You are on page 1of 13

See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.

net/publication/236735347

Validating Design Methods & Research: The Validation Square

Conference Paper · January 2000

CITATIONS READS
81 4,018

5 authors, including:

Janet Allen Farrokh Mistree


University of Oklahoma University of Oklahoma
393 PUBLICATIONS   7,336 CITATIONS    562 PUBLICATIONS   9,439 CITATIONS   

SEE PROFILE SEE PROFILE

Jan Emblemsvåg
Transition Pilots / Norwegian University of Science and Technology
57 PUBLICATIONS   604 CITATIONS   

SEE PROFILE

Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:

Self-Assessment in Engineering Design Education View project

The Automation of Design Space Exploration II - design capacity improver View project

All content following this page was uploaded by Farrokh Mistree on 31 May 2014.

The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file.


Proceedings of DETC ‘00
2000 ASME Design Engineering Technical Conferences
September 10-14, 2000, Baltimore, Maryland

DETC2000/DTM-14579

VALIDATING DESIGN METHODS & RESEARCH: THE VALIDATION SQUARE

*
Kjartan Pedersen Jan Emblemsvåg Reid Bailey, Janet K. Allen and Farrokh Mistree
Kvaerner Oil and Gas AS Considium Consulting Systems Realization Laboratory
Postboks 169 Group AS The George W. Woodruff School of Mechanical
1324 Lysaker Postboks 1115 Engineering
Norway 1361 Billingstad Georgia Institute of Technology
Norway Atlanta, GA 30332-0405
USA

ABSTRACT KEYWORDS: Philosophy of science, epistemology,


Validation of engineering research is typically anchored in engineering design, research validation.
the scientific inquiry tradition that is based primarily on logical
induction and / or deduction. Since much engineering research NOMENCLATURE:
is based on mathematical modeling, this kind of validation has DSP Decision Support Problem
worked – and still works – very well. There are, however, other EPV Empirical Performance Validity
areas of engineering research that rely on subjective statements ESV Empirical Structural Validity
as well as mathematical modeling, which makes this type of TPV Theoretical Performance Validity
validation problematic. One such area is that of design methods TSV Theoretical Structural Validity
within the field of engineering design. In this paper, we explore
the question of how one validates design research in general,
1. WHAT IS SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE?
and design methods in particular.
Searching for a New Approach to Design Method
Being anchored in the scientific inquiry tradition, research
Validation
validation is strongly tied to a fundamental problem addressed
Validation refers to internal consistency (i.e., a logical
in epistemology, namely, what is scientific knowledge and how
problem), whereas verification deals with justification of
is new knowledge confirmed? Thus, we first look to
knowledge claims. In modeling literature, these terms are
epistemology for answers to why an approach solely based on
swapped, and in this paper we use the terms as used in the
‘formal, rigorous and quantifiable’ validation constitutes a
modeling literature; i.e., verification refers to internal
problem, and for an augmented approach to research validation.
consistency, whereas validation refers to justification of
We then propose the ‘Validation Square’ which we validate by
knowledge claims (Barlas and Carpenter 1990). Validation of
testing its internal consistency based on logic in addition to
engineering research is anchored in the tradition of the scientific
testing its external relevance based on its usefulness with
method. This tradition demands “formal, rigorous and
respect to a purpose.
quantitative validation” (Barlas and Carpenter 1990), which is
We recognize that no one has the complete answer to the
based primarily on logical induction and / or deduction. Since
question we pose. To help us converge on an answer to these
much engineering research is based on mathematical modeling,
questions we "think aloud" and invite you to join us in doing the
this kind of validation has worked – and still works – very well.
same. It is our hope that in so doing we, the members of this
There are, however, other areas of engineering research that
design research community, will all be the richer for it. rely on subjective statements as well as mathematical modeling
in which validation that is rooted in ‘formal, rigorous and
*
Corresponding Author, to whom correspondence should be addressed: janet.allen@me.gatech.edu, Phone/FAX: 404-894-8168/9342.

1 Copyright © 2000 by ASME


quantitative’ measures becomes problematic. One such area is [analytically true] or true by virtue of experience [synthetically
that of design methods within the field of engineering design. true]” (Honderich 1995). Hence, non-quantifiable, synthetic
In this paper, we explore the question how does one validate propositions are neither true nor false, that is, they are
design research in general, and design methods in particular? meaningless. From this it follows that unless statements can be
In this section we address the question: what are the formalized for analytical and/or empirical investigation, they
problems encountered in implementing a formal, rigorous and are meaningless. Hence, most positivists consider
quantifiable scheme to validate a method in engineering metaphysical, religious, aesthetic, and ethical claims as inferior
design? We investigate this question by going to the roots of to those produced by science, resulting in an extreme focus on
epistemology to evaluate the applicability of the fundamental science in general and mathematical proofs in particular. This
assumptions upon which ‘formal, rigorous and quantifiable’ ‘urge’ to formalize statements into mathematics (to allow
validation rest. Then, based on the literature, we propose new analytical judgements) links logical positivism to formalism, a
assumptions where old assumptions fail, before proposing a view that is integral to many different philosophical schools
new approach to research validation based on a new set of which share the fundamental assumption that rational
assumptions. knowledge is the only valid knowledge.
Logical positivism became ‘obsolete’ in the late 1960’s,
1.1 The Historical Roots of Modern Epistemology however, many of the basic ideas of atomism and
Epistemology (the theory of knowledge) started in ancient foundationalism are embodied in what later came to be known
Greece with Phyrro and his skeptics. They tried to produce ‘a as reductionism. Reductionism is a wide term and is normally
criterion for truth’, a search that was strongly influenced by split into ontological, methodological and theory reduction.
Plato and Aristotle. Plato, who defined knowledge as “that over Ontological reductionists postulate that the whole of realities
which there cannot be error”, confined knowledge to a particu- consists of a minimal number of materialistic substances.
lar realm of perfect and unchangeable entities referred to as Hence, they deny the existence of immaterial phenomena and
“Forms” (Honderich 1995). Plato later acknowledged that advocate “biological organisms to be no more than complex
“correct belief can be turned into knowledge by means of a functioning machines”. Methodological reductionists postulate
reason or cause”, something Aristotle acknowledged. This that the properties of the whole are the sum of the properties of
constitutes the basis for foundationalism, where knowledge of the parts. Hence, analysis of the parts is sufficient to gain
the world rests on a “foundation of indubitable beliefs from knowledge about the whole. Theory reductionists assert that
which further propositions can be inferred to produce a new theories absorb old theories rather than replace them.
superstructure of known truths” (Honderich 1995). Moreover, From this it follows that biology, for instance, will in the end be
it is from this foundationalist basis that modern epistemology totally explained by chemistry and/or physics. In modern
emerged in the seventeenth century, starting with Rene science, methodological reductionism has been the most
Descartes and rationalism. influential reductive approach with the discovery of DNA as
perhaps the most important triumph. Although successful,
1.2 The Foundationalist/Formalist/ Reductionist building on the assumptions that knowledge is innate and
School of Epistemology absolute and can only be verified by reason, reductionists are
The rationalists asserted that “the truth is innate and prior to totally dependent on objective quantification. Hence,
all experience” and that “human knowledge about the truth is reductionism is based on the fundamental assumption that
based on reasoning” (Descartes [1641] 1931). The empiricists objectivity exists
asserted that “all human knowledge about the truth is based on In the preceding, we have documented that the tradition of
experience rather than reasoning” (Locke [1690] 1894). Both scientific inquiry demanding ‘formal, rigorous and quantitative’
views, however, are based on the fundamental assumption that validation is anchored in the foundationalist/formalist/
truths are absolute and innate, which links them to the views of reductionist school of epistemology. From this it follows that
Plato and Aristotle, and hence, to foundationalism. ‘formal, rigorous and quantitative’ validation is based on the
The foundationalist view was brought forward by Bertrand fundamental assumptions that:
Russell who introduced logical atomism, and by his student
Ludwig Wittgenstein. With his “Tractatus Logico- 1) truths (knowledge) are innate and absolute,
philosophicus” Wittgenstein brought the atomist and founda- 2) that only rational knowledge is valid, and
tionalist tradition to full fruition by asserting that the “function 3) that objectivity exists.
of philosophy is to monitor the bounds of sense, and to show
that attempts to traverse the bounds of sense are futile” Having identified ‘formal, rigorous and quantitative’ validation
(Honderich 1995; Wittgenstein [1921] 1961). This became the as problematic when validating research that is based on
basis for logical positivism, a movement which was in favor in subjective statements, we assert that the fundamental
the scientific community until the 1960’s. Their doctrine was assumptions (1 through 3 above) are at the core of the
centered around the ‘verification principle’ asserting that problems. To substantiate this assertion we turn to the litera-
“knowledge can only be claimed if judged true by meaning ture.

2 Copyright © 2000 by ASME


are preferred. The underlying assumption is of course that
1.3 The Relativistic/Holistic/Social School of following the rules is a rational act in itself. This assumption
Epistemology – Challenging the ‘Ruling’ fails, since determining which rules to follow also requires
Fundamental Assumptions of Knowledge rules. Hence, total rational assessments are based on an infinite
The notion of innate and absolute truths was first challenged regress and therefore impossible. In reality the choice of rules
by Immanuel Kant who synthesized rationalism and empiricism is contextual as pointed out in the previous paragraph (i.e.,
in a search for knowledge on neutral ground by asserting that dependent on the ruling paradigm). Hence, our ability to be
“all knowledge starts with experience” however, “not all rational depends on a basic ability to exercise intelligent
knowledge arises out of experience” (Kant [1781] 1933). judgement that cannot be completely captured in systems of
Hence, he suggested that not all truths are innate and absolute – rules, i.e., they are not accessible to investigation through the
there are some that might be added by the mind. This raises the senses or calculation. This is the definition of intuitive
question: who is to determine what is given (i.e., innate and knowledge, and it is ironic that hypotheses (the cornerstone of
fundamental) and what is derived/added? This question is the scientific method) often are proposed as a result of intuitive
referred to as “the myth of the given” in (Sellars 1963). Hegel, processes (Honderich 1995). According to Albert Einstein
on the other hand, rejected the whole idea of innate truths and expressed:
introduced a new logic in which conflict and contradictions are “The justification (truth content) of the system [physics]
regarded as necessary elements of truth (thesis, antithesis, and rests in the proof of usefulness of the resulting theorems on
synthesis). As a consequence Hegel regarded truth as a process the basis of sense experiences, where the relations to the
rather than a fixed state of things. In his view knowledge is latter to the former can only be comprehended intuitively”
socially, culturally, and historically dependent, hence, there are (Einstein 1950)
no neutral foundations of knowledge, and entirely objective Based on this we assert that scientific knowledge is
verification of knowledge claims is not possible (Hegel [1817] anchored in the rationality for facts, and on intuition for values.
1959). This view was supported by Thomas Kuhn who As a consequence, intuitive knowledge is linked to the
presented a historical analysis of how science progresses, and application of rational knowledge through the determination of
he argued that in any given epoch scientists work within and purpose.
against the background of an unquestioned theory or set of The impossibility of total rational assessments also chal-
beliefs (a paradigm). According to Capra: “scientific facts lenges the very existence of objectivity, the last of the funda-
emerge out of an entire constellation of human perceptions, mental assumptions upon which formal, rigorous and quanti-
values, and actions – in one word, out of a paradigm – from fiable validation rest. This assumption is also challenged by
which they cannot be separated” (Capra 1996). Based on this Werner Heisenberg who claims that a procedure for acquiring
we assert that scientific knowledge is not innate nor absolute, knowledge will affect the acquired knowledge itself (Capra
strictly, but are inseparable from the social scientific context 1991). Albert Einstein was also aware of this problem and he
within which they are developed. stated that “one may compare these rules [related to the scien-
Science progresses, according to Kuhn, when the ruling tific method] with the rules of a game in which, while the rules
paradigm cannot provide adequate explanations to scientific are arbitrary, it is their rigidity alone which makes the game
problems under investigation, and this inadequacy makes way possible. However, the fixation will never be final. It will have
for new paradigms. Central to Kuhn’s view is that the change validity only for a special field of application”. What about the
to a new paradigm cannot be based on strictly logical reason objectivity of mathematics? Wittgenstein addressed the issue of
(Kuhn [1962] 1970). This is supported by Quine who argues objectivity in mathematics, and claimed that “logic [mathe-
that, “we choose a particular way of doing it [i.e., accommodate matics] is merely a tool consistent only within itself and hence
a new theory to an experiment] not because some absolute sci- content free” (Wittgenstein [1921] 1961). This view was sup-
entific principle [i.e., based on rationality] but because it is ported by Kurt Gödel who claimed in his “Incompleteness
convenient, causing minimal disturbance in the existing theory”. Theorem” that “every formal number theory contains an indeci-
(Quine 1953). This links validation to preferences based on sive formula, i.e., neither the formula nor its negation is prov-
usefulness, similarly to Toulmin’s proposal that a ‘better’ able in the theory” (Gödel 1931). From this it follows that
method is equivalent to a more useful method. This is important attempting to prove something formally and/or objectively is an
since it challenges the notion that only rational knowledge is illogical and hence, an invalid act since the underlying axiom of
valid knowledge. such an approach, i.e., that objectivity exists, is already logi-
Rational knowledge, or rational beliefs, is arrived at by cally refuted by Wittgenstein and Gödel. Ultimately this leads
accumulating and evaluating an adequate body of relevant evi- to the proposition that a conversational, contextual and subjec-
dence (Honderich 1995). The accumulation and evaluation of tive validation approach is more logical, and therefore more
scientific evidence is addressed in the Scientific Method, formal, since it does not refute its own axioms, i.e., that subjec-
wherein Sir Francis Bacon suggested that scientific knowledge tivity is unavoidable. Based on this we assert that total objec-
is gained and claimed by a process of induction. This again tivity does not exist, and hence, that knowledge validation must
requires rigorous rules, where formal logic and/or mathematics be linked to contextual usefulness.

3 Copyright © 2000 by ASME


A new school of epistemology is based on the refutation of Accordingly, we assert that formal, rigorous and quantifiable
the fundamental assumptions upon which the foundationalist/ validation (i.e., based on logic) can be applied to a design
reductionist/formalist school of epistemology rests, namely, the method’s internal consistency but fails to validate its external
relativist/holistic/social school of epistemology (Barlas and relevance (i.e., its usefulness). Hence, formal, rigorous and
Carpenter 1990). Needless to say, we adhere to the relativist quantifiable validation is necessary but not sufficient, and we
school of epistemology, and hence, we adopt a relativist view therefore suggest including the validation of a method’s
on scientific knowledge. What remains, however, is to evaluate usefulness with respect to a purpose as well. We further
what impact the different views on scientific knowledge have on suggest that the validation of a method's usefulness be done
research validation, which we do next. using a set of carefully chosen example problems that will
support a claim of generality.
1.4 Different Views of Knowledge: The Impact on The example problems that we are speaking of are
Research Validation synonymous with case studies from (Yin, 1994). Yin
Logical empiricist validation is a strictly formal, algo- distinguishes cases studies from sampling units of an
rithmic, reductionist, and ‘confrontational’ process, where new experiment based on the role of theoretical propositions. In an
knowledge is either true of false. The validation becomes a experiment, the sampling units are chosen randomly and their
matter of formal accuracy rather than practical use. This ap- power is in their large numbers. In a case study, however, each
proach is appropriate for closed problems that have right or case is connected to a specific theory. Accepting the usefulness
wrong answers associated with them, like mathematical expres- of a design method for some case studies, then, is a matter of
sions or algorithms. Relativist validation, on the other hand, is assessing whether the cases support or refute the theory. In this
a semiformal and communicative process, where validation is way, “individual case studies are to be selected as a laboratory
seen as a gradual process of building confidence in the useful- investigator selects the topic of a new experiment” (Yin, 1994,
ness of the new knowledge (with respect to a purpose). This pg. 31) and not as a laboratory investigator selects the samples
approach is appropriate for open problems, where new knowl- used within an experiment.
edge is associated with heuristics and non-precise represen- In the next section we introduce the ‘Validation Square’ that
tations. provides a framework for validating internal consistency as well
Through addressing how to validate engineering design re- as external relevance for some particular instances in order to
search, we are addressing the fundamental nature of engineering build confidence in its general usefulness with respect to a
design. We assert that engineering design is primarily con- purpose.
cerned with open problems that involve objective and subjec-
tive elements and no single right answer. This separates design 2. THE VALIDATION SQUARE – A Process of
from most of the traditional engineering disciplines, in which a Building Confidence in Usefulness –
given problem has only one right answer. Engineering design In the previous section we asserted that research validation
requires both science and art to achieve a goal, separating it as is a process of building confidence in its usefulness with respect
fundamentally different from the analytical aspects of engi- to a purpose. We associate usefulness of a design method with
neering. A formal, rigorous and quantifiable validation proce- whether the method provides design solutions ‘correctly’ (effec-
dure only acknowledges the closed part of engineering design, tiveness), and whether it provides ‘correct’ design solutions
while ignoring the significance of subjectivity. Hence, a rela- (efficiency). Correct in this context are design solutions with
tivist validation procedure is asserted in this paper. acceptable operational performance, that are designed and
As stated, the principal objective in this paper is to synthe- realized with less cost and/or in less time. Hence, the process
size a framework for validating design methods. There are no we present aims at evaluating the effectiveness and the effi-
right or wrong answers to this problem, there are many heuris- ciency of the method, based on qualitative and quantitative
tics involved, and non-precise representations are common. measures respectively. This is illustrated in Figure 1, where the
Based on this assumption the relativist validation is adopted, Validation Square at the bottom is the synthesis of this process,
and the validation strategy is based on the following statement. and this process is detailed next.

We define scientific knowledge within the field of 2.1 Structural Validation – A Qualitative Process
engineering design as socially justifiable belief according As can be seen from Figure 1, being effective embodies
to the Relativistic School of Epistemology. We do so due three things:
to the open nature of design method synthesis, where new (1) accepting the individual constructs constituting the method;
knowledge is associated with heuristics and non-precise (2) accepting the internal consistency of the way the constructs
representations, thus knowledge validation becomes a are put together in the method; and
process of building confidence in its usefulness with (3) accepting the appropriateness of the example problems that
respect to a purpose. will be used to verify the performance of the method.
A description of each follows.

4 Copyright © 2000 by ASME


Input:
DESIGN Output:
•information I I
METHOD •Design Solution
•resources

PURPOSE :
Defined based on METHOD
METHOD VALIDITY
VALIDITY
Intuitive Knowledge Criteria:
Criteria:USEFULNESS
USEFULNESS with with
(i.e., experience) respect
respect to a PURPOSE
to a PURPOSE

Effectiveness : USEFULNESS ::
USEFULNESS
Efficiency :
METHOD
METHOD Efficient
Efficient and
and//or
or
Qualitative Evaluation of Quantitative Evaluation of
Effective
Effective ininachieving
achievingthe
the
METHOD METHOD
articulated purpose(s).
articulated purpose(s).

Appropriateness of Performance of Design


Correctness of METHOD- Performance of Design
example problems used to Solutions and Method with
constructs, both Separately Solutions and Method
verify METHOD respect to example
and I ntegrated beyond example problems
usefulness problems

(1) and (2) (6)


THEORETICAL THEORETICAL
STRUCTURAL PERFORMANCE
VALIDITY VALIDITY
“a Leap of Faith ”

(3) (4) and (5)


EMPIRICAL EMPIRICAL
STRUCTURAL PERFORMANCE
VALIDITY VALIDITY

Figure 1 --
Design Method Validation - Building Confidence in Usefulness.
The Validation Square is in the gray box.

(1) Accepting the construct’s validity: In order to build confi-


dence in the validity of the individual constructs constituting (3) Accepting the example problems: In order to build confi-
the method, we suggest using the literature. Based on the dence in the appropriateness of the example problems cho-
name of the author and publisher, the number of references sen for verifying the method performance, we suggest
associated with the construct, how long the construct has documentation in stages. First, document that the example
been referenced, and so, an inference towards acceptance problems are similar to the problems for which the method
can be built. In addition, if the constructs are being used as constructs are generally accepted. Then, document that the
benchmarking for new constructs, they should be example problems represent the actual problem for which
demonstrated to be highly accepted and valued. the method is intended. Finally, document that the data
associated with the example problems can support a
(2) Accepting method consistency: In order to build confidence conclusion.
in the way the constructs are put together in the method (i.e., As can be seen, the validity of the method constructs –
in the method’s internal consistency) we suggest using flow- individually (1) and integrated (2) – deals with the structural
chart representations focusing on information flow. In this soundness of the method in a more general sense, and are
way it can easily be demonstrated that for each step (con- therefore denoted Theoretical Structural Validity. The
struct) there is adequate input available, that the anticipated validity of the example problems for which the method is to
output from the step (construct) is likely to occur based on be tested (3) deals with the structural soundness for some
the input, and that the anticipated output is an adequate input particular instances, and are therefore denoted Empirical
to another step (construct). Further, identifying the infor- Structural Validity, However, both ‘validities’ are evaluated
mation flow unveils what information is assumed to be qualitatively.
readily available, hence, facilitates evaluation against reality.
Method inconsistency refers to generating information that
is inadequate or not necessary, or invalid assumptions upon
which the method rests.

5 Copyright © 2000 by ASME


2.2 Performance Validation – A Quantitative Process of going through the Validation Square is to present
As can be seen from Figure 1 being efficient embodies three ‘circumstantial’ evidence to facilitate a leap of faith, i.e., to
things: produce belief in a general usefulness of the method with
(4) accepting that the outcome of the method is useful with respect to an articulated purpose.
respect to the initial purpose for some chosen example The greatest impact of applying Yin’s case study ap-
problem(s); proach to validation is in establishing the external validity of
(5) accepting that the achieved usefulness is linked to applying a design method. External validity refers to the validity of
the method; and an approach to situations other than the individual cases
(6) accepting that the usefulness of the method is beyond the studied in Steps 4 and 5 of the Validation Square. By
case studies. avoiding the temptation to treat case studies as a sampling
A description of each follows. units in a statistical experiment, the method of generalization
is ‘analytic generalization,’ in which a previously developed
(4) Accepting usefulness of method for some example problems: theory is used as a template with which to compare the
To build confidence in the usefulness of the method, we empirical results of the case study. If two or more cases are
suggest using representative example problems. In this way, shown to support the same theory, replication may be
the outcome of the method can be evaluated in terms of its claimed (Yin, 1994, pg. 31). Each case is treated as a dif-
usefulness. As indicated, metrics for usefulness are linked ferent experiment (where analytic generalization is sup-
to the degree an articulated purpose has been achieved. ported with a small number of cases), not as different points
However, the purpose for proposing a design method may within the same experiment (where statistical generalization
vary. From an industrial perspective the purpose is typically requires a large number of samples). Generalization (i.e.,
linked to reducing cost and/or time and/or improving support for external validity) is not accomplished with a
quality. From a scholarly perspective, the purpose is handful of data points, but instead with a handful of case
augmented to include addition of scientific knowledge that studies which assess a theoretical proposition. Through
can help produce more scientific knowledge. connecting the example problems to analytic generalization
and theory development, the “Leap of Faith” depicted in
(5) Accepting that usefulness is linked to applying the method: Figure 1 as part of the step from empirical to theoretical per-
To build confidence that the usefulness of the resulting ex- formance validity is not necessarily a large leap. If the
ample problem solutions is linked to applying the method, method is deemed useful for some limited instances (4) and
we suggest evaluating the contributions to usefulness from (5), we denote this as Empirical Performance Validity.
each construct individually. This is done by comparing the Similarly, if the method is deemed useful beyond some
solutions with and without the construct, allowing a quanti- limited instances (6), i.e., useful in a more general sense, we
tative evaluation. In addition, solutions should be compared denote this as Theoretical Performance Validity.
to those found with existing design approaches. In terms of
Yin’s case studies, Step 5 is a matter of evaluating rival Having proposed a framework for validating design
theories, in which alternative explanations for the usefulness methods, namely the Validation Square, this framework itself
of a case are investigated. needs to be validated.

(6) Accepting usefulness of method beyond example problems: 3. VALIDATING THE VALIDATION SQUARE
To build confidence in generality, we suggest using In this section, we provide a brief albeit cursory overview of
induction that entails the following: our thinking on this topic and the status of validation. Further
In (1), we demonstrate that the individual constructs are details are presented in Pedersen (1999). Much more needs to
generally accepted for some limited applications. be done and we look forward to other members of the design
In (2), we demonstrate the internal consistency of the way research community joining us in this effort.
the constructs are put together in the method. We validate the ‘Validation Square’ by validating its
In (3), we demonstrate that the constructs are applied internal consistency in addition to its external relevance, i.e., we
within their accepted ranges. apply the ‘Validation Square’ to validate itself. For those who
In (4), we demonstrate the usefulness of the method for regard this as circular argumentation, we refer them to
some chosen example problems, which in (3) are mathematics - mathematics is validated by means of
demonstrated to be appropriate for testing the method. mathematics.
In (5), we demonstrate that the usefulness achieved is due
to applying the method.
Based on this we claim generality, i.e., that the method is
useful beyond the tested example problems. However, as
shown in Section 1.3, every validation rests ultimately on
socially justifiable belief, that is, faith. Hence, the purpose

6 Copyright © 2000 by ASME


3.1 The Theoretical Structural Validity of the be valid. This is very well demonstrated by ‘the battle’ between
Validation Square Windows 3.1 and IBM’s OS2 operative system; most experts
The Theoretical Structural Validity (TSV) of deemed OS2 to be a better operative system, however, the OS2
the Validation Square refers to accepting the lost the competition. Non-quantifiable, social issues prevented
x structural/logical soundness of its constructs, both the superior OS2 from winning the support of computer users.
individually and integrally. The constructs of the Based on this observation we assert that internal consistency
Validation Square are represented by the four alone does not assure external relevance, hence, we feel that
internal squares as illustrated in Figure 1: validation has to be augmented to address external relevance by
Theoretical Structural Validity (TSV), Empirical Structural evaluating usefulness. In this context, it should not be hard to
Validity (ESV), Empirical Performance Validity (EPV) and accept that any example problem used to verify a method’s
Theoretical Performance Validity (TPV). Hence, accepting the usefulness has to:
TSV of the Validation Square implies accepting the a) be similar to the problems for which the
structural/logical soundness of each of these ‘validities’ in tools/constructs/etc. are generally accepted;
addition to accepting that they are put together in a logical and b) be representative of the problems for which the method is
consistent manner. intended; and
c) provide sufficient data to support a conclusion.
(1) Accepting the individual ‘validities’: It should not be Hence, we assert that ESV as outlined in Section 2.1 is a
hard to accept that any tools/constructs/etc. to be used in a structurally valid proposition.
design method must be individually valid, and that the Accordingly, it should not be hard to accept that unless a
tools/constructs/etc. must be organized in a way that creates design method is able to produce useful results (i.e., design
internal consistency. Hence, we assert that TSV as outlined in solutions) for a particular problem it cannot be deemed valid for
Section 2.1 is a structurally (logically) valid proposition. that particular problem. (It does not mean, however, that the
This view is supported in (Hazelrigg 1999). However, method is invalid in general.) Hence, we assert that EPV as
Hazelrigg asserts that “validation of a design alternative outlined in Section 2.2 is a structurally valid proposition.
selection method can be done only mathematically, and only Finally, the TPV-validity is based on the other three internal
through validation of the procedure, not by verification through ‘validities’ being accepted, as well as accepting that the induc-
results”, a view based on (Barzilai 1998). We find it difficult to tion presented in Section 2.2 (6) is logically valid. The first is
accept the preceding statement. Both Hazelrigg and Barzilai given in the previous paragraphs, while the latter is dealt with
must be viewed as advocating ‘rigorous, formal, and next.
quantifiable’ validation, an approach based on fundamental
assumptions which we have questioned. That is, they are only (2) Accepting the Validation Square consistency: We assert
considering the closed, objective and scientific part of that the induction presented in Section 2.2 (6) is logically valid.
engineering design. Further, Hazelrigg argues that “only if all To substantiate this claim we turn to the literature. The
steps in a procedure are valid, that is, rational, self-consistent, consistency of viewing validation as a process of building confi-
and derivable from axioms, is it possible for a method [as a dence in usefulness (with respect to a purpose) is argued in
whole] to be valid”. This is based on the view that rational Section 1.3. Here we argue that a conversational, contextual
assessments yield universal and necessary results; hence, if and subjective validation approach is logical, and therefore
methods produce significantly different results with identical formal, since it does not refute its own axioms, i.e., that subjec
input, at most one of the methods can be logically valid. tivity is unavoidable. This view is fully supported in
Hazerigg's approach is further challenged by bounded Emblemsvåg 1999, and is based on a tradition of building
rationality, where human cognitive limitations are viewed to confidence based on posits, (for details see Chen 1995; Lewis,
yield a considerable scope for rational disagreement (Honderich 1996; Koch 1997; Peplinski, 1997; Simpson 1998). Further,
1995). Hence, we suggest that the presented axioms in splitting this process of building confidence in one structural
(Hazelrigg 1999) can be challenged and logically refuted by (qualitative) and one performance (quantitative) part, and in one
using a different set of rules. theoretical (general) and one empirical (particular) part comes
Finally, we contend that the total disregard for the usefulness from the area of system dynamics (Richardson and Pugh 1981).
of the results as part of validation, as suggested by Hazelrigg, is This area has been heavily criticized for not employing ‘formal,
illogical. Let us explain. The purpose of a typical ‘alternative rigorous, objective and quantitative’ model validation proce-
selection method’ is to recommend the best alternative based on dures (Barlas and Carpenter 1990; Barlas 1996), which makes
some criteria. Hence, what is really important is to have a good this approach even more interesting from the perspective of
set of alternatives, and the right set of criteria for what is best. design method validation. The first time we have noticed these
Both of these aspects cannot be addressed by rational validation aspects used in the area of engineering design is in
assessments, hence, the usefulness of having a totally rational Bailey 1997, where they are arranged in a square. This was
selection process becomes limited; the process with which an subsequently developed by Bailey et al., 1999. However, the
alternative is recommended is valid, but the alternative may not prescriptive and comprehensive Validation Square as presented

7 Copyright © 2000 by ASME


in this paper is first presented Pedersen 1999, where it was used Further, in (Pedersen 1999) HPP’s were developed for a
to validate that the doctoral research contributed new scientific family of gravitational separators and a family of marginal field
knowledge to the field of engineering design. Finally, it has vessels, which constitutes two instances for which the HPPRM
been used in Siddique 1999 to validate doctoral research as is tested. Hence, we claim that this is sufficient data to support
well. Thus we assert that the Validation Square is Theoretically a conclusion regarding the usefulness of the HPPRM, and thus,
Structurally Valid. regarding the usefulness of the Validation Square. Based on the
following we assert that the HPPRM is an appropriate example
3.2 The Empirical Structural Validity of the Validation problem to test the usefulness of the Validation Square, i.e.,
Square using the HPPRM is Empirically Structurally Valid.
As stated in Section 2.2, any example problem
intended for method testing, has to be validated 3.3 The Empirical Performance Validity of the Valida-
itself and deemed appropriate. As mentioned in tion Square
the previous paragraph, the Validation Square has
The purpose of applying the Validation Square
x been used to validate a design method, namely,
to the HPPRM is to build confidence in its
the Hierarchical Product Platform Realization
validity. Hence, the usefulness of the
x
Method, or the HPPRM for short (Pedersen
Validation Square is linked the degree to which
1999). Hence, we use the HPPRM as our example problem to
confidence is built (4) and to whether this confidence is due to
test the usefulness of the Validation Square and show in the
applying the Validation Square (5).
following its appropriateness.
(4) Accepting usefulness of the Validation Square: In order
(3) Accepting the HPPRM as an example problem: The to build confidence in HPPRM validity we applied the
HPPRM is a design method intended for realizing large and Validation Square in the following manner.
complex made-to-order systems that are very expensive and ΠWe demonstrated by means of the literature that the core
produced in small numbers. The outcome of the HPPRM is a constructs of the HPPRM are generally accepted for their
so-called Hierarchical Product Platform (or HPP for short), intended applications. Further, we demonstrated by means
which is a product platform serving as a basis for products ad- of flow chart representation that there is no redundant
dressing different market segments. The HPPRM consists of information being generated and the underlying
three phases, namely, Define, Model, and Solve. Each of these assumptions are valid. Based on this we asserted Theoreti-
phases is centered around an independent construct, namely, cal Structural Validity.
Numerical Taxonomy, Technology Diffusion, and the compro- ΠWe demonstrated by means of induction that a (1)
mise DSP, see Figure 2. Gravitational Separator example problem was appropriate
ΠNumerical Taxonomy (Sneath and Sokal 1973) is used to for exemplifying and illustrating the HPPRM in detail, and
identify the potential for standardization in an existing (2) that the Marginal Field Vessel example problem was
design portfolio by means of clustering. The clustering it- appropriate for testing the usefulness of the HPPRM.
self is ‘objective’ whereas interpreting the clusters is based Based on this we asserted Empirical Structural Validity.
on subjective judgements. ΠWe demonstrated by means of the example problems that
ΠTechnology Diffusion (Silverberg, Dosi et al. 1988; (1) the resulting HPPs represented feasible solutions realiz-
Silverberg 1991; Hall 1994) is used to discount the per- able in less time with less cost, and (2) that each construct
formance of alternative technologies according to their contributed to usefulness: Numerical Taxonomy by
maturity and leverage potential to existing technology. reducing the combinatorial problem to a manageable size,
Application of the discounting factor is objective whereas Technology Diffusion by advocating a continuous improve-
decisions regarding learning rates and leverage potentials ment approach, and compromise DSP by advocating robust
are based on subjective judgements. and adaptive solutions. Based on this we asserted Empiri-
ΠThe compromise DSP (Mistree, Hughes et al. 1993) is used cal Performance Validity.
to enable designers to minimize the distance to their goals ΠBased on the outcome of the previous steps in the Valida-
for the total system with respect to operational perform- tion Square we inferred general validity of the HPPRM
ance, time and cost. Solving the compromise DSP is based on the following. (1) The key method constructs are
objective in the mathematical sense whereas deciding on applicable for problems beyond the example problems, (2)
scenarios as well as making the final decision is based on the example problems are representative of the general
subjective judgements. problem, and (3) the HPPRM is useful for the represen-
tative example problems. Based on this we asserted Theo-
Applying the HPPRM is preparing subjective input to objec- retical Performance Validity.
tive mathematical constructs that produces output which is
judged subjectively; hence, it complies with the kind of
problems for which the Validation Square is intended.

8 Copyright © 2000 by ASME


THE METHOD (HPPRM) CORE METHOD CONSTRUCTS
Phase I: DEFINE

Gather Data

Numerical Taxonomy
Cluster Data
(Sneath & Sokal 1973)
Phase II: MODEL

Establish Design Partition Realization Technology Diffusion


Requirements Processes (Silverberg, Dosi et al. 1988)

Model Relations
& formulate c-DSPs
Phase III: SOLVE

Solve for each Compromise DSP


Establish Scenarios
Scenario (Mistree, Hughes et al. 1993)

Decide on HPP

Figure 2 --
The HPPRM and its Constructs: An Overview

3.4 The Theoretical Performance Validity of the Vali-


We assert that the Validation Square as applied in Pedersen
dation Square
1999, built confidence in usefulness with respect to a purpose.
The general validity of the Validation
What remains is to evaluate whether this confidence was due to
the Validation Square.
Square is based on accepting its usefulness x
beyond the example problem, which is
(5) Accepting that usefulness is linked to applying the Vali- presented next.
dation Square: Theoretical Performance Validity implies that
(6) Accepting usefulness of the
all other ‘validities’ are accepted, and hence, each of the
Validition Square beyond the HPPRM example: We assert that
‘validities’ is necessary but not sufficient. However, confidence
the Validation Square is useful to validate design methods with
can be built with very little evidence presented; it all comes
mixed subjective and objective statements beyond the HPPRM
down to a socially justifiable belief as pointed out in Section
example, and we substantiate this claim as follows.
1.3. Nevertheless, we claim that the likelihood of accepting
ΠAs long as a design method can be evaluated for its likeli-
something as valid increases with the amount of relevant and
hood of ‘producing’ the wanted outcome, it can be deemed
accepted evidence.
Theoretically Structurally Valid.
We have now demonstrated that applying the Validation
ΠAs long as an example problem can be evaluated for its
Square provided a sufficient amount of evidence to build
appropriateness regarding method testing, it can be deemed
confidence in validity for at least one instance, namely, the
to have Empirical Structural Validity (validating the
HPPRM. Based on this we assert that the Validation Square
structure of the example problems).
has Empirical Performance Validity.
ΠAs long as a design method can be evaluated in terms of
how well the resulting design solution performs compared

9 Copyright © 2000 by ASME


to design solutions arrived at by other methods, it can be validation rest, suggested a new set of assumptions and
deemed to have Empirical Performance Validity (validating postulated a new hypothesis for knowledge validation in
the performance of the method for the examples). engineering design, namely, a relativist/holistic/social view (see
ΠAnd finally, as long as inference can be made towards a Table 1). Through asserting this view on validation in
design method’s general usefulness, it can be deemed to engineering design, we recognize engineering design as having
have Theoretical Performance Validity (validating the both scientific (i.e., objective) and artistic (i.e., subjective)
performance of the method in general). components.
Based on this, we assert that the Validation Square is gen- Based on the changed view, we assert that validating a
erally applicable for validating design methods in particular, design method is a contextual process of demonstrating
and for validating research in general. The latter is based on usefulness with respect to a purpose. Based on this assertion we
expanding the previous induction in the following way. present a framework for guiding this process, namely, the
ΠAs long as any research result can be evaluated in terms of Validation Square (see Figure 3). This framework builds on
the likelihood of fulfilling its intended application, it can be research in systems dynamics, and a tradition of using posits in
deemed Theoretically Structurally Valid. engineering design. However, the Validation Square as
ΠAs long as any test of research usefulness can be evaluated presented in this paper extends all these efforts by offering a
for its appropriateness, it can be deemed Empirically Struc- prescriptive approach that is more comprehensive and
turally Valid. systematic.
ΠAs long as any research results can be evaluated in terms of The Validation Square has been used to validate a design
its usefulness for some particular applications, it can be method for realizing large and expensive made-to-order sys-
deemed to have Empirical Performance Validity. tems, namely, the HPPRM (Pedersen 1999), and to validate a
ΠAnd finally, as long as inference can be made towards the method for product platform configuration (Siddique 1999).
general usefulness of any research results, it can be deemed Based on this paper we assert that the Validation Square is
to have Theoretical Performance Validity. appropriate for validating research results in general, as long as
it can be subjected to qualitative and quantitative evaluation as
Based on this we assert that the Validation Square has Theo- outlined in Section 2.
retical Performance Validity, hence, it is deemed valid for vali- By introducing usefulness and purpose into the validation
dating new knowledge associated with heuristics and non-pre- procedure, we absolutely are not advocating that “anything
cise representations. From this it follows that we have achieved goes.” The validation square is specifically designed to bring
the principal objective of this paper, namely, to synthesize a rigor to a validation process that is both quantitative and
framework to validate design methods in particular and research qualitative. When dealing with open constructs such as design
results in general. And we have done so according to the rela- methods, open validation procedures are imperative. It is only
tivist/holistic/social school of epistemology, where scientific in a relativistic validation procedure that the validity of an open
knowledge is defined as socially justifiable belief, and research construct can be fully assessed.
validation is viewed as a process of building confidence with As we note in the abstract, we recognize that no one has the
respect to a purpose. answer. We trust that you enjoyed thinking aloud with us. We
now invite you to comment upon what we have presented so
4. CLOSURE that we together can create something of value not only to us
In this paper, we have questioned the fundamental but for our student colleagues - the next generation researchers!
assumptions upon which 'formal, rigorous and quantitative'
Table 1 -- Summary of Foundations for the Validation Square

Old View of Knowl- Fundamental Basis for New Emerging New View on
edge Validation Assumptions Refutation Assumptions Knowledge Validation

Foundationalist Knowledge is Kant, Hegel, Sellars, Knowledge is socially Relativist


absolute/innate Quine, Kuhn justifiable belief

Reductionist Rationality only Honderich, Einstein Intuition valid basis for Holistic
valid basis for defining purpose for ap-
knowledge plication of knowledge

Formalist Objectivity exists Hegel, Kuhn, Research validation linked to Social and
Wittgenstein, Gødel, usefulness conversational
Einstein

10 Copyright © 2000 by ASME


REFERENCES
Bailey, R., 1997, The Design of Industrial Ecosystems. M.S.
THEORETICAL THEORETICAL Thesis, The George W. Woodruff School of Mechanical
STRUCTURAL PERFORMANCE Engineering, Georgia Institute of Technology, Atlanta, GA.
VALIDITY VALIDITY Bailey, R., Bras, B., and Allen, J.K., 1999, "Using Robust
Concept Exploration and Systems Dynamics Models in the
Design of Complex Systems," Engineering Optimization,
Vol. 32, No. 1, pp. 33-58.
EMPIRICAL EMPIRICAL Barlas, Y., 1996, “Formal Aspects of Model Validity and Vali-
STRUCTURAL PERFORMANCE dation in System Dynamics.” System Dynamics Review Vol.
VALIDITY VALIDITY 12, No. 3, pp. 183-210.
Barlas, Y. and S. Carpenter, 1990, “Philosophical Roots of
Model Validation: Two Paradigms.” System Dynamics
Review Vol. 6, No. 2, pp. 148-166.
Figure 3 - - The Validation Square Barzilai, J., 1998, "Measurement Foundations for Preference
Function Modeling." The 1998 IEEE Conference on Sys-
The Validation Square has been used to validate a design tems, Man, and Cybernetics, San Diego, CA.
method for realizing large and expensive made-to-order sys- Capra, F., 1991, The Tao of Physics. Boston, MA, Shambala.
tems, namely, the HPPRM (Pedersen 1999), and to validate a Capra, F., 1996, The Web of Life. New York, Doubleday.
method for product platform configuration (Siddique 1999). Chen, W., 1995, A Robust Concept Exploration Method for
Based on this paper we assert that the Validation Square is Configuring Complex Systems. Ph.D. Dissertation, The
appropriate for validating research results in general, as long as George W. Woodruff School of Mechanical Engineering,
it can be subjected to qualitative and quantitative evaluation as Georgia Institute of Technology, Atlanta, GA.
outlined in Section 2. Descartes, R., [1641] 1931, Meditations on First Philosophy.
By introducing usefulness and purpose into the validation The Philosophical Works of Rene Descartes. Cambridge,
procedure, we absolutely are not advocating that “anything Cambridge University Press.
goes.” The validation square is specifically designed to bring Einstein, A., 1950, The Theory of Relativity & Other Essays.
rigor to a validation process that is both quantitative and New York, MJF Books.
qualitative. When dealing with open constructs such as design Emblemsvåg, J., 1999. Activity-Based Life-Cycle Assessments
methods, open validation procedures are imperative. It is only in Design and Management. The George W. Woodruff
in a relativistic validation procedure that the validity of an open School of Mechanical Engineering, School of Mechanical
construct can be fully assessed. Engineering, Georgia Institute of Technology, Atlanta, GA.
As we note in the abstract, we recognize that no one has the Gödel, K., 1931. “Über Formal Unentscheidbare Sätze der
answer. We trust that you enjoyed thinking aloud with us. We Principia Mathematica und Verwandter Systeme.”
now invite you to comment upon what we have presented so Monatshefte für Math. u. Physik Vol. 38, pp. 173-198.
that we together can create something of value not only to us Hall, P., 1994, Innovation, Economics and Evolution - Theo-
but for our student colleagues - the next generation researchers! retical Perspectives on Changing Technology in Economic
Systems. Hertfordshere England, Harvester Wheatsheaf.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS Hazelrigg, G. A. (1999). “Validation of Engineering Design
Kjartan Pedersen's doctoral study was supported both finan- Alternative Selection Methods.” unpublished.
cially and by way of information by Kvaerner ASA, Norway. Hegel, G. W. F., [1817] 1959, Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
We acknowledge the financial support. We gratefully acknowl- New York, Philosophical Library.
edge the encouragement that we have received from Rolf Honderich, T., Ed., 1995, The Oxford Companion to Philoso-
Kvamsdahl (Kvaerner ASA) and Stian Erichsen (NTNU, phy. New York, Oxford University Press.
Trondheim) to think out of the box and in making change a Kant, I. [1781] 1933, Critique of Pure Reason. London, St.
handmaiden of success. Reid Bailey has been supported by a Martins Press.
Department of Energy Integrated Manufacturing Fellowship. Koch, P. N., 1997, Hierarchical Modeling and Robust Synthe-
Finally, we acknowledge the contribution of Carolyn Seepersad sis for the Preliminary Design of Large Scale Complex
in identifying and smoothing over some of the rough spots in Systems. Ph.D. Dissertation, The George W. Woodruff
this paper. School of Mechanical Engineering, Georgia Institute of
Technology, Atlanta, GA.

11 Copyright © 2000 by ASME


Kuhn, T., [1962] 1970, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Sellars, W., Ed., 1963, Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind.
Chicago, University of Chicago Press. Science, Perception and Reality. New York, Humanities
Lewis, K., 1996, An Algorithm for Integrated Subsystem Em- Press.
bodiment and System Synthesis. The George W. Woodruff Siddique, Z., 1999, Common Platform Development: Designing
School of Mechanical Engineering, Georgia Institute of for Product Variety, Ph.D. Dissertation, The George W.
Technology, Atlanta, GA. Woodruff School of Mechanical Engineering, Georgia
Locke, J., [1690] 1894, An Essay Concerning Human Under- Institute of Technology, Atlanta, GA.
standing. Oxford, Clarendon Press. Silverberg, G., 1991, “Adoption and Diffusion of Technology
Mistree, F., O. F. Hughes and B. A. Bras, 1993, "The Compro- as a Collective Evolutionary Process.” Technological Fore-
mise Decision Support Problem and the Adaptive Linear casting and Social Change, Vol. 39, pp. 67-80.
Programming Algorithm." Structural Optimization: Status Silverberg, G., G. Dosi and L. Orsenigo, 1988, “Innovation,
and Promise. M. P. K. (Ed.). Washington, D.C., pp. 247- diversity, and diffusion: a self-organisation model.” The
289. Economic Journal Vol. 98, pp. 1032-1354.
Pedersen, K., 1999, "Designing Platform Families: An Evolu- Simpson, T. W., 1998, A Concept Exploration Method for
tionary Approach to Developing Engineering Systems." Product Family Design. Ph.D. Dissertation, The George W.
Ph.D. Dissertation, The George W. Woodruff School of Woodruff School of Mechanical Engineering, Georgia
Mechanical Engineering. Georgia Institute of Technology, Institute of Technology, Atlanta, GA.
Atlanta, GA. Sneath, P. H. A. and R. R. Sokal, 1973, Numerical Taxonomy.
Peplinski, J., 1997, Enterprise Design: Extending Product San Francisco, W.H. Freeman and Company.
Design to Include Manufacturing Process Design and Toulmin, S. (1977) "From Form to Function: Philosophy and
Organization. Ph.D. Dissertation, The George W. Woodruff History of Science in the 1950s and Now," Daedalus, Vol.
School of Mechanical Engineering, Georgia Institute of 106, pp. 143-162.
Technology, Atlanta, GA. Wittgenstein, L., [1921] 1961, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus.
Quine, W. v. O., Ed., 1953, Two Dogmas of Empiricism. From London, Routledge and Kegan Paul.
a Logical Point of View. Cambridge, MA, Harvard Univer- Yin, R.K., 1994, Case Study Research: Design and Methods,
sity Press. 2nd edition, Sage Publications, Thousand Oaks, CA.
Richardson, G. P. and A. L. Pugh, 1981, Introduction to System
Dynamics Modeling with DYNAMO. Cambridge, MA, MIT
Press.

TO CITE THIS WORK:

Pedersen, K., Emblemsvag, J., Bailey, R., Allen, J.K. and Mistree, F., 2000, “The ‘Validation Square’ –
Validating Design Methods & Research,” ASME Design Theory and Methodology Conference, (Allen, JK, Ed.),
New York: ASME, 2000. ASME DETC2000/DTM-14579.

12 Copyright © 2000 by ASME

View publication stats

You might also like