You are on page 1of 15

Revista Colombiana de Matemáticas

Volumen 53(2019)2, páginas 205-219

Existential Graphs on nonplanar


surfaces
Gráficos existenciales sobre superficies no planas

Arnold Oostra

Universidad del Tolima, Ibagué, Colombia

Abstract. Existential graphs on the plane constitute a two-dimensional rep-


resentation of classical logic, in which a Jordan curve stands for the negation
of its inside. In this paper we propose a program to develop existential Alpha
graphs, which correspond to propositional logic, on various surfaces. The ge-
ometry of each manifold determines the possible Jordan curves on it, leading
to diverse interpretations of negation. This may open a way for appointing a
“natural” logic to any surface.
Key words and phrases. Existential graphs, 2-dimensional topological manifolds,
Jordan’s Curve Theorem.
2010 Mathematics Subject Classification. 03B99, 14H99.

Resumen. Los gráficos existenciales sobre el plano constituyen una repre-


sentación bidimensional de la lógica clásica, en la cual una curva de Jordan
indica la negación de su interior. En este artı́culo se propone un programa para
desarrollar los gráficos existenciales Alfa, que corresponden a la lógica proposi-
cional, sobre diferentes superficies. La geometrı́a de cada variedad determina
las posibles curvas de Jordan sobre ella, lo cual conduce a interpretaciones
diversas de la negación. Esto puede abrir el camino para asignar una lógica
“natural” a cualquier superficie.
Palabras y frases clave. Gráficos existenciales, 2-variedades topológicas, teorema
de la curva de Jordan.

1. Introduction
Existential graphs, which were considered by his creator Charles S. Peirce his
chef d’œvre [11], may be seen as a geometric representation of mathematical
logic. In this system, logical formulas are laid out as two-dimensional diagrams

205
206 ARNOLD OOSTRA

on the plane and inference is attained by appropriate graphical transformations


on this figures. Just as geometry changes when the plane is replaced by a
different surface, if existential graphs are drawn on a non planar surface the
outcoming system most surely corresponds to some non classical logic. This
paper is an incipient inquiry into the general features of systems of existential
graphs on surfaces different from the plane. Possibly, it is also the first time
that Geometry returns through existential graphs to Logic, if not results at
least some genuine mathematical problems.
In this first approach we will consider only propositional logic, which is ex-
pressed graphically by the subsystem of existential graphs called Alpha. Section
2 contains an elementary introduction to classical Alpha graphs and a descrip-
tion of the role of Jordan’s Curve Theorem in this setting. In section 3 we
embark on the adventure of studying existential (Alpha) graphs on a number
of different surfaces. In this paper we will consider only the representation of
propositional formulas, leaving the general study of the transformation rules
on surfaces as an open problem. In section 4 we slightly enter into the logical
interpretation of mappings between surfaces. Finally, in section 5 we draw some
conclusions and also pose a few suggestions for future research.

2. Alpha Graphs and Jordan’s Curve Theorem on the plane


The basic components of the Alpha graph system are, in Peirce’s terminology,
the sheet of assertion, the propositional letters, and cuts that are simple, closed
curves. In any Alpha graph drawn on the sheet there are finitely many letters or
cuts, and this components never touch each other although a cut may appear
around other components, including other cuts. An area is a portion of the
sheet limited by cuts, and an area is even or odd according to the number of
cuts drawn around it.
The basic interpretation of Alpha graphs consists in two conventions. First-
ly, writing a letter means to assert the proposition it stands for; writing two
letters together means to assert both; in general, drawing a graph means to
assert it. On the other hand, enclosing a letter or a graph means to negate the
content of the cut. In this way, we obtain the graphs of the basic propositional
connectives shown on Figure 1.
The rules of transformation for Alpha graphs are the following:

1. Erasure in even. On an even area, any graph may be erased.

2. Insertion in odd. On an odd area, any graph may be drawn.

3. Inward iteration. Any graph may be iterated on its own area or inside
any cut contained in it, as long as this cut is not part of the iterated graph.

4. Deiteration from the outside. Any graph whose occurrence could be the
result of iteration may be erased.

Volumen 53, Número 2, Año 2019


EXISTENTIAL GRAPHS ON NONPLANAR SURFACES 207

¬A A

A∧B A B

A∨B A B

A→B A B

Figure 1. Alpha graphs for propositional connectives.

5. Double cut. A double cut, consisting of two nested cuts without letters or
cuts in the area between them, may be drawn or erased around any graph
on any area.

These rules are sufficient for the complete development of propositional


logic in a graphical way. For instance, Figure 2 shows a diagrammatic proof
of modus ponens. For more details about existential graphs, both Alpha, Beta
and Gamma, for Peirce’s views on assertion, and for different proofs of the
equivalence between Propositional logic and Alpha graphs, see [1, 2, 4, 10, 11,
12, 13, 14].

A B A 4 B 5 1
⇒ A ⇒ B A ⇒ B

Figure 2. Proof of modus ponens by means of Alpha graphs.

Alpha graphs can be defined in a formal way as topological objects. As a


model for the sheet of assertion we take the Cartesian plane R2 with its usual
structure; a cut is a simple closed curve or Jordan curve, that can be defined
as a continous injective function from the unit circle to the plane; at last, we
represent a letter as a function (which is always continuous and injective) from
the unit set to the plane. An Alpha pre-graph is an injective sum of a finite
set of these functions, here the injectivity means that the different cuts do not
touch each other nor the letters. Finally, an Alpha graph is an isotopy class of
Alpha pre-graphs [9].
The celebrated Jordan’s Theorem states that every Jordan curve divides
the plane into two connected components, one of them bounded (the “inside”)
and the other unbounded (the “outside”), and that every point of the curve

Revista Colombiana de Matemáticas


208 ARNOLD OOSTRA

is adherent to both regions [3, 5]. From this result it follows that n disjoint
Jordan curves divide the plane into n + 1 connected components, n of them
bounded and just one unbounded (the “outside”).
In the framework of existential graphs, a first consequence of Jordan’s Curve
Theorem is that the logic on the sheet of assertion has two truth values. Since
the cuts correspond to Jordan curves and the areas are exactly the connected
components of the complement of the curves, a cut divides the sheet into just
two areas specifying as many truth values. But a deeper effect of Jordan’s
Theorem is that n cuts define n + 1 areas and that, among all these areas, there
is one which is easily distinguishable. This is the unbounded component, which
conventionally is associated with the truth value True. Hence, all other areas
are automatically assorted into True or False according to their separation
from the unbounded area by an even or odd number of cuts. This is another
way to state the idea, basic to the theory of existential graphs, that an area
is even or odd according to the number of cuts that enclose it. This parity
is essential in the application of the rules of Erasure and Insertion. Moreover,
the way of counting the areas from the outmost, i.e. the only unbounded one,
provides a natural orientation in the structure of the graphs which was called
by Peirce endoporeutic [11]. At its turn, this orientation is crucial in the use of
the rules of Iteration and Deiteration.
In the clearly intended interpretation of existential graphs, the sheet of
assertion relates to an intuitive notion of truth since every graph drawn on
it is automatically asserted. A cut constitutes a rupture with this truth, but
on the sheet as a whole it remains obvious with which of the two regions the
truth is related. Hence, in a natural way, in this system there is one unique
or “absolute” truth, given by the only unbounded component. Also, there is
only one kind of negation, expressed by a cut, that ascribes to the enclosed
component the truth value which is contrary to the value of the component
where the cut is drawn.

3. Shifting towards other surfaces


Even though Jordan’s Theorem generalizes to higher dimensions, it also makes
sense to ponder its validity on different surfaces because the definition of a
Jordan curve in this setting is straightforward. Here a surface is a topological
2-manifold [7, 8], which includes but is not restricted to differential manifolds
and also Riemann surfaces. If we regard a surface as a generalized sheet of
assertion, then we can view a Jordan curve on it as the cut of a certain system
of Alpha graphs. Depending on the surface’s geometry, these new existential
graphs allow the interpretation of some or all propositional connectives. An
adequate adaptation of the transformation rules gives rise to a deductive system
or “logic” that we may reckon as been distinctive of the selected surface.
Just like in Geometry, on every surface we will find a local logic and a
global one. In the local case, since the manifold has dimension 2, every point

Volumen 53, Número 2, Año 2019


EXISTENTIAL GRAPHS ON NONPLANAR SURFACES 209

has an open neighborhood which is homeomorphic to the plane R2 . If we restrict


our attention to Jordan curves that are completely contained in such an open
set, thus considering only graphs which are “small” compared to the whole
surface, all diagrams on this subset behave like they were drawn on the plane.
In some varieties the open sets homeomorphic to the plane fall apart into
bounded an unbounded ones. If the open set is unbounded then Jordan’s Curve
Theorem holds exactly as on the plane, hence the definition of even and odd
areas resembles completely the original Alpha graphs and the logic is classical.
If the open set is bounded in some sense, it is anyway homeomorphic to R2
and its boundary corresponds to the point at infinity. In this way, it suffices to
assign the truth value True to the boundary and then again we can regard the
“small” graphs just as if it were plane graphs. In both cases the value True is
attached to what is “far away”.

Remark 3.1. On any surface, every open set homeomorphic to R2 has a local
logic given by a system of Alpha graphs that is equivalent to the Alpha graphs
on the plane.

Hence, the local logic on any surface is the two-valued classical logic. Fur-
thermore, the veritable interest in studying existential graphs on surfaces lies
in its global logic, which according to the selected manifold most assuredly has
interesting and meaningful differences with classical logic.
In the next paragraphs we will ponder the attributes of such a global logic
on some particular surfaces.

3.1. The sphere

On this surface, Jordan’s Theorem states that a Jordan curve divides the sphere
into two connected components, both of them bounded [6]. Therefore, n disjoint
Jordan curves divide it into n + 1 connected and bounded components, see
Figure 3.
Since there is no natural way to highlight one spherical component over
the rest, the global logic on the sphere lacks any “absolute” truth. Even if this
logic is two-valued, given a certain area it is altogether unfeasible to decide
whether it is True or False. This implies that if two graphs are drawn on
the same component of the sphere we may not regard this juxtaposition as a
conjunction, again because there is no way to determine whether the graphs
are both True or both False. The only thing that can be said with certainty is
that these graphs are congruent or equivalent in some sense. On the contrary,
if the graphs are drawn on two adjacent components they are incongruent or
opposite, but again it is impossible to label any of them as True or False.
Regarding to some form of the double negation principle, we can extend
the above conventions to more curves between the components. Thus, in the
Alpha graphs on the sphere two areas are defined to be equivalent if they are

Revista Colombiana de Matemáticas


210 ARNOLD OOSTRA

Figure 3. Jordan curves on the sphere.

separated by an even number of cuts, and opposite if they are separated by


an odd number. About this two relations it would be feasible to decide, in a
metalogical way, whether they are true or false about given areas and about
graphs contained in them. In some sense this relations are consistent with
the usual connectives biconditional ↔ and exclusive disjunction ∨, which are
complementary to each other in classical logic.
Thus, the global logic on the sphere might merely express this two relations,
equivalence and oppositeness, as well as the interplay between them. Hence this
logic may correlate to the segment of classical propositional logic given by two
connectives, biconditional and exclusive disjunction. Although it seems a rather
poor logic, its generality and symmetry may turn out to be powerful.
With respect to the rules of transformation it seems reasonable to keep the
freedom to draw or erase a double cut. About all other rules it is clear that
they can not maintain their original form because on the sphere there are no
even or odd areas, and there is no endoporeutic direction. Most certainly the
rules should be thought of in a relative way.
Some of the above findings are true for any closed surface, i.e. for any
compact 2-manifold without boundary, regardless of its genus. Of course, the
surface should be connected.

Remark 3.2. The global logic on a connected closed surface has no “abso-
lute” truth and, consequently, the areas have no evenness nor endoporeutic
orientation.

3.2. The cylinder

We consider a right circular cylinder unbounded in both directions, or in a


homeomorphic presentation, a bounded circular cylinder without borders. On

Volumen 53, Número 2, Año 2019


EXISTENTIAL GRAPHS ON NONPLANAR SURFACES 211

this surface there are two essentially different kinds of Jordan curves: those
that are contractible to a point (by means of a homotopy on the cylinder) and
those that are not contractible because they circle the cylinder once, see Figure
4. Contractible curves correspond to the trivial element of the fundamental
group, while non-contractible give rise to a generator of this group which is
infinite cyclic, or isomorphic to Z. In another sense, contractible curves are
contained in an open subset homeomorphic to the plane, but non-contractible
are not contained in any such a subset. Finally, contractible curves divide the
cylinder into two connected components, one bounded and another unbounded,
while non-contractible divide the surface into two components which are both
unbounded. This last distinction comprises Jordan’s Curve Theorem on this
manifold: on the cylinder a Jordan curve divides the surface into two connected
components. These components can be one bounded and one unbounded, or
else both unbounded.

Figure 4. Jordan curves on the cylinder.

The global logic on the cylinder has two “relative” truths given by the two
unbounded ends, and two kinds of negations associated to the two types of
cuts. A contractible cut means the negation of the bounded area or inside with
respect to the unbounded or outside. Hence, in any graph, an area might be
considered True or False regarding any of the relative truths if it is separated
from the appointed end by an even or odd number of cuts. On the other hand,
a non-contractible cut that turns around the cylinder is a negation that sets
up an antithesis between the relative truths. Since the cuts on the cylinder are
intrinsically different, it seems reasonable that the negations represented by
them have also distinct behavior. In case that the negation associated with non-
contractible cuts satisfies the double negation principle, then an even number of
this cuts drawn on the cylinder indicate that the relative truths are equivalent,
while an odd number of non-contractible cuts mean that they are opposite.
Under this circumstances, if the relative truths are compatible then every area
has only one truth value and the logic becomes classical; on the contrary, if

Revista Colombiana de Matemáticas


212 ARNOLD OOSTRA

they are opposite then every area is True with respect to one relative truth
and False with respect to the other.

Figure 5. Jordan curves on a cylinder with four unbounded ends.

We can generalize this construction. A cylinder with three unbounded ends is


like a three-way pipe joint; a cylinder with four unbounded ends is the inter-
section of two common cylinders, like a four-way fitting, see Figure 5. More
generally, we can consider a surface with n unbounded cylindrical ends. The
logic determined by Alpha graphs on such a manifold has n relative truths.
The non-contractible cuts around this surface describe the compatibilities be-
tween these truths, while a contractible cut just expresses the negation of the
bounded inside with respect to the unbounded outside. Every area will have
n truth values, each one with respect to a certain relative truth: it is True or
False whether the area is separated from the appointed end by an even or odd
number of cuts. Again, if the negation given by the non-contractible cuts sat-
isfies the double negation principle and all relative truths are equivalent, then
each area has an unique truth value and the logic becomes classical.

3.3. The Möbius strip

We consider the Möbius strip without border, i.e. as a non-bounded surface.


Any contractible Jordan curve on this well-known surface divides it into two

Volumen 53, Número 2, Año 2019


EXISTENTIAL GRAPHS ON NONPLANAR SURFACES 213

connected components, one bounded and another unbounded, just as on the


cylinder and on the plane. This curves are contained in an open set homeomor-
phic to the plane and they determine the trivial element of the fundamental
group. But on the Möbius strip there are also non-contractible Jordan curves
over the length of the band. This “long” curves are not contained in any open
set homeomorphic to R2 and originate a non-trivial element of the fundamental
group, which again is isomorphic to Z. But there are two different types of this
curves along the Möbius strip: in one case, the curve traces two turns along the
surface and divides it again into two connected components, one bounded and
another unbounded (see Figure 6); in the other case, the curve draws a single
turn along the Möbius strip and does not divide it into two components, (see
Figure 7). This last type of curve determines a generator of the fundamental
group and is completely contained in the bounded component delimited by
any curve of the preceding class. In brief, a Jordan curve on the Möbius strip
divides it into two connected components or not. If it divides the surface, one
component is bounded and the other is not.

Figure 6. Separating Jordan curves on the Möbius strip.

Revista Colombiana de Matemáticas


214 ARNOLD OOSTRA

In the global logic on the Möbius strip there is just one “absolute” truth, but
there are at least two kinds of negations. As always, a cut on the strip that
divides it into a bounded area and an unbounded one expresses the negation
of the bounded inside with respect to the unbounded outside. So far, this logic
seems close to classical logic, although it remains to clarify the meaning of
the non-contractible cuts. But on this surface there are also cuts that do not
mark out two different areas, which is a novel and quite strange element of this
graphs. What does it mean, in the framework of existential graphs, to draw
a cut that does not divide the sheet of assertion? One fact we can point out
in this juncture is that, since different cuts are always disjoint in existential
graphs, if on the Möbius strip we draw a cut that does not divide it then we
may not trace another with the same peculiarity.

Figure 7. A non-separating Jordan curve on the Möbius strip.

3.4. The torus

On this surface there are again two different kinds of Jordan curves. Con-
tractible curves are contained in an open set homeomorphic to the plane, gen-
erate the trivial element of the fundamental group and divide the torus into
two connected and bounded components. On the other hand, there are non-
contractible curves not contained in any open set homeomorphic to R2 , that
give rise to a non-trivial generator of the fundamental group (which is isomor-
phic to Z × Z), and do not divide the torus into two components. For this last
kind of curves there are various different possibilities: a Jordan curve may circle
the “hole” of the torus once, or it may circle the “body” of the torus once, or
describe a spiral around the body of the torus, or else a spiral around the hole,
see Figure 8. These options correspond to elements (1, 0), (0, 1), (1, m) and
(n, 1) in the fundamental group, and each of them generates an infinite cyclic

Volumen 53, Número 2, Año 2019


EXISTENTIAL GRAPHS ON NONPLANAR SURFACES 215

subgroup. Thus, a Jordan curve divides the torus into two connected compo-
nents, both bounded, or else does not divide it, for which there are multiple
possibilities.

Figure 8. Jordan curves on the torus.

The global logic on the torus has no “absolute” truth by Remark 3.2, and there
are at least two kinds of negations. A cut on the torus that divides it into two
components expresses the incompatibility or antagonism between the separated
areas, in a similar way to the logic on the sphere. But again, a cut on the torus
that does not divide it into two areas is an element whose logical meaning is
not yet clear. In contrast to the previous surface, on the torus it is possible to
draw essentially different cuts that do not divide it into two areas. Anyway, if
a graph on the torus has such a non-contractible cut then all non-contractible
cuts are of the same type: for instance, if we draw a cut circling the tube of the
torus then we can not draw any around the hole nor any spiral, and all drawn
cuts should circle the tube.

3.5. Punctured surfaces

According to Remark 3.2, on the closed surfaces like the sphere and the torus
there is no “absolute” truth because it is not feasible to highlight in a natural
way some area that stands for the truth value True. One way to achieve this is
punching holes in the surface by removing a finite set of points.
By the well-known stereographic projection, a sphere with just one point
removed is homeomorphic to the plane, and hence the global logic on the sphere
punctured at one point is exactly classical logic. This fact constitutes a quite
interesting turnabout because now classical logic materializes as a particular

Revista Colombiana de Matemáticas


216 ARNOLD OOSTRA

case of a more fundamental system. First, classical logic is expressed by existen-


tial graphs on the plane; then, the graphs are developed on the sphere defining
there a new logical system; finally, since the plane can be obtained from the
sphere, classical logic becomes a special case of another system.
The sphere punctured at two points is homeomorphic to the cylinder, and
more generally the surface with n unbounded cylindrical ends, mentioned in
section 3.2, is just a sphere punctured at n different points. In this way, the logic
on the sphere attains still greater relevance because various logics mentioned
arise from this one.
A torus punctured at one point may be thought of as a cylinder that fini-
shes as a torus at one of its ends (Figure 9), hence this surface has only one
unbounded end and the logic on it has an “absolute” truth. Besides the con-
tractible cuts and the cuts on the torus that do not divide the surface, now
there are cuts circling the cylinder that express a negation of the whole surface
of the torus with respect to the absolute truth.

Figure 9. Jordan curves on the punctured torus.

In this way it seems a prospective project to study in a systematic way the


logic intrinsic to all closed surfaces, oriented and unoriented, and then each of
them punctured at any finite number of points.

4. Mappings
Now that it appears feasible to assign a natural logic to any surface, a mapping
between different surfaces attains a logical connotation as a translation (in the
sense of rendering) from one logic into another.
The class of mappings chosen between certain surfaces depends naturally on
the structure considered on the manifolds. For instance, we would consider con-
tinuous maps between topological manifolds, differentiable mappings between

Volumen 53, Número 2, Año 2019


EXISTENTIAL GRAPHS ON NONPLANAR SURFACES 217

smooth manifolds, and holomorphic functions between Riemann surfaces. But


this requirements may turn out not to be sufficient in order to translate any
logical features, not even the local logic. Along the project put forward in this
paper, the logic inherent to any surface is given by the Alpha graphs on it,
and in turn the behavior of Alpha graphs on any manifold depends on the Jor-
dan curves on the surface. Hence, in order that any mapping between surfaces
somehow translates a surface logic, it should preserve Jordan curves besides
any likely topological features associated with them.
If a mapping between surfaces restricts to a homeomorphism between open
sets both homeomorphic to the plane, then all Jordan curves contained in one
of these open sets translate faithfully into the other and, moreover, the inside
and outside are preserved in all cases. This means that the logic given by the
Alpha graphs is translated in a perfect way. Particularly local homeomorphisms,
which include for instance all conformal maps, preserve the local logic.

Remark 4.1. Any local homeomorphism between surfaces preserves the local
logic intrinsic to both surfaces.

Some other suggestive examples of mappings are in place here. As mentioned


earlier, the inverse of the stereographic projection is a homeomorphism and
translates the logic of the plane into the logic of the sphere. On the other hand,
complex meromorphic functions from the torus to the sphere correspond to
double periodic functions, known as elliptic functions. In this way, the theory
of elliptic functions may help to elucidate the logic associated to the torus.

5. Concluding remarks
By means of a very natural generalization of Peirce’s existential graphs, any
topological 2-manifold is furnished with an inherent logic. As stated above, the
propositional part of this logic is given by the Alpha graphs on the surface, and
this graphs depend on the Jordan curves on it. On many surfaces the behavior
of this curves, and hence the behavior of the negation in this logic, is described
by Jordan’s Curve Theorem on the manifold. However, as might be expected,
these considerations result in many open problems. In the first place, it is
imperative to investigate more deeply into the logic on the mentioned surfaces,
or at least, on certain families of manifolds.
Here we can already specify certain general issues. If we read the contractible
Jordan curves as the usual negation, just as on the plane, how do we interpret
non-contractible ones? And the curves that do not divide the surface into two
components? These questions are, in turn, deeply related to the open problem
of specifying the rules of transformation for the graphs on the various manifolds.
For instance, it seems feasible that in any case a double cut, made up of two
nested contractible cuts without signs between them, may be drawn or erased
freely. But for the remaining rules we foresee serious difficulties. What does it

Revista Colombiana de Matemáticas


218 ARNOLD OOSTRA

mean that a certain area is even or odd? What does it mean that a graph is
contained in a given area? Is there always an endoporeutic orientation?
The idea of developing existential graphs on surfaces may turn out to have
connections with other topics of current interest in mathematics, like dessins
d’enfants on Riemann surfaces, or the possibility to understand geometrically
different types of negation.
Beyond many technical details and quite interesting connections, the line
of inquiry suggested in this paper seems to have deep consequences in itself.
Actually, by the course outlined here the way of thinking ascribed to a certain
logic becomes associated very precisely to the global form of a specific surface.
Perhaps, the form of our reasonings relies on the form of our living space.

Aknowledgements Parts of this paper were presented in talks at the Uni-


versidad del Tolima (Ibagué) and at the Universidad Nacional de Colombia
(Bogotá). Special thanks to Fernando Zalamea, Leonardo Solanilla, Andrés
Villaveces, and Franciso Vargas for very enlightening discussions on this topic,
and also for their substantial comments on earlier versions of this paper. The
author wishes to thank the anonymous referee for his valuable suggestions,
which improved the submitted draft. The drawings in this paper were created
with pst-solides3d.

References
[1] F. Bellucci, Peirce on assertion and other speech acts, Semiotica 2019
(2019), no. 228, 29–54.
[2] F. Bellucci, D. Chiffi, and A.-V. Pietarinen, Assertive Graphs, Journal of
Applied Non-Classical Logics 28 (2018), no. 1, 72–91.
[3] T. tom Dieck, Algebraic Topology, European Mathematical Society, Zürich,
2008.
[4] C. Fuentes, Cálculo de secuentes y gráficos existenciales Alfa: Dos es-
tructuras equivalentes para la lógica proposicional, undergraduate thesis,
Universidad del Tolima, Ibagué, Colombia, 2014.
[5] T. C. Hales, Jordan’s Proof of the Jordan Curve Theorem, Studies in Logic,
Grammar and Rhetoric 10 (2007), no. 23, 45–60.
[6] A. Hatcher, Algebraic Topology, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge,
2002.
[7] J. Jost, Riemannian Geometry and Geometric Analysis, fourth ed.,
Springer, Berlin, 2005.
[8] P. Malliavin, Géométrie différentielle intrinsèque, Hermann, Paris, 1972.

Volumen 53, Número 2, Año 2019


EXISTENTIAL GRAPHS ON NONPLANAR SURFACES 219

[9] Y. Martı́nez, Un modelo real para los gráficos Alfa, undergraduate thesis,
Universidad del Tolima, Ibagué, Colombia, 2014.
[10] A. Oostra and D. Dı́az, Álgebras booleanas libres en álgebra, topologı́a y
lógica, Boletı́n de Matemáticas 23 (2016), no. 2, 143–163.
[11] D. D. Roberts, The Existential Graphs of Charles S. Peirce, Mouton, The
Hague, 1973.
[12] J. Taboada and D. Rodrı́guez, Una demostración de la equivalencia entre
los gráficos Alfa y la lógica proposicional, undergraduate thesis, Universi-
dad del Tolima, Ibagué, Colombia, 2010.
[13] F. Zalamea, Los gráficos existenciales peirceanos, Universidad Nacional de
Colombia, Bogotá, 2010.
[14] J. J. Zeman, The Graphical Logic of C. S. Peirce, Ph.D. dissertation, Uni-
versity of Chicago, Chicago, 1964.

(Recibido en abril de 2019. Aceptado en agosto de 2019)

Departamento de Matemáticas y Estadı́stica


Universidad del Tolima
Facultad de Ciencias
Barrio Santa Helena
Ibagué, Colombia
e-mail: noostra@ut.edu.co

Revista Colombiana de Matemáticas

You might also like