17, p. 94) and generation of
ation of personality (in the sense of a seeming “just so” (disconcertingly spe- delusional beliefs. The very salience or
structural basis for subjectivity) or cific or precise) or bristling with strange, framing of particular items may suggest
mode of consciousness of the patient: cosmic, intentional significance (15, p. that something of particular impor-
“a transformation in [one’s] total 61), or of the disconcerting experiences tance or “weighting” is being indicated,
awareness of reality” (1, p. 95) that of losing one’s sense of self or of living conveying an aura of intensified “sym-
remains “largely incomprehensible. . . in a shared and objective world. bolic content” (17, p. 95). Dis-embed-
and beyond our understanding” (1, p. Among the many interesting phenom- ding and a certain derealization can
98). This primarily distinguishes it enologically-oriented theorists in Jaspers’ also allow these emerging significances
from “normal belief”, “overvalued wake who wrote on delusions (these to link up more easily with other, iso-
idea”, and “delusion-like idea” (the lat- include Minkowski, Binswanger, Ey, lated features or meanings floating out-
ter found in other “psychotic” condi- Ru € mke, among others (6,14,16)) are side any standard or practical context,
tions as well as in schizophrenia). P. Matussek and K. Conrad, psychia- and perhaps also separated from nor-
Most subsequent phenomenological trists who brought phenomenology mal sorts of reality-claims. “One is
investigations have followed Jaspers’ together with Gestalt psychology. much clearer about the relatedness of
lead by focusing on delusion in schizo- things, because one can overlook the
phrenia, especially on three types of factuality of things. They don’t exist
global change that contribute to the dis- Matussek: decontextualization so one has nothing to do with them”
tinctive “incomprehensibility”: delusion- (17, p. 96), said one patient, who
al mood; disturbance of basic, minimal, Matussek described a “loosening of reported special, revelatory access to
or core self; and certain alterations in the natural perceptual context” (17, p. meanings ignored by others and stat-
the apparent reality-status of delusional 90) that allows “individual perceptual ed: “my ability to see connections had
beliefs. components” to float free of standard been multiplied many times over”.
Jaspers suggested that delusions and anchoring in commonsense unities or
delusional perceptions often arise out scenes; this, in turn, opens the way to
of feelings of unidentified significance attributions of exaggerated or peculiar Conrad: apophany and anastrophe
(12). Occurring most notably in schizo- significance and a bringing-together of
phrenia, this psychological state in- isolated elements into relationships of K. Conrad (18) offers a compelling
volves feelings of strangeness and delusional meaning that may be kalei- account of global alterations in delu-
tension and of suggestive yet ineffable doscopic but can become rigidified. sional mood. He refers to the first stage
meaning: “perception is unaltered in The delusional significance is typically of delusion formation as the trema –
itself but there is some change which “experienced directly as inherent in theatrical jargon referring to stagefright
envelops everything with a subtle, the object” (17, p. 98), as if rooted in before the play begins. The patient
pervasive and strangely uncertain sensory perception. senses that something is in the offing.
light” (1, p. 98). The second feature Matussek describes a distinctive com- Most commonly he feels a sense of
involves mutations of basic self-expe- bination of passivity with activity. The threat and associated anxiety, depres-
rience: “The individual, though he patient experiences a rigid gaze, feeling sion, inhibition, or indecisiveness (18,
exists, is no longer able to feel he exists. “held captive” (17, p. 94) by the object pp. 93,105); there may also be anticipa-
Descartes’ cogito ergo sum (I think or objects. Yet he also has an exaggerat- tory excitement, exaltation, manic-like
therefore I am) may still be superficial- ed “ability” to “focus his attention on euphoria. Despite some difficulties with
ly cogitated but it is no longer a valid such isolated details” (17, p. 93) and concentration, there is no clouding of
experience” (1, pp. 122,578; see also may indeed take “pleasure” in this consciousness, but hyper-vigilance,
13,14). The third feature of “delusion “fixing [of] attention” (17, p. 94), there- feelings of being hyper-awake (18,
proper” (1, p. 95) or of schizophrenic “in- by further transforming the perceptual pp. 230,249).
comprehensibility” (less explicitly stat- field via a “prolonged gazing” difficult What typically ensues in this delu-
ed by Jaspers: see 1, pp. 95,99,105,106) for normal individuals to sustain. One sional or pre-delusional mood is the

165
apophany. “Apophany” comes from a sense of existing as a unified and vital peculiarly inconsequent at times. . .
Greek word meaning “to become visi- subject of experience), with two com- Belief in reality can range through all
ble or apparent”; it refers to an abnor- plementary facets: hyperreflexivity and degrees, from a mere play with possi-
mal, sometimes excruciating sense of diminished self-affection – also associ- bilities via a double reality – the empiri-
meaningfulness – tantalizing but typi- ated with disturbance in cognitive/per- cal and the delusional – to unequivocal
cally unidentifiable – that can affect ceptual “grip” or “hold” on the external attitudes in which the delusional con-
“internal” (body, stream of conscious- world (20-22). “Hyperreflexivity” de- tent reigns as the sole and absolute
ness) as well as “external space”. The scribes how experiences normally tacit reality” (1, pp. 105-106).
patient attributes these changes to the emerge into focal awareness, where But even when delusions reign as
external world and searches for clues they are experienced as objects separate “sole and absolute”, it is not clear that
to render the new unpredictable changes from self-as-subject, whereas diminish- they are necessarily experienced within
more comprehensible. ed self-affection (also termed diminish- the “natural attitude” – the common-
Often the patient experiences the ed self-presence) describes decreased sense orientation that takes objects
world as somehow false, inauthentic, sense of existing as an experiencing and persons as objectively real and
or insinuating, and as referring some- consciousness or lived body. intersubjectively available (2,25). It is
how to himself: “I have the feeling that Self-disturbance “destabilize[s] the noteworthy that patients who claim
everything turns around me” (18, p. natural ontological attitude and may absolute confidence in their delusion,
161). Conrad uses the term anastrophe throw the patient into a new onto- may nevertheless not act on its basis.
(literally: turning-back or turning- logical-existential perspective, an often Schreber, for example, often does not
inward) to capture this self-referential, solipsistic framework, no longer ruled make claims about the external or
introversive, or self-observing quality – by the ‘natural’ certitudes concerning interpersonally shared world, claims
what could be termed a form of space, time, causality, and noncon- that could be supported or refuted by
“hyper-reflexivity” (15). tradiction” (11, p. 544), thereby facili- evidence independent of the experi-
Apophany and anastrophe are two tating experiences of the world as ence itself. His delusional beliefs are
sides of a coin. Changes in perceived staged or mind-dependent, and a gran- frequently described in a way that gives
environment (e.g., sense of things being diose sense of gaining access to deeper them a coefficient of subjectivity – as
oddly significant, false, or planned) layers of reality. Although self-distur- when he speaks of appreciating his
elicit reflection and inhibit spontane- bances involve atmospheric and cate- psychotic experiences “only in part
ous engaged activity; yet these changes gorically subjective qualities, there is with my mind’s eye” or “inner eye” (9,
themselves can only occur in the pres- growing evidence that they can be pp. 110,123,136,157,234,235,312). At
ence of a veritable “spasm of reflexion” meaningfully measured, thereby bridg- times he even makes the solipsistic or
(18, pp. 167,199). ing phenomenology and scientific de- quasi-divine claim that “seeing” –
Conrad describes progression from mands for reliable measurement (23,24). awareness itself – is “confined to my
subtle to blatant alterations of inner person and immediate surroundings”
space (“inner apophany”) that occur (9, p. 322).
during anastrophe. The inward focus- Reality-testing and quasi-solipsism If the delusion is believed in the con-
ing actually has an externalizing effect, text of something like a (subjectively
transforming proprioceptive sensations With its sensitivity to kinds of reality experienced) natural attitude, one ought
or internal mental threads into some- subjectively felt or ascribed within to act in relation to that belief. But if the
thing felt as distanced and alien delusion, phenomenology is cautious delusion is felt to be true only for me, in
(15,19). An intriguing example is de- about assuming that delusions are my mind’s eye and for me alone (or, at
scribed in a classic article by Tausk “false beliefs” about external reality. least, only for me and my delusional
and later discussed by Sass as exempli- Phenomenologists question the gener- others), the contradiction is resolved:
fying hyperreflexivity (15): the patient al applicability of the standard “poor- one need hardly seek evidence for an
Natalija’s illness began with mild expe- reality-testing” formula assumed in experience (akin, in some respects, to
riences of estrangement from herself DSM-IV, DSM-5, ICD-10, and much an imaginary realm) that makes no
and culminated in a full-blown delu- of psychiatry. claim with regard to normal intersubjec-
sion regarding a distant “influencing Jaspers remarked on “the specific tive reality; one will hardly take action
machine” that determined her every schizophrenic incorrigibility” of (true) in actuality with regard to what one
thought, sensation, and movement; it delusions, and their peculiar tendency senses as existing in a purely or quasi-
crystallized the apophany of her inner to be associated with irrelevance for virtual realm.
space under conditions of “reflexive action (“inconsequentiality”): “Reality This provides a phenomenological
spasm”. for [the patient] does not always carry way of accounting for at least some
These mutations have been formu- the same meaning as that of normal instances of the famous “double book-
lated recently as an alteration of mini- reality. . . Hence the attitude of the keeping” of which Bleuler (26) spoke.
mal or core self or ipseity (the basic patient to the content of his delusion is The very unreality of the delusional

166 World Psychiatry 14:2 - June 2015


world may, in fact, be the feature that with later consideration of efforts to tancies (“empirical prior beliefs” (33, p.
most recommends it, perhaps provid- relate the concept of the default mode 347)) in unrealistic, dysfunctional, often
ing, in some instances, the deepest to schizophrenia and delusions (34-36). delusional directions, because of the
motivation for dwelling in the delu- We consider three, somewhat over- distorting influence of input that should
sional realm – as Sartre suggests of lapping, issues: a) the consistency – have been filtered out as irrelevant or
the “morbid dreamer” who thereby within certain limits – between phe- inconsequential (as mere noise) and the
escapes the anxieties and demands of nomenological perspectives and the attempt to understand the anomalous ex-
real-world experience (15,27,28). prediction error and salience dysregula- perience. Because “the errors are false”
tion models; b) the problematic tenden- (32, p. 55), no amount of associated
cy of contemporary neurocognitive (as updating of beliefs can ever adequate-
Summary well as cognitive-behavioral) accounts ly model the world; hence “prediction
to adopt an overly homogenizing and errors will be propagated even further
The phenomenological approach has insufficiently “ontological” perspective up the system to ever-higher levels of
focused almost exclusively on delusions on “delusion”; c) some ways phenome- abstraction”. Dysfunctions in the meso-
in schizophrenia, which (contrary to nology might broaden the contempo- corticolimbic dopamine system, right
current usage) are sometimes under- rary neurocognitive vision, expanding prefrontal cortex, and glutamate trans-
stood to be the only “true delusions”. the range of testable hypotheses. Given mission may underlie these dynamic
Phenomenological accounts of delu- phenomenology’s focus on delusions in processes.
sional mood/atmosphere discuss loos- schizophrenia, we mostly deal with that Corlett et al’s (33) prediction error
ening of perceptual context, promiscuous particular syndrome or disorder. formulation offers a rich and stimulat-
linkages between de-contextualized ing neurobiological account. They aim
elements, a sense of being at the cen- to provide a comprehensive and unify-
ter of things, and alienating hyper- Compatibility of phenomenology ing framework, postulating “a singular
reflexivity. with prediction error and salience dysfunction” (33, p. 361), or “single fac-
Such a perspective helps to clarify dysregulation accounts tor, prediction error dysfunction for
how paranoid, metaphysical, influence- delusion formation and maintenance”,
related, bodily, and solipsistic delusions The prediction error model assumes underlying all delusions, across diag-
– together with altered experience of that principles of Bayesian inference nostic groups – a view consistent with a
self, intersubjectivity, and felt reality – (method whereby probability estimates “complaint-oriented approach” (38, p.
might develop on the basis of overall are continuously updated as additional 221) and the U.S. National Institute of
structural or ontological changes asso- evidence is acquired) play a crucial Mental Health’s initiatives to focus on
ciated with delusional mood and its role in human perception and learning. symptoms or “problem behaviors” (39,
aftermath. One may wonder whether Applied to delusion, the model intro- p. 635) and “aberrant systems that
these constitute heterogeneous features, duces three postulates. implement psychopathology” (39, p.
and to what extent they derive from or The first is that the patient experien- 633) rather than syndromes (40). Our
reflect some central disruption. The ces an exaggerated sense of strange- own preference is for transcending this
notion of ipseity disturbance (20,22,29) ness, novelty or surprise – due to potentially misleading polarity between
is one hypothesis regarding such a trou- “disrupted prediction-error signaling” symptoms and syndromes, by empha-
ble generateur (see 21,23). (37, pp. 2387,2388) – of the signifi- sizing how “syndromes” (such as schiz-
cance of what, objectively speaking, ophrenia) can embody distinctive
are minor discrepancies between per- global modes of psychological life that
NEUROCOGNITIVE APPROACHES ceptual expectancies and perceptual may render symptoms (such as delu-
input, thereby “engender[ing] predic- sion) more heterogeneous than they
We turn now to a consideration, tion error where there ought to be otherwise appear.
from a phenomenologist’s standpoint, none” (33, p. 357) (“noise in predictive The compatibility of phenomenologi-
of contemporary neurocognitive theo- learning mechanisms”). cal and prediction error (and related)
ries of delusion. We focus on promi- The second is that this disconcerting accounts has been discussed in two
nent recent representatives of two sense of anomaly, whereby objectively recent articles on salience dysregulation
domains: a) the phenomenological hy- “redundant or irrelevant environmen- and source monitoring as possible neu-
potheses of minimal-self or ipseity dis- tal cues” (33, p. 347) nevertheless seem rocognitive correlates of the disturbance
turbance (20) and hyperreflexivity/ “strange and sinister”, readily gives rise of minimal-self/ipseity emphasized by
alienation (15), introduced above; b) to delusions that serve to account for phenomenologists (41,42; see also 43
neurocognitive models (30) postulat- the sense of anomaly. for an alternative discussion of phen-
ing aberrant salience (31) and predic- The third is that this over-emphasis omenology/neurobiology/delusion).
tion error offered by Fletcher and Frith or over-“weighting” (32) also skews Though Corlett et al’s (33) model par-
(32) and especially Corlett et al (33), future perceptual and cognitive expec- ticularly emphasizes “prediction error”,

167
it incorporates both the aberrant salience turbed self-experience – especially of The “beliefs” and “propositions” at
theory of Kapur (31) and Frith’s model of lived-body or body-schema (implicitly issue pertain to spontaneous bodily
source monitoring (44-46). sensed body-awareness that serves as action/perception, yet are described
Already in 1992, Sass (15) discussed background to our experience of the on the model of intellectual conjec-
neurocognitive accounts consistent with world) – to constituting the overall ture or formulation, reminiscent of
his emphasis on the “hyperreflexive” ontological transformations, including the explicit “conjectures and refuta-
and alienated aspects of schizophrenic those pertaining to the external world, tions” of scientific theorizing (55; see
subjectivity; he linked the latter directly inherent in delusional mood or delu- also 56 and Merleau-Ponty’s critique of
to phenomenological accounts of delu- sion formation. These ontological trans- intellectualism (54)); they seem to per-
sion formation by Conrad and Matussek, formations, expressed and grounded in tain to facts within the world rather
and to both Hemsley and Gray’s model of distortions of the lived-body (as locus of than to alterations in global foundations
disturbed expectancies (“weakening of basic selfhood), are, in any case, neces- or self-world structures. Closer to the
the influence of regularities” that nor- sary considerations for accounting for spirit of phenomenology (or, at least, its
mally orient and constrain ongoing the “bizarreness” (50) of many schizo- vocabulary) is an attempt to link distur-
perceptual processes) (47, p. 18; 15, p. phrenic delusions and experience more bances of predictive precision with
69); and Frith’s (45) diminished effer- generally, which seem less a matter of diminished “self-presence” (ipseity) and,
ent “feedback from willed intentions” straightforward threats from the mun- in turn, with associated delusions (57).
(neurocognitive feedback indicating to dane environment than more founda- We see, then, that there is sub-
oneself that one’s own bodily move- tional alterations of experience of self, stantial compatibility between contem-
ment is an intentional action) (15, p. 435) lived-body, or world. Indeed, many porary neurocognitive and phenome-
undermining normal self-experiences of schizophrenic delusions are closely in- nological accounts. Phenomenology,
possession and control. terwoven with altered bodily ways of however, with its commitment to sub-
Important details of the neurocogni- being, which they in a sense express (51). jective dimensions, stresses the con-
tive model have obviously changed Consider Natalija’s classic influ- stitutive role of basic self-experience
over two decades. The psychological encing-machine delusion and Schreb- and ontological aspects of delusional
processes now postulated are not very er’s solipsistic delusional world of mood as crucial to characterizing de-
different, however, since the key ele- “nerves” and “rays”. Each manifests, in lusions.
ment of both Hemsley’s expectancy a particularly blatant way, the experi-
hypothesis (prominently cited by Cor- ence of being alienated from one’s own
lett et al, 33) and the current prediction corporeal and mental feelings and The paranoia paradigm
error model is “mismatch between movements (while also taking these
expectation and experience” (33, p. feelings and movements – even one’s Our second point criticizes the ten-
345) and the consequent prominence own subjectivity – as prime objects of dency to view “delusion” (using this
of (inappropriate) salience and sur- attention), together with concomitant term in the broad, contemporary sense)
prise. Corlett et al (48) present their derealization of the external world as a distinct, even modular phenome-
Bayesian prediction error model as an (15,28). non, and to assume the possibility of a
extension, in terms of “underlying neu- Such delusions might be better unifying account that cuts across diag-
rochemistry”, of the perspectives of- captured by perspectives that favor nostic entities and phases of illness,
fered by Hemsley and Kapur. Sass “enactive” or “radical embodied” offering “a unifying explanation for
(15,49) notes that this disruption of approaches to cognition (52,53), in- delusions with disparate contents” (33,
expectancies would affect experience spired by phenomenology’s – espe- p. 346) by postulating “a singular dys-
not only of the external world (Hems- cially Merleau-Ponty’s (54) – stress function” (33, p. 361) or “single factor”.
ley’s original emphasis; Conrad’s exter- on how world-experience is imbued We acknowledge the remarkable the-
nal apophany), but also of core-self with the perceiver’s own implicit oretical ingenuity and subtlety especially
and lived body (Conrad’s internal apo- sense of bodily capacities and disposi- of Corlett et al’s (33) hypotheses, based
phany). Although these self-aspects are tions. Here there is at least the appear- on an overarching prediction error
not stressed in Kapur’s (31) account of ance of conflict with the more in- model that views mind/brain as an
salience dysregulation, the issue of tellectualistic-sounding prediction-error inference machine. To us, however, the
agency is extensively discussed in pre- formulations, e.g., regarding “false Bayesian prediction error model lacks
diction-error theory, with prediction inference” (33, p. 346, emphasis added) face validity as an account of (at least)
errors in self-generated action explain- and “maladaptive beliefs that mis- such delusions as those involving pro-
ing both delusions of motor control represent the world”, with “belief” found guilt, death, or bodily disintegra-
and excessive sense of agency (33). defined (within the Bayesian frame- tion, or wealth and power, that are com-
It is noteworthy, however, that phe- work) as “the subjective probability mon in severe depression and mania, or
nomenologists have emphasized (e.g., that some proposition about the world of solipsistic grandeur and metaphysical
15) the potential contribution of dis- is true” (32, p. 50, emphasis added). revelation found in some chronic/

168 World Psychiatry 14:2 - June 2015


withdrawn patients with schizophrenia um, and that all involve claims about ing supposed “reasoning abnor-
(e.g., 58,59). Such delusions seem likely the world that are believed by the malities”, “top-down reasoning impair-
to be more decisively linked to different patient more or less from within the ments” or lesions in “belief evaluation”
psychological states, not the “powerful (subjectively experienced) “natural atti- regions of the brain), and also regard-
and uncomfortable experience” (33, p. tude”. There is merit in questioning ing potential psychological treatments:
353) of uncertainty and surprise, but absolute and categorical claims. But, as for instance, can proffering counter-
rather self-hatred, despair, devitaliza- indicated, consideration of lived dimen- evidence really be the true therapeutic
tion, elation, or the possibilities for gran- sions of key delusional experiences sug- element in successful CBT for psycho-
diosity or awe inherent in solipsistic gests the importance of appreciating sis (74)?
withdrawal. The emphasis on surprise, certain qualitative differences regarding
novelty, or strangeness may apply best implicit reality-claims or experiences of
to paranoid delusions, representing reality. Expanding the range of
what we term the “paranoia paradigm”: Some delusions, especially perse- neurocognitive hypotheses
the tendency to view literal beliefs about cutory, may well involve “mistaken be-
external threat or attack as constituting liefs” that prompt action. But, as Jaspers’ The tendency to conceive of delu-
the prototypical instance of delusion. observations suggest, not all delusions are sions in terms of hypersalience and
Paranoid/persecutory delusions fre- of this nature. Many schizophrenia surprise, typically involving a sense of
quently occur in schizophrenia and patients, especially perhaps withdrawn ontic threat from external reality, may
delusional disorders (60-62), which, individuals, describe forms of double be related to a certain asymmetry with-
historically speaking, are the delusion- bookkeeping or quasi-solipsistic subjec- in the prediction error account.
al conditions par excellence; they are tivization (27,28). Patients with grandiose Both Fletcher and Frith (32) and
common in affective psychoses and and guilt-based delusions are less likely to Corlett et al (33) do acknowledge that
certain neurological conditions (63). act on delusions, despite being more cer- prediction error can be awry through
This is one reason why such delusions tain and more impervious to counter- overweighting but also through under-
may play a disproportionate role in evidence (68,69; see also 70,71). Such weighting or under-emphasizing of
inspiring neurobiological and cogni- delusions may pertain to what the patient prediction error or perceptual anoma-
tive theories. Another reason concerns experiences (albeit ambiguously) as ly. Thus, Fletcher and Frith (32) speak
the understandability and at least ratio- occurring only in another realm where of “relatively augmented response to
nal possibility (non-bizarre quality) of the usual sources of refutation – or moti- stimuli that should be neutral” (32, p.
many paranoid delusions (especially vations for action – are rendered phe- 53), but also of “relatively suppressed
outside schizophrenia): this means nomenologically and logically irrelevant, response to stimuli that [since unex-
that they more readily conform with or at least dubious. This begs for a distinc- pected] should be relevant and im-
both commonsense and standard psy- tion between empirical or ontic delusions portant”, noting evidence for both in
chiatric assumptions about the nature and those of a more autistic, solipsistic, or schizophrenia (see also 37). Despite
of beliefs. This understandability, how- ontological nature (4,15,28,72). Both this recognition, their accounts of delu-
ever, may align this kind of delusion should, however, be recognized as ideal sion formation clearly emphasize exag-
with what Jaspers termed a “delusional types, involving transitional and overlap- gerated prediction-error signaling: how
idea” – something that can be “com- ping possibilities rather than dichoto- “excessive bottom-up signaling” (48, p.
prehend[ed] vividly enough as an exag- mous forms. Cognitive scientists tend to 517) or “aberrant novelty. . . signals
geration or diminution of known base their models of delusion formation drive attention” (33, p. 347) or “grab
phenomena” (1, p. 577) (namely, anx- on formal logic and notions about scien- attention” (32, p. 55), demanding “an
ious scanning and sense of threat). tific discovery (e.g., 73). But once the limi- explanation or an updating of belief. . .
Some would stress that psychotic tations of the belief model or “paranoia [which in turn] forms the germ of a
delusions are not, in fact, categorically paradigm” are recognized, the notions of delusional belief”.
different from what Jaspers termed aesthetic or imaginative experience may A striking feature of schizophrenia’s
“delusion-like” ideas, overvalued ideas, seem equally or more relevant (27,58). characteristically paradoxical nature is
and normal beliefs (64). Such a view Thus, at least some delusions, espe- that schizophrenic persons seem unusu-
has been influential in cognitive models cially in schizophrenia, are not straight- ally capable not only of finding the banal
of delusions (65), cognitive-behavior forward instances of mistaken belief, in to be strange (which would accord with
therapy (CBT) for delusions (66), psy- the usual sense of the term, or of “false hypersalience), but also of finding the
chometric measurement of delusions inference” (33, p. 346) that “misre- strange banal (hyposalience).
(67), and neurocognitive attempts to present” objective reality. To recognize Sass (15) cites the neglected work of
model delusions as “maladaptive beliefs this should force us to raise questions Polyakov (75) on disturbances of “prob-
that misrepresent the world” (33, p. regarding underlying pathology (e.g., ability prognosis”. Using tachistoscopic
346). The operative assumption is that the role of hypothesized “deficits” or studies, Polyakov demonstrated exag-
all such phenomena lie on a continu- biases in cognitive processes, includ- gerated openness in schizophrenia:

169
enhanced ability to quickly identify, and hyperawareness, perhaps charac- standard view at the time), but rather as
accept, and take in stride phenomena terized less by overemphasis on than withdrawal from “goal-directed action”
that most people would find anomalous, by relative indifference to anomaly. (15, p. 389), “orientation to the external
strange to the point of being difficult to Ipseity or minimal-self-experience seems world”, or pragmatic cognition in pref-
recognize. Related tendencies are men- likely to be altered in this default, erence for “more introverted and
tioned by Fletcher and Frith and by Cor- anything-goes mode, probably in the detached modes of cognition” (15, p.
lett et al, who speak, respectively, of direction of disengagement and dimin- 556) – modes that could underlie
dream-states in which experiences “are ished presence or vitality. Further, this characteristic “transformations of self
often bizarre yet accepted without ques- orientation may have some relation- and world” (15, p. 390) that occur in
tion” (32, p. 52) and of enhanced capac- ship with what has been termed the schizophrenia, including perceptual
ity, in schizophrenia, to recognize a “default-mode network” (DMN) activ- disorganization, abnormal salience,
concave mask rather than “correcting” ity, already found to be related to the and introversion conducive to delu-
to the standard convexity of a face (33, generation of positive symptoms, hal- sions and hallucinations.
p. 352). They do not, however, clearly lucinations, and possibly delusions as Gerrans (34) has offered an original
relate this propensity (for taking anom- well (36,78-80). but compatible discussion of the default
alies in stride) to delusions. The DMN – first identified by mode’s role in generating delusions.
We suggest that this latter propensi- Raichle (81) in 2001 – is activated Whereas he emphasizes suppression of
ty may often foster an attitude – call it when there is withdrawal from practi- “reality-testing”, we speak of an alter-
an “anything-goes” orientation – that cal, world-oriented activity in favor of nate ontological modality in which
is intimately related to the characteris- self-referential processing, autobio- intersubjective reality is suspended.
tically schizophrenic loss of common- graphical recall and mind-wandering Thus, there may be at least two
sense or natural self-evidence (76,77), (82,83). The network includes medial abnormal modalities (“overweighting”
and thereby to delusion formation as prefrontal cortex, posterior cingulate/ and “underweighting” of prediction
well. An “anything-goes” orientation retrosplenial cortex, and left and right errors), apparently opposed, both com-
obviously undermines the overall inferior parietal lobules (36). Various mon in schizophrenia and both related
grounding in habitual, commonsense experts have mentioned a “give and to development of delusions – albeit
reality that ordinarily bolsters our abili- take” between DMN and “task-positive” not necessarily delusions of the same
ty to recognize and reject that which is systems (“reciprocal patterns of activa- type. But what of the relationship bet-
eminently implausible; hence this ori- tion and deactivation”) (82, p. 1276), ween these two modes?
entation may facilitate the genesis, since DMN normally suppresses the A possibility consistent with Kapur
acceptance, and persistence of objec- attention and salience systems or cen- (31), Fletcher and Frith (32), and Corlett
tively implausible meanings and con- tral-executive network systems (which et al (33) is that the overweighting would
nections that can be central in delusion involve dorsolateral prefrontal cortex have pathogenetic priority, coming first,
formation, especially in some “bizarre” and parietal regions) activated in sit- and then giving rise to an underweighting
and solipsistic delusions characteristic uations requiring response selection that results from fatigue or withdrawal.
of schizophrenia. The lack of con- and working memory that presumably Neurobiologically, hyperactivation of
straints may foster a kind of “patho- increase weighting of anomalous per- salience network would be followed by
logical freedom” (15, p. 127) that is ceptions (84). hyperactivation of DMN and concomi-
characteristic of schizophrenia. Recall Interestingly, in schizophrenia, there tant suppression of salience and attention
Matussek’s patient: “One is much seems to be poor deactivation of the systems. Psychologically, anxious hyper-
clearer about the relatedness of things, DMN even when such persons are awareness of anomaly would be fol-
because one can overlook the factuali- attending to external stimuli (36,84,85), lowed by psychological withdrawal or
ty of things” (17, p. 96). In this sense it suggesting “reduced engagement with non-reactivity, perhaps because con-
could underlie some – though not all – the external world” (82, p. 1276). This stant strangeness accustoms one to
instances of the so-called “jumping-to- finding suggests that a dreamlike, intro- the strangeness of the strange. But in
conclusions” style studied by CBT versive, or subjectivistic orientation can some schizophrenic patients – perhaps
theorists. prevail even during ostensible engage- those of a more “disorganized” type
This mode of experience – “bizarre- ment in practical action. and with insidious onset – the
as-banal” – may be associated with The importance of this sort of intro- “anything-goes” orientation might be
underweighting rather than over- verted orientation is discussed by Sass more crucial to the initial formation of
weighting of the significance of predic- (15) in relation to the “hypofrontality” delusions. Delusions are less promi-
tion errors, involving distinct patterns (deactivation of dorsolateral prefrontal nent in such patients, but they certainly
of activity in neural pathways and in cortex) often found in schizophrenia. occur, and clearly demand explanation
neurotransmitters such as dopamine Sass argued that this hypofrontality in any comprehensive account.
and glutamate. Psychologically, it may should be understood not as decline of Another possibility, however, is that
be associated with passive withdrawal higher or more abstract functions (a a kind of “anything-goes” orientation

170 World Psychiatry 14:2 - June 2015


could have a more intrinsic relation- A phenomenological approach sup- 10. Nordgaard J, Sass LA, Parnas J. The psy-
ship to the banal-as-bizarre experience. ports the relevance, for many delusions, chiatric interview: validity, structure, and
subjectivity. Eur Arch Psychiatry Clin
Many patients might clearly recognize of the now-prominent overweighting-of- Neurosci 2013;263:353-64.
or perhaps sense – at some level of prediction-error model, while also sug- 11. Henriksen MG, Parnas J. Self-disorders
implicit but encompassing (ontologi- gesting other aspects of, and pathways and schizophrenia: a phenomenological
cal) awareness – that a world in which to, delusion that are not addressed by reappraisal of poor insight and noncom-
things loom up as salient for no appar- this model. These latter include forms of pliance. Schizophr Bull 2014;40:542-7.
12. Fuchs T. Delusional mood and delusional
ent reason (banal-as-strange, due to distorted ipseity or minimal-self and also perception – a phenomenological analy-
“overweighting”) is, in fact, a distinctly alterations of ontological dimensions sis. Psychopathology 2005;38:133-9.
different world involving different neglected outside phenomenology – 13. Berze J, Gruhle HW. Psychologie der
“feelings of being” (86,87) and in such as overall derealization, solipsism, Schizophrenie. Berlin: Springer, 1929.
which standard assumptions or reality- and an “anything-goes” orientation. 14. Ey H. Schizophr enie: 
etudes cliniques et
psychopathologiques. Le Ptessis Robin-
criteria are suspended. The very fact of In our opinion, the diversity of these son: Synthelabo, 1996.
these changes would undermine the factors raises doubts about the wisdom 15. Sass LA. Madness and modernism: insan-
“natural attitude”, leading to feelings of viewing delusion as a unitary phe- ity in the light of modern art, literature,
that the world is somehow unreal and nomenon – whether in experiential, psy- and thought. New York: Basic Books,
therefore no longer subject to standard chological, or neurobiological terms. 1992.
16. Tatossian A. La ph enom enologie des psy-
constraints of logic and realism. choses. Paris: L0 Art du Comprendre,
Perhaps, then, even without an 1997.
underweighting of Bayesian prediction Acknowledgement 17. Matussek P. Studies in delusional percep-
errors, there could be a shift to an tion. In: Cutting J, Shepherd M (eds). The
“anything-goes” attitude, albeit one The authors thank P. Gerrans and J. clinical roots of the schizophrenia con-
Parnas for helpful comments on an cept. Cambridge: Cambridge University
that may also differ from the more Press, 1987:89-104.
purely permissive, less anxiety-ridden earlier draft of the paper. 18. Conrad K. Die beginnende Schizophre-
“anything-goes” of the prototypical nie: Versuch einer Gestatlanalyse des
disorganized schizophrenia patient. Wahns. Stuttgart: Thieme, 1958.
This would accord with some findings References 19. Fuchs T. Delusional mood and delusional
perception – a phenomenological analy-
indicating reduced functional network sis. Psychopathology 2005;38:133-9.
1. Jaspers K. General psychopathology, 7th
connectivity in schizophrenia, especial- ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 20. Sass LA. Phenomenology as description
ly reduced mutual suppression between 1997/1963. and as explanation: the case of schizo-
salience and default-mode networks 2. Sass LA, Pienkos E. Delusions: the phe- phrenia. In: Schmicking D, Gallagher S
(84), such that “systems normally inhib- nomenological approach. In: Fulford W, (eds). Handbook of phenomenology and
Davies M, Graham G et al (eds). Oxford cognitive science. Dordrecht: Springer,
ited by the DMN (e.g. the salience sys- 2010:635-54.
handbook of philosophy of psychiatry.
tem) may slip from its control” (82, p. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013: 21. Sass LA. Self-disturbance and schizo-
1276), allowing DMN and salience sys- 632-57. phrenia: structure, specificity, pathogene-
tem to be activated simultaneously. 3. Heidegger M. Being and time. Albany: sis (current issues, new directions). Schiz-
Obviously we are in the realm of State University of New York Press, 2001/ ophr Res 2014;152:5-11.
1962. 22. Sass LA, Parnas J. Schizophrenia, con-
speculation. These hypotheses derive, sciousness, and the self. Schizophr Bull
4. Bovet P, Parnas J. Schizophrenic delu-
in large measure, from patient self- sions: a phenomenological approach. 2003;29:427-44.
reports and theoretical conjectures Schizophr Bull 1993;19:579-97. 23. Parnas J, Henriksen MG. Disordered self
grounded in phenomenological philos- 5. Parnas J, Sass LA. Self, solipsism, and in the schizophrenia spectrum: a clinical
ophy and psychopathology. They are, schizophrenic delusions. Philos Psychiatr and research perspective. Harv Rev Psy-
Psychol 2001;8:101-20. chiatry 2014;22:251-65.
however, also grounded in the neuro- 24. Parnas J, Moller P, Kircher T et al. EASE:
6. Ru€ mke HC. Significance of phenomenol-
biological findings and hypotheses of ogy for the clinical study of sufferers of Examination of Anomalous Self-Experi-
contemporary neuroscience. delusion. In: Morel F (ed). Psychopatho- ence. Psychopathology 2005;38:236-58.
logie des delires (papers from Congr es 25. Husserl E. Ideas pertaining to a pure phe-
International de Psychiatrie). Paris: Her- nomenology and to a phenomenological
mann, 1950:174-209. philosophy: first book. Dordrecht: Kluwer,
Summary 1983.
7. Sass LA. Heidegger, schizophrenia and
the ontological difference. Philos Psychol 26. Bleuler E. Dementia Praecox or the
The phenomenological perspective 1992;5:109-32. group of schizophrenias. New York:
is congruent with (and has anticipated) 8. Møller P, Husby R. The initial prodrome International Universities Press, 1950.
many aspects of contemporary neuro- in schizophrenia: searching for naturalis- 27. Sass LA. Delusion and double book-
tic core dimensions of experience and keeping. In: Fuchs T, Breyer T, Mundt C
scientific approaches to delusions, in- (eds). Karl Jaspers’ philosophy and psycho-
behavior. Schizophr Bull 2000;26:217-32.
cluding models emphasizing salience 9. Schreber DP. Memoirs of my nervous ill- pathology. New York: Springer, 2014:125-47.
dysregulation, prediction error, and ness. Cambridge: Harvard University 28. Sass LA. The paradoxes of delusion:
hyperactivation of DMN. Press, 1988. Wittgenstein, Schreber, and the schizo-

171
phrenic mind. Ithaca: Cornell University Truman symptoms, and aberrant salience. 63. Moutoussis M, Williams J, Dayan P et al.
Press, 1994. Schizophr Bull 2013;39:278-86. Persecutory delusions and the condi-
29. Sass L, Parnas J, Zahavi D. Phenomeno- 44. Frith C. Explaining delusions of control: tioned avoidance paradigm: towards an
logical psychopathology and schizophre- the comparator model 20 years on. Con- integration of the psychology and biology
nia: contemporary approaches and mis- scious Cogn 2012;21:52-4. of paranoia. Cognitive Neuropsychiatry
understandings. Philos Psychiatr Psychol 45. Frith CD. The cognitive neuropsychology 2007;12:495-510.
2011;18:1-23. of schizophrenia. Hove: Erlbaum, 1992. 64. Freeman D. Delusions in the nonclinical
30. Murray G. The emerging biology of delu- 46. Frith CD, Done DJ. Towards a neuropsy- population. Curr Psychiatry Rep 2006;8:
sions. Psychol Med 2011;41:7-13. chology of schizophrenia. Br J Psychiatry 191-204.
31. Kapur S. Psychosis as a state of aberrant 1988;153:437-43. 65. Garety PA, Bebbington P, Fowler D et al.
salience: a framework linking biology, 47. Gray JA, Feldon J, Rawlins J et al. The Implications for neurobiological research
phenomenology, and pharmacology in neuropsychology of schizophrenia. Behav of cognitive models of psychosis: a theo-
schizophrenia. Am J Psychiatry 2003;160: Brain Sci 1991;14:1-20. retical paper. Psychol Med 2007;37:1377-
13-23. 48. Corlett P, Frith CD, Fletcher P. From 91.
32. Fletcher PC, Frith CD. Perceiving is drugs to deprivation: a Bayesian frame- 66. Kingdon DG, Turkington D. The use of
believing: a Bayesian approach to explain- work for understanding models of psy- cognitive behavior therapy with a nor-
ing the positive symptoms of schizophre- chosis. Psychopharmacology 2009;206: malizing rationale in schizophrenia: pre-
nia. Nat Rev Neurosci 2009;10:48-58. 515-30. liminary report. J Nerv Ment Dis 1991;
33. Corlett P, Taylor J, Wang X et al. Toward 49. Sass LA. Negative symptoms, schizo- 179:207-11.
a neurobiology of delusions. Prog Neuro- phrenia, and the self. Int J Psychol Psy- 67. Peters ER, Joseph SA, Garety PA. Mea-
biol 2010;92:345-69. chol Ther 2003;3:153-80. surement of delusional ideation in the
34. Gerrans P. Delusional attitudes and 50. Cermolacce M, Sass L, Parnas J. What is normal population: introducing the PDI
default thinking. Mind & Language 2013; bizarre in bizarre delusions?. A critical (Peters et al. Delusions Inventory). Schiz-
28:83-102. review. Schizophr Bull 2010;36:667-79. ophr Bull 1999;25:553-76.
35. Gerrans P. Pathologies of hyperfamiliar- 51. Fuchs T, Schlimme JE. Embodiment and 68. Wessely S, Buchanan A, Reed A et al.
ity in dreams, delusions and d eja
 vu. psychopathology: a phenomenological Acting on delusions. I: Prevalence. Br J
Front Psychol 2014;5:97. perspective. Curr Opin Psychiatry 2009; Psychiatry 1993;163:69-76.
36. Whitfield-Gabrieli S, Ford JM. Default 22:570-5. 69. Buchanan A, Reed A, Wessely S et al.
mode network activity and connectivity 52. Chemero A. Radical embodied cognitive Acting on delusions. II: The phenomeno-
in psychopathology. Annu Rev Clin Psy- science. Cambridge: MIT Press, 2011. logical correlates of acting on delusions.
chol 2012;8:49-76. 53. Thompson E. Mind in life: biology, phe- Br J Psychiatry 1993;163:77-81.
37. Corlett PR, Murray GK, Honey GD et al. nomenology, and the sciences of mind. 70. Mu € ller-Suur H. Das Gewissheitsproblem
Disrupted prediction-error signal in psy- Cambridge: Harvard University Press, beim schizophrenen und beim paranoi-
chosis: evidence for an associative account 2007. schen Wahnerleben. Fortschritte der
of delusions. Brain 2007;130:2387-400. 54. Merleau-Ponty M. Phenomenology of Neurologie, Psychiatrie under ihrer
38. Bentall R. Madness explained: why we perception. New York: Routledge, 2002/ Grenzgebiete 1950;18:44-51.
must reject the Kraepelinian paradigm and 1945. 71. Spitzer M. On defining delusions. Compr
replace it with a ‘complaint-orientated’ 55. Popper K. Conjectures and refutations: Psychiatry 1990;31:377-97.
approach to understanding mental illness. the growth of scientific knowledge. Lon- 72. Parnas J. Belief and pathology of self-
Med Hypotheses 2006;66:220-33. don: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1963. awareness a phenomenological contribu-
39. Sanislow CA, Pine DS, Quinn KJ et al. 56. Gerrans P. Mechanisms of madness: evo- tion to the classification of delusions.
Developing constructs for psychopathol- lutionary psychiatry without evolutionary Journal of Consciousness Studies 2004;
ogy research: Research Domain Criteria. psychology. Biology and Philosophy 2007; 11:148-61.
J Abnorm Psychol 2010;119:631-9. 22:35-56. 73. Coltheart M, Langdon R, McKay R.
40. Carpenter W. How the diagnosis of 57. Seth AK, Suzuki K, Critchley HD. An inter- Delusional belief. Annu Rev Psychol
schizophrenia impeded the advance of oceptive predictive coding model of con- 2011;62:271-98.
knowledge (and what to do about it). In: scious presence. Front Psychol 2011;2:395. 
74. Skodlar B, Henriksen MG, Sass L et al.
Silverstein SM, Maghaddam B, Wykes T 58. Sass L. Affectivity in schizophrenia: a Cognitive-behavioral therapy for schizo-
(eds). Schizophrenia: evolution and syn- phenomenological view. Journal of Con- phrenia: a critical evaluation of its
thesis. Cambridge: MIT Press, 2013:49- sciousness Studies 2004;11:127-47. theoretical framework from a clinical-
62. 59. Sass L. Adolf Wo € lfli, spatiality, and the phenomenological perspective. Psycho-
41. Nelson B, Whitford T, Lavoie S et al. sublime. In: Spoerri E (ed). Adolf Wo € lfli: pathology 2012;46:249-65.
What are the neurocognitive correlates draftsman, poet, composer. Ithaca: Cor- 75. Polyakov UF. The experimental investiga-
of basic self-disturbance in schizophre- nell University Press, 1997:136-45. tion of cognitive functioning in schizophre-
nia?: Integrating phenomenology and 60. Liddle P. Descriptive clinical features of nia. In: Cole M, Maltzman I (eds). A hand-
neurocognition. Part 1 (Source monitor- schizophrenia. In: Gelder M, Andreasen book of contemporary Soviet psychology.
ing deficits). Schizophr Res 2014;152:12- N, Lopez-Ibor J et al (eds). New Oxford New York: Basic Books, 1969:370-86.
9. textbook of psychiatry, 2nd ed. Oxford: 76. Blankenburg W. Der Verlust der Naturli-
42. Nelson B, Whitford T, Lavoie S et al. Oxford University Press, 2012:526-31. chen Selbstverstandlichkeit: Ein Beitrag
What are the neurocognitive correlates of 61. Munro A. Persistent delusional symptoms zur Psychopathologie Symptomarmer
basic self-disturbance in schizophrenia?: and disorders. In: Gelder M, Andreasen Schizophrenien. Stuttgart: Ferdinand
Integrating phenomenology and neuro- N, Lopez-Ibor J et al (eds). New Oxford Enke Verlag, 1971.
cognition. Part 2 (Aberrant salience). textbook of psychiatry, 2nd ed. Oxford: 77. Stanghellini G. Vulnerability to schizo-
Schizophr Res 2014;152:20-7. Oxford University Press, 2012:609-28. phrenia and lack of common sense.
43. Mishara AL, Fusar-Poli P. The phenome- 62. Cummings JL. Organic delusions: phe- Schizophr Bull 2000;26:775.
nology and neurobiology of delusion for- nomenology, anatomical correlations, and 78. Rotarska-Jagiela A, van de Ven V, Oertel-
mation during psychosis onset: Jaspers, review. Br J Psychiatry 1985;146:184-97. Kno € chel V et al. Resting-state functional

172 World Psychiatry 14:2 - June 2015


network correlates of psychotic symp- 82. Carhart-Harris RL, Friston KJ. The default- tal cortex in schizophrenia: dysfunction
toms in schizophrenia. Schizophr Res mode, ego-functions and free-energy: a of the default mode network? Psychol
2010;117:21-30. neurobiological account of Freudian ideas. Med 2008;38:1185-93.
79. Garrity A, Pearlson G, McKiernan K Brain 2010;133:1265-83. 86. Ratcliffe M. Feelings of being. Oxford:
et al. Aberrant “default mode” functional 83. Buckner RL, Andrews-Hanna JR, Schacter Oxford University Press, 2008.
connectivity in schizophrenia. Am J Psy- DL. The brain’s default network. Ann N Y 87. Ratcliffe M. Interpreting delusions. Phe-
chiatry 2007;164:450-7. Acad Sci USA 2008;1124:1-38. nomenology and the Cognitive Sciences
80. Broyd SJ, Demanuele C, Debener S et al. 84. White TP, Joseph V, Francis ST et al. 2004;3:25-48.
Default-mode brain dysfunction in men- Aberrant salience network (bilateral insula
tal disorders: a systematic review. Neuro- and anterior cingulate cortex) connectivity DOI 10.1002/wps.20205
sci Biobehav Rev 2009;33:279-96. during information processing in schizo-
81. Raichle ME, MacLeod AM, Snyder AZ phrenia. Schizophr Res 2010;123:105-15.
et al. A default mode of brain function. 85. Pomarol-Clotet E, Salvador R, Sarro S
Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 2001;98:676-82. et al. Failure to deactivate in the prefron-

173

You might also like