You are on page 1of 11

Martin Jay

SCOPIC REGIMES OF MODERNITY

The modern era, it is often alleged,l has been dominated by the


sense of Sight in a way that set it apart from its premod ern pre-
decessors and poss ibl y its postmodern successor. Beginning with
the Renaissance and the scientifi c revolution, modernity has
been normally considered resolutely ocuJarcentri c, The im'enti on
of printing, according to th e familiar argwnent of McLuhan and
Ong,l reinforced the pri\'ileging of the \'isual abetted by such in -
ventions as the telescope and the microscope. "The perceptual
field thus constituted," co ncludes a typical account, " was funda-
mentally no nreAexive, visual and quantitati\·e,"3
Although the implied characterization of different eras in
this generalization as mo re fa\'orably inclined to other se nses
should not be taken at face \·a]ue,4 it is difficult to deny that the
visual has been dominant in modern Western culture in a wide
variety of \\'ays. Whethcr we focus o n "the mirror of nat ure"
metaphor in philosophy with Ri chard Rorty or emphasize the
prevalence of sun'eillan ce with Mi chel Foucault or bemoan the
society of the spectacle with Guy Debord,5 we confront again
and again the ubiquity of vis ion as the master sense of the mod-
ern era,
But what preCisely constitutes the \·isual culture of thi s era
is not so readily apparent. Indeed , we might well ask, borrowing
Christian Metz's term , is thcre one unified "scopic regi me"6 of
the modern or are there se\'cral , perhaps competing o nes? For,
as Jacqueline Rose has recently reminded us, "our predous his-
Gion.nni Battista Tiepolo. Th£ lVarld Pap Homt1fJ£ 10 Sp<lin. 1762-64. Washington, D.C., tory is not the petrified block of a Single \'isual space si nce,
Na tional Gallery of Art, Samuel H. Kress Collection. (Courtesy Na tional Gallery of Art) looked at obliquely, it can always be seen to conta in its moment
Martin Jay I SCO P I C REG I MES OF" MODERNIT Y

of unease."? In fact, may there possibly be several such mo- peoples of Eu rope. "M The second is from Richard Rorty's \\"ide ly
ments, which can be discerned, if often in repressed form, in the discussed Philosop~r and che Mirror oj Noture. puhlished in 1979:
modern era? If so, the scopic regime of modernity may best be " in the Cartesian model the intellect inspects entities modeled on
understood as a contested terrain, rather than a harmoniously retinal images" " " . In Descartes' conception-the one that be-
integrated complex of visual theories and practices. It may, in came the basis for 'modern' epistemo log~·- it is represencotions
fact, be characterized by a differentiation of visual subcultures, wh ich are in the 'mind_'''~ The assumpt ion expressed in these
whose separation has allowed us to understand the multiple im- citations that Ca rtesian perspecti,"alism is the reigning ,"isua l
pli cations of sight in ways that are now only beginn ing to be ap- model of modernity is often ti ed to the further contention that
preciated. That new understanding, I want to suggest, may well it succeeded in becoming so because it best ex pressed the "natu-
be the product of a radica l reversa l in the hierarchy of visual ral" expe rience of Sight ,·alori zed by the scient ifi c ,,·orld d ew"
subcultures in the modern scopi c regime. When the assumed equh"alence bet\\"ee n scientific obse n "ation
Before spelling out the competing ocular fi elds in the mod- and the natura l world was disputed, so too ,\·as the dominati on
ern era as I understand them, I want to make clear that I am of this ,-isual subculture, a salient insta nce being Erwin Pan-
presenting only very crude ideal typical characterizations, which ofsky's celebrated critique of pcrspecti,·c as merely a CQ m·en-
can easily be faulted for their obvious d istance from the complex tiona 1 symboliC form" [0
rea liti es they seek to approximate" I am also not suggesting that But for a ,"c ry long time Cartesian perspecti,·alism was
the three main visual subcultures I si ngle out for spec ial atten- identifi ed with the modern scopi c regime roue court. With full
tion exhaust all those that might be discerned in the lengthy and awareness of the schematic nature of what folio\\"s, let me try to
loosely defined epoch we call modernity" But, as will soon be- establish its most important characterist ics. There is, of course,
come apparent, it will be challenging enough to try to do justice an immense literature on the discovery, rediscQ\·e ry, or im·entio n
in the limited space I have to those I do want to highlight as of perspecti ve -all three terms are used depending on the
most significant" writer's interpretation of ancient ,·isual knowledge-in the ital-
Let me begin by turning to what is normally claimed to be ian Quattroce nto. Brunelleschi is traditionallv accorded the
the dominant, even totally hegemoni c, visua l model of the mod - honor of being its practical im"entor or discowrer, wh ile Alberti
ern era , that which we can identi fy with Renaissance notions of is almost unh·e rsally acknowledged as it'i first theoreti ca l inter-
perspective in the visual arts and Cartesian ideas of subjective preter. From I\-ins, Panofsky, and Krautheimer to Edgerto n,
rationality in philosophy. For conve ni ence, it can be called Car- White, and Kubon·,, II scholars ha,"e im"estigated ,"ir tua ll\", c'"er\",
tesian perspectivalism" That it is often assumed to be equivalent aspect of the perspecti,·alist re,·olution, technical, aestheti c, psy-
to the modern scopic regime per se is illustrated by two remarks chologi ca l, religiOUS, e'·en economic and polit ical.
from prominent commentators" The first is the claim made by Despite many still disputed issues, a rough consensus see ms
the art historian William Ivins, Jr., in his An and Geometry of to have emerged around the fo llOWing points. GrOWing out of
1946 that "the history of art during the five hundred years that the late medic,"a l fascination with the metaphysica l impli cations
have elapsed since Alberti wrote has bee n little more than the of light - light as di,·ine lux rather than pe rceh-ed lumen- linea r
story of the slow diffusion of his ideas through the artists and perspecth"e came to symbolize a harmony bet\\"een the mathe-


School of PitTO della Francesca. View rf £In /dUll Cil)'. 1470(?). Urbino, Palano D\lcale.
(Co\ln es)' Art Reso\lrce, N.Y.)

matica l regularities in opticS and God's will. Even after the re- famous metaphor, could also be understood as a Rat mirror re-
ligious underpinnings of this equation were eroded , ~he favorable Aecting the geometri calized space of the scene depicted back
connotations surrounding the allegedly objecti ve optical order onto the no less geometricalized space rad iating out from t he
remained powerfully in place. These positive associations had viewing eye.
been displaced from the objects, often religious in content , de- Significa ntly, that eye was singular, rather than the two
picted in earlier painting to the spatial relations of the perspec- eyes of normal binocular vision. It was conceived in the manner
tival canvas themselves. T his new concept of space was geo- of a lone eye looking through a peephole at the scene in front of
metrically isotropic, rectilinear, abstract, and uniform. The velo it. Such an eye was, moreover, understood to be static, unblink-
or veil of threads Alberti used to depict it conventionalized that ing, and fixated, rather than dynami C, moving with what later
space in a way that anticipated the grids so characteristic of scientists would call " saccadic" jumps from one foca l point to
twent ieth-ce ntury art , although, as Rosalind Krauss has re- another. In Norman Bryson's terms, it followed the logic of the
minded us, Alberti's veil was assumed to correspond to external Gaze rather than the Glance, thus producing a visual take that
reality in a way that its modernist successor did not . i2 . was eternalized, reduced to one "point of view," and disem-
The three-dimensional, rationalized space of perspectival bodied. In what Bryson ca lls the "Founding Perception" of the
visi on could be rendered on a two-dimensional surface by fol- Cartesian perspectivalist tradition ,
lowing all of the transformational rules spelled out in Alberti's
De Pirwra and later treatises by Viator, DUrer, and others. The
the aaze '!! the painter arrests the flux if phenomena, comemplares the
visual field from a vamage-poine outside the mobility if duration, in
basic device was the idea of symmetrical visual pyram ids or
cones with one of their apexes the reced ing vanishing or centri c
an eternal momem if disclosed presence; while in the momem if view-
ina, the viewina subjea unites his aaze with the Founding Perception,
poi nt in the painting, the other the eye of the painter .or the b~~
holder. T he transparent window that was the canvas, m Alberti s
in a momene if perfect recreation if that fi rst epiphao/. 13


SCOPIC REGIMES OF MODERNITY
Norlin Joy \

A number of implications follO\ved from the adoption of this vi- from any substantive content, which is part of the cliched his-
sual order. The abstract coldness of the perspectival gaze meant tory of twentieth-century modernism, was already prepared by
the withdrawal of the painter's emotional entanglement with the the perspecti"al revolution fi ve centuri es earl ier. What Bryson in
obj ects depicted in geometricalized space. The pa~ti~i~atory .in- his book Word and Image call s the diminution of the discursive
"olvement of more absorpti"e visual modes "vas dlmlOlshed, If function of painting, its telling a story to the unlettered masses,
not entirelv suppressed, as the gap between spectator and spec- in fayor of its figura l fun ction,16 meant the increaSi ng autonomy
tacle wide~ed. The moment of erotic proj ecti on in vision -what of the image from any ex trinsic purpose, religious or otherwise.
" I d . "14
St. August ine had anxiously condemned as ocu ar eSlre - The effect of realism was conse<juently enhanced as ca nvases
. I
"as ost a.~" the bodies of the pa inter and viewer were forgottenh were filled with more and more information that seemed unre-
in the name of an allegedly disincarnated, absolute eye. Althoug lated to any narrati ve or textual fun ction. Cartesian perspectival-
such a gaze could, of course, sti ll fall on obj ects of desire- . ism was thus in league with a scientific world view that no
think , for example, of the female nude in DUrer's famous pnnt longe r hermeneutically read the world as a divine text, but
of a draftsman drawing her through a screen of perspectival rather saw it as situated in a mathematica lly regular spatio-tem-
threads IS _ it did so largely in the service of a reifying male look poral order filled 'w ith natural objects that could only be ob-
that turned its targets into stone. The marmoreal nude drained se rved from without by the dispassionate eye of the neutral
of its ca pacity to arouse desire was at least tendentially the out- researcher.
come of this development. Despite important exceptions, such as It was also compli citous, so many commentators have
Carayaggio's seductive boys or Titian's Venus cif Urbina, the ~udes claimed, with the fundamentally bourgeOiS ethi c of the modern
themsekes fail to look out at the "iewer, radiating no erotiC en- world. According to Edgerton, Florentine businessmen with
ergy in the other direction. Only much later in .the histo,r y o,f their newly im'ented technique of doubl e-entry bookkeeping may
Western art, with the brazenly shocking nudes m Ma n~t s D~­ have been "more and more disposed to a visual order that would
jeuner sur l'herbe and Otl'mpia, did the crossing of the vIewer s accord wi th the tidy principles of mathematica l order that they
gaze with that of the subject finally occur. By then the ra- applied to their bank ledgers."17 John Berge r goes so far as to
tionalized "isual order of Cartesian perspectival ism was already claim that more appropriate than the Albertian metaphor of t he
coming under attack in other ways as well. . window on the world is that of "a safe let into a wall, a sa fe in
In addition to its de-eroti cizing of the visual order, It had which the visible has been deposited."IB It was, he contends, no
also fostered what might be called de-narratiyization or de-tex- accident that the invention (or rediscovery) of perspect i\'e ,'ir-
tualization. That is, as abstract, quantitatively conceptualized tuaUy coincided with the emergence of the Qil painting detached
space became more interesting to the artist than th~ qualitatively from its conte .. t and available for buying and selling. Separate
differentiated subjects painted within it, the rendermg of the from the painter and the viewer, the visual field dep icted on the
sce ne became an end in itself. Alberti, to be sure, had empha- other side of the canvas could become a portable commodity
sized the use of perspective to depict isroria, ennobling stories, able to enter the circulation of capitalist exchange. At the same
but in time they seemed less important than the visual skill time, if philosophers like Martin Heidegger are correct, the nat-
shown in depicting them . Thus the abstraction of artistic form ural world was transformed through the techno lOgical ,vorld

• •
Martin Jay I SCOP I C REGIMES OF" MOOERNIT Y

view into a "standing reserve" for the sUT\'eillance and manip- denunciations of their failings are often directed at a straw man
ulation of a dominating subject, 19 (or at least his straw eye),
Cartesian perspectival ism has, in fact, been the target of a Equa lly problematic is the subject pOsition in the Cartesian
widespread phjlosophical critique, which has denounced its pri\'- perspecth'a list epistemol ogy, For the mo nocular eye at the apex
ileging of an ahistorical, disinterested, disembodi ed subj ect en- of beholder's py ramid could be co nstrued as transce ndental and
tirely outside of the world it claims to know only from afar, The uniye rsal - that is, exactly the same for any human viewer oc-
questio nable assumptio n of a transcendental subjectivity charac- cupying the same point in time and space-or contingent -
teristic of universalist humanism, which ignores our embedded- solely dependent on the particular, individual visio n of distinct
ness in what Maurice Merleau-Ponty liked to call the Aesh of the beholders, with their own concrete relatio ns to the scene in .
world , is thus tied to the "high altitude" thinking characteristic front of them , When the fo rmer was e.x plicitly tra nsformed into
of this scopic regime, In many accounts, this entire tradition has the lat ter, the relati vist ic impl icat ions of perspect ival ism could
thus been subjected to wholesale condemnation as both false and be eaSily drawn, Even in the nineteenth century, th is potential
pernicious, was apparent to thi nkers like Lei bniz, alth ough he generally
Looked at more closely, however, it is possible to discern sought to escape its more troubling implications. These were not
internal tensions in Ca rtesian perspectiyalism itself that suggest expliCitly stressed and than praised until the late nineteenth cen-
it was not quite as uniformly coercive as is sometimes assumed, tury by such thinkers as Nietzsc he, If (' ,'eryone had his or her
Thus, for example, John White distinguishes between what he own came ra obscura with a distinctly different peephole, he
terms "artificial perspective," in which the mirror held up to gleefully concluded, then no transcendental world ,'iew was
nature is Rat, and "syntheti c perspecti\'c," in which that mirror poss ibl e,11
is presumed to be concave, thus producing a curved rather than Finally, the Cartesia n perspecti,'alist traditio n conta ined a
planar space on the canvas, Here, according to White, Paolo potential for internal contestation in the possible uncoupling of
Uccello and Leonardo da Vinci were the major innovators, offer- the painter's \'i ew of the scene from that of the presumed be-
ing a "spherical space which is homogeneous, but by no means holder, Interestingl), Bryso n ident ifies this dc,'elopment with
simple, and which possesses some of the qualities of Einstein's Ve rmeer, who represents for. . . him a seco nd state of pcrspect iyal-
fini te infinity,"lO Although artificial perspective was the domi- ism even more di sinca rnatcd th;-il that of Alberti, "The bond
nant model, its competitor \vas never entirely forgotten, with the ,'icwe r's physique is broken and thc \'ie\\'ing subject,"
Michael Kubovy has recently added the observation that he writes, " is now proposed and assumed as a notional pOint, a
what he ca lls the "robustness of perspective"l l meant that Ren- non-empiri ca l Gaze, "13
aissance canvases could be success full y dewed from more than What makes this last obse n 'ation so sugg:es ti\'e is the open-
the imagined apex of the beholder's \' isual pyramid, He criticizes ing it proddes for a co nsideration of an alternati\'e scopic regime
those .." ho najvely identify the rules of perspect ive established by that may be understood as more than a slilwariant of Cartesian
its theoretical champions with the actual practice of the artists perspecth'a lism, Although I cannot prete nd to be a serious stu-
themse h'es, Rather than a procrustean bed, they were practically de nt of Vermeer ab le to guarrel w ith)~r'yson's interpretati on of
subordinated to the exigencies of perception, whi ch means that his wo rk, it might be lIseful to si t uate the painter in a differe nt

10
II
Martin jay ! SCOPIC FlE:GIME:S OF MO DE:RNITY

context from the one we have been discussing. That is, we might menc in a leaible space; an wiframed imaae versus one chac is clear!J

include him and the Dutch seventeenth-century art of which he framed; one wich no clear!! siwated I'iewer compared to one with such

was so great an exemplar in a dsual culture very different from a viewer. The disrincLion fo11oll's a hierarchical model if distinauishina
that we associate with Renaissance perspective, one which between phenomena commonl), r:Jerred to as primary and secondary:

S"etlana Alpers has recently called The Art if Describina. 24 objeccs and space versus the surfaces, forms I'USUS the (extures if the
According to Alpers, the hegemonic role of Italian painting world. 26

in art history has occluded an appreciation of a second tradition, If there is a philosophical correlate to Norther n art, it is
which flourished in the seventeenth-century Low Countries. not Cartesianism with its faith in a geomet rica lized, rationalized , !

'"
Borrowing Georg Lukacs's distinction between narration and de- essentially intellectual concept of space but rather the more em-
scription, which he used to contrast realist and natur.alis~ ficti~n, pirical "isual expe ri ence of observationally oriented Baconian
~e argues that Italian Renaissance art, for all its fascmatlo~ wIth empiricism. In the Dutch context Alpers identifi es it wi th Con-
the techniques of perspective, still held fast to the storytellmg stantin Huygens. The nonmathematical impulse of this traditi on
function for which they were used. In the Renaissance, the accords well with the indifference to hierarchy, proportion, and
world on the other side of Alberti's window, she writes, "was a analogical resemblances characteristic of Cartesian perspectival-
stage in which human figures performed significant actions ism. Instead, it casts its attentiye eye on the fragmentary, de-
. ms N th
based on the tex ts of the poets. It is a narratIve art. - or ern tailed, and richly articulated surface of a world it is content to
art, in contrast, suppresses narrative and textual reference in describe rather than explai n. Like the mi croscopist of the seven-
fa"or of description and visual surface. Rejecting the privileged, teenth century- Leeuwenhoeck is her prime example-Dutch
constituti" e role of the monocular subject, it emphasizes instead art savors the d iscrete particularity of yisual experience and re-
the prior existence of a world of obj ects depicted on the Rat ~an­ sists the temptation to allegorize or typologize what it sees, a
vas a world indifferent to the beholder's position in front of It. temptation to which she claims Southern art readily succumbs.
Th~s world , moreover, is not contained entirely within the frame In two Signi fica nt \vays, the art of describing can be said to
of the Albertian w indow, but seems instead to extend beyond it. haye anti cipated later visual models, however much it was subor-
Frames do exist around Dutch pictures, but they are arbitrary dinated to its Cartesian perspectivalist riyal. As we ha"e already
and without the totalizing function they serve in Southern art . noted, a direct fi liation between Alberti 's velo and the grids of
If there is a model for Dutch art, it is the map ''lith its un- modernist art is problematic because, as Rosalind Krauss has ar-
apologetically flat surface and its willingness to include words as gued, the former assumed a three-dimensional world out there
well as objects in its visual space. Summarizing the difference in nature, whereas the latter did not. A more likely predecessor
between the art of describing and Cartesian perspectival ism, can thus be located in the Dutch art based on the mapping im-
Alpers posits the following oppositions: pulse. As Alpers notes,

aHenrion to many small thinas versus a Jew larae ones; baht rllecred Althouah the arid thor Ptolem), proposed, and those thal Mercator larer
cfJ objecrs ~'ersus objecrs modeled by baht and shadow; the surface if imposed, share the mathematical uniformity if the Renaissance perspec-
objects, their colors and textures, deah with rather chan cheir place- tive arid, they do not shore the positioned viewer, the frame, and the

13
12
SCOP I C REG I MES OF' MODERNIT Y

defini tion cif the picwre as a lVindo lV throu8 h which an enema/I'jewel


looks. On rhese accounts the Prolemaic arid, indeed carto8raphic arids
in aeneral, mUSt be distinguished from, nor corifused with, the perspec-
rh'o f arid. Th e projecrion is, one miBhl say. viewed f rom nowhere. Nor
is it (0 be looked rhrouah . It assumes a fiOt wotkins su:Jace. 27

Secondly\ the art of describing also anticipates the visual experi-


ence produced by the ninetee nth-century im"ention of photogra-
phy. Both share a number of salient features: "fragmentariness,
arbitrary fram es, the immediacy that th e first practitioners ex-
pressed by claiming that the photograph gave Nature the power
to reproduce herself directly unaided by man." 28 The parallel
frequently drawn between photography and the anti-perspec-
tivali sm of impressionist art, made for example by Aaron Scharf
in his discllss ion of Degas,29 should thus be extended to include
the Dutch art of the se\'enteenth century. And if Peter Galassi is
correct in Brjore Photography, there was also a tradition of
topographical painting- landscape sketches of a fragment of
reality-that resisted Cartesian perspectival ism and thus pre-
pared the way both for photography and the impressionist re-
turn to two-dimensi onal canvases.30 How wides pread or se lf-
consciously oppositional such a traditi on was I will leave to
experts in art history to dec ide. What is important for our pur-
poses is simply to register the existence of an alternative scopic
regime even during the heyday of the dominant tradition.
Alpers's attempt to characterize it is, of course, open to
possible criticisms. The strong opposit ion between narrati on and
description she posits may seem less firm if we recall the de-nar-
rati vizing impulse in perspectival art itself mentioned above. And
if we can detect a certain fit between the exchange principl e of
cap ita lism and the abstract relational space of perspecti\"c, we
might also disce rn a comp lementary fit between the valorization
" I G II of Art (Courtc$)" of of material surfaces in Dutch art and the fetishism of com-
GerTh Dou. A pouJltre,5 Shop. c. 16 17. London, NaUona a cry .
the Trust ee~, T he National G31lery. Lo ndon) modities no less characteri sti c of a market economy. In this

15
Marlin Jay 1 SCOPIC REGIMES OF' MODERNITY

sense, both scopic regimes can be sa id to re\'cal different aspects sional space seen with a God's-eye-\"iew from afar. She also
of a complcx but unified phenomenon . just as Cartesian and taCitly contrasts the Dutch art of describing, with its belief in
Baconian philosophies can be said to be consonant, if in dif- legi ble surfaces and faith in the material solidity of the world its
ferent \\'ays, with the sc ientifi c world de\\". paintings map. with the baroq ue faSCination for opacity, unread-
If, however, we turn to a third model of d sion, or what ability, and the indeCipherability of the rea lity it depicts.
can be ca lled the second moment of unease in the dominant . For BUci-Glucksmann , the ba roque self-conSC iously revels
model, the possibilities for an e,'en more radical alternati\'c can III the contradicti ons between surface and depth, disparaging as
be discerned. This third model is perhaps best identified with .a result any at tempt to reduce the multipli ci ty of visual spaces
the baroque. At least as earl ~- as 1888 and Heinrich Woffiin's mto anyone coherent essence. Sign ifi cantly, the mirror that it
epochal study, Renaissance and Baroque, art historians have bee n holds up to nature is not the Rat reAecting glass that Commenta-
tempted to postulate a perennial oscillation between two styles tors li ke Edgerton and White see as "ital in the development of
in both painting and architecture. 31 In oppositi on to the lucid, rationali zed or "analyti c" perspective, but rather the anam or-
linear, so lid, fixed , planimetric, closed fo rm of the Renaissance, phosistic mirror, either Concave or com'ex, that distorts the vis ual
or as W olffiin late r ca lled it, the classica l style, the baroque was image-or, more preCisely, rnea ls the com'en tio nal rather than
painterly, recessional, soft-focused, multiple, and open. Deri\'ed, natural quality of "normal" specu larity by shOWing its depend -
at least according to one standard etymology, from the Por- ence on th e materi ality of the medium of reAection. In fact, be-
tuguese word for an irregular, oddly shaped pea rl , the baroque cause of its greater awa reness of that materiality-what a rece nt
connoted the bi za rre and peculiar, traits whi ch were normally commentator, Rodolphe Gasche, has drawn attention to as the
di sdained by champions of clarity and transparency of form. "t ' f h . "34 b
al~ 0 t e mirror - aroq ue \'isual experi ence has a strongly
Although it may be prudent to confine the baroque largely tactile or haptic quality, which prevents it from turning into the >
to the seventee nth century and link it with the Catholic Counter absolute ocularcentrism of its Ca rtesia n perspccti" alist rival.
Reformation or the manipulati on of popular culture by the In philosophi cal terms , although no one system ca n be seen
newly ascendant absolutist state-as has, for e.xampic, the Span- as its co rrelate, Leibniz's pluralism of monadic ,·iewpoints.35 Pas-
ish historian Jose Antonio Mara\"all 12 - it may also be possible to c~l '~ medi~at.i ons on paradox, and the Counter Reformat ion mys-
see it as a permanent, if often repressed, \'isual poss ibility tiCS su bmlsslon to "crtiginous expe riences of rapture might all
throughout the entire modern era. In the rece nt work of the be seen as related to baroque vision. MoreO\'cr, the philosophy it
French philosopher Christine Buci-G lucksmann, La raison baroque favored se lf-conScio usly eschewed the model of intellectua l clar-
of 1984 and La folie du \"Oir of 1986,1.3 it is prec isely the explos i\'e ~ty ex pressed in a literal language puri fied of ambiguity. Instead,
power of baroque \'isio n' that is seen as the most Significant al- It recognized the inextricabil ity of rhetoric and visio n, which
ternati\'e to the hegemonic \'isual style we ha\-e called Cartes ian meant that images were signs and that concepts always contained
perspectivalism. Celebrating the dazzling, disor ienting, ecstatic an irredUCibly imagisti c component.
surplus of images in baroque visual exper ience, she emphasizes Baroque vision, Buci-Glucksma nn al so suggests, sought to
its reject ion of the monocular geometricali zation of the Carte- represe nt the un represe ntable and, necessarily f..liling, produced
sian traditio n, with its illusion of homogeneous three-dimen- the melancho ly that Walter Benjamin in particular saw as

16
11
Martin Jay I SCOPIC REGIMES OF" MODERNITY

characteristic of the baroque se nsibility. As such, it was closer to prefer, counter-art form). There are as well contemporary artists
what a long tradition of aesthetics called the sublime, in co ntrast like the German Jewish, now Israeli painter Joshua Neustein,
to the beautiful, because of its yearning for a presence that can whose fascination with the flat materiality of maps has recently
never be fulfilled. Indeed, desire, in its erotic as well as meta- earned a comparison with Alpers's seventeenth-century
physi cal forms, courses through the baroque scopic regime. The Dutchmen. 36
body returns to dethrone the disinterested gaze of the disincar- Still, if one had to Si ngle out the scopic regime that has fi-
nated Cartesian spectator. But unlike the return of the body nally come into its own in our time, it would be the "madness of
celebrated in such twentieth-century philosophies of vision as vision" Bud-Glucksmann identifi es with the baroque_ Even pho-
Merleau-Ponty's, with its dream of mea ning-laden imbrication of tography, if Rosa lind Krauss's recent work on the Surrealists is
the viewer and the viewed in the flesh of the 'Norld, here it gen- any indication,37 ca n lend itself to purposes more in line with
erates only allegories of obscurity and opacity_Thus it truly pro- this visual impulse than the art of mere describing. In the
duces one of those "moments of unease" whi ch Jacqueline Rose postmodern discourse that elevates the sublime to a position of
sees challenging the petrification of the dominant d sual order superiority over the beautiful, it is surely the "palimpsests of the
(the art of describing seeming in fact far more at ease in the unseeable,"38 as Buci-Glucksmann calls baroque vision, that seem
world). most compelling. And if we add the current imperati\-e to re-
A great deal more might be said about these three ideal store rhetoric to its rightful place and accept the irreducible lin-
typical visual cultures, but let me conclude by offering a few guistic moment in vision and the equally insistent visual moment
speculations, if I can use so visual a term, on their current sta- in language, the timeliness of the baroque alternative once again
tus. First, it seems undeniable that we have . .vitnessed in the seems obvious.
twentieth ce ntury a remarkable challenge to the hierarchical In fact, if I may conclude on a somewhat pen 'erse note, the
order of the three regim es. Although it would be foolish to claim radi ca l dethroning of Cartesian perspectival ism may ha\-e gone a
that Cartesian perspectivalism has been dri ven from the field, bit too far. In our haste to denaturalize it and debunk its claims
the extent to whi ch it has been denaturalized and Vigorously to represent vision per se, we may be tempted to forget that the
contested, in philosophy as well as in the visual arts, is truly re- other scopic regimes I have qUic kly sketched are themseh-es no
markable. The rise of hermeneutics, the return of pragmatism, more natural or closer to a "true" vision. GlanCi ng is not some-
the profusion of linguistically oriented structuralist and how innately superior to gazing. vision hostage to desire is not
poststructuralist modes of thought have all put the epistemolOgi- necessarily always better than casting a cold eyei a Sight from
cal tradition derived largely from Descartes ve ry much on the the situated context of a body in the world may not always see
defensive. And, of course, the alternative of Baconian observa- things that are d sible to a " high-altitude" or "God's-cye-\-iew."
tion, which periodically resurfaces in variants of positivistic However we may regret the excesses of scientism, the Western
thought, has been no less vulnerable to attack, although one scientific tradition may ha,-e only been made poss ibl e by Carte-
might argue that the \'isual practice with which it had an elec- sian perspecti\'alism or its complement, the Baco nian art of de-
tive affinity has shown remarkable resilience with the growing scribing_There may weII ha\-e been some link between the
status of photography as a nonperspectival art form (or, if you absence of such scopic regimes in Eastern cultures, especially the

18 19
SCOPIC REGIMES OF M OOER N ITY

Marlin Jay \

Notes
former, and their general lack of indigenous scientifiC revolu-
tions. In our scramble to scrap the rationalization of sight as a I. Sec, for example, Lucicn Febne
Tire Rtligion or R bel .
TM
, e m f! Unbch~f in rhe Si.Hunrh (cnfUfI':
Prob! { .
'2 0 01$, trans. Aeatrice Gottlieb (Ca b 'd M •
pernicious reification of visual Huidity. we need to ask what the "crsit)' Press 1982) d R be m n ge. ass.: HanOlrd Un i-
J 500-1640' ~n . ~ n . 0 . rl Mandrou, JmrOOIl(fion 10 Il rooern Fto",e.
costs of too uncritical an embrace of its alternatives may be. In . &so) In HIS/Of/col PSJ<:hoIOS)" trans R E H II k(
Holmes & Meier, 1975). . . . . a mar New York:
the case of the art of describing. \ve might see another rei fica-
tion at work. that which makes a fetish of the material surface ~ ~arsh~ \~c Luhan, Und~mondiflg Mooio : The Enensions of .IIan (New York·
e raw- I ,1964); Walter J. Ong, The Pwencc aflhe Hhrd' .
instead of the three-dimensional depths. Lukacs's critique of nat- [il/IUTO/ and Rdig/oUJ HisloTr (New Haren' Yale U '. _ . P ' 501J1(' PtolegomcnaIot
uralist description in literature, unmentioned by Alpers, might Elizabeth L. Eisemtcin Th p ' I p' O!H'rslty reliS, 1967); Set' al.~
, e fin! ng tess os an A8en! of (hon e' [am
II~"
' .
be applied to painting as well. In the case of baroque vision, we [IIII IITa/ Trans'ormOllons In E I .
V'
E . '8'
or I I (}(lcrn uropt 2 \"DIs (C b'd
mumCOllom and
University Press, 1979). ... , . am n gc: Camnridgc
might wonder about the celebration of ocular madness, which
may produce ecstasy in some, but bewilderment and confusion 3. Donald
"' P M 'c HiSIOty ~f Bollt8eais Percepcion (Chicago: Unin-rsitv
19'8Lo)\', or"",'
... go ress, 2 , p. 26. '. ....-
in others. As historians like Maravall have darkly warned, the
4. For an account of the POSltll'C.. attitude to\\OIrds vision in th~' mcdil'val
phantasmagoria of baroque spectacle was easily used to manipu- h h see Margaret R M' I J
[~/ru;ee;~0::~:a~::!~r:p~:=II~~~;sl~,ndin9 Illw~rn
cure,
late those who were subjected to it. The current vision of "the [litiSliofli!)' ond 5cculor in.
gument of FcblTe and Mand rou , which h" .. L~cen ,-err
' . ' ontrar~
mAuen, ',1 h toI t 1(' ar- I
culture industry," to use the term Mara,'all borrows from extent to which si ht \\ b . . - I ,S C S l OW5 t 1('
, g OIS) no mcans WIdely dC/Jl('ancd in the Middl , >\
Horkheimer and Adorno in his account of the seventeenth cen-
5. Richard Rorty, Philosoph)' OM lhe Jilirrot of ,vOlUTe Prin .' t:. gcs ..
tury, does not seem very threatened by postmodernist visual ex- "ersity Press 1979)' M' h I F l ' (ccton. Pnnceton Un!-
1979n)~ ~
, • IC e oucau t, Discipline ond Pu ·sh· Th B' h {
periments in ul a foli e du voir." In fact, the opposite may well be trans. Alan Sheridan (New Yo rk: Vintage Books . e '" ? the Prison.
lhe S i d • • UI Debord Socierr of
pte'OCC, reL C • (Detroit: Alack and Red 1977) . ' •.
the case. 6 Ch' . . . ' .
Rather than erect another hierarchy, it may therefore be · I' Bns~lan Metz, lhe Imaginal')' Signifier: PI".rchoonalj"SiJ ond lhe Onemo trans
7 e la Tltton
C . et al . (8100 mmgton:
. Ind'lana University Press, 1982). '. 61. .
more useful to acknowledge the plurality of scopic regimes now
available to us. Rather than demonize one or another, it may be
. Jacquelme Rose. 5exuoJir) '
pp, 232-233.
in lhe Field rYVision (L d . V P
o n on. erso, 1986).

less dange rous to explore the implications, both positive and Mas~.'. : ' Arr an d Geomelry: A Silldy in Space Imuirions (Cambrid e
8. W illiam .M' Idns. 'Jr
negative, of each. In so doing, we won't lose entirely the sense of ~ Hanard UIlI I"Crslt)' Press • 1946) , p. 8 I . g,
9. Rorty, p. 45.
unease that has so long haunted the visual culture of the West,
I~.
Blb/lorh~k Worbll19 4 ( 1924-1925): 258-331.
Erwin Panofsky, "Die Perspekti\"e als 'symbolischen Form'" c
but we may learn to see the virtues of differentiated ocular ex- ' \'orrrii8 der
periences. We may learn to wean ourselves from the fiction of a 11. William M. I nns.
M ' Jr., an rhe Ralionali7.olion if Siahl (New York· Met I'
"true" vision and revel instead in the possibilities opened up by .uscum
h d of Art ' 1938)', Pa nofsky. "d.Ie Perspektil'e als 'sl'lTlbolischcn
. Foropo"'.ltan

the scopic regimes we haw already invented and the ones, now RIC ar Krautheimer, "8 rune IIesch'I and linear Perspect' il'c ". B rm .. ,

SO hard to envision, that are doubtless to come. Samu I;


PersptClirC comp Is bell H
Ed . a
' m fIllleifeschl m
e yman (Englcwood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall , 1974)'
e . gerton, Jr., The RenoilSQnu D' . . ~r . •
Basic Books 1975)' J h W ho I$(OIC,) lj Lmeot PersptClil'e (Ncw York:
(Camb'd' ,on Ite, The B/rrh and Rebirrh if Picroriof Spac~. 3rd cd,
. n ge, Mass.: Belknap Press. 1987); Michael Kubo\")' The PSI'chol ,~r Po
speer/I'e and Rcnaissance An (Camb n'dge.. C ambndge
. . ' Press,
U lll\"ersit~, ;t "8.' C!J u-
1986).

21
20
Marlin Jay 1 SCO P IC REGIME S OF" MODERN ITY

12. Rosalind E. Krauss, Tht Oriaina/il}" rf 1M Arone-Garde and Orhu Modernist tlljtths Editions Galilee, 1984) and LaJo/it du 1"Olr: de J'esrhili'lue baroqut (Paris: Editions
(Cambridge, Mass.: The M IT Press, 1985), p. 10. Galilee, 1986).
13. Norman Bryson, Vision and Paimins: The Loaic rf the GalC (New Ha\"en: Yale 34. Rodolphc Gasche, The Taln rf Ihl! Mirror: Derrido and the Philosoph)' of Rif/tcfion
Uni\"ersity Press, 1983), p. 94. (Cambridge, Mass.: Har\"3rd Unh'ersity Press, 1986).
14. Augustine discusses ocular desire in C hapter 35 of the CI)f![euions. 35. As Bud-Glucksmann recognizcs, Leibnizian pluralism retains a faith in the
IS. For a discussion o f the gender implications o f this work, see S"etlana Al- harmonizing of perspectives that is absent fro m the mo re radically Nietzschean
pers, "Art History and its Exclusions," in Feminism and An H iswr)'= Questionina t~ impulse in the baroque, See La Jolie du \·oir. p. 80, where she identifies that im-
Uro~l'. cd, Nonna Bro ude and Mary' D. Garrard (New Yo rk: Harper and Row, pulse with Gracian and Pasca l.
1982), p. 187. 36. Sce Irit Rogoff, "Mapping Out Strategies of Dislocation. " in thc catalogue
16. Norman Bryson, Word and fmaae: Funch POimina f?fthe Anden Resime (Cam- for Neustein's October 24-No\"embcr 26, 1987 show at the Exit Art gallery in
bridge: Cambridge Un iversity Press, 198 1), chapte r I. New York.
17. Edgerton, p. 39. 37. Krauss, "The Photographic Conditions of Surrealism," in The Or/Sina/il)' rf
18. John Berger, W'!rs rfSeeina (London: BBC, 1972), p. 109. fhe Avon/ - Gorde. See also her work with Jane lidngston, L 'omollr Jou: PhotO[Jraphy
19. Martin Heidegger, " The Question Concerning TCi:hnology," in Th~ Queslion and Surreo/ism (New York: Abbeville Press. 1985).
Concernina uchnoJos.,\·, and Of her Essoys. tra ns. Will iam Lovitt (New York: Harpe r 38. Bud-Glucksmann, La folie du \·oir. chapter VI.
and Row, 1977). Heidcgger's most extensh'e critique of Cartesian perspt'"ct h'al-
ism can be found in his essay " The Age of the World Picture," in the same
volume.
20. White, p. 208.
2 1. Kubo\")", chapter IV.
22 . Sarah Kofman , Camera Obscura, de I'ideo/asie ( Pari~: Editions GaiMe, 1973),
t reats this theme in Nit-tl'.sche.
23. Br:'son, I'ision and Paimina. p. 112 .
24. 5\"edana Alpers, Til< An ~[Docribina: Dlltch Art in III< St"enttenth CenulI)"
(Chicago: U n iver~it~· of C hicago Press. 1983).
25 . Ibid., p. xix.
26. Ibid .• p. 44.
27 . Ibid ., p. 138.
28. Ibid. , p. 43.
29. Aaron Sl,·harf. Art and Phol"9rap~r (Lofl(lon: Allen Lant" 1968; reprint , New
\ 1- "
York: Pcnguin Books, 1986), ('haptcr VII I.
30. P{'trr Ga lassi, B~[ore Phol"9ra~r: Paintirra and /he Im-cnrion t?[ Pha1oorophy (New
r York: MU~'um or Moder n .~ r t, 1981).
31. Heinrich WolflHn, Renai$SOnre and &roque. trans. Kathrin Simon (Ithaca,
N.Y.: Corncll Unin' rsity Pn·ss. 1966). Sn' also tht' syst{'matic dc\'e!opmcnt of
the t'ontrast in Principles f?[ Art H;5to~r: The Problem t?[ the Derdopment f?f S~rle in
La fer Art. trans. M. I) . Hottingl'r (London: G. Bcll & Sons. Ltd., 1932).
32. JOSl- Antonio Mar;I\'all, Culture t?f the Baroque: Ano~rJis f?[ a Historical Srructure.
trans. Trrry Cochran (Minm'apolis: Unh·crsit~· o f Mimwsota Prcss, 1986).
33. Christ im' Bud-Glul' bmann, La raison baroque; de Boudcloire Ii lkn;amin (Paris:

22 23

You might also like