You are on page 1of 9

in Islamic Theology and Philosophy, ed. M.

Marmura (Albany: 1984), 172-187 Efficient Causality in Avicenna

that differs from itself."1 In order to avoid pantheism (this is never


explicitly stated, but is certainly suggested by the text), there is in
Avicenna an emphasis, almost a harping, on the distinctness of
CHAPTER 12 efficient cause from its effect, its otherness. Both the metaphysical
concept of the efficient cause as productive of existence itself and
the emphasis on the otherness of cause and effect are found, not
The Metaphysics of Efficient Causality in only where one expects to find them, in the "Metaphysics" of the
voluminous Shifa' (Healing), but also in the "Physics" of this work
Avicenna (lbn Sina) where the treatment on the whole follows Aristotle very closely. It
should be added that the discussions of efficient causality in these
MICHAELE. MARMURA two parts of the Shifa'(as well as the "Demonstration" of the "Logic"
of the same work) complement and shed light on each other.
To turn first to the "Physics," in Book I, Chapter 10, Avicenna
begins by giving a restricted definition of efficient causality "in natural
things." He defines it as that which "is said of the principle of
motion in something other than itself,"3 explaining that the term
motion refers to any change in .matter from potentiality to actuality.
I The otherness of cause and effect, we note, is included in the
definition. It is emphasized further by what immediately follows as
That Avicenna's discussions of efficient causality are rooted in an answer anticipating a possible objection to the definition. What
Aristotle is hardly a matter for dispute-his language bespeaks this about Aristotle's example-given in a different context and analyzed
at almost every turn. This does not mean, however, that in ex­ for a different purpose-of the physician engaged in curing himself?
pounding a theory of efficient causality Avicenna is merely para­ Is this not an instance contrary to the definition of efficient causality
phrasing Aristotle. His expositions exhibit differences in emphases as "the principle of motion in something other than itself?" Antic­
and include refinements and expansions that go beyond Aristotle. ipating such an argument, Avicenna immediately after giving his
Such expansions and refinements sometimes take the form of answers definition writes:
to criticisms of the general Aristotelian causal position and sometimes
suggest Avicenna's own experience as a scientist and a practicing The physician, moreover, in treating himself is also the prin­
physician. But above all, they include a distinctive Neoplatonic ciple of motion in another by being another. For he would be
element. For his theory of efficient causality is developed within a moving the patient, by way of his being the patient, not the
metaphysical framework that is not purely Aristotle's. Rather, it physician, whereas he would be administering treatment by way
forms an integral part of Avicenna's emanative system which he of his being himself-that is, by way of his being a physician.
intimately connects with his ontology-his distinction between es­ His undergoing treatment, his receptivity to treatment, and his
sence and existence. His theory, though certainly owing a great deal being moved by treatment, [on the other hand], is not by way
to Aristotle, has characteristics all its own. of his being a physician, but by way of his being a patient.3
The Neoplatonic element manifests itself in Avicenna's distinction
between efficient causality as conceived by the natural philosopher Avicenna then gives a broader, metaphysical definition of efficient
and by the metaphysician. For the natural philosopher it is the causality, where again the distinction between cause and effect form
principle of motion, of change, "in something other than itself." The part of the definition.
metaphysician, however, does not confine his interest to this, but is
concerned with divine efficient causality. Divine efficient causality �
If, howe er;. the efficient cause is taken, not according to
is productive of existence itself. It is a "cause which bestows existence natural things, but in terms of existence itself (bi hash a/-wujud

172 173
MICHAEL E. MARMURA Efficient Causality in Avicenna

nafsihi), it would then constitute a meaning more general than system of successive emanations being for the moment ignored. A
this. Then everything which is a cause of an existence different more specific form of the suggested model, however, would take into
than itself becomes-inasmuch as it is different and inasmuch account Avicenna's emanative doctrine. The model would then con­
as the new existence is not for the sake of the former-an sist of God as efficient cause and the first intelligence directly em­
efficient cause.4 anating from Him as the effect. For, properly speaking, in the
A vicennian scheme, God is the proximate cause only of this intel­
We note in this broader definition not only the inclusion of the ligence, the rest of the existents being caused by Him through
emphasis on the otherness of cause and effect, but also the separation mediation.
between efficient and final causality. Both these points are conveyed To take the model in its general form first, God is the supreme
in the complementary and lengthier definition in the "Metaphysics" efficient cause, the necessary and sufficient condition for the existence
where Avicenna makes a direct reference to divine causality. of the world, the effect. The causal conditions are ideal. There is
and can be no impediment. Hence the effect follows necessarily. For,
By agent, [we mean], the cause which bestows existence that according to Avicenna, as we shall indicate, God necessitates the
differs from itself. In other words, the essence would not be in world's existence. Since God, the necessitating cause, is eternal and
a . primary sense a receptacal of something that is informed by changeless, the world, the necessitated effect, is eternal. Cause and
it whereby it would possess within itself the potentiality for the effect coexist, God's priority to the world being non-temporal. Since
existence of the former, except accidentally. In addition to this, the one cause necessitates the world, taken in its totality as a unit,
it is necessary that the existence should not be for the sake of the i:nferential relation between God and the world is reciprocal.
the agent by way of its being an agent, but if inescapably so, Before turning to the model in its more specific form, one must
then in some other respect. This is because the metaphysicians draw attention to the importance of this reciprocal inferential relation
do not mean by agent only the principle of motion, as the between efficient cause and effect for Avicenna's metaphysical system.
naturalists do, but they mean the principle and bestower of It is in terms of this relation that he strives to achieve the high
existence as in the case of God with respect to the world. 5 point of his metaphysical endeavours, namely, to prove first of all
God's existence rationally, a priori, without reference to the sensible
The direct reference to God as the cause of the world's existence world, the proof including an argument from effect to cause; and
is quite fundamental for understanding Avicenna's theory of efficient then, inferring the existence of the world from the existence of God,
causality.6 Not only is it an expression of his Neoplatonism (the inferring that is the effect from the cause. Full expression of this
reference can only be properly understood in terms of his emanative goal is given in the "Metaphysics" of his Shifa'.
scheme), but it also provides us with a guide indicating the various
aspects of the relation between the efficient cause and its effect, It will become clear to you anon through an intimation that
regardless, as we hope to show, of whether this effect is existence we have a way for proving the First Principle not by the method
itself or motion in one of its forms. For God and the world as His of evidential inference (al-istidlal) from the things perceived by
effect suggest the model for the relation between cause and effect in the senses, but by way of universal rational premises that renders
Avicenna's thought. A brief pause to consider such a model may it necessary that there is for existence a principle that i� necessary
prove helpful to our endeavour to reconstruct his theory. in its existence, that makes it impossible for this principle to
be in any manner multiple, and makes it necessary that it is
the principle of the whole of existence and that the whole is
II necessitated by Him according to the order possessed by the
whole.
The model in its most general form would be that of God as the Because pf our own incapacity, however, we are unable to
efficient cause and the world as His effect, where the world, the adopt this demonstrative method which is the method of arriving
effect, is taken in its totality as a unit, its inner composition as a at the secondary existents from the [primary] principles and the

174 175
MICHAEL E. MARMURA Efficient Causality in Avicenna
effect from the cause, except with some groupings of the ranks ciprocal. Moreover, when it is reciprocal, certain conditions, some
of existing things, not in detail.7 peculiar to the world of generation and corruption, must first obtain.
Nonetheless, the principle of necessitation underlying this relation
This important passage is a reminder of the need for making the is there even, as we shall indicate, when voluntary agency is involved.
cause-effect model more specific. For it indicates that the inference
of the world from God takes place in successive steps corresponding
to the emanative scheme. This is conveyed by Avicenna's statement III
that we are able to infer the effects from their principles only in the
case of "some groupings of the ranks of existing things, not in detail." In any attempt to reconstruct Avicenna's theory of efficient caus­
These groupings are none other than the emanations in the celestial ality, one must clarify the distinction between efficient causality as
realm which include the triads proceeding from the first intelligence. treated in natural philosophy and in metaphysics. As we have seen,
Detail here is possible because the number of emanated entities is Avicenna holds that for the metaphysician the efficient cause is not
small and, moreover, each entity represents the sole member of its confined to the production of motion (as it is for the natural phi­
species. It is when the emanative process reaches the terrestrial realm, losopher}, but produces existence itself. This, however, gives only a
where plurality abounds and where the causal sequences and con­ partial criterion for this distinction. For he does not exclude the
ditions become complex, that detail becomes impossible for us and concept of efficient causality as a principle of motion from meta­
the inferences of the effects from their causes have to be made in physics. How then does the treatment of efficient causality as a
terms of kinds of existents, not, as with celestial emanation, in terms principle of motion in the realms of physics and metaphysics differ?
of individual existents as well as kinds.8 Avicenna's answer-very much in tune with Aristotle-has to be
If, then, the world proceeds from God in successive steps, the extracted from contexts that sometimes yield nothing more explicit
model for the cause-effect relation must be modified accordingly. than a passing allusion or example. It is to his discussions of the
From the One, from God, as Avicenna proclaims, only one proceeds.9 nature of metaphysics that one first naturally turns for the answer.
The one direct effect of divine causality is the first celestial intelligence The subject (al-mawdu') of metaphysics, as distinct from the things
from which the rest of creation successively emanates. This one sought after (al-matlubat) in it, he argues, is the existent inasmuch
effect is necessitated by God. Cause and necessitated effect coexist, as it exists. The ultimate causes of things are not the "subject" of
God's priority to the first intelligence being non-temporal. There is metaphysics, but are among the things "sought after" within this
and can be no impediment to the divine creative act. The inferential branch of knowledge. The four causes, moreover, are concomitant
relation between proximate cause and direct necessitated effect is attributes (lawahiq) of existents inasmuch as they exist. This, how­
reciprocal. ever, is not a circumstance that is self-evident, but is something
In this model, however, the effect is the existence of the first argued for and established within metaphysics.
intelligence; it is not motion. Does then the various aspects of this This applies to efficient causality, not only as productive of ex­
model's cause-effect relation, namely their necessary connection and istence itself, but also of motion. For the concern here is not with
coexistence, obtain when the effect is motion in one of its forms? the manifestations of this principle as a specific kind of efficient
The answer is in the affirmative. Now there are causes that precede causality operative in a specific kind of material change. This latter
their effect in time, but these are "accidental," not "essential" causes.10 concern belongs to natural philosophy. Rather, the concern is with
For Avicenna, the essential, proximate cause in the realm of nature the principle as a concomitant attribute of an existent regarded simply
(when all causal conditions, including the absence of impediments, as an existent. As such, it is a metaphysical principle, established
are fulfilled) necessitates its effect and coexists with it. To use his within metaphysics as a branch of knowledge.12
·
own example, the hand's movement that turns the key, necessitates Such a view, extracted from the "Metaphysics" of the Shifa', is
the latter's movement and coexists with it.11 This, however does not complemented ,by Avicenna's discussion of metaphysics in the "Is­
mean that in the realm of nature, particularly the terrestrial realm, agoge" of the same work. Here he confines himself to defining
that the inferential relation between cause and effect is always re- metaphysics as that discipline whose object of knowledge is the

176 177
MICHAEL E. MARMURA Efficient Causality in Avicenna

immovable and the immaterial. Some existents, he maintains, are IV


necessarily dissociated from matter and motion-God and mind, for
example. There are "things" (umur), such as "individual identity The causal principle which Avicenna strives to establish through
(huwiyya), unity, plurality and causality," that can mix with motion an a priori, purely rational argument, has two components: the first
but which can be considered in terms of what they are in themselves is that every contingent existent must be caused by something other
(min haythu hia hia), abstractly.13 Causality, as we have seen, is than itself; the second is that every contingent existent that is caused
included among such things. When these things are looked on ab­ is caused by necessity-it is necessitated. This argument, it should
stractly, they are the object of metaphysical thought; when considered be remarked, does not occur where one expects to find it, in Book

in association with a specific kind of matter, they belong to natural


6 of the "Metaphysics" of the Shifa', devoted entirely to causality,
but in Chapter 6 of Book 1, in Avicenna's pivotal discussion of
philosophy, for example, "causality inasmuch as it is either warmth
possible and necessary existence. There is a complementary argument
or coldness."14
to this in Chapter 1 of Book 4,16 devoted to causal priority, but for 1:29-38
As we have indicated, efficient causality as one of the four Aris­
our purposes we will confine our attention to the argument in
totelian causes is something "sought after" and established in meta­
"Metaphysics," Book 1, Chapter 6.
physics. Once established in metaphysics it is handed down, so to
In order to appreciate fully the a priori nature of this argument,
speak, to natural philosophy where it serves as a general principle
however, we must tum briefly to the chapter preceding it (Chapter
(mabda')-this in accordance with Avicenna's Aristotelian demon­ 5 of Book 1).17 In Chapter 5, Avicenna argues that just as there are
strative methodology. This is partly conveyed by a brief remark in self-evident, purely rational propositional truths, there are also con­
the "Physics" of the Shifa'. The remark which is made almost in cepts that are known immediately by the mind. Epistemologically
passing is one of Avicenna's more explicit utterances regarding the they are on a par with self.;evident propositional truths. These include
respective treatment of causality in metaphysics and natural philos­ the concepts of 'the existent', 'the thing', and 'the necessary'. The
ophy: last is one of two other modal concepts, "the possible" and "the
impossible." Avicenna argues that it is difficult to determine which
That for every generable and corruptible thing, for everything of the three modal concepts is the more primitive since each is
occurring in motion, or everything composed of matter and definable in terms of the other two. Nonetheless, he maintains that
form, there are existing causes which are these four, this is a the concept of "the necessary" has the greater claim to be the more
matter which the speculation of the natural philosophers does (ta'akkud a/­
primary since it indicates the assuredness of existence
not undertake [to show], but belongs to the metaphysical. As­ wujud).18 If the concept of the necessary is the more primary, then
certaining the quiddities [of these causes], however, and indi­ the other two modal concepts would be derivable from it. They
would still be a priori since their derivation is purely rational and
cating their states as they are given (wad'an), this is something
does not depend on our observation of the external world. Hence
which the natural philosophers cannot do without.15
such ideas as 'the existent', 'the necessary', 'the possible' and 'the
impossible' are rational a priori concepts. It is in terms of these
Efficient causality, hence, is a principle in natural science, estab­
concepts that Avicenna argues for his causal principle in "Meta­
lished, however, in a higher 'science', in metaphysics. We encounter physics," Book 1, Chapter 6.
in Avicenna two metaphysical arguments to establish such a principle: Avicenna's argument can be paraphrased as follows. The impossible
one is purely a priori, purely rational, that makes no reference to cannot exist. Hence we know rationally that if anything enters the
the world observed by the senses; the other has an empirical com­ realm of existence it would have to be either an existent that is in
ponent. We will, however, postpone discussion of the second to the itself necessary or an existent that in itself is only possible. If necessary
concluding part of this paper where we will raise the question of in itself, then such an existent cannot be caused. Otherwise it would
the relation of Avicenna's theory to the then current occasionalism be necessary through another, not itself. Avicenna then argues that
of the Islamic theologians, the mutakallimun. such an existent would necessarily have to be numerically one, the

178 179
MICHAEL E. MARMURA Efficient Causality in Avicenna
only such existent, simple and changeless. If, on the other hand, the to the agent's essence or quiddity, where the action is a consequence
existent is in itself only possible, this means that in terms of its of this essence. This restricted sense is quite properly used for the
own quiddity it is something that can exist or not exist. Implicit efficient causes in the celestial realm and for the natural, as distinct
here is Avicenna's distinction in contingent things between essence from voluntary agents, in the terrestrial world. Avicenna refers to
and existence. The quiddity or essence of the contingent does not the natural, non-voluntary, efficient cause as an essential accident
include existence. Thus, if such a contingent exists, then it must ('arad dhatiyy),20 'accident' here being used in the sense of •attribute'.
have been •specified' with existence rather than non-existence. Sim­ But it is not appropriately used with reference to voluntary agents.
ilarly, if it does not exist, this is because it has been specified with As we shall see shortly, the question of voluntary agency, particularly
non-existence rather than existence. But the contingent's own quiddity human agency, poses difficulties in our attempt to understand the
cannot account for this specification. Hence, if the contingent exists, Avicennian theory of efficient causality.
its existence is due to something extraneous which is its cause; To return to the question of why Avicenna insists on the coex­
similarly, if it does not exist then this is also due to something istence of efficient cause and its effect, there is to begin with a
extraneous, in this case the absence of the cause. metaphysical reason relating to his denial of a doctrine of creation
Thus far, Avicenna has argued for the first part of his causal ex nihilo. 21 If the world's existence was preceded by nothingness, by
principle, namely, that the contingent, if it exists, must have a cause. privation (al- 'adam), then God's relation to this privation is inexpl­
The argument for the second part of this principle, namely, that the icable-he can neither act on it (there is nothing to act on) nor can
caused contingent is necessitated, can be paraphrased as follows. The He create it (there is nothing to create). But closer to home, and
existing contingent, though in itself is possible, must become nec­ indeed underlying the above argument, is the concept of the cause
essary through its cause and 'with respect to it'. If it were not, that necessitating its effect. Let us take our paradigm of God as cause
is, if it remained possible with respect to its cause, then the fact of and the first celestial intelligence as the effect. Here there is one
its existence rather than its non-existence cannot be explained. We proximate cause and one necessitated effect. The cause is prior in
would then have to suppose another cause and if again, in relation existence to the effect, indeed, it produces its existence. Embodied
to it, it remains possible, then we would have to suppose yet another in this relation between cause and effect are the conditions of suf­
and so ad infinitum. But even if we allow the possibility of the ficiency and necessity. If the cause exists, the effect exists, and if
infinity of such causes, this will not explain the fact of the contingent's the cause does not exist the effect does not exist. If we suppose a
existence, for it would remain possible, not only in terms of its own temporal priority of such a cause to its effect, then there must be a
quiddity, but also in relation to all these infinite causes. But we have span of time in which the cause existed without the effect, and this
supposed the contingent to exist. Its existence can only be explained would be a contradiction. Similarly, it would be a contradiction if
in terms of a cause that renders it necessary. Thus it becomes the cause ceases to exist but we affirm that the effect persists without
necessary through the cause and 'with respect to it'. In other words, it. In natural things this only seems to be the case, as for example,
if the cause exists, all other conditions being satisfied, the effect must the house continues to exist when the efficient cause, the builder,
exist necessarily. no longer exists. But this, Avicenna argues, is only seeming, because
We have remarked earlier that when Avicenna speaks of the its continuation is due to new causes contemporaneous with it that
efficient cause that necessitates its effect he is referring to the essential sustain it.22
cause (al-sabab al-dhatiyy or al-'ilia al-dhatiyya). It is this essential Ideally then, efficient cause and its proximate effect, are coexistent
cause, as distinct from the accidental, that coexists with its effect. and the inferential relationship between them is reciprocal. But as
Before returning to the reason why Avicenna insists on this coex­ we pursue the A vicennian emanative scheme as it descends to the
istence, a comment on his terminology is needed. terrestrial realm, we encounter diversity and variations in the rela­
One can distinguish two senses of the term dhat, from which the tionships between efficient causes and their effects. This does not
term dhatiyy 'essential' derives. There is a general sense that refers p
mean that the reci rocal inferential relation no longer obtains, but
to the entity which is the cause, as when we say, ••x itself is the it now obtains when conditions, many peculiar to the terrestrial
cause," and there is a more restricted sense that refers specifically realm, are satisfied. Thus, for example, the efficient cause must be

180 181
MICHAEL E. MARMURA Efficient Causality in Avicenna

the proximate, specific cause and must represent the only kind of hand, in "Metaphysics," Book 4, Chapter 1, he speaks of the will
cause productive as a specific effect. 23 It must be actual, the effect as necessitating the effect.34 One suspects that Avicenna is using the
in itself possible.24 In natural, non-voluntary agents, the cause must term will or its equivalent in these two passages in different senses.
relate to the essence or nature of the agent and, for the effect to There is evidence to show this.
follow, the recipient of the action must exist and must be properly In "Metaphysics," Book 4, Chapter 2 Avicenna differentiates be­
disposed for the reception of the act. 25 This in tum means the activity tween two meanings of 'will'. There is, first of all, what he terms a
of other causes, preparatory causes that predispose the recipient for will that inclines(irada rnurnila), that is, that inclines the soul towards
accepting the act. Moreover, in the terrestrial realm all the other some action. Such a will is not sufficient for producing the effect.
Aristotelian causes are involved forming part of the conditions to He then speaks of a "decisive will" (irada jazirna), which is "the
be satisfied for the production of the effect.26 Last but not least, resolution (al-ijrna') that necessitates the motion of the organs."35
there must be no impediments.27 The "decisive will" hence necessitates its effect. This explanation
All these conditions are not always present. Thus, for example, resolves the apparent conflict in Avicenna's statements. But the
the conditions of sufficiency and necessity do not always combine. perennial question remains: What renders the will a "decisive will"?
Sometimes the efficient cause may be a necessary condition, but not Are the causes (teleological for Avicenna) that render it decisive
a sufficient one. The wall, for example, is a necessary, but not a necessitating?
sufficient condition for the existence of the ceiling.28 The same cause
may have different effects on differing receptive substrata.29 Without
knowledge of these substrata, one cannot infer the effect from the v
cause. Again, the cause may be a sufficient but not a necessary
condition for the production of the effect.30 The same effect may be It was not Avicenna's views on human agency (however these are
produced by any one of a number of alternative proximate causes. interpreted) that brought his philosophical system into a headlong
In such a case, one can infer the effect from the cause, but not the clash with Islamic theology (kalarn), more specifically, with Ash'arite
cause from the effect. The inference, however, can become reciprocal kalarn. Rather, as far as causality was concerned, it was the neces­
if it is established that the alternative causes share a common element sitarianism of his system, particularly as it pertained to the concept
sufficient for producing the effect.31 For then this element is in reality of divine agency. The Ash'arites rejected the view that the divine
the one proximate cause that is coexstensive with the effect. Another act proceeded as the necessary consequence of the divine essense.
example of this causal diversity mentioned by Avicenna is the case The divine act, they maintained, was the voluntary decree of the
where the same cause produces more than one effect, for example, divine will, an attribute additional to the divine essence. They went
a disease and its symptom. From the symptom we can infer the farther than this to deny that any act proceeds from an existent's
presence of the disease-or the likelihood of such a presence. The essence or nature. They denied natural causes, adopting the occa­
inference here, however, is from one effect to another, both being sionalist doctrine that real causal efficacy resides with God alone.
the effects of the same cause. 32 Now, as we know, the conflict came to a head some half a century
It is, however, when we come to voluntary agency, particularly after Avicenna's death with the Tahafut al-Falasifa (The Incoherence
human agency, that one encounters a major difficulty in understand­ of the Philosophers) and other related works of the Ash'arite theo­
ing Avicenna's theory of efficient causality. Is there a necessary logian al-Ghazali (d. 1 1 1 1). Al-Ghazali is particularly noted for
relation here between voluntary cause and effect and if so in what articulating the epistemological argument that necessary causal con­
sense? Part of the difficulty is that Avicenna's actual statements on nection in nature cannot be established empirically. Observation only
this question are sparse and, in addition, seem to be conflicting at shows concomitance, not necessary causal connection. 36 But this
first glance. In the "Demonstration" of the Shifa', for example, he argument did not originate with al-Ghazali. It has a background in
states that when the existing cause is not natural, but is one of the early kalarn, and w� find its essentials in the writings of the Ash'arite
human "technical, voluntary or appetitive powers," the effect need al-Baqillani who died in 10 13, some twenty-five years before Avi­
not follow, even if the recipient of the action exists.33 On the other cenna's death. Thus the question arises: To what extent, if at all,

182 183
MICHAEL E. MARMURA Efficient Causality in Avicenna
was Avicenna reacting to Ash'arite occasionalism in his discussions and fire approached and its present state of being intoxicated,
of efficient causality'? burnt, and changed from its previous condition-nothing more.
The question is a tantalizing one. For with one exception, Avicenna Knowledge of the agent of this new occurring state, however,
makes no explicit references to the Islamic theologians on causal does not come about by experiencing such an agent, but is
questions. The explicit reference is in the Najat where he criticizes something apprehended through subtle examination and probing.
theologians for their doctrine of a/-huduth 'origination'. There are, Thus some say that it is the act of an eternal being, a creator
however, in addition to this, two arguments that provide-whether
out of nothing (mukhtarn, powerful-and this is the truth we
by accident or design-answers to two criticisms of efficient causality
uphold. Others say it is the act of the human who came close
encountered in kalam. These two criticisms are found in al-Baqillani.
to the fire and who took the drink, that it is generated by his
Before turning to them, however, we must consider briefly Avicenna's
action which is the cause of the body's burning and intoxication.
criticism of the theologians' concept of huduth.31
Some say that it is the act of the nature in the body, although
Avicenna agrees that huduth 'origination', means 'coming into
I do not know whether this is the very body imprinted with
existence after non-existence.' But this posteriority (al-ba 'diyya) is a
posteriority in essence, not in time. All existents other than God,
the nature or some other 'notion' (ma'na) in it. Then there are
those who say that the nature is an accident.38
whether eternal celestial beings or transient existents, are 'originated'
in this sense. In the case of transients, it is true, in addition to the
essential posteriority of non-existence, there is also a posteriority It is in connection with this criticism that we will now consider
which is temporal. But this temporally prior non-existence has noth­ Avicenna's second argument (referred to earlier) to establish his
ing to do with the cause that brings them into existents. This is causal principle. In his writings there is no concrete evidence to
where the theologians err. For, not only do they maintain that all indicate that in formulating his argument he was also responding to
existents other than God are temporally preceded by non-existence, this type of Ash'arite criticism. On the other hand, there are grounds
but that their being originated in this sense requires an originator, for at least suspecting that this might well have been the case. For
God. This is a mistaken doctrine because there is no causal action he repeatedly acknowledges that the observation of regularities in
on the temporally prior non-existence of which they speak. What
nature by itself shows only concomitance, not necessary causal con­
demands a cause is the contingent, that which is in itself only possible,
nection. To this extent he is in total agreement with the Ash'arite
regardless of whether or not it is preceded by temporal non-existence.
empirical position. But, he then goes on to argue, in a very Aris­
This argument, it should be remarked, is not necessarily directed
totelian fashion, that in addition to the observation of regularity,
specifically against Ash'arite occasionalists since non-Ash'arite Is­
there is a hidden syllogism (qiyas khafiyy) to the effect that if this
lamic theologians also subscribed to the doctrine that origination is
regularity were accidental or coincidental, it would not have contin­
always temporally preceded by non-existence. But it shows Avicenna's
ued always or for the most part.39 From this he concludes that the
concern with theological views pertaining to the causal question.
regularity is essential and derives from the causal powers in natural
Turning to the criticisms of necessary causation encountered in
al-Baqillani, the first has all the elements of al-Ghazali's empirical things. It should also be remarked here that when Avicenna speaks
critique. Al-Baqillani writes: of the occurrences happening "for the most part," he is not relin­
quishing necessitarianism. The exceptions to the natural regularities,
Regarding the thing about which they rave so much, namely, he maintains, are due to impediments that are causally explicable.
that they know through sense perception and necessarily (hissan The second argument al-Baqillani uses is directed against the theory
wa ittiraran) that the occurrences of burning and of becoming that the efficient cause is a nature that necessitates its effect and
intoxicated are due to the heat of the fire and to excessive coexists with it. More specifically, it is an objection to those naturalist
drinking, this is monumental ignorance. thinkers-discussed iq kalam literature-who maintain that the world
This is because what we observe and perceive with the senses is the necessary product of the four eternal natures and is hence
is only the change of state of the body when drink is consumed eternal. He argues:

184 185
MICHAEL E. MARMURA Efficient Causality in Avicenna

If the nature is pre-eternal and post-eternal and the thing We have to begin with the arguments themselves. In the first there
generated by it is likewise pre-eternal and post-eternal, then why is the parallel positions of Avicenna and the occasionahsts on the
is it more proper for one of the two to necessitate and cause role of experience (by itself) in causal investigations. The second
the other than it is for the [supposed] effect to be the cause (al­ argument is a response to an objection that has a striking similarity
sabab) and ground (a/-'i//a)?4o to the one used by the Ash'arite al-Baqillani. But while this parallel
and similarity do not prove Avicenna's acquaintance with kalam
Now we encounter in "Metaphysics," Book 4, Chapter 1, an criticisms of natural causation, they are not irrelevant. Other factors,
argument that has a kinship to the above and which Avicenna however, must be taken into account.
introduces as a possible objection to his own theory of the coexistence We encounter in Avicenna's writings discussions and allusions to
of cause and effect and which he proceeds to answer. views that are definitely identifiable as belonging to kalam, indicating
that he was not oblivious to developments within this discipline.
Someone may say: If each of the two things are such that if For our purposes the most pertinent of these is the one we have
one exists, the other exists, and if one is removed from existence, discussed, his criticism of the Islamic theologians' doctrine of orig­
the other is removed, then one is not the cause nor the other ination (al-huduth). As we have pointed out, Avicenna does not only
the effect, since neither has the better claim to be the cause in make an explicit reference to the theologians-something he seems
existence than the other.41 normally to avoid, but criticizes a doctrine that involved the causal
question. It is true that the doctrine though adopted by the occa­
Avicenna then gives a detailed answer,42 pointing out the ambiguity sionalists was not confined to them. Nonetheless, his criticism of it
of the statement, "if one exists, the other exists." He distinguishes reveals his acquaintance with aspects of kalam causal theory.
between the existence of cause and effect in external reality, their All this, as we see it, makes it quite probable that Avicenna was
existence in the mind, and the indication to the mind of the existence acquainted with occasionalist criticisms of natural causation and that
of either in external reality. In external reality, he argues, it is only he was-in an unobtrusive way-replying to them. But the conflict
when the cause is removed that the effect is removed. Thus when between philosophy and kalam on causal matters was still relatively
the effect is removed, we have the certain knowledge that this is dormant, and one surmises that Avicenna was not particularly anx­
because the cause has been removed. The idea that concomitance ious to have it aroused.
alone does not prove necessary causal connection, which formed
part of his argument to justify the causal principle, is conveyed in
part in the concluding statement of this detailed answer.43

It is not conjunction that rendered one of the two existents


necessarily the cause so that neither has the better claim to be
the cause than the other, since with respect to conjunction they
are at par. Rather, they differ because we supposed that the
existence of the one is not rendered necessary through the other,
but with the other, whereas in the case of the second, just as
we supposed its existence to be with the other, likewise, we
supposed it to be through the other. 43

Was then Avicenna-whether wholly or in part-responding to


occasionalist criticisms of the concept of natural efficient causality?
A conclusive answer to this question cannot be given. The indications,
however, point to the affirmative answer as the more probable one.

186 187
NOTES Notes

7. Ilahiyyat, 1:21. See also, Ibn Sina, al-Isharat wa al-Tanbihat, ed. S. Dunya, vols
3&4, (Cairo, 1938), 482.
8. See M.E. Marmura, "Some Aspects of Avicenna's Theory of God's Knowledge
of Particulars," Journal of the American Oriental Society 83 no. 3 (1962):299-312.
9. Ibid., 305.
IO. Ilahiyyat, 2:265.
11. Ibid., I:165.
12. Ibid., Chs. 1-4, particularly pp. 7-9 and 26.
13. Ibn Sina, al-Shifa': al-Mantiq I; al-Madkhal "lsagoge", ed. M. Khudayri, G.C.
Anawati, and A.F. Ahwani (Cairo, 1953), 13.
14. Ibid. For a translation of the relevant passage, see M.E. Marmura "Avicenna
on the Division of the Sciences," Journal for the History of Arabi� Science 4
(1980):244-45.
15. Tabi'iyyat, 21.
16. Ilahiyyat, 2:165-67. For a translation see my article, "Avicenna on Causal
Priority," in Islamic Philosophy and Mysticism, ed. P. Morewedge (Delmar' N.Y.,
1981), 75-77.
17. Ilahiyyat, 1:29-38.
18. Ibid., 36.
19. Ibid., 37-39.
20. Ibn Sina, al-Shi/a': al-Mantiq IV; al-Durhan "Demonstration" ed. A.E. Affifi
(Cairo, 1956), 140. This work will be abbreviated, Durhan, in the notes.
21. Ibn Sina, al-Najat (Cairo, 1938), 213-214; Ilahiyyat, 2:266-267.
22. Ibid., 274-65.
23. Durhan, 299, 319-310.
24. l/ahiyyat, 2:276-78.
25. Durhan, 298.
26. Ibid., 181, 298, 321.
27. Ibid., 96; Ilahiyyat, I: l 80.
28. Durhan, 303.
29. Ilahiyyat 2:271-72.
30. Durhan, 322-21.
31. Ibid., 322-24.
32. Ibid., 79-80.
33. Ibid., 298.
34. Ilahiyyat, I:166.
35. Ibid., 174.
36. See M.E. �arm�ra, "Ghazali's �ttitude to the Secular Sciences and Logic," in
Essays on Islamic P�1losophy and Science, ed. G.F. Hourani (Albany, N.Y., 1975),
100-111; "Al-Ghazah's Second Causal Theory in the 17th Discussion of his Tahafut"
in Islamic Philosophy and Mysticism, ed. P. Morewedge (Delmar, N.Y., 1981), 65-8J .
Chapter 12. Michael E. Marmura. The Metaphysics of Efficient 37. See above, n. 21.
Causality in Avicenna (lbn Sina) 38. Al-Baqillani, al-Tamhid, ed. R.J. McCarthy (Beirut, 1957), 43, para. 77.
39. Ilahiyyat, 1:8; Durhan, 96, 223, 4249-50.
40. al-Baqillani, al-Tamhid, 38, para. 67.
I. Ibn Sina (Avicenna), al-Shifa': al-Ilahiyyat (Metaphysics), ed. G.C. Anawati, S. 41. Ilahiyyat, 1:167.
Dunya, M.Y. Musa and S. Zayid. 2 vols. (Cairo, 1960), 2:257, I:I0. This work will 42. Ibid., 167 ff.
be abbreviated Ilahiyyat in the notes. 43. Ibid., 169.
2. Ibn Sina (Avicenna), al-Shifa': al-Tabi'iyyat (Natural Philosophy I; al-Sama' al­
Tabi'i "Physics," (lithograph, Tehran, 1885), Bk. I, Ch. IO, 21. This work will be
abbreviated Tabi'iyyat in the notes.
3. Ibid. See also Ch. 12, 24.
4. Ibid., 21.
5. Ilahiyyat, 2:257.
6. See Barry S. Kogan, "Averroes and the Theory of Emanation," Mediaeval Studies
43 (1981):384 If.

304 305

You might also like