You are on page 1of 24

apsa

Trapping The Prince: Machiavelli and the Politics of Deception


Author(s): Mary G. Dietz
Source: The American Political Science Review, Vol. 80, No. 3 (Sep., 1986), pp. 777-799
Published by: American Political Science Association
Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/1960538
Accessed: 09-03-2020 16:32 UTC

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content

in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship.

For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

https://about.jstor.org/terms

American Political Science Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend
access to The American Political Science Review

JSTOR

This content downloaded from 146.155.48.109 on Mon, 09 Mar 2020 16:32:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
TRAPPING
THE PRINCE:
MACHIAVELLI AND
THE POLITICS
OF DECEPTION
MARY G. DIETZ
University of Minnesota

^/Machiavelli's most famous political work, The Prince,


was a masterful act of political deception. I argüe that Machiavelli's intention was a
republican one: to undo Lorenzo de Medid by giving him advice that would jeopardize
his power, hasten his overthrow, and allow for the resurgence of the Florentine republic.
This interpretation retums The Prince to its specific histórica! context. It considers
Machiavelli's advice to Lorenzo on where to reside, how to behave, and whom to arm in
light of the political reality of sixteenth-century Florence. Evidence extemal to The
Prince, including Machiavelli's other writings and his own political biography, confirms
his anti-Medicean sentiments, his republican convictions, and his proclivity for decep­
tion. Understanding The Prince as an act of political deception continúes a tradition of
reading Machiavelli as a radical republican. Moreover, it overcomes the difficulties of
previous republican interpretations, and provides new insight into the strategic perspec-
tive and Renaissance artistry Machiavelli employed as a theoretician.

[F]or some time I have never said what I believed now it has become commonplace for po­
and never believed what I said, and if I do litical scientists in fields as diverse as in-
sometimes happen to say what I think, I always temational relations, comparative poli­
hide it among so many lies that it is hard to
recover. tics, organization theory, and political
—Machiavelli psychology to construct explanations
about political life and political conduct
Rjealism is that rely in part on the "axioms" that
generally considered a necessary first evolved from Machiavelli's little treatise.
move in the effort to make the study of These inelude the necessities of "naked
politics scientific, and when political self-interest," the maintenance of ruler-
scientists turn to the history of ideas, they ship at all costs, the utility of unethical
tend to acknowledge Machiavelli as the and manipulative behavior, and the cen-
champion of realism, and The Prince, in trality of power as an end in and of itself.1
particular, as the first treatise in political Accordingly, in many areas of political
thought to infuse the contemplation of inquiry Machiavelli has come to be
political affairs with a spirit of em- regarded as the theorist of "Machiavelli-
piricism, realpolitik, and raison d'état. By anism," and Machiavellianism itself en-

AMERICAN POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEW


VOL. 80 NO. 3 SEPTEMBER, 1986

This content downloaded from 146.155.48.109 on Mon, 09 Mar 2020 16:32:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
American Political Science Review Vol. 80

tails understanding politics primarily in practiced by the wily Ligurio, who helps a
terms of who dominates whom and how young rake bed the beautiful wife of a
successfully. pompous oíd doctor. The Art of War
As far as it goes, this understanding of argües that a commander who vanquishes
politics as power is true to Machiavelli's an enemy by stratagem is as praiseworthy
purposes in The Prince, but, in the end, I as one who gains victory by forcé. The
think it does not go far enough. What is History of Florence tells the story of a city
missing from the political scientists' rendi- where deceit and guile secure power,
tion of Machiavelli is another visión of while honesty and blind trust ruin it.
politics, a republican one rooted in love of Nowhere, of course, is Machiavelli's love
liberty and respect for self-govemance, for the art of deception more vividly un-
which political theorists have long con- masked than in The Prince. There the sub-
sidered as vital to Machiavelli's thought ject of crafty assault takes its notorious
as power and realpolitik.2 This second vi­ form in his advice to a ruler on how to
sión of politics as participation is one play the fox, "confuse men's brains," and
theorists tend to associate with Machia­ employ cunning in the political world. In
velli's later works, particularly The short, whether the subject is love, war, or
Discourses and The History of Florence. politics, Machiavelli recognizes the ad-
Thus, like political scientists, they too vantages of crafty assault in any form, be
often read The Prince in terms of the it trickery, stratagem, or artífice.
politics of power and domination. For those who believe that Machiavelli
I suggest that neither political scientists was a republican and a Florentine patriot,
ñor political theorists have realized the this view of him as the master theorist of
full forcé of the Florentine's intentions in deceit poses difficulties. As Hanna Pitkin
The Prince. By offering a different (1984) reminds us, foxes make poor citi-
perspective on the treatise I hope to show zens—their deceit undermines civic
that both groups have underestimated virtú—and The Prince abounds with
Machiavelli, and in ironic ways—the foxes and advice on deception. Further-
theorists by not seeing the republican more, in Machiavelli's infamous tract to
goals that guide the treatise, the political Lorenzo de Medici we find no defense of
scientists by not recognizing the full forcé the Florentine republic, no cali for
of the "Machiavellian" intentions that in- popular liberty, no praises of republican
form it. My purpose, then, is not only to Rome. Far from denouncing tyranny, as
present a new interpretation of this most would any bold republican, Machiavelli
famous of Machiavelli's works, but also appears to content himself with forging
to encourage a reconsideration of the ad- the absolute and ruthless power of an
jective that bears his ñame and the visión autocrat. How, then, is it possible to hail
of politics it represents. him as a defender of liberty, self-
government, and civic virtü, when these
Republicans and The Prince appear to be the very valúes he teaches his
Medici protégé to subvert?
No political thinker was more aware of Proponents of the thesis that Machia­
how crafty assault by deceit could serve velli was a republican, despite his author-
as a substitute for brute assault by ship of The Prince, fall into two camps.
violence than Niccoló Machiavelli. The According to the "weak republican"
theme of deception weaves through all of thesis, The Prince is an aberration.
his work—his drama, his military Despairing of the future of Florence,
writings, his history, his political theory. much less its republican government,
Mandragola is a tale of crafty assault Machiavelli saw the Medici as the only

778

This content downloaded from 146.155.48.109 on Mon, 09 Mar 2020 16:32:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1986 Machiavelli and Politics of Deceptíon

altemative to total chaos, and so wrote sympathies abound in The Prince, then
his advice book in reaction to an impend- something else must be moving beneath
ing crisis (Barón, 1961; Hale, 1961; the surface of the text; some drama that
Pocock, 1975). This thesis maintains that the protagonist-prince does not see must
after 1513 Machiavelli simply abandoned be taking shape. This is precisely what the
the idea of the prince as a "political in­ strong republican camp wants to argüe,
novator"; he renewed his commitment to but as is so often the case with Machia­
republicanism, developed an admiration velli, there are differences of opinión on
for antiquity, and refueled his antipathy the matter of the subtext of The Prince.
for the Medici. The result of this renewal Three main views emerge.
was The Discourses, complete with its The first is Rousseau's (1978, p. 88)
dedication to republican sympathizers claim that The Prince is a book for
and its repudiation of the entire genre of republicans. Rousseau argües that the ad­
princely advice books. Thus, these vice book was not intended for the Medici
scholars view The Prince as a tract that at all, but rather to expose to the people
reflects both Machiavelli's acceptance the brutal ruthlessness of princes and lay
(reluctant though it might have been at bare their methods and madness. There is
the time) of Medicean domination and his a paradoxical quality to this interpreta-
clear-sighted, if opportunistic, attempt to tion of the sort we have come to expect
ingratiate himself with the new rulers of from Rousseau, namely, that even as
Florence. Machiavelli is fashioning masks for a
Among other things, the weak repub­ prince, he is unmasking him. By exposing
lican thesis strains credulity. To read The the prince's stock-in-trade, Machiavelli is
Prince as a sudden capitulation to Medici arming republicans with all the knowl-
rule, or as a tool to curry favor is, argu- edge they need to avoid being deceived. A
ably, to underestimate Machiavelli as a simple and telling criticism can, however,
citizen and a theorist. Though I find Gar- be lodged against this Rousseauian opin­
rett Mattingly's (1958) ultímate assess- ión: Machiavelli could not be writing a
ment of The Prince unconvincing (for book for republicans, because he never in­
reasons I will explain shortly), I think he tended that they read it. Interpretad ve ac-
poses in dramatic terms the correct riposte curacy often hangs on matters of practical
to the weak republican thesis: political action, not to mention the inten-
tion of where to publish and for whom,
I suppose it is possible to imagine that a man who
has seen his country enslaved, his life's work
and in this case we find no evidence that
wrecked and his own career with it, and has, for Machiavelli did or attempted to do
good measure, been torturad within an inch of anything with his treatise but send it to
his life, should thereupon go home and write a Francesco Vettori, his contact in the
book intended to teach his enemies the proper Medici Palace.
way to maintain themselves.. . . But it is a little
difficult for the ordinary mind to encompass. A second versión of Machiavelli as a
(1958, p. 485) strong republican hardly takes The Prince
seriously, for it assumes that the treatise
The other camp advances a "strong was not intended seriously. Garrett Mat­
republican" thesis, arguing that even as tingly (1958) holds that Machiavelli's ad­
Machiavelli writes The Prince, he remains vice book is nothing more than a joke, a
a defender of republican liberty and an "diabolical burlesque" of the mirror-of-
opponent of the Medici (Gentili, 1924; princes literature prevalent in the Renais-
Mattingly, 1958; Rousseau, 1978; sance. Nominally agreeing with Rous­
Spinoza, 1945; Wolin, 1960). However, if seau, Mattingly argües that Machiavelli
this is indeed the case, and if republican wrote The Prince as an alarm, a "tocsin"

779

This content downloaded from 146.155.48.109 on Mon, 09 Mar 2020 16:32:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
American Political Science Review Vol. 80

to the people of Florence. However, this superfluous or how he gives way to the
agreement is surely more literary than republic, Wolin does not say; the implica-
political, for, unlike Rousseau, Mattingly tion, roughly, is that he creates institu-
does not read the treatise as revealing cer- tions that will subsume and outlive him.
tain truths about princely power that Henee the major issue, for Wolin (1960, p.
republicans should know. He sees The 231), is whether or not the state will be
Prince primarily as a fine example of capable of "generating its own momen-
Machiavelli's dramatic temperament, a tum" after the founder is dead.4
reflection of his ability simultaneously to Two problems beset Wolin's attempt to
shock and amuse his audience. Machia- solve the puzzle of the transition from The
velli surely intended to shock and perhaps Prince to The Discourses, and so to shore
to amuse, and Mandragola fully displays up the third versión of the strong
his dramatic skills, but this does not suf- republican thesis. The first problem is tex­
fice to make The Prince a burlesque, even tual: in The Prince, Machiavelli gives no
if a diabolical one. The most obvious specific advice conceming the foundation
problem with Mattingly's reading is that it of republican institutions. Indeed, he does
fails to take seriously Machiavelli's desire not deal with republics at all. On this
to reconstitute the political world. In The score, we should compare The Prince
Prince, Machiavelli (P, p. 56) declares his with a later work, Machiavelli's advice to
intention "to write something of use to Pope Leo X, "On Reforming the State of
those who understand."3 He wishes to Florence" (Pansini, 1969, pp. 633-34).
reveal reality, not ridicule it, and his There he does offer lengthy and detailed
repeated instruction conceming princely directives on the organizaron of a
virtü sounds less like a satire on the cor- republic, and advises, among other
ruption of power than an attempt to things, the reopening of the hall of the
determine how those in power might use Council of the Thousand, the redistribu-
guile and deceit to mitígate the corruption tion of offices to the general public, and
of the state. the return of a gonfalonier. Nothing even
The third strong republican perspective remotely similar to this appears in The
reads The Prince literally, as an advice Prince, where Machiavelli seems content
book for a founder. Machiavelli's prince to develop Lorenzo's knowledge of
is to be the restorer of order, the man of historical examples and his appreciation
virtü who will lay the foundations from of deceit and violence, rather than his
which the republic will emerge. Thus, The familiarity with republican ordini.
Prince is "phase one" of a series of events The second problem with Wolin's thesis
that will lead to liberty and republican is more political in nature: Would a
govemment in "phase two." On this ac- theorist as cognizant of the vicissitudes of
count, The Discourses takes its point of fortuna as Machiavelli content himself
departure from the (hoped-for) realization with the notion that "heroic politics" will
of the prince's plans. Put another way, somehow "give way" to mass politics,
The Prince has to do with "heroic" that the death of the prince will lead to the
politics, The Discourses with mass politics rise of the republic? Moreover, would a
of a republican sort, made possible by the Florentine who knew well the per-
heroism of the virtuoso leader. Thus sonalities of the Medici princes—Giuliano
Sheldon Wolin (1960, p. 231) contends (a man of little ambition, with a lack of
that the prince will "render himself aptitude for dealing with Florentine af-
superfluous" and therefore "give way" to fairs) and Lorenzo (an unapproachable
the rise of mass politics and the republic. autocrat with Spanish pretensions)
Exactly how the founder renders himself (Gilbert, 1984, p. 135; Hale, 1977, p.

780

This content downloaded from 146.155.48.109 on Mon, 09 Mar 2020 16:32:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1986 Machiavelli and Politics of Deception

99)—truly imagine them fit subjects for Prince to be reconciled with the author of
heroic politics, much less men great- The Discourses?
hearted enough to relinquish their power These questions can be answered only if
after creating the conditions for a new we remember Machiavelli's awareness of
republic? the advantages of crafty assault, and con-
Surely these rhetorical questions sider another, arguably more plausible,
answer themselves. The history of the interpretative possibility: that The Prince
govemment of Florence, with its unpre- is not simply about deception, but is itself
dictable oscillations between various an act of deception, and that this theorist
forms of princely and republican rule, of deceit is at the same time a practitioner
taught Machiavelli at least one lesson: of that very art. In other words, The
that to wait (as was the Florentine habit) Prince is a tract that in fact aims to restore
and expect to benefit from circumstances a republic, though in appearance it
brings disaster. What is necessary is to act dedicates itself to maintaining a prince-
and to act boldly to change circum­ dom. Machiavelli indeed intends this
stances. This, in fact, is the very lesson book for the Medici. Thus, his deception
Machiavelli teaches his prince, so it seems resides not in exposing princely tricks to
odd, to say the least, to assume that republicans, but in something far more
Machiavelli himself is willing to wait for crafty: he intends for a gullible and vain-
the prince's retirement or death and ex­ glorious prince to heed the duplicitous ad-
pect that circumstances will, in due vice of The Prince, and thereby take ac-
course, eventuate in a republic. tions that will jeopardize his power and
These last observations give us the bring about his demise. Thus, even as
needed purchase, I believe, to understand Machiavelli (P, p. 65) tells Lorenzo that
Machiavelli's strong republican intentions "one who deceives will always find those
and to solve the puzzle of The Prince. who allow themselves to be deceived," he
Given the Florentine's commitment to is deceiving Lorenzo. Even as he presses
boldness and his conviction that success- upon the prince the need to establish a
ful political action requires the mastery of relationship to others that is unknown to
circumstances, does it not seem plausible them, Machiavelli places Lorenzo in ex-
that The Prince could be read as a actly this relation to himself. Even as he
political act in itself, a bold attempt to offers his Medici a "humble testimony of
change existing conditions? Despite its devotion," Machiavelli devises a plot, a
main fault, the Rousseauian interpreta- series of moves that, if followed, will lead
tion is compelling precisely because of Lorenzo to disaster.
this—it approaches The Prince as praxis This reasoning presumes, of course,
and renders Machiavelli a political actor that Machiavelli was a decided enemy of
as well as a political theorist. Again, the Medici, and that he intended his ad-
however, it must be remembered that vice to be followed to its damning letter.
Machiavelli sent his tract to the prince We will turn to that shortly. First we need
and not to Piero Soderini, the deposed to consider how, in the course of The
gonfalonier, or to his republican friends in Prince, this master of political deception
the castle at Volterra. So the puzzle re- sets his trap, disguises his own true aims,
mains. If we are to be committed to a and makes Lorenzo his mannerino.
reading of Machiavelli as a strong repub­
lican and of The Prince as praxis—as I Trapping the Prince
propose we should—then in what sense is
this little book a bold attempt to alter cir­ Machiavelli's conception of politics in
cumstances? How is the author of The The Prince is quite clearly drawn from his

781

This content downloaded from 146.155.48.109 on Mon, 09 Mar 2020 16:32:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
American Political Science Review Vol. 80

understanding oí and experience in the art the form of subversive directives for his
of war. Politics, like warfare, is a vicious Medici lord, which he then covers over
struggle to gain control, to domínate and with promises of power, glory, and
conquer opposing forces, to battle one's popular support. This deceptive advice to
way to victory over the enemy. Machia­ Lorenzo concems three decisive matters
velli (P, p. 53) thus advises his prince to for a prince: where to live, how to
"have no other aim or thought . . . but behave, and whom to arm. If we read
war and its organization and discipline." Machiavelli's counsel to the prince with
That art alone is necessary for glory in historical information at hand, its subver­
politics. The organizer of the Florentine sive character begins to appear. If we read
civilian militia also knows that though it with a complete understanding of
there is "no comparison" between the Lorenzo de Medici's circumstances in
armed and the disarmed man, success in Florence, the conclusión seems obvious:
war depends upon more than brute Machiavelli is out to undo this enemy of
assault by sheer forcé of arms (P, p. 54). the republic. Let us consider what he says.
Machiavelli (1965) recommends another
sort of assault in The Art of War:
Where to Live
Where the nature of the terrain is such that you
cannot draw the enemy into an ambush easily, Machiavelli begins The Prince by
you may, however, dig ditches and pitfalls in the
plains, cover them over lightly with brushwood stating that his subject matter concems
and clods and leave areas of solid ground monarchies, not republics (P, p. 5). This
through which you may retire in the heat of bat­ is surely disingenuous, for although his
tle; if the enemy pursues, he is undone. (1965, p. discussion of kinds of principalities and
118)
how they are acquired and kept (P, pp.
Thus, for the general and the prince, 5-41) focuses primarily on princely power
the art of war and the art of politics re- and not popular govemance, one of his
quire a knowledge of crafty assault as well main categories of principality is the
as of armed combat. The political actor former republic. Machiavelli says that of
must be as skilled at setting traps as he is all the new princes, the one who becomes
at bold, ferocious attack, for when one is ruler of a once-free city faces the most
foiled by "terrain" and unable to ambush overwhelming difficulties, and he devotes
easily, it may be necessary to deceive. a short chapter (P, pp. 18-19) to explain-
The political terrain of Florence in 1512 ing princely options in such a situation.
was not advantageous for Machiavelli. We, like Machiavelli, might expect that
No "easy ambush" of the Medici lords Lorenzo, a new prince in a former repub­
was possible, and therefore we might lic, would be particularly interested in this
remember Machiavelli's advice to chapter, so we should note what Machia­
generáis in such situations: employ velli prescribes when he addresses "the
strategy and deception and your enemy way to govem cities or dominions that,
will be undone. The Prince is previous to being occupied, lived under
Machiavelli's stratagem, an act of assault their own laws" (P, p. 18). Machiavelli of-
in the form of deception. As has been fers the prince in a formerly free state
recognized for centuries, the text itself three choices: he may either despoil, live
provides areas of "solid ground," or firm within, or restore the freedoms of the oc­
advice a new prince in a new territory can cupied city. He then discounts the third
rely upon to gain and maintain his power. altemative by appealing to history: The
What has been missed, however, is Romans unsuccessfully tried to hold
Machiavelli's deceit. Amidst this solid ad­ Greece and, at the same time, allow her
vice he prepares "ditches and pitfalls" in freedom; henee, their only recourse was

782

This content downloaded from 146.155.48.109 on Mon, 09 Mar 2020 16:32:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1986 Machiavelli and Politics of Deception

to lay waste and despoil the country as Poggio a Caiano—outside the city (Burk-
they had done in Capua, Carthage, and hardt, 1958, p. 399; Wackernagel, 1981).
Numantia. The paradox is not lost on Machiavelli's advice seems designed to
Machiavelli—in order to maintain power change the residential practice of the fam­
in a former republic, one must destroy it. ily by strategically placing the prince in-
What renders such extreme measures side the city's walls. Yet at the same time
necessary is the character of the citizenry it seems to run counter to his warning
of a subjugated republic: 'They do not about the vengeful nature of former
and cannot cast aside the memory of their republicans—why should a prince live in
ancient liberty," Machiavelli warns, but their midst?
then he concludes his chapter by offering Perhaps our perspective is not yet com­
the second option as another resort. If the plete. Machiavelli may be determined to
prince can neither "lay waste" to the city assure Lorenzo's power by offering fur-
ñor restore its freedoms, then he must ther advice on how to neutralize the
reside in it (P, p. 19). "desire for vengeance" and the love of
Upon first reading, Machiavelli's advice liberty that inflame republican hearts, so
in chapter 5 seems solid. Indeed, he does that even though the prince resides within
not even bother to defend it. In chapter 3, the city, he will be secure. Machiavelli
on "mixed monarchies," he argües that a does give advice on this score, but what
prince's residence within his conquered he says is curious indeed.
territory renders possession "more secure
and durable" (P, p. 8) and allows for the How to Behave
immediate remedy of disorder, and in
chapter 6, he reiterates that the main- If any one piece of advice occurs
tenance of power is facilitated by a prince repeatedly in The Prince, it is
"being obliged to reside personally in his Machiavelli's dictum that the ruler should
own territory" (P, p. 21). Yet there is always strive to gain the favor of the peo­
something curious, even contradictory, ple. In chapter 9, "Of the civic principal-
about his advice in chapter 5. Before he ity," Machiavelli tells Lorenzo to reject
counsels residence, Machiavelli unequivo- the "trite proverb" that, "He who builds
cally states that "whoever becomes the on the people builds on mud," for the
ruler of a free city and does not destroy it, prince who animates the masses will find
can be expected to be destroyed by it." A "he has laid his foundations well" (P, p.
motive for rebellion against the prince, he 38). Machiavelli reiterates this point in
argües, can always be found in "the ñame various ways throughout the treatise (P,
of liberty," which republican citizens can­ pp. 60, 61, 63, 67, 71, 75, 76, 80). Because
not cast aside (P, p. 18). the friendship of the people is the prince's
If this is the case, then what should we "main resource" in times of adversity, he
make of his advice? It seems that a prince must avoid incurring their hatred in order
who lives within a conquered republic to insure against conspiracy or ruin; this
would stand to lose rather than benefit, is "one of the most important matters a
particularly if the people have not forgot- prince has to confront" (P, p. 67). Machi­
ten "the ñame of liberty." A prince within avelli acknowledges that princes cannot
a city is easier to find and destroy than always avoid being hated by someone,
one who lives in a country villa, as had but it is best if those who hate him not be
been the habit of the Medici family; they the people (P, p. 67). In a new age, then,
maintained a palace within Florence but all princes (except the Turk and the
spent much of their time in their villas— Sultán) ought to aim at satisfying the
Careggi, Cafaggiolo, Castello, Fiesole, popolani. Implicit is a corollary Machia-

783

This content downloaded from 146.155.48.109 on Mon, 09 Mar 2020 16:32:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
American Political Science Review Vol. 80

velli makes explicit in his chapter on civic fact, he says exactly the opposite and
principalities: be wary oí the nobility. issues warnings about trusting nobles and
The nobles are portrayed as untrust- alienating the people. Of course, it may
worthy, dishonest, greedy, and danger- be that between 1512 and 1521 Machia­
ous. Machiavelli writes: velli simply changed his mind on the sub-
[FJrom hostile nobles [the prince] has to fear not ject of whose favor the prince should
only desertion but their active opposition, and as seek, but before we draw this conclusión
they are always more far-seeing and more cun- we might look at another aspect of his ad­
ning, they are always in time to save themselves vice on how to behave.
and take sides with one who they expect to con-
quer. (P, pp. 36-37)
Machiavelli takes up the subject "Of
liberality and niggardliness" in chapter
Henee the wise prince will, when possible, 16. In advising the prince on how to
esteem his nobles, but more often he will behave, he again reminds him of the im-
be suspicious oí them. The people provide portance of not being hated by the people,
a far firmer foundation for power. observing that
Before we accept the astuteness of
Machiavelli's advice to Lorenzo, we one who wishes to obtain the reputation of
should recall this Medici's situation. As liberality among men, must not omit every kind
we shall see, the Florentine people were of sumptuous display, and to such an extent that
a prince of this character will consume by such
not well inclined toward the new Medici. means all his resources and will be at last com-
The mood of the city had changed mark- pelled, if he wishes to maintain his ñame for
edly since the days of il Magnifico. The liberality, to impose heavy taxes on his people,
Florentines had become accustomed to a become extortionate, and do everything possible
to obtain money. This will make his subjeets
republic; what opposition there was to it begin to hate him. (P, p. 58)
carne primarily from the aristocracy. It
seems, then, that an astute advisor would To underscore his warning against
have told Lorenzo to turn for support to liberality (liberalita), Machiavelli con-
the very class Machiavelli tells him to cludes the chapter by saying, "of all things
suspect—the ottimati. All the more
that a prince must guard against, the most
curious is Machiavelli's own acknowl-
important are being despicable or hated,
edgement of this elsewhere (though not to
and liberality will lead you to one or other
Lorenzo in The Prince). In his document of these conditions" (P, p. 60). Thus, the
to Pope Leo X, "On Reforming the State
prince (who has already noted the danger
of Florence," Machiavelli tells the Pope
of alienating the people) will agree to
what would have to be done if a prince
practice "niggardliness" (parsimonia)—it
wished to turn the city into a monarchy: is one of the vices that secures his power.
[I]n Florence where there is a great sense of equal- However, we have evidence to suggest
ity, one would first have to introduce inequality that Machiavelli's warning against liberal­
and create nobles with castles and villas, who ity in The Prince is more a matter of
would join the prince in suppressing the city and republican sympathies than helpful ad­
the whole province with their armies and fac-
tions. A prince alone, without the nobles, cannot
vice, for in The History of Florence he
bear the weight of a monarchy. (Pansini, 1969, reveáis how the Medici benefitted from
p. 20) liberality.
Book 8 of Machiavelli's History relates,
Despite the fact that The Prince is among other things, the famous tale of the
(ostensibly) dedicated to a prince who Pazzi conspiracy against il Magnifico,
wishes to maintain his power, nowhere in Lorenzo de Medici, in 1478. The details of
the treatise does Machiavelli offer the attempted but unsuccessful plot
Lorenzo the advice he gives Pope Leo. In against Lorenzo's life need not concern us.

784

This content downloaded from 146.155.48.109 on Mon, 09 Mar 2020 16:32:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1986 Machiavelli and Politics of Deception

but what Machiavelli says about the out- Whom to Arm


come of the conspiracy is instructive. One
of the elements of the plan called for In chapter 20 of The Prince, Machia­
Francesco Pazzi to ride to the gates of the velli takes up the matter of "whether fort-
city in the aftermath of Lorenzo's assas- resses and other things which princes
sination, calling the people to liberty and often contrive are useful or injurious."
to arms. However, events took a different Alian Gilbert (1938, p. 162) has noted this
tum. Francesco was wounded in the at- chapter's "un-Machiavellian" advice to
tempt to kill the prince, and it fell to his the ruler about how to gain the support of
únele, Iacopo, to sound the alarm. Machi­ the people, but let us take another look.
avelli explains and analyzes the failure of The chapter begins with a review of what
this final effort by the Pazzi in the follow- princes who want "to hold their posses-
ing way: sions securely" have done, and Machia­
velli notes that no "definitive judgment" is
Iacopo rodé out with perhaps a hundred men possible on these matters (P, p. 77). Con-
who had been prepared for this job, to make this
last trial of their fortune, and he went to the ditions and circumstances vary and re-
Palace square calling the people and liberty to his quire different responses. But, then he
aid. But the first had been deafened by fortune issues a most definitive statement:
and the liberality of the Medid and the second
was unknown in Florence, so there was no A new prince has never been known to disarm
response. (1970, p. 273, emphasis added) his subjeets, on the contrary, when he has found
them disarmed he has always armed them, for by
arming them these arms become your own, those
It is impossible to miss Machiavelli's con­ that you suspected become faithful and those
clusión—the liberality of the Medici had that were faithful remain so, and from being
merely subjeets become your partisans. (P, p.
gamered the people's support. Indeed, the 77)5
family's practiced munificence and heavy
public spending had deafened the Floren- As if to leave no further doubt on the
tines to the cri de coeur of the republic— matter, Machiavelli goes on to argüe that
that is, to liberty. the new prince who disarms his subjeets
Armed with Machiavelli's analysis of offends them and generates hatred toward4
this event, we can now read his advice in himself. As we have seen, he has taken
chapter 16 of The Prince in a different care to prepare the solid ground for this
light. His injunction against liberality is advice by telling the prince that the hatred
intended to deprive Lorenzo of a tactic of the people is precisely what he must
that had worked exceedingly well for the avoid; one of his most potent remedies
Medici in the past. As Machiavelli sees it, against conspiracy is not being hated by
a liberal prince can spend, then depend on the masses. Therefore, Machiavelli con-
the people's goodwill, a miserly one can- cludes, "a new prince in a new dominión
no t. It seems, then, that even as he assures always has his subjeets armed. History is
Lorenzo that miserliness will win him full of such examples" (P, p. 78). His ad­
public support and keep him from being vice on this score follows from chapter 14,
hated, Machiavelli takes steps to where the prince has been wamed of the
guarantee that the ñame of liberty is not evils of being disarmed, and from chapter
forgotten in Florence—and it is in liberty 12, where the prince has been told of the
that citizens of a former republic "can disastrous consequences of hiring
always find a motive for rebellion" (P, p. mercenary and auxiliary troops.
19). Yet, as Machiavelli knows, rebellion On the surface, perhaps, Machiavelli's
may come to naught unless there are good advice on arms seems sound, even "un-
arms to strengthen it. We must now con- Machiavellian," but that impression
sider his advice on arms. begins to blur if we consider a seemingly

785

This content downloaded from 146.155.48.109 on Mon, 09 Mar 2020 16:32:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
American Political Science Review Vol. 80

obvious point. Machiavelli's suggestion Lorenzo to emulate, his grandfather


that the granting oí arms inspires loyalty would have been the best. Not only was zl
and makes partisans out oí subjects, if Magnifico the most artful principe of the
taken to be sincere, fails to account for the Medicean line, he was also the most
possibility, indeed the probability, that brilliant secular figure of the age, both
arms may also facilitate plots, incite in- loved and feared by the Florentines.
surrection, and inspire rebels. The new But quite clearly, the example of Lorenzo
prince who arms his subjects may just as the Magnificent directly contradicts
easily make himself a mark for overthrow Machiavelli's advice on arming subjects,
by creating the very instrument of his and Machiavelli appears content to omit
own destruction, namely, a civilian this piece of information in his "defini-
militia. Moreover, earlier in the treatise, tive" advice to the new prince.
when Machiavelli discusses such virtuous The issue here, however, is not simply
new princes as Francesco Sforza in Milán whether new princes have in the past
or Cesare Borgia in the Romagna, he routinely armed their subjects and, in
makes no mention of their having armed essence, created civilian militias. At issue
their subjects, doubtless because they did is another, more immediately historical
not. His bold claim that "history is full of matter: is Machiavelli's advice wise
such examples" is followed by no exam- counsel for a Medici in Florence? From
ples at all, an odd omission for a thinker what we know of the history of the city,
who is otherwise so willing to present the answer to this question can only be
specific historical examples for the prince no.
to emulate. In Florence, the idea of liberty was
Most curious of all, however, is Machi­ deeply rooted in political tradition. The
avelli's omission of a historical example city's sense of freedom persisted through
that would ha ve meant much to Lorenzo. periods of oligarchical rule, rigged elec-
In a letter written to Piero Soderini at the tions, and partisan foreign policies. A
same time he was composing The Prince, proclamation of July 1329, passed by the
Machiavelli (1961) makes mention of pratica (a citizen assembly), declared that
some causal histories that have led the city would never submit to the auto-
various princes to greatness, and notes cratic rule of one man, "since liberty is a
that celestial good which surpasses all the
wealth of this world" (Rubinstein, 1968,
Lorenzo de Medici disarmed the people to hold p. 450). That "celestial good" was what
Florence; Messer Giovanni Bentivogli in order to the Florentines believed contributed to
hold Bologna armed them; the Vitelli in Castello their greatness. Coupled with this tradi­
and the present Duke of Urbino in his territory
destroyed the fortresses in order to retain their
tion of republican liberty, the Florentines
states; Count Francesco and many others built had a history of strong opposition to the
them in their territories to make themselves sure Medici, which grew particularly virulent
of them. (1961, p. 98) in the mid-fifteenth century. In an oath
swom in May of 1466, 400 citizens over
Machiavelli cites the Bentivogli, the Vi­ the age of 14 declared a political program
telli, and Francesco Sforza in his discus- of opposition to Medici rule that de-
sion of the things princes contrive in manded, in part, that citizens "be free to
chapter 20, but he never acknowledges debate and judge public and popular
the example of Lorenzo de Medici, a new govemment" (Rubinstein, 1968, p. 458).
prince who disarmed his subjects in order Ñor were the Florentines without in­
to hold them. Surely this is odd, for of all dividual voices raised in defiance of the
the historical examples for the younger Medici usurpation of liberty. In his

786

This content downloaded from 146.155.48.109 on Mon, 09 Mar 2020 16:32:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1986 Machiavelli and Politics of Deception

Laudatio Florentinae Urbis, Leonardo about their popularity. Perhaps this is


Bruni declared, "nothing can be achieved why the younger Lorenzo, unlike his
by the covetousness of single citizens grandfather, il Magnifico, rarely ventured
against the will of so many men," and into public places to mingle and meet with
suggested safeguards against autocratic the citizens. When he did, he was accom-
power (Rubinstein, 1968, p. 446). panied by armed guards (Gilbert, 1984, p.
Alamanno Rinuccini published De libér­ 108).
tate, a powerful attack on Medici tyranny With respect to the matter of arms and
(Rubinstein, 1968, pp. 461-62), and Florence, let us further consider Machia-
Girolamo Machiavelli, Niccolo's great- velli's advice to Lorenzo on fortresses, for
granduncle, was tortured and executed it is as curíous as his advice on arming the
for his part in leading the opposition to citizenry. In fact, his injunction against a
Medicean measures instituted under the fortress, when read in light of Florentine
rule of Cosimo (Machiavelli, 1970, p. 218; republicanism, also seems far more in
Ridolfi, 1963, p. 2). keeping with the interests of the republic
There is no reason to suspect that this than with those of the Medici.
opposition to the Medici or the spirit of In chapter 20, Machiavelli tells Lorenzo
Florentine republicanism itself had that "a prince who fears his own people
softened or disappeared by 1512, or that more than foreigners ought to build for­
Machiavelli was unaware of it. Without tresses, but he who has greater fear of
question, the republic was anything but foreigners than of his people ought to do
stable and secure; intemal struggles be- without them" (P, pp. 80-81). This is
tween the middle class and the aristocracy clever strategy, considering that Machia­
were unending, making institutional velli has previously condemned the prince
reform immensely difficult and extemal who fears his own people, and has
affairs precarious. By 1510, Piero stressed the danger of placing too much
Soderini, the gonfalonier, was out of trust in foreign powers. Henee, the prince
favor; the aristocracy was pressing for his who can read at all cannot help but
removal from office and for a retum to decide, as Machiavelli would have it, not
govemo stretto, though not for an end to to build a fortress. More metaphorically,
the republic. There is, in fact, little the best fortress is to be found in the "love
evidence to suggest that there was any of the people" (P, p. 81).
popular sentiment favoring the retum of Militarily, Machiavelli's counsel on for­
the Medici, ñor is there any indication tresses runs counter to the prevailing
that the Medici's assumption of power views in Tuscany in the early Renais-
was genera ted in any major way by forces sance. Fortresses were considered useful
within the city.6 No doubt the family had in defending a dominión from outside
allies among a small number of wealthy enemies. In opposition to this, Machia­
families and some younger aristocrats velli argües that a fortezza is useless and
who stood to gain commercially and cites the example of the Castello Sfor-
politically from the decline of the republic zesco, which gave "more trouble to the
(Brucker, 1969), but in the end, the house of Francesco Sforza than any other
Medici resumed their power with the aid disorder in the state" (P, p. 81).7 At best,
of Spanish bayonets, not the Florentine Machiavelli's military analysis of this
citizenry (Gilbert, 1984; Hale, 1977; matter is exceedingly thin. He seems more
Schevill, 1936). The fact that, once in- interested in the internal, political im-
stalled in power, the princes kept foreign plications of this strategy, rather than the
troops in the city and guards at the palace external military ones. Again, we must
indicates that they felt some uncertainty examine what such an intemal strategy

787

This content downloaded from 146.155.48.109 on Mon, 09 Mar 2020 16:32:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
American Political Science Revíew Vol. 80

would mean in the context of Florence problems a fortress would present for
under a Medici lord. republican activity, Machiavelli does not
If the tradition oí liberty distinguished recommend that Lorenzo build one; ñor
Florentine republicanism in a political does he recommend any strategies of
sense, then the walls of the city marked "containment" other than the "love of the
her republicanism in a strategic one (Hale, people." How can we account for this
1968, p. 502). The Florentines were notor- puzzling advice on arms and fortresses?
iously wary of the subject of fortresses The mystery or oddity of Machiavelli's
within the city. A fortezza symbolized the treatment of arms and fortresses can be
antithesis of republicanism, signaling the explained in only one way. He offers
demise of popular governance and the Lorenzo advice on security, with the in-
emergence of an inner power elite by pro- tention of delivering him into republican
viding an autocrat with an impregnable hands. Machiavelli has not lost sight of
stronghold. Observing the circumstances the reality of Florentine politics; he knows
of neighboring city states, the Florentines full well what the consequences will be if
saw that princes often constructed for­ Lorenzo resides in the city, foregoes
tresses in the ñame of military security, liberality, arms the people, distrusts the
but in fact used them for purposes of nobles, refuses a fortress, and mingles
domestic oppression. Not surprisingly, "from time to time" with the Florentines.
then, the Florentines, with their strong In a city where "the desire for vengeance"
republican traditions, viewed the building runs deep and "the memory of ancient
of a fortress as both a symbolic and a liberty" shines bright, an "unarmed pro-
literal danger. phet" is never fully secure; an unwanted
Machiavelli shares this suspicion. In a prince who arms his subjects and does not
letter to Guicciardini, written in 1526, he protect himself is even less likely to sur-
equates the building of a fortress with the vive. As his "advice book" proceeds,
enslavement of the Florentines and warns Machiavelli's warning in chapter 5, "who-
that "the most harmful thing a republic ever becomes the ruler of a free city and
can undertake is to enact something does not destroy it, can be expected to be
strong or that easily can be made strong destroyed by it," (P, p. 18) takes on the
within its body" (Machiavelli, 1961, p. character of prophecy. Lorenzo will not
235). He goes on to observe that, if a for­ destroy Florence; that much is clear. His
tress existed in Florence, "any powerful only alternative (if he takes Machiavelli's
man" who conquered the city would, counsel) is to reside in the city. Once
upon entering, find it a convenient therein, Machiavelli will have him adopt
stronghold, and the Florentines "would policies that are, in fact, republican snares
become slaves without any protection" designed to entrap him. He will be
(Machiavelli, 1961, p. 235).8 These obser- destroyed. These are the "ditches and pit-
vations raise yet another puzzle. If Machi­ falls" that lie beneath the seemingly solid
avelli is so convinced of the danger a for­ ground of Machiavelli's advice to his
tress poses to a free Florence and of the Medici lords.
advantages it holds for a prince, then
why, when devising a strategy for the
Medici, does he not recommend the Machiavelli and
building of a fortezza? Indeed, what 'The New Sons of Brutus"
would a Medici prince who is backed by
Spanish troops in a city under siege stand If I read it aright, The Prince is itself an
to gain by not fortifying himself? Yet in act of political deception. In addition to
the face of such facts, and knowing the the deceitful "advice" in the text itself,

788

This content downloaded from 146.155.48.109 on Mon, 09 Mar 2020 16:32:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1986 Machiavelli and Politics of Deception

signs of craf ty assault are also to be found would do well to consider what Machia­
outside Machiavelli's text, and all point in velli has to say in The Discourses about
only one direction: not only was Machia­ "the sagacity and severity of Junius
velli no friend of the Medici; he was a de- Brutus," the "father of Román liberty" (D,
cided enemy. He believed that the Floren- p. 402). We will return to the severity of
tine republic had to rid itself of their con­ Brutus shortly. Let us first consider his
trol if it was to revive and flourish. Other sagacity.
documentary sources and Machiavelli's In book 3, chapter 2 of The Discourses,
own political biography help shore up my Machiavelli notes that more than anyone
case. else, Junius Brutus deserves to be es-
Among Machiavelli scholars, it is teemed for his "simulation of folly" (D, p.
generally agreed that in 1513 he was con­ 403). Having neither the arms ñor the
cerned with getting into the Medici's good forces to mount an open war against the
graces, finding employment, and return- kings of Rome, Brutus instead ingratiated
ing to active political life. According to himself with those in power. On this mat-
Quentin Skinner (1981, p. 21), "As soon ter, Machiavelli takes issue with Livy's in-
as he carne out of prison, Machiavelli terpretation of Brutus's motives and sug-
began scheming to recommend himself to gests a reading of his own:
the city's new authorities." To insure the
success of his scheming, Machiavelli Titus Livius gives but one reason that induced
Brutus to this simulation, namely, that he might
wrote numerous letters to his friend, the live in greater security and preserve his
erstwhile republican Francesco Vettori, patrimony, yet if we well consider his conduct
now the Medici's ambassador to Pope we are led to believe that he had another reason,
Julius II and Machiavelli's only access to which was that by thus avoiding observation he
would have a better chance of destroying the
the corridors of power. At every tum, the kings and of liberating his country, whenever an
political exile appears eager to ingratiate opportunity should offer. (D, p. 403)
himself to the Medici and, through Vet­
tori, to assure the family of his trust- Clearly, Machiavelli not only holds
worthiness, his honesty, and his support. Brutus in great esteem for his simulation
In the famous letter of December 10, of folly, but also for his commitment to
1513, Machiavelli (1961, p. 142) tells Vet­ liberating his country, and he offers
tori of his "little work" On Princedoms Brutus as a model for others who are "dis-
and of his intention to offer it to the new satisfied with their ruler." In Machiavel­
prince, Giuliano, in the hope that the lian terms, if one cannot play the lion and
prince will welcome it and make use of the threaten the prince directly by forcé of
talents of the author. The dedicatory arms, then one must be a fox and under-
pages of The Prince seem to provide fur- mine the enemy from within. "It is ad-
ther evidence that Machiavelli was con­ visable . . . at times to feign folly, as
cerned with promoting the greatness of Brutus did," Machiavelli writes, "and this
the Medici and with assuring their success is sufficiently done by praising, speaking,
through the benefit of his knowledge of seeing and doing things contrary to your
the "art of the state." way of thinking and merely to please the
That Machiavelli was a schemer is prince" (D, p. 404).
beyond doubt. Ñor does there seem to be Interpreters of Machiavelli should be
any question that he was eager to have wary of repeating Livy's mistake about
The Prince gain the eye and approval of Brutus, and so avoid being tricked by ap-
Giuliano and, later, Lorenzo. However, pearances. If Machiavelli had designs on
those who are tempted to read The Prince the Medici, as I think he did, then it seems
as so much Machiavellian opportunism reasonable to expect that he would seek to

789

This content downloaded from 146.155.48.109 on Mon, 09 Mar 2020 16:32:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Amerícan Political Science Review Vol. 80

prove himself a trustworthy advisor, and liberty: "The enjoyment of freedom


so get the Medici to follow his advice. If makes cities and citizens great: this is well
we keep Machiavelli's praise of Brutus's known. But places under tyranny become
sagacity in mind, then his own flattery of deserted by their citizens and engage in
Lorenzo and his appeals to Vettori seem their extermination" (Pitkin, 1984, p.
even less likely to be matters of simple op- 204). Whether Machiavelli knew of
portunism, and rather more- deeply Francesco's speech is uncertain, but its
political. Like Brutus, Machiavelli trades sentiments were in all likelihood passed
on the appearance of friendship and ad- on, for they are clearly evocative of some
miration for his ruler; he "feigns folly" for of the central tenets of The Discourses.
a political purpose—to ingratiate himself In short, there seems little question that
to Lorenzo, thereby earning his trust so the Machiavelli family viewed Piero de
that the prince might be destroyed—much Medici's ouster in 1494 (when Niccoló
as Junius Brutus destroyed the kings and was 25) and the revival of republicanism
restored the liberty of Rome. more favorably than did the aristocratic
There are other reasons to question Tournabuoni, Guicciardini, Strozzi, or
whether Machiavelli was so monomani- Neroni families, who feared for their in-
acally consumed with getting his oíd job terests under a radically republican
back that he simply shed his republican regime. Also, the sentiments of Florence
sympathies and dedicated himself to serv- itself were generally more "Machia-
ing Florence's Medici lords. First, there is vellian" than aristocratic. Piero's three at-
the political history of the Machiavelli tempts to return forcibly were met with
family itself. Though family legacy need armed resistance from the citizenry. Effec-
not determine one's loyalties, it generally tively defeated in 1498—the year Niccoló
serves as a source of personal identity as was appointed Second Chancellor—the
well as of reflection, particularly in an age Medici finally ceased plotting against the
where a family's identification with the republic, retired to their country villas,
political order is of great and lasting im- and left fortuna to do what they could
portance. Machiavelli himself points out not.
in a chapter in The Discourses—straight- In compiling evidence of Machiavelli's
forwardly entitled "Reasons why the same animus toward the Medici, we must, sec-
family in a city always preserves the same ondly, consider some crucial events in his
character"—that what a youth hears own life, as well as the wary view the
praised or censured within his family Medici took of him. Al though the family
"becomes afterwards the rule of his life for was a suspicious lot, they were not wholly
all time" (D, p. 535). As Machiavelli's undiscriminating in their purge of repub-
biographer tells us, the Machiavelli were licans. Thus, when the chancery was reor-
an oíd Florentine family, noted for their ganized in 1512, the First Chancellor,
active participation in Florentine public Marcello Virgilio, was allowed to remain
life and, most significantly, for their in office (Hale, 1961, p. 134). In fact,
devotion to the republic. They gave the Machiavelli was the only chancery official
city some 12 gonfalonieri and 54 priors dismissed by the Medici (Gilbert, 1984, p.
(Ridolfi, 1963, p. 2). As I have noted, 173).9 Without doubt, the Medici re-
Girolamo Machiavelli died in prison garded Machiavelli with considerable
because he dared to speak out against the suspicion. As we know, nearly a decade
oligarchy of Cosimo de Medici, and later they granted him a modest stipend to
another Machiavelli, Francesco, was write his Florentine history, but even
remembered for a public speech in 1424 though his literary skills were gaining
that condemned tyranny and praised fame, his political trustworthiness was

790

This content downloaded from 146.155.48.109 on Mon, 09 Mar 2020 16:32:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1986 Machiavelli and Politics of Deception

still very much in doubt. Indeed, the fam- the latter view, at least in part. His
ily never allowed him back into any posi- famous chapter on conspiracies in The
tion of political power. Discourses (which Buondelmonti must
We must also remember the Boscoli- have read), though filled with advice on
Capponi affair. A few months after his how to conspire, is replete with warnings
removal from office, Machiavelli was im- about the slim chances corispirators have
plicated in a conspiracy against Giuliano for success (D, pp. 410-36). And in his
when his ñame was found on a list in the history, Machiavelli writes, in reference
possession of one of the two young con- to attempted assassinations of the Medici,
spirators. The Medici imprisoned and tor- that "because conspiracies rarely succeed,
tured him on the rack but found out no- they most often bring about the ruin of
thing (Mattingly, 1958, p. 485). Machia­ those who plan them and they bring
velli may have been ignorant of the plotz greatness to those against whom they are
but it is a significant political fact that the directed" (D, p. 263). We might expect,
anti-Mediceans surely perceived him to be then, that Machiavelli's reluctance (if
a potential ally, one who might be reluctance it was) to particípate in con­
counted on for support had the assassina- spiracies owed more to caution than to
tion succeeded. allegiance. Indeed, his republican friends
Nine years later, in 1522, Machiavelli must have taken his noninvolvement in
again fell under suspicion following the their conspiracies (if again, noninvolve­
abortive plot to assassinate Cardinal ment it was) in this latter light, for in
Giulio de Medici. The plot was organized 1527, when the Medici were once again
by two of his closest friends, Zanobi forced from Florence, Buondelmonti and
Buondelmonti (to whom he had dedicated Alamanni, now returned, supported their
The Discourses a few years earlier) and friend's appeal for employment in the
Luigi Alamanni, a poet and fellow restored republic, at a time when the
member of the Oricellari circle. In 1524, "enemies of the republic," Guicciardini
one of the accomplices revealed that and Vettori among them, were being
Buondelmonti had mentioned Machia- called into court (Gilbert, 1984; Ridolfi,
velli's ñame as one of several citizens who 1963).
should be invited to join the plot (Ridolfi, Apart from The Prince, Machiavelli's
1963, p. 203), but by then the dust had writings provide us with some final clues
settled. Buondelmonti and Alamanni had about his attitude toward the Medici.
fled the country, two others had been ex- What he writes in reference to the family
ecuted, and Machiavelli was in refuge in and their supporters is decidedly negative,
San Casciano, writing his Florentine although his true opinión is not always
history. immediately apparent—ñor could it be.
For all we know, Machiavelli may have These were treacherous times and one
or may not have been involved in either risked imprisonment, or worse, if one
or both of these conspiracies. Assuming, spoke too critically of the Medici lords or
conservatively, that he was not, we can their policies. Political tracts and cor-
read this noninvolvement either as a sign respondence had to be crafted slyly; an
that he was loath to conspire against and enemy of the regime had to know how to
more willing to work with the Medici in appear to be loyal, even though he actu-
order to stabilize Florence, or as a sign of ally was not.10
his wariness about the success of conspir­ Machiavelli practices this political
acies in general, even if he wanted to see strategy in the History of Florence. The
the Medici removed from power. What work was not simply an intellectual
Machiavelli writes appears to substantiate endeavor; there were political implica-

791

This content downloaded from 146.155.48.109 on Mon, 09 Mar 2020 16:32:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
American Political Science Review Vol. 80

tions as well, since it had been commis- lower classes with public benefactions and
sioned by Cardinal Guilio, a member oí amusements. In short, the prívate citizen
the Medici family. Machiavelli was not crea tes a coterie of "hangers-on," as
unaware oí the delicacy oí his task. He Machiavelli puts it, in order to advance
wrote to Guicciardini asking f or advice on his own personal goals. Machiavelli's tone
what to say about the family and how to indicates his contempt for such activity
say it. Then he concluded, "I . . . shall and for citizens such as these, who con­
try to act in such a way that, since I tell tribute to the corruption of cities like
the truth, nobody will be able to com- Florence.
plain" (Machiavelli, 1961, p. 206). What We need only match Machiavelli's
we find in the history, particularly in the description of the offensive behavior of
sections devoted to the Medici, is truth prívate citizens with his ostensible praise
telling of a particularly "Machiavellian" of the Medici to see that in extolling the
kind. There are numerous flattering princes he is actually condemning them.
references to the Medici, to be sure. By his account, the Medici are prívate
Machiavelli calis Cosimo, "the most citizens; they corrupt the republic by
famous and respected citizen . . . who playing to factions. Liberality was
ever lived," describes Piero de Medici as a Cosimo's forte. We have already seen that
man of "virtu and goodness" and a great Machiavelli thinks liberality deafens a
citizen, and extolls Lorenzo the Magnifi- people to the cry of liberty and lulls them
cent's beneficience, his contribution to the into forgetting their freedom. Lorenzo
city, his dignity, and his property, dispensed pensions and aid to the nobility
"worthy of a King" (Machiavelli, 1970, and put on toumaments and pageants for
pp. 220, 246, 315-17). In short, Machia- the populace, tactics used by the prívate
velli's truth telling seems designed to cast citizen in order to foster partisan support.
the Medici in the best possible light, and It is Machiavelli's lengthy account of
to play to the cardinal's family pride. Piero's short-lived regime, however, that
A closer reading, however, reveáis a best captures his aversión for Medici
different sort of truth telling. If we put maneuvers, for he gives there a detailed
Machiavelli's assessment of the Medici picture of the ravages of factional and
princes in the context of some of his more party circumstances that plagued Florence
general comments on the corruption of during the Medici years (1970, pp.
Florence, the family does not fare so well. 228-41). In various ways, then, Machia­
At the start of book 7, where he shifts velli shows us how circumstances at once
from a consideration of foreign affairs to necessary for this family's perseverance
"troubles at home," Machiavelli notes were profoundly destructive of Florence
that the unity of a city is threatened most herself.
by the presence of factions and partisans. Guilio's (now Pope Clement) enthusias-
Citizens, he says, can make a reputation tic acceptance of this historical master-
either publicly or privately. The latter work suggests that Machiavelli achieved
course is reprehensible, for "this sort of his goal—writing a truthful account in
behavior gives rise to factions and par­ such a way that nobody complained. He
tisans, and a reputation won in this way is had also, however, registered a distinc-
as offensive as the other kind is valuable" tively "Machiavellian" conviction, one
(Machiavelli, 1970, pp. 214-15). The tac- that took the form of subtle historical
tics employed by prívate citizens inelude analysis: in order to survive, the Floren-
doing good to various other citizens, help- tine republic must rid itself of the
ing someone with money, getting him Medici.11
undeserved honors, and beguiling the We might tum to one final piece of

792

This content downloaded from 146.155.48.109 on Mon, 09 Mar 2020 16:32:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1986 Machiavelli and Politics of Deception

written evidence. Machiavelli's convic- time—suggests there is more at stake for


tion that the Medid were a threat to him here than the mere salvaging of his
Florentine liberty surfaces in The reputation. When evil threatens liberty,
Discourses as well, and returns us to his hopes hang on the sagacity and severity of
discussion of Junius Brutus. If Brutus's those who revere the republic. Brutus met
sagacity enabled him to restore the this test; Soderini failed it, and so
republic of Rome, his severity helped him Florence lost her freedom. In Machia­
to maintain it. The father of the Román velli's eyes, Soderini's great weakness was
republic condemned his own sons to that he did not love the republic enough
death because they were the enemies of to act boldly and eliminate her enemies
liberty, even as he was liberty's defender. before they could conquer Florence and
The lesson Machiavelli (D, p. 405) draws oblitérate liberty.12 Machiavelli's disdain
from Brutus's example is a characteristic for Soderini is outweighed only by his
one; whoever makes himself a tyrant and hatred for those whom Soderini could not
fails to kill Brutus, or restores liberty to a destroy—those who threatened liberty—
former republic and fails to kill the sons of the "new sons of Brutus," the Medici and
Brutus, will not maintain himself for long. their allies.
This seemingly nonpartisan advice is fol-
lowed by an example, that of Piero
Soderini, the deposed gonfalonier of The Prince in Perspective
Florence. Soderini realized that the "new I began by suggesting that Machiavelli's
sons of Brutus" had to be destroyed, but, genius resides in his appreciation of crafty
as Machiavelli (D, p. 405) writes, he did assault in all its guises—the lover's
not have the courage to do it. However, trickery, the general's stratagem, the
Machiavelli's story of Soderini is more prince's artífice—but in truth, Machiavelli
than just a counterexample of the severity directs his most penetrating attention to
of Brutus; what makes it interesting is the the actor/advisor behind the assault, the
moral gloss he adds after telling the tale of one who, observing the scene from a
the fallen gonfalonier: distance, controls the lover, the general,
[O]ne should never allow an evil to run on out of the prince. That is, what Machiavelli ad­
respect for the law, especially when the law itself mires is a kind of Renaissance artistry—a
might easily be destroyed by the evil and strategic perspective—that allows for a
[Soderini] should have born in mind that as his
acts and motives would have to be judged by the unique conception of space or terrain, and
result. . . everybody would have attested that consequently makes possible the manipu-
what he had done was for the good of his coun- lation of persons and events. Ligurio
try and not for the advancement of any am- employs just such a perspective in Man-
bitious purposes of his own. . . . But Soderini
was the dupe of his opinions, not knowing that
dragóla; Fabrizio exhibits it in his
malignity is neither effaced by time, ñor placated topographical advice to generáis in The
by gifts. So that by failing to imítate Brutus he Art of War. But Mandragola and The Art
lost at the same time his country, his state and his of War are simply later versions—one
reputation. (D, p. 406)
dramatic, the other military—of the stra­
Machiavelli's harsh judgment of tegic perspective Machiavelli himself
Soderini can be read cynically, of course; practices as advisor to the prince.
the gonfalonier's decline was Machia­ We might measure Machiavelli's suc-
velli's as well, and he had reason to resent cess as a political advisor who sees things
it. However, the nature of Machiavelli's strategically by the labels he has earned—
criticism—his reference to the "evil" that "political realist" and "master of real-
threatened the country and the "malig­ politik"—and by the statesmen and politi-
nity" that would not disappear over cians, from Metternich to Kissinger, who

793

This content downloaded from 146.155.48.109 on Mon, 09 Mar 2020 16:32:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
American Political Science Review Vol. 80

have adapted his strategic perspective to velli consciously invokes Renaissance ar­
their own times and circumstances. Yet to tistry in its most literal sense, and draws
stop here, as do so many oí the political an analogy between himself, the advisor
scientists and political actors who cite to princes, and the landscape painter:
him, is to overlook a matter of deepest [FJor in the same way that landscape painters sta-
importance to Machiavelli, namely, the tion themselves in the valleys in order to draw
political valúes—republicanism and mountains or high ground and ascend an
liberty—that inform his perspective as ad­ eminence in order to get a good view of the
plains, so it is necessary to be a prince to know
visor to Lorenzo de Medid. When, in the thoroughly the na ture of a people and one of the
introduction to The Discourses, Machia­ populace to know the nature of princes. (P, p. 4)
velli (D, p. 101) tells his friends to "[look]
rather to the intention of him who gives By inviting us to recall the great in-
than to the thing offered," he implicitly novation of Florentine painting—its at-
underscores the distinction between the tention to accurate representation of pic-
apparent meaning of any given work, torial space—Machiavelli also discloses a
political counsel, or strategic perspective necessary quality of the political advisor.
and its deeper purpose. To put this more The intellectual disposition, or, to retum
broadly, political advising involves more to Machiavelli's visual metaphor, the
than the capacity to analyze events or to "vantage point" of the advisor, must be
see things as they "really are/' for the fully dimensional and complete. It encom-
"reality" that informs the analysis is passes the actors and influences that
neither a neutral observation ñor a scien- popúlate and permeate the vast political
tific truth, but a perspective colored by landscape, and thus avoids the restricted
the valúes, purposes, and political com- perspectives of the prince or the populace,
mitments of the advisor who offers them. whose visions are governed solely by their
When these are at odds with the interests respective relationships to one another.
of those in power, the advisor may choose Unlike the actors he observes, the advisor
to retire, to capitúlate, to oppose openly, stands "outside" the political canvas and
or (as Ligurio puts it) "to pursue deceit to integrates particulars into a sweeping con­
its envisioned dearest goal" (Machiavelli, textual visión of reality. He sees actors
1957, p. 38) by painting a particular vi­ not as isolated figures and events not as
sión of reality for the ruler whom he or disconnected instances, but as parts of a
she counsels, with a precise purpose in richly constituted tapestry, a variegated
mind. The latter is Machiavelli's strategy field of competing interests and ambi-
as advisor in The Prince; his purpose is tions. The advisor's special disposition
the restoration of republican liberty. and imagination are, then, the very op-
I want to argüe, then, that there is more posite of the short-sightedness Machia­
involved in Machiavelli's advice in his lit- velli deplores as the mark of politically in-
tle treatise than a presentation of effectual men, those who cannot control
realpolitik, but at the same time suggest events or see beyond their immediate cir­
that his deeper purpose—to deceive—is cumstances.13
not at odds with reading The Prince either But, as I have argued, there is more in­
in terms of a new science or as a work of volved in Machiavelli's advice than a
Renaissance artistry. By way of clarifica- detached depiction of political reality, just
tion, let us consider how Machiavelli as there was more involved in the Renais­
himself depicts his perspective in The sance art of perspective than the achieve-
Prince and thereby gain one final inter- ment of pictorial veracity. In a literal
pretative clue to his aims and intentions. sense, the discovery of perspective also in-
In his dedication to Lorenzo, Machia­ troduced the art of deception to Renais-

This content downloaded from 146.155.48.109 on Mon, 09 Mar 2020 16:32:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1986 Machiavelli and Politics of Deception

sanee painting. Though the depiction of recall the moment in Mandragola where
reality was a central concern for the Machiavelli (1957, p. 25) offers a poetic
painter, it did not involve a simple mir- comment on Ligurio's power and on the
roring of the physical universe. Rather, outrageous gullibility of oíd Nicia:
the painter selected particular elements of
the visible world, then arranged and con- Our doctor here, would not suspect a lie
If he were told that jackasses can fly;
veyed them so as to give the illusion of He has a heart so set on fatherhood,
reality (Brucker, 1969). This act of artistic That he's forgotten every other good.
deception involved more than a dazzling
display of technical virtuosity; also vital Ligurio can deceive Nicia because of his
to it was the relationship the painter strategic perspective. He knows how to
forged between the illusion he presented play upon the oíd man's desires and to
and the person who observed it. Thinking organize his field of choices by advancing
of his canvas as a window through which some altematives and concealing others.
he viewed the world, the artist sought to He makes the prospect of Nicia's fathering
convey the illusion as reality, and to a child so palpable that this promise of
stimulate the observer's emotions and living on comes to control Nicia's world,
sense of possibility (Ackerman, 1969; his sensibilities, and his every perception.
Brucker, 1958). From "inside" the paint­ Thus the oíd doctor is trapped; duped not
ing, the artist tantalized his observers only by Ligurio's wiles but by his own
with a seductive vista and pulled them vanity, his grandiose expectations set the
toward a point or prospect that seemed stage for his becoming the cuckold.
attainable. At its most powerful, perspec- If we bring our own strategic perspec­
tival art induced the viewers into actually tive to The Prince and look to the rela­
feeling a part of the painting, as though tionship Machiavelli establishes between
they could step into it and secure the pro­ his text and its intended reader, we might
spect that beckoned them. The artist per- see a political versión of Ligurian decep­
formed a feat of aesthetic manipulation tion at work. Machiavelli offers Lorenzo
even as he accomplished an act of pic- the promise of a different sort of
torial veracity. He used his science to pro­ fatherhood—the fathering of the state
duce a material work of deception, an art. of Italy. Machiavelli's strategy is Ligurian
In much the same way as the art of —to promise greatness to the Medici
deception is a distinguishing characteristic lord and thus render him susceptible
of Renaissance perspectival painting, so it to the further flatteries that will, in
is a part of Machiavelli's strategic perspec- fact, undo him. Nowhere in The Prince is
tive in The Prince. Just as we can only ap- the Ligurian strategy as evident as in the
preciate the artist's act of aesthetic mani­ famous chapter 26. There Machiavelli
pulation if we consider how the painting paints the prospect of the prince as
plays upon the observer's sensory impres- saviour of Italy, leader of his people,
sions and "tactile valúes" (Berenson, unifier of the fractious city-states, forever
1909, p. 11), so we can confirm Machia­ immortalized by his power and glory. The
velli's act of political manipulation only if passion and spirit of these Machiavellian
we consider how The Prince as text plays declamations have long troubled many of
upon his reader's—Lorenzo de Medici's— his interpreters, who puzzle over the
valúes, desires, and sense of political marked contrast between this final
possibility. Machiavelli will entice chapter and the coid calculation of the
Lorenzo with a visión that will over- rest of The Prince. However, the
whelm his every other thought and distort troublesomeness of chapter 26 begins to
his senses. With this in mind, we might recede if we remember that technical

This contení downloaded from 146.155.48.109 on Mon, 09 Mar 2020 16:32:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
American Political Science Review Vol. 80

precisión and vivid imagination were no The deceiver himself would have a wry
strangers to the Renaissance painter ñor, and ready answer: Fortuna, that mysteri-
for that matter to Ligurio as he set out to ous goddess who govems half our ac-
trap his prey. Accordingly, we might read tions, thwarted his plans and fouled his
Machiavelli's final cali to action as the chances for success. As the chronicler tells
"bait," or, to return once more to perspec- it, on the day Machiavelli presented The
tival art, as the "vista" he offers Lorenzo. Prince at the palace, Lorenzo was also
If the chapter does its work, Lorenzo, like given a gift of greyhounds, an unfortu-
Nicia, will "forget every other good" and nate circumstance indeed, for the Medici
so become not only Machiavelli's puppet, lord was more intrigued with his hounds
but the dupe of his own grandiose expec- than with princely govemance (Barincou,
tations of earthly power and political im- 1961, pp. 76-78). Yet there is more to the
mortality. tum of fortune's wheel than this. Despite
Thus, Machiavelli sets out to manipú­ the greyhounds, it is hard to imagine why
late the dimensions of Lorenzo's world. Lorenzo, a suspicious prince, would have
After presenting a particular scope of taken this former republican, this man-
possibilities in The Prince, he artfully nar- nerino of Soderini, into his confidence in
rows the field of choices so that, in the the first place. Machiavelli's every at-
end, the prince will live, act, and arm tempt to appear to be other than he was
himself in the manner that his advisor in the end was no match for his unblem-
recommends. Thus Machiavelli performs ished reputation as a Florentine republi­
a feat of crafty assault, even as he accom- can, and so The Prince remained unread
plishes an act of political veracity. and Machiavelli unsummoned, forced to
Lorenzo will be lured into following his return to the countryside, where he
advisor's dangerous counsel even as he divided his days between the "ancient
reads this indeed unprecedented work of courts" and his favorite and altogether ap-
realpolitik. The beauty of the deception, propriate pastime—snaring thrushes with
were it to work, lies in Lorenzo's belief his bare hands (Ridolfi, 1963, p. 140).
that his acts follow from his own virtü His misfortune takes yet one more tum,
and seem perfectly in keeping with his aim however, and the story is well known.
to maintain power in life and achieve When the republic was restored in 1527,
glory after death, while in reality they Machiavelli eagerly reapplied for his oíd
work to restore the republic. job at the Second Chancery. The new
republicans, however, were suspicious—
Postscript at the least they viewed him as an untrust-
worthy opportunist, at the most as a pro-
As a text, The Prince succeeded in Medicean. They had, it seems, been more
securing Machiavelli's future fame and in successfully duped by The Prince than
sealing his notoriety. As a trap, it secured Lorenzo himself, and they too refused to
nothing. From all we know, Lorenzo allow Machiavelli's return to political life.
never even read it. The republic Machia­ The irony is hard to miss: Machiavelli
velli wanted so passionately to see revived had, quite simply, outfoxed himself.
in Florence did indeed come later, but by Whatever misfortune was dealt this
different means than he envisioned and master of deception, however, his designs
for but three short years, after which the in The Prince now seem clear. We need
Medici were installed in the city again. only to remember circumstances and
How could Machiavelli's stratagem have recall what the chronicler reports on the
come to naught? How could his trap have occasion when the advice book was
failed to spring as he had hoped? eclipsed by the hounds. Upon leaving the

796

This content downloaded from 146.155.48.109 on Mon, 09 Mar 2020 16:32:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1986 Machiavelli and Politics of Deception

Medid palace, Machiavelli was said to tresses; in fact, his discussion centers not upon their
have muttered that "though he was not a usefulness but upon their size, their relation to sur-
rounding ditches, the design of portculisses, and the
man to plot against princes, his little book like. Machiavelli (1965, pp. 183-94) seems to be sug-
would avenge him" (Barincou, 1961, p. gesting that fortresses are both important and
78). Far from avenging him, The Prince necessary. In The Discourses, however, he appears
has for five centuries accused this Floren- resolutely opposed to fortresses, deeming them both
tine patriot. His vindication is long over- "unnecessary" and "injurious" to prince and republic
alike. "Good armies," he writes, will suffice instead
due. of citadels (D, p. 365). The fact remains, however,
that Machiavelli argües against a fortezza in The
Notes Prince, and the advice, whatever else it is, is fully in
keeping with Florentine republican sensibilities.
The research for this article was supported by a 8. Machiavelli's thesis was tested dramatically in
Summer Research Fellowship from the University of 1534, when Alessandro de Medici not only disarmed
Minnesota. I thank Terence Ball, J. Peter Euben, the Florentines, but also constructed a fortress. The
James Farr, and Joan Tronto for their careful reading Fortezza da Basso secured Alessandro from his sub-
and helpful criticisms of my argument, and Norman jects, but not from his cousin Lorenzino, who assas-
Jacobson for the inspiration behind it. sinated him in bed in 1537. More importantly,
1. In intemational relations, see Waltz (1954) and however, it seems Machiavelli's prediction was ac-
Gulick (1955); in comparative politics, see Bluhm curate—Florentine republicanism was never
(1965); in organization theory, see Pfeffer (1981); in restored. Hale (1968, p. 502) notes that the Fortezza
political psychology, see Nardulli, Flemming, and da Basso was "the visible evidence that freedom was
Eisenstein (1984). in fetters."
2. See, among others, Wolin (1960), Pocock 9. Machiavelli's dismissal seems to have been
(1975), Shumer (1979), Skinner (1981), Hulliung motivated by at least three factors: (1) his special
(1983), and Pitkin (1984). friendship with Gonfalonier Soderini (he was con-
3. Quotations from Machiavelli's works are cited temptuously known as Soderini's mannerino);
in the text using the following abbreviations: P: The (2) the hostility of the pro-Medicean aristocracy,
Prince (1950, pp. 3-98); D: The Discourses (1950, who never ceased viewing Machievelli as an enemy
pp. 101-540). of their class and a supporter of the republican
4. In a related fashion. J.R. Hale (1961, p. 175) cause; and (3) his reputation as the organizer of the
suggests that Machiavelli thought "regeneration can Florentine civilian militia that had fought the Medici
be best organized by a prince, but when he feels that and their Spanish allies at Prato (see Gilbert, 1984,
civic virtue has been restored, he should retire." Yet pp. 172-74; Hale, 1961, pp. 134-35; and Ridolfi,
surely Machiavelli would not think that a prince 1963, pp. 130-32).
would simply "retire" after restoring civic virtue or, 10. Although my argument bears some similaríty
for that matter, be interested in restoring the only to that of Leo Strauss, especially as expressed in his
virtue Machiavelli considers "civic"—republican- Persecution and the Árt of Writing (1952), the dif-
ism. He knows too much of political rulership and ferences seem to me much more important. Strauss
Renaissance Florence to expect that. (1952, p. 33) excepts Machiavelli's ñame in his list of
5. Machiavelli (P, p. 78) offers one exception to persecuted writers, but surely Machiavelli was po-
this armament rule: the prince who acquires a new litically persecuted; we have the biographical
state in addition to the oíd one where his troops are evidence, and Machiavelli himself (circumspectly)
stationed should disarm the former. However, this expresses as much on a number of occasions
exception does not apply to the Medici, who were in (Machiavelli, P, p. 4; 1961, pp. 10, 104, 143-44). 1
exile as prívate citizens before their retum to suspect that Strauss did not inelude the Florentine in
Florence and in control of no "oíd" state. his list because of his commitment to reading
6. Furthermore, circumstances did not change Machiavelli as a teacher of evil and his writings as
dramatically. A report on Lorenzo, made in 1515 by "immoral and irreligious" (Strauss, 1958, p. 12), a
the Venetian ambassador, notes: "This Lorenzo has view that often blinds him to the historical context
been made captain of the Florentines against their and the political and biographical circumstances we
own laws. He has become ruler of Florence: he must bring to bear upon our understanding of
orders and is obeyed. . . . They used to cast lots; no Machiavelli's aims and intentions.
longer ... the majority of the Florentines have no 11. A number of scholars have drawn this conclu­
taste for the power of the house of Medici" (Hale, sión on the basis of their reading of The History of
1977, p. 99). Florence as so much Machiavellian dissembling (see
7. Overall, Machiavelli's advice on fortresses is Gilbert, 1977, pp. 82-92; Najemy, 1982, pp. 575-76;
ambiguous and could be a short essay in itself. In and Skinner, 1981, pp. 84-86).
The Art of War, Fabrizio never advises against for­ 12. Ridolfi (1963, p. 203) cites an epitaph Machia-

797

This content downloaded from 146.155.48.109 on Mon, 09 Mar 2020 16:32:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
American Political Science Review Vol. 80

velli wrote for Soderini that gives graphic evidence Rubinstein, ed., Florentine Studies: Politics and
of his Opinión of the man who might have saved the Society in Renaissance Florence. London: Farber
republic but had not the virtú to do so: and Farber.
The night Pier Soderini died Hale, John Rigby. 1977. Florence and the Medici.
His soul went to the mouth of Hell; London: Thames and Hudson.
And Pluto cried: Silly soul, Hulliung, Mark. 1983. Citizen Machiavelli. Prince-
Why come to Hell? ton: Princeton University Press.
Go to Limbo with the Infants. Machiavelli, Niccoló. 1950. The Prince and the Dis-
13. Wolin (1960, pp. 21-22, 203-9) quite rightly courses. Luigi Ricci, trans. New York: Modem
characterizes similar attributes as part of the Library. Pp. 3-98; 101-540, respectively.
political theorist's vocation, Machiavelli's included. (Original works published in 1532 and 1531.)
However, the tensión between the role of "advisor" Machiavelli, Niccoló. 1957. Mandragola. Anne and
and the vocation of "theorist" is equally important, Henry Paolucci, trans. New York: Bobbs-
and though beyond the scope of this essay, deserves Merrill.
more concentrated attention. Machiavelli, Niccoló. 1961. Letters. Alian Gilbert,
trans. New York: Capricorn.
Machiavelli, Niccoló. 1965. The Art of War. Ellis
References Fameworth, trans. Indianapolis and New York:
Bobbs-Merrill. (Original work published in
Ackerman, James. 1969. Concluding Remarks: 1521.)
Science and Art in the Work of Leonardo. In Machiavelli, Niccoló. 1970. The History of Florence.
Charles Donald O'Malley, ed., Leonardo’s New York: Washington Square Press. (Original
Legacy. Berkeley: University of California Press. work published in 1532.)
Barincou, Edmond. 1961. Machiavelli. H. Lañe, Mattingly, Garrett. 1958. Machiavelli's Prince: Po­
trans. New York and London: Grove Press and litical Science or Political Satire? American
Evergreen Books. Scholar, 27:482-91.
Barón, Hans. 1961. Machiavelli: The Republican Najemy, John. 1982. Machiavelli and the Medici:
Citizen and the Author of The Prince. English The Lessons of Florentine History. Renaissance
Historical Review, 299:217-53. Quarterly, 35:551-76.
Berenson, Bemhard. 1909. The Florentine Painters Nardulli, Peter, Roy Flemming, and James Eisen-
of the Renaissance. New York: Putnam's Sons. stein. 1984. Unraveling the Complexities of Deci­
Bluhm, William. 1965. Theories of the Political sión Making in Face-to-Face-Groups: A Contex­
System: Classics of Political Thought and tual Analysis of Plea-Bargained Sentences.
Modem Political Analysis. Englewood Cliffs: American Political Science Review, 78:912-27.
Prentice Hall. Pansini, Anthony. 1969. Niccolo Machiavelli and
Brucker, Gene. 1969. Renaissance Florence. the United States of América. Greenvale, NY:
Berkeley: University of California Press. Greenvale Press.
Burckhardt, Jacob. 1958. The Civilization of the Pfeffer, Jeffrey. 1981. Power in Organizations.
Renaissance in Italy. 2 vols. New York: Harper Marshfield, MA: Pitman Press.
and Row. Pitkin, Hanna Fenichel. 1984. Fortune Is a Woman.
Gentili, Alberico. 1924. De legationibus libri tres Berkeley: University of California Press.
[Three books about legations). New York: Ox­ Pocock, J. G. A. 1975. The Machiavellian Moment.
ford University Press. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Gilbert, Alian. 1938. Machiavelli's Prince and Its Ridolfi, Roberto. 1963. The Life of Niccolo Machia­
Forerunners. Durham, NC: Duke University velli. Chicago: University of Chicago. (Original
Press. work published in 1954.)
Gilbert, Félix. 1977. Machiavelli's Istorie Fiorentine. Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. 1978. On the Social Con-
In Myron P. Gilmore, ed., Studies on Machia­ tract. Judith Masters, trans. New York: St. Mar-
velli. Florence: G. C. Sansoni. tin's Press. (Original work published in 1782.)
Gilbert, Félix. 1984. Machiavelli and Guicciardini: Rubinstein, Nicolai. 1968. Constitutionalism and
Politics and History in 16th Century Florence. Medici Ascendency. In Nicolai Rubinstein, ed.,
New York and London: W. W. Norton and Co. Florentine Studies. London: Farber and Farber.
Gulick, Edward Vose. 1955. Europe’s Classical Rubinstein, Nicolai. 1972. Machiavelli and the
Balance of Power: A Case History of One of the World of Florentine Politics. In Myron Piper
Great Concepts of European Statecraft. Ithaca: Gilmore, ed., Studies on Machiavelli. Florence:
Comell University Press. G. C. Sansoni.
Hale, John Rigby. 1961. Machiavelli and Renais­ Schevill, Ferdinand. 1936. History of Florence from
sance Italy. London: English University Press. the Founding of the City Through the Renais­
Hale, John Rigby. 1968. The End of Florentine sance. New York: Ungar Publishing Company.
Liberty: The Fortezza da Basso. In Nicolai Shumer, Sara. 1979. Machiavelli: Republican Pol-

798

This content downloaded from 146.155.48.109 on Mon, 09 Mar 2020 16:32:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1986 Machiavelli and Politics of Deception

itics and Its Corruption. Political Theory, 7:5-34. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Skinner, Quentin. 1981. Machiavelli. New York: Wackemagel, Martín. 1981. The World of the
Hill & Wang. Florentine Renaissance Artist. Alison Luchs,
Spinoza, Benedictus de. 1962. Tractatus politicus trans. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
[Political treatise]. T. E. Jessop, trans. Montreal: Waltz, Kenneth. 1954. Man, the State, and War:
M. Caselini. (Original work published in 1677.) A Theoretical Analysis. New York: Columbia
Strauss, Leo. 1952. Persecution and the Art of Writ- University Press.
ing. Glencoe, IL: Free Press. Wolin, Sheldon. 1960. Politics and Visión. Boston:
Strauss, Leo. 1958. Thoughts on Machiavelli. Little, Brown and Co.

Mary G. Dietz is Assistant Professor of Political Science, University of Minnesota,


Minneapolis, MN 55455.

799

This content downloaded from 146.155.48.109 on Mon, 09 Mar 2020 16:32:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms

You might also like