You are on page 1of 13

According to Aristotle, "the structure of the best tragedy should not be simple but

complex and one that represents incidents arousing fear and pity—for that is peculiar to
this form of art."

THE NATURE, DEFINITION AND FORMATIVE


ELEMENTS OF TRAGEDY
Introduction : “Poetics” Chiefly Concern with
Tragedy
The very word ‘tragedy’ brings to mind Aristotle and
the Poetics. Some aspects of the definition and discussion of
tragedy in that treatise may be considered controversial,
unacceptable or outdated, but its influence continues unabated.
Tragedy, indeed, is the major concern of the Poetics, as it has
come down to us. Tragedy is considered by Aristotle to be the
highest poetic form. His definition and theory of tragedy
presents remarkable insight and comprehension. It has become
the type of the theory of literature, as Abercrombie says.
The Greek Conception of the Term “Tragedy”
It is necessary at the very outset, to remember that the Greek
conception of Tragedy was different from ours. In the modern
ages tragedy means a drama (sometimes story) with an unhappy
ending, and disastrous enough to have ‘tragic’ effect. But the
origin of the term ‘tragedy’ is not too clear. Dante said that an
unhappy tale was called a “tragedy” or “goat-song” because goats
are noisy. The real source is still under dispute. It is not certain
whether the goat was a prize or whether it was sacrificed, or
whether the original dancers dressed up in goat-masks or goat-
skins. However, the Greek conception of tragedy was that it was a
serious drama, not necessarily with an unahppy ending. The
essence of tragedy was that it handled serious action of serious
characters, whereas comedy dealt grotesquely with grotesque
characters.
The Greek had their dramatic festivals, with four plays being
performed on each day. There were three serious plays, and one
satyr-play or burleque. Tragedy, for the Greeks, simply meant
“one of the three serious plays presented before the satyr-play at
a dramatic festival”. The Greek tragedy has scenes and incidents
of pain and sorrow, but need not end disastrously. This is clear
from Aristotle’s classification of four possible tragic plots (in ch.
13) , which include two plots which represented a change from
misery to happiness—a contention which seems unacceptable in
the modern times.
The Origin of Tragedy and Its Superiority over The
Epic
Aristotle traces the possible origin of tragedy in
his Poetics. According to him, tragedy developed from the heroic
strain of poetry, which in its turn, developed from the hymns
sung in praise of gods and great men. Tragedy is considered by
Aristotle to be a higher form than the heroic or epic form of
poetry, because it was a later development. Tragedy has greater
degree of concentration and coherence than the epic, and has a
greater effect. Aristotle traces the different stages in the
evolution of tragedy, from the single singer to the addition of
actors and scenery. He considers tragedy to have attained full
development by the time he wrote about it.
The Definiton of Tragedy
Aristotle’s famous definition of tragedy says : A tragedy is the
imitation of an action that is serious, and also as having
magnitude, complete in itself in language with pleasurable
accessories, each kind brought in separately in the parts of the
work; in a dramatic, not in a narrative form: with incidents
arousing pity and fear; wherewith to accomplish its catharisis of
such emotions. (Ch. 6)
The definition clearly falls into two parts. The first part tells
us about the nature of tragedy, its object, manner, and medium
of imitation; the second part points out the function of tragedy.
Tragedy : Difference from Other Forms of Poetic
Imitation
Tragedy, like all other forms of art, is a form of imitation. It
differs from other arts in the object, manner, and medium of
imitation. Its objects of imitation are ‘serious actions’. It is
always to be kept in mind that ‘imitation’ in the Aristotelian
sense is not slavish copying. It involves grasping and presenting
the essence of a universal truth. Poetic imitation is re-creation or
a creative reproduction of objects. Tragedy, then, differs from
comedy, because its object of imitation is a serious action.
Comedy imitates a ‘groteseque’ action. The term ‘serious’ has
aroused controversy. Generally, critics have said that it implies
‘weighty’ or ‘important’. It is something that matters, and hence
of permanent significance.
In its manner of imitation, tragedy is different from the epic.
The epic uses the manner of narrative, while tragedy represents
life through acting. It differrs from other forms of poetry in that
it employs embellishments1 of pleasurable accessories2 of
different kinds. It uses, for instance, verse for dialogues, and
song for the chorus.
The Action: Complete with a Beginning, Middle, and
End
Aristotle does not define the word ‘action’. But we get the .
implication through the qualities which Aristotle ascribes to it.
For convenience’s sake, one can say that an action shows the
progress of an individual from one position to another, at which
he either dies, or becomes involved in a completely changed set
of circumstances. Action is the plot, consisting of the logical and
inevitable sequence of incidents. The action must be complete,
which means that it must have a beginning, middle and end “The
beginning is that which does not itself come after anything else in
a necessary sequence, but after which some other thing does
naturally exists or come to pass.” In one sense, there is nothing
that has a beginning or an end. There is a continuous causal1
relationship between events. What Aristotle means, however, is
that a play should have good reason for beginning where it does,
and for. ending where it does. As F.L. Lucas comments, events
do tend to occur in clusters. A volcano, even when continuously
active has eruptions, which form episodes complete in
themselves; and the events of a tragedy are like such an
eruption. T.R. Henn remarks that the beginning of an action
might be perceived to be “a sort of a momentary slack water
before the turn of the tide. At the opening of Hamlet there is
every indication that, if-it were not for appearance of the Ghost,
events in Denmark would have settled down into a period of
rest”. The end is that which naturally comes after something else,
but has nothing else following it. And a middle is that which
follows something else, and leads to something else. In every
case, there is the clause of ‘inevitability’, probability and
‘logicality’.
The Magnitude
Besides being serious, the action must have a certain
magnitude. The term been wrongly interpreted as “important” or
dignified. It actually refers to the size. A tragedy must of a correct
length. It must not be so long that it cannot be grasped in its
entirety without confusion. Neither must it be so short that its
parts cannot be comprehended properly. Aristotle comares the
tragic plot to a living organism in order to bring out the
importance of the correct size. The plot or action should be of
such a size that it allows human memory to encompass the whole
of it. It should, at the same time, be long enough to permit the
orderly and natural development in the change of fortune,
leading to the catastrophe2. The parts and the whole should form
a coherent, complete and intelligible pattern.
Furthermore, the action should be long enought for the
characters to develop the sympathy and interest of the spectator.
This is specially so if the drama is about characters who are
not familiar, traditional figures. A certain amount of length is
necessary to create the impression of the plot-pattern being a
complete and ‘inevitable’ story in which the events are logically
and causally connected. However, the length should be
proportionate; the play should be an organic whole.
Aristotle means verse and song by the term, ‘embellishment’.
Tragedy uses different kinds of ‘embelishment’. Verse is used for
the dialogues. Chorus speaks in song. These add beauty and
decor to tragedy, and their end is to please the spectator or
reader. Melody and Verse, however, are not indispensable or
absolutely esssential parts of tragedy, according to Aristotle.
The Function is to Arouse Pity and Accomplish Its Catharsis
of such Emotions
The most debated term in the Poetics perhaps, is ‘Catharisis’.
Usedonly once in the whole of the Poetics, the term has
unfortunately been left unexplained. Critics have been given
scores of explanations— contradictory, controversial, and
confusing. In the main, interpretation of the term goes along
three lines.
One set of critics have explained the term in the sense of
‘purgation’.Tragedy arouses pity and fear through its painful and
horrific incidents. The sight and experience of these purge the
human mind of such emotions, or rather, reduce such emotions
to a proper balance in the human psyche. There is the
“homeopathic” explanation of the ‘like curing the like’. It says
that the excitement of tragedy provides a safe outlet for our pent
up1 feelings, which we cannot express in actual life. Plato for
instance says: “When babies are restless, you do not prescribe
quiet for them; you sing to them and rock them to and fro”. The
external agitation overcomes the internal agitation, and leads to
calm and peace.
Another set of critics interpret the term as ‘purification’. The
emotions are purified of their morbidity2 and distressing quality,
which accompany them in real life. The emotions are purified
and reduced to their just measure.
The ‘clarification’ theory, of Catharsis relates the term to the
structure of incidents rather than to the emotional response of
the audience. The tragedy by presenting an integrated whole of
incidents arousing pity and fear, brings about a clarification of
such events. It presents these incidents in such a way that the
relation between the particular and the universal is brought out.
The poet takes his material and selects and orders it according to
probability and necessity. The incidents will be clarified in the
sense that their relation, in universal terms, will be manifest in
the tragedy. This leads to the pleasure peculiar to tragedy, and
this pleasure comes out of the representation of incidents of pity
and fear.
 ARISTOTLE’S CONCEPT OF TRAGEDY 
Catharisis, in any case, has to do with the function of tragedy,
which is to provide the tragic variety of pleasure.
The Quantitative Elements of Tragedy
Aristotle divides tragedy into five quantitative parts. These
are not relevant to modern drama, and apply only to the typical
Greek traedy. It thus has little interest for the modern reader.
The quantitative elements are : Prologue, Episode, Exode,
Choric Song; Choric song is further divided
into Parade andStasimon.
The Formative Elements of Tragedy
After having given a definition of tragedy, Aristotle comes to
the consideration of the formative elements of tragedy. He gives
six formative elements of tragedy—Plot, Character, Thought,
Diction Spectacle and Song.Three of these i.e. Plot, Character,
and Thought are internal aspects; three, namely, Diction,
Spectacle, and Song, are external aspects. Diction and Song are
concerned with the medium of imitation, while Spectacle, with
the manner of imitation. Plot, Character, and Thought are
concerned with the objects of imitation.
The Spectacle according to Aristotle, has more to do with the
stage effects. A successful poet depends on his own ‘writing1 than
on Spectacle to produce the effect he wants. Fear and pity, for
instance, can be produced by Spectacle, but that would be rather
vulgar. Spectacle obviously means the appearance of the actors
on stage, costume, scenic effect, and so on.
Diction is, of course, the language through which the
characters express themselves. The Diction is a means of
interpreting the thought, feelings and sentiments of the
character. It includes technical devices such as, metaphor, rare
words, etc., made use of by the poet. The language of tragedy
must be highly expressive. The ‘gift of metaphor’ is valuable, says
Aristotle, and cannot be taught. At the same time, the language
of tragedy must be clear, though not mean or low.
Thought is the intellectual element in the tragedy, and is
expressed through the character. It is the “power of saying
whatever can be said, or what is appropriate to the occasion”.
Thought is there whenever something is proved or disproved.
Thought and diction are related in the sense that it is through
diction that thought is expressed. The speech of the character
expreses the views and feelings of a character.
Unified Plot : Element of Primary Importance in
Tragedy
Tragedy imitates ‘men in action’. The men, or the dramatis
personae, must have the two qualities, namely moral and
intellectual: what Aristotle calls theethos and dianoia. But even
speeches, which are expressive of character, would not be
producing the tragic effect as powerfully as a well constructed
plot.
Aristotle considers plot to be the most important part of
tragedy; indeed, it is the very soul of tragedy. Plot is the
arrangement of the incidents in a logical sequence.
Significantly enough, plot is compared to a living organism.
Just as the parts of a living organism must be probably related to
each other and to the whole, the part of a tragedy should relate to
one another and produce a unified effect. Each event should
further the action, and no part should be superfluous or
irrelevant. If any part can be removed withut damaging the effect
of the work, then that part is superfluous. Aristotle does not
advocate a formal or mechanical unity, as his comparison of a
plot with a living organism shows.
Furthermore, unity does not arise from a play having a single
hero. A single person may experience- several incidents, all of
which cannot, and should not, be presented in one play. Plurality
of action is appropriate for an epic, but not for a tragedy. Thus,
the tragic poet should select and arrange his material to give it
Plotartistic unity.
Plot : Simple or Complex
, says Aristotle, is the most important aspect of a tragedy. We
will now discuss the main formative elements of tragedy. The
Plot can be of two types, simple and complex :
Plots are either simple or complex, since the actions they
represent are
naturally of this two-fold description. The action proceeding
in the way
defined, as one continuous whole, I call simple, when the
change in the
hero’s fortunates takes place with out Peripety or Discovery;
and complex,
when it involves one or the other, or both. These should each
of them arise
out of the structure of the Plot itself, so as to be necessary and
probable, of
the antecedents. There is a great difference between a thing
happening
propter hoc and post hoc.   (Ch. 10, Poetics)
Simple plots have continuous movements, and involve no
violent
change. Complex plots involve changes arising out
of Peripety and
Anagnorisis. The turns in a complex plot, it is emphasised,
must
arise out of the structure of the Plot.
Peripety and Anagnorisis in a Complex Plot
Peripety, or reversal, is the change in the fortune of the hero.
The change of reversal in the situation is brought about by
human actions producing the results very opposite to what was
intended. It is, as F.R. Lucas remarks, working in blindness to
one’s own defeat. Anagnorisis or recognition is the change from
ignorance to knowledge, i.e. knowledge of the true identity of
persons, or the truth of facts, or circumstances. The effect of
tragedy is greatest if the Peripety and discovery come together as
in Sophocles’s Oedipus the King. Aristotle prefers the complex
plot, for it is more effective in capturing attention.
 The third kind of tragedy depends for its effect on scenes of
suffering, or of painful incidents, such as murders, violent
deaths, torture, wounding, etc., on the stage.
Probability and Necessity : Plot is a Complete Whole
Probability and necessity are aspects on which Aristotle lays
‘great emphasis. It is necessary that the plot of a tragedy be a
choherent whole, in which the events are connected to each other
and to the whole, logically and causally. There should be nothing
superfluous or irrelevant in the Plot. The removed or the
transposal of any part should disjoin the whole, otherwise that
part is superfluous. What is presented should be presented in a
convincing manner, so that the sequence of’events seem credible
and probable. In this context, Aristotle makes a statement which
is acute for its artistic truth— that a likely impossibility is better
than an unlikely possibility. The scheme of events, in other
words, should be reduced to a comprehensible and intelligible
pattern. This is what constitutes a sense of inevitability. Aristotle
condemns the ‘episodic plot’ which is not a unified whole and
where episodes seem unconnected. Play of chance should be
limited, and preferably confined to narration and not presented
on stage.
Fatal Plots : Aristotle’s .Implied Preference
There can be four types of plots. It is necessary to remember
here that in the Greek sense of the term, tragedy could have what
is called a “happy end’. The plots to be avoided are enumerated
by Aristotle as follows:
(i) that which shows a perfectly good man passing from
happiness to misery ; (it) that which shows a bad man passing
from happiness to
misery; . (Hi) that which shows a bad man passing from
misery to
happiness.
The first kind will merely shock us, and arouse pity and fear.
The second would satisfy our moral sense, but again fail to
arouse pity and fear, the proper tragic emotions. The third one is
obviously unsuitable for tragic action. The best plot, therefore,
will be of a good, but not perfect man suffering as a result of
some error or fault of judgement, namely Hammartia.
The Dramatic Unities
Aristotle wrote Poetics as an analysis of the extant practice in
dramatist art. As such, he lays down no hard and fast rule. But
there is one Unity he stresses upon—the Unity of Action. That
the action of the tragedy be a logical sequence and a coherent
whole, directed towards a single end, Aristotle does stipulate1.
As regards the Unity of Time, Aristotle merely states a
general observation that tragedies tended to limit the time to a
single revo-
1. specific as essential.
lution of the sun, or a little more. But the observation is of a
tentative kind and not a rigid rule.
The Unity of Place he does not mention, let alone stress
upon. The three unities came into force with later critics, who
wrongly ascribed two of them to Aristotle.
Character : The Four Essentials
Four essentials are enumerated by Aristotle for successful ,
characterisation in tragedy : (i) Goodness (it) Appropriateness
(in) True to life (iv) Self-consistency
The most important aspect of characterisation in tragedy,
says Aristotle, isgoodness. The character should be good. This is
so, if the » purpose he shows is good. The tragic characters
should be ‘better than ordinary life’. Secondly, the character
must be appropriate to the status or type he represents. Thus it
would be improper to ascribe valour1 to a woman, and nobility to
a slave. Thirdly, the character has to show truth to life. The
character must be true respresentatives of actual human nature.
Or, they must be like the historical persons names they bear.
Fourthly, the character should be self-consistent. A person of
given character should speak or behave in a given way. The
inconsistent character should be represented as inconsistent all
through the play. Character should also be governed by the laws
of probability and necessity. The speech and behaviour of the
character should be the outcome of his nature.
The Ideal Tragic Hero
The ideal tragic hero should not be perfectly good, nor utterly
depraved2. He should be a man not “pre-eminently good and
just, yet whose misfortune is brought about not by vice or
depravity, but by some error or fraility. He must be one who is
highly renowned and prosperous”.
Thus a tragic hero should be a mixture of virtue and human
frailty3; his misfortune should come about from an error of
judgement; and he must fall from a height of glorious position.
Such a man would arouse the tragic emotions of pity and fear.
Comparative Importance of Plot and Character
According to Aristotle, plot is of supreme importance in a
tragedy. Plot in tragedy is like an outline in painting; it gives
meaning to the work. Col; ifs thrown haphazardly on a canvas
have little significance—only the outline gives meaning.
Similarly, the soul of tragedy is to be found in the plot. Aristotle
goes so far as to say that there can be a tragedy without
character, but none without plot. Such a statement seems asburd
on the face of it, for how, one may ask, can there be a play
without characters ? it is, however, to be noted that Aristotle’s
concept of ‘character’ here does not mean thedramatis
personae, but the “moral bent” of a person. He means the
tendency of a person to act in a certain way. Now, the moral bent
of a character is only revealed when he is faced with a dilemma,
where choices becomes necessary. In his choice he will reveal his
nature, and it is this ‘nature’ which Aristotle refers to as
‘character’. In a tragedy, there may or may not be such situations
of choice were ‘character’ is revealed, and in this sense, there can
be a tragedy without ‘character’. But there can be no play without
some form of ‘action’. Even a modern audience will agree that a
plot is essential if a play is to succeed on stage.
The Tragic Pleasure
Tragedy, Aristotle correctly remarks, has its special kind of
pleasure. He recognised the emotional effects of tragedy, and
said that it aroused the feelings of pity and fear. And he accepted
that these feelings excited in the human psyche need not be
harmful.
The pleasure is also derived from the instinctive response of
human beings to imitation and harmony. It is also derived from
the satisfaction one gets from learning. Tragedy clarified certain
incidents for us, relates the particular to the universal; it
increases our understanding of life. The unity of plot, the diction
and the spectacle add to the pleasure, i.e. the pleasure of art.
Limitations in Aristotle’s Concept of Tragedy
It is true that the concept of tragedy put forward by Aristotle
is no mean achievement. It lends itself to a remarkable amount
of adaptation, beyond what was immediately present to the mind
of the writer. Yet, the fact that Aristotle was writing of only the
Greek tragedy he knew, does put a limitation to his concept of
tragedy. Later experience in the field of tragedy has shown the
immense scope for modification in Aristotle’s theory, especially
regarding the tragic hero.
There is another limitation in Aristotle’s theory. He does not
take into account the religius origions of tragedy. Neither does he
give enough importance to the outside forces which interact with
the human forces in a play. In other words, he does not discuss a
very basic issue in tragedy—conflict, both inner and outer
conflict. In Greek tragedy itself, one feels the existence of the
mysterious and divine forces; there is the effect of the unseen on
the seen. It is the tragic choice faced by the heroies and heroines
which makes the Greek tragedy so awesome. Greek tragedy
dramatises the struggle between contending moral forces.
Aristotle does not discuss the collision offerees: the collision
between man, who is imprisoned within the limits of the actual,
and the forces outside, belonging to a superior power which
restricts man’s freedom. The conflict between man and outside
forces, between problems of good and evil, are very much a part
of tragedy of all ages. It is unfortunate that Aristotle does not
discuss these factors.
Conclusion
The main features of Aristotle’s conception cannot be ignored
easily There are weaknesses as there are bound to be. His
conception is based on Greek tragedy alone. Yet his views lend
themselves to a remarkable amount of universalisation. Today,
we may not agree with his ‘essentials’ of tragic characterisation—
Shakespeare has shown us the possibilities of a tragic
characterisation—Shakespeare has shown us the possibilities of a
tragic ‘villain’. But what he says regarding Peripety and
Discovery and Hammartia,are conceptions which are still valid.
At any rate, “Aristotle’s theory of Tragedy is the foundation on
which all subsequent discussion of literary aesthetics has most
securely based itself. His views on tragedy are the “history” of
tragedy

You might also like