You are on page 1of 15

Forthcoming in T. Lombrozo, J. Knobe, & S. Nichols (Eds.

), Oxford Studies in Experimental


Philosophy, Volume 3. Oxford: UK, Oxford University Press.

Fuller and the Folk: The Inner Morality of Law Revisited

Raff Donelson Ivar R. Hannikainen


LOUISIANA STATE UNIVERSITY PONTIFICAL CATHOLIC UNIVERSITY
rdonelson1@lsu.edu OF RIO DE JANEIRO
ivar.hannikainen@gmail.com

The philosophy of law, or jurisprudence, is an concept has—this empirical debate would


area of study wherein experimental methods benefit from empirical research. In
are largely absent but sorely needed. It is particular, we might seek out folk
puzzling that the experimental turn has been psychological evidence, predicated on the
slow in coming to jurisprudence, as the field positive impact such evidence has had in other
straddles two disciplines where empirical domains of philosophy.
evidence is increasingly common. On one The foregoing may not be convincing.
flank, empirical studies have long been Traditional legal philosophers who do not use
popular among non-philosophers in law empirical methods will need to hear more to
departments; on the other, experimental appreciate why strange, new techniques
methods now abound in many areas of might be appropriate. Experimental
philosophy. philosophers who have yet to consider
While it is difficult to understand why few jurisprudence will need to hear more about
have adopted an experimental approach to the subfield and its issues to understand how
jurisprudence, it is clear why experimental they might contribute. We hope to address
jurisprudence should be on the agenda: legal such philosophers and others, but not with a
philosophers routinely ask questions that are purely metaphilosophical tract. Instead, our
explicitly empirical. To give just one brief essay aims to exemplify the potential for
example, consider the fact that in experimental approaches to jurisprudence. As
contemporary jurisprudence, some such, we focus on a narrow issue in
philosophers are concerned, in part, to give jurisprudence. We appraise Lon Fuller’s
the correct account of our concept of law or procedural natural law theory using
our concept of a legal system (Raz 2009), experimental techniques. Admittedly, his is
while others are anxious to show that there is just one of many theories about law; however,
no single concept of law (L. Murphy 2005; it is a prominent theory, and legal
Priel 2011). It would seem that this debate— philosophers have written extensively to
about whether we have a shared concept of criticize (Hart, 1965; D’Amato, 1981), defend
law at all, and if so, what contours that (C. Murphy, 2005), and extend that theory
(Winston, 2005). If our experiments usefully made public for those regulated to learn of
add to this debate, we thereby establish the their rights and duties), and the prospectivity
legitimacy and value of experimental principle (that a legal rule of conduct may only
jurisprudence. regulate conduct performed after the
The trajectory of the essay is as follows. We promulgation of said rule of conduct).1 Since
begin with background on Fuller’s theory of its initial formulation in the 1960s, Fuller’s
law and on the state of jurisprudence. For theory has been widely discussed and
those well-versed in those debates, this can be continues to enlist new adherents. This is not
skimmed or skipped. Next, we offer an surprising because the view has certain
overview of the studies that we performed. In theoretical virtues, virtues one can identify
this overview section, we state with precision upon reviewing other well-known views in
how our experimental approach helps to this debate.
assess Fuller’s theory. After the overview, we If the key discussion in jurisprudence is the
present each of the three studies themselves. search for necessary and sufficient conditions
For each study, we discussion our predictions, for law, the most notorious debate within that
the motivating thoughts behind those key discussion concerns whether a norm has
predictions, the manner by which the to have particular content in order to count as
experiment was performed, and the results. legal norm. Legal philosophers have been
In the final section of the essay, the general especially interested in whether a norm’s
discussion, we elaborate on results of our content has to comport with the strictures of
research and explore their limitations, and morality in order to be a legal norm. If a norm
muse in more broad-minded way about the permits or even requires those subject to it to
future of experimental jurisprudence. perform grossly immoral acts, can that norm
be a legal norm? That kind of question has
long been the hot-button issue in
Fuller’s procedural natural law theory
jurisprudence. Those who answer in the
The key discussion in jurisprudence concerns affirmative are, roughly speaking, legal
the necessary and sufficient conditions positivists; whereas, those who answer in the
something must satisfy in order to count as a negative are, roughly speaking, natural law
law or a legal system. Fuller (1969) offered a theorists. Legal positivism has a long list of
major contribution to this discussion when he famous proponents (e.g., Austin, 1998;
proposed a novel set of necessary conditions. Kelsen, 1967; Hart, 1994; Raz, 2009;
Specifically, Fuller argued that a social Waluchow, 1994; Shapiro, 2011); while
arrangement is a legal system insofar as that
natural law theory has its own list of famous
arrangement satisfies eight principles that he proponents (e.g., Aquinas, 1994; King, 1986;
collectively called “the inner morality of law.” Finnis, 1980; Dworkin, 1986; Murphy, 2011).
These principles include the generality Fuller set himself apart by straddling the
principle (that legal systems must have divide between the two camps.
general rules of conduct), the publicity
principle (that legal rules of conduct must be

1
We reproduce the full set of Fullerian principles
below and only offer this abbreviated list to help fix
ideas.

2
Scholars are often drawn to natural law sees as necessary features of law, laws
theory because they hold as a considered minimally treat people fairly. Arguably, this
judgment the thought that, prima facie, those feature of law would deserve respect and
subject to a law’s provisions have a moral would give subjects some moral reason to
reason to obey it. Or to put this considered comply with law. To illustrate the minimal
judgment another way, prima facie, law sense in which law treats people fairly on
deserves subjects’ respect. If this considered Fuller’s theory, consider two of his principles.
judgment is used as a desideratum for The publicity principle (that legal rules of
selecting one’s theory of law, one will endorse conduct must be made public for those
some content restriction as a condition for regulated to learn of their rights and duties)
some norm to count as law. On the other and the prospectivity principle (that a legal
hand, scholars are often drawn to legal rule of conduct may only regulate conduct
positivism because they hold as a considered performed after the promulgation of said rule
judgment the thought that some laws are of conduct) together imply that law
unjust such as those of the Third Reich, necessarily gives subjects fair notice of which
apartheid South Africa, and the antebellum behavior will elicit adverse state responses.
American South. The foregoing explains how Fuller can
Because, for Fuller, a norm can be law only accommodate one of the driving thoughts
if it has certain content (e.g. it is prospective behind traditional natural law theory, but he
and not retrospective), his view is often does not incur that theory’s key theoretical
classed as a version of natural law theory. cost, denying that there are unjust laws. It is
However, Fuller’s natural law theory differs to Fuller’s theoretical advantage over other
from more familiar versions of natural law natural lawyers that he can claim with legal
theory which claim that a norm is a law only positivists that some norms are both unjust
if the norm is just (Aquinas, 1994; King, 1986) and legal in the fullest sense.
or claim that unjust norms can, at best, be Before concluding this section on Fuller’s
defective instances of law (Finnis, 1980; work and its place in contemporary
Murphy, 2011). Fuller’s conditions only jurisprudence, we summarize the eight
disqualify norms which exhibit certain principles which comprise Fuller’s inner
procedural failings from being laws. Thus, for morality of law. The principles are as follows.
Fuller, many unjust norms can be laws, and (For ease of exposition, n will signify some
only some unjust norms would fail to be laws. norm, L will signify law, and all claims
For this reason, commentators often label concern a single jurisdiction.)
Fuller’s view an instance of procedural natural
law theory. CONSISTENCY: n1 and n2 are both L only if n1
Fuller’s procedural natural law theory and n2 are mutually consistent
might be thought to enjoy theoretical virtues
ENFORCEMENT: n is L only if the published
of both traditional natural law theory and
version of n accords with how n is enforced
legal positivism. Fuller’s view can
countenance the considered judgment that GENERALITY: n is L only if n is a general rule
law, prima facie, deserves subjects’ respect. of conduct
Given the procedural constraints that Fuller

3
INTELLIGIBILITY: n is L only if n can be whether his attempt has been successful. The
understood by subjects folk intuitions are the very subject of Fullerian
claims on this construal. Alternately, insofar
POSSIBILITY: n is L only if n requires only
as Fuller attempts to do descriptive analysis of
those acts subjects are physically capable of
law, analysis of what law actually is, folk
performing
intuitions bear indirectly on whether Fuller is
PROSPECTIVITY: n is L only if n regulates right. It is a familiar epistemic principle that
only conduct performed after the views requiring a massive error theory, that
promulgation of n is, views that imply that most people have
PUBLICITY: n is L only if n is publicly false beliefs with respect to a given
announced proposition, are to be regarded skeptically
(Jackson, 1998; Wright, 1994). To be fair, this
STABILITY: n is L only if n does not change epistemic principle has its detractors
too frequently (Frances, 2013), but generally, philosophers
Overview of the studies hold that extraordinary evidence is needed to
Having outlined our general ambitions and overturn widespread, commonsense views.
offered a sketch of Fuller’s position, we now Given that, determining what people believe
must explain our experiments. This is essential to determining whether the
explanatory task is twofold: to chart the presumption against error theories weighs for
specific steps we took and to justify using or against Fuller’s theory.
these experiments in appraising Fuller’s Whether one understands Fuller’s
procedural natural law theory. effort as an instance of conceptual analysis or
Broadly, our experiments attempt to descriptive analysis, experimental data would
ascertain the extent to which Fuller’s inner best bolster his account if it demonstrated that
morality of law reflects the folk understanding the folk widely and reliably agree with his
of law. The folk understanding of law can be principles. This implies that there are two
important for assessing Fuller’s theory in two ways that the data could cause trouble for the
different ways, depending on how one account: folk support for Fullerian principles
understands his effort. might be modest or even meager, or folk
support for Fullerian principles might be
Following Haslanger (2012a, 2012b),
unstable. If the data should reveal modest
philosophical analysis of the kind that Fuller
support, his account faces problems, whether
and others engage usually proceeds in one of
construed as conceptual or descriptive
two modes, either as conceptual analysis,
analysis. If few share his view and Fuller is
analysis of what ‘we’ take the analysandum to
attempting to predict our shared concept of
be, or as descriptive analysis, analysis of what
law, we may have to reject the account
the analysandum actually is, irrespective of
entirely as an inaccurate prediction. If we
how we see it. If Fuller was engaged in
view the theory as descriptive analysis, the
conceptual analysis, he was trying to
presumption against error theories may tell
determine ‘our’ concept of law. As such, his
against him. If the data should reveal unstable
theory is, more or less, a prediction of what
those who possess the concept of law would support among the folk – presented in one
fashion, Fullerian principles garner
say. Therefore, folk intuitions bear directly on

4
widespread support; presented another way, Throughout our studies, we investigate
they are roundly rejected – supporters of whether intuitions about Fuller principles are
Fuller would need to explain away the Fuller- susceptible to effects of construal level—in the
unfriendly response pattern. Otherwise, some contrast between (i) hypothetical (higher-
of Fuller’s opponents will attempt to explain level) versus actual (lower-level) laws in
away the Fuller-friendly response pattern, Studies 1 and 3, and (ii) between the essence
thereby saddling the view with the previous of law (higher-level) and concrete instances of
problem, that of modest support. law (lower-level) in Study 2.
With the foregoing in mind, we Evaluation mode
developed three experiments in which we Judgments and decisions can be made in one
probe folk (Studies 1 and 2) and expert (Study of two evaluation modes (Hsee, Loewenstein,
3) concepts of the law. Our studies aim to Blount, & Bazerman, 1999): separate
capture the levels of support that Fullerian evaluation, in which a single option or
principles garner while also examining two alternative is evaluated, or joint evaluation, in
kinds of effects on judgments about the nature which various options are presented and
of law. These effects, of construal level (Trope evaluated at once and often by comparison to
& Liberman, 2010) evaluation mode (Hsee, each other.
Loewenstein, Blount, & Bazerman, 1999), A wealth of studies has shown that our
have already been observed in other areas of preferences and judgments can vary as a
judgment and decision-making. Below, we function of evaluation mode—perhaps
briefly describe both effects and summarize because judgments in separate evaluation
evidence of their impact upon decision- depend on more spontaneous impressions
making at large. and easily evaluable features, while in joint
Construal level evaluation, secondary characteristics that are
The theory of construal level posits that harder to evaluate can be taken into account
mental representations (e.g., of a soccer (Hsee, 1996).
player scoring a goal) can occur at different In an oft-cited example, when asked
construal levels: Higher-level construal separately, participants offered to pay more
focuses on the abstract and functional for a new dictionary with only 10,000 entries
properties (e.g., whether it was a winning than for a dictionary with 20,000 entries and
goal, or a beautiful goal), while lower-level a torn cover. Then, when asked jointly,
construal highlights the concrete, participants were willing to pay more for the
sensorimotor and/or descriptive properties dictionary with more entries. Thus, it is
(e.g., whether it was a shot or a header, sometimes argued that joint evaluation
whether it had spin, etc.). Psychological provides the opportunity for spontaneous
distance is closely linked to construal level assessments—i.e., assigning more weight to
(Trope & Liberman, 2010) because events that the defective cover than to the number of
are closer to us in some respect, whether entries—to be checked against subjects’ own
temporally, spatially, or socially, are normative benchmarks—i.e., believing that
construed at lower levels. Distant events, by one ought to value the number of entries more
contrast, tend to be construed at higher levels. than the condition of the cover (Bazerman,
Gino, Shu & Tsay, 2011).

5
In Study 1, we examine whether the folk to determine how likely the folk were to
conception of law varies as a function of endorse these principles in the manner set
evaluation mode. In particular, we test forth by Fuller, as necessary conditions for
whether the folk endorse the procedural something to count as a law. We also sought
natural lawyer’s view—that laws necessarily to determine how likely the folk were to
observe Fullerian principles—more in endorse these principles, if understood as
separate or joint evaluation. mere contingent truths. Finally, we also
sought to explore the effect of evaluation
mode.
General methods
In this and the subsequent studies, we test
Our studies were conducted on samples
whether Fullerian principles enjoy
drawn from two populations: (1) United
endorsement at the 2:1 supermajority level. A
States adults (N = 242) with no specific
case can be made that “widespread support”
training or knowledge of the law, and (2) bar
is satisfied at any level of support at or above
association members (N = 92) with training
a simple majority. For that reason, our choice
and substantial experience in the legal
of 2:1 may appear arbitrary. Several
profession. Complete study materials, data
considerations recommend this level of
and scripts are available at
support. A bare majority is consistent with
https://osf.io/my2xe/.
rife disagreement. If, for instance, 50.1% of
Lay sample the folk endorsed Fullerian principles, it
242 participants (39% women; Age: Q1 = 27, would seem premature and perhaps even
Mdn = 31, Q3 = 40) were recruited from misleading to claim that Fuller’s theory
Amazon Mechanical Turk to take part in comports with the folk conception of law. It
Studies 1 and 2. All participants were US may even be premature to posit a univocal
residents with a 90% approval rate and were folk conception of law in the face of such
compensated for their participation (at disagreement. At the other extreme, requiring
$7.25/hour, based on median completion time unanimity seems unduly onerous and
during pre-testing). uncharitable to Fuller’s view. If all but a small
Law professionals fraction of participants endorse Fullerian
73 participants (56% women; Age: Q1 = 38, principles, it would be unreasonable to claim
Mdn = 52, Q3 = 63) were contacted via state that Fuller’s theory fails to track folk
bar associations. All participants were intuitions. With both simple majority and
members of bar associations, and most (87%) unanimity ruled out as reasonable options,
were lawyers. Median years of experience both the 2:1 and the 3:1 levels recommend
doing law-related work was 25 (Q1 = “10”, Q3 themselves. The 3:1 level looks particularly
= “30 or more”). attractive because it seems to “split the
difference” between simple majority and
unanimity. However, because we predicted
Study 1: Necessary or actual? Fullerian that Fullerian principles would not even
principles in separate and joint evaluation garner support at the 2:1 level, we chose this
In our first study, we sought to determine level as opposed to the more demanding 3:1
the degree of support Fullerian principles level.
enjoy among the folk. In particular, we sought

6
To continue about our predictions, we Imagine that anthropologists discover a
predicted that Fullerian principles would few previously unknown societies on Earth,
garner only modest support, falling below the referred to as the Faraway nations. Their
2:1 level, whether the principles were inhabitants are Homo sapiens like us and,
understood as necessary claims or claims though their customs and traditions are
about the actual world. This skeptical unique, they have government and laws
prediction is motivated by general skepticism much like the rest of nations on Earth. In
that Fuller’s theory reflects folk intuitions as this survey, we are interested in what you
well as some concern that there is a univocal suppose Faraway nations are like.
folk conception of law to be tracked. We also Specifically, we will ask you eight questions
predicted that the folk would be more likely to about their laws.
endorse Fullerian principles as true of the Next, participants were shown pairs of
actual world than as true necessarily. Two statements for each Fullerian principle and
reasons backed this prediction. First, since were asked to endorse one statement from
necessity entails actuality but not vice versa, each of the eight pairs. In each pair, one
the necessity claim is the more ambitious. statement was a Fullerian principle, phrased
Second, we expected that participants’ own either as an empirical claim (“The law as
experience living in polities that observe the enforced does not differ much from the law as
rule of law would dispose them to claim that formally announced”) or as a necessary claim
actual legal systems often do respect Fullerian (“The law as enforced [in Faraway nations]
principles; however, we also expected could not differ much from the law as
participants to be familiar with political formally announced”). The other statement
orders—historical, contemporary, and even in the pair was the negation of the Fullerian
fictional—with little respect for the rule of law, principle.
and this familiarity would dispose them to
Results
reject the idea that Fullerian principles are
necessary truths. There was substantial variation in
endorsement by principle: Some principles,
Study 1a: Fullerian principles in separate
like the publicity principle and the possibility
evaluation
principle, garnered endorsement by a
In this part of our first study, we ask one supermajority; others, such as the consistency
group of participants to evaluate Fullerian principle, fell even below a simple majority
claims as actually true, and another group to view (see Figure 1 and Table 1).
evaluate whether they are necessarily true.
To generate an overall measure of support
Procedure for Fullerian principles, we first averaged
Participants were randomly assigned to one of participants’ responses across all eight
two conditions, Actual or Necessary. In the principles: Agreement with Fullerian views
Actual condition, participants read: ranged between 46% and 54% in the Actual
In this survey, we will ask you eight condition (M = 0.50, SD = 0.21), and between
questions regarding the law. 52% and 64% in the Necessary condition (M
= 0.58, SD = 0.27). One-sample t-tests against
Meanwhile, in the Necessary condition, the 2:1 supermajority level revealed that
participants read: support for Fuller principles fell short of a

7
supermajority in both conditions: Actual t(82) It is unclear why a majority of participants
= 7.16, p < .001; Necessary t(80) = 2.81, p = treated Fullerian principles as necessarily true
.006. with regard to hypothetical laws, but not
Surprisingly, agreement with Fuller empirically true of the laws they know. First,
principles appeared to be higher in the it could be that participants do not fully
Necessary than in the Actual condition— understand necessity and possibility
opposite our original prediction. A mixed- (◊A→~□~A). Alternately, by appealing to
effects logistic regression confirmed this hypothetical laws in one condition and known
result: We entered condition as a fixed effect, laws in another, perhaps we inadvertently
and participant and principle as random asked participants to report on distinct
effects, while allowing the slope of condition concepts (Knobe, Prasada, & Newman, 2013).
to vary across principles. The model revealed If, however, participants view these
a significant effect of condition, OR = 1.55 distinct intuitions as conflicting or
[1.04, 2.34], t = 2.21, p = .027. In other words, inconsistent, then the difference in
participants were more likely to believe that participants’ judgments regarding actual
Fuller properties are necessary for law (when versus hypothetical laws ought to vanish (or
thinking about hypothetical legal systems) even reverse) under joint evaluation—a
than that they are actual properties of laws. hypothesis we pursue in Study 1b.

Figure 1. Actuality (x-axis) and necessity (y-axis) judgments for each Fuller principle under separate (blue) and joint
(red) evaluation. The solid diagonal line highlights the judgment reversal between conditions. The diagonal dashed lines
correspond to supermajority disbelief (1:2) and belief (2:1) averaging across judgment types.

8
Study 1b: Joint evaluation participants to spot the seeming inconsistency
In this second part of the study, we asked a in claiming that laws obey Fullerian principles
single group of participants to assess whether by necessity though many laws fail to do so in
Fullerian principles actually hold, and practice.
whether they hold necessarily. We predicted Procedure
that the surprising result we obtained in Participants were asked to make both types of
Study 1a would dissipate when participants judgments (actuality and necessity) regarding
make both judgments at once. Joint each Fuller principle. A short introduction to
evaluation, we surmised, would help the study made this clear.

Model 1 Model 2
Weighted prop. Necessity Joint Evaluation Necessity×Joint Evaluation
0.7 0.89 0.71 0.28 **
Publicity
[.65, .75] [0.56, 1.43] [0.44, 1.14] [0.11, 0.73]
0.68 0.7 0.71 0.30 *
Possibility
[.63, .73] [0.42, 1.18] [0.42, 1.20] [0.11, 0.88]
0.57 0.57 * 0.85 0.71
Stability
[.52, .63] [0.34, 0.94] [0.51, 1.42] [0.27, 1.87]
0.57 0.81 0.69 0.46
Generality
[.52, .63] [0.51, 1.30] [0.43, 1.10] [0.18, 1.18]
0.53 1.29 1.01 0.33 *
Prospectivity
[.48, .59] [0.83, 1.99] [0.66, 1.57] [0.13, 0.82]
0.49 1.18 1.43 0.59
Enforcement
[.43, .54] [0.77, 1.82] [0.93, 2.21] [0.25, 1.40]
0.46 1.06 0.96 0.53
Intelligibility
[.41, .52] [0.68, 1.65] [0.61, 1.65] [0.22, 1.31]
0.29 1.56 # 1.46 0.49
Consistency
[.24, .34] [0.96, 2.52] [0.90, 2.35] [0.18, 1.30]
Model 1: 0.87 0.94 -
Main effects only [0.73, 1.05] [0.74, 1.19]
Model 2: 1.60 ** 1.45 * 0.42 **

+ Necessity×Joint interaction [1.26, 2.04] [1.05, 2.01] [0.28, 0.62]

Table 1.
Endorsement of Fuller principles (in descending order) and effects (odds ratio and 95% confidence interval) of statement
modality, evaluation mode, their interaction derived from mixed-effects logistic regression models on agreement.
#
: p < .10. *: p < .05. **: p < .005.

9
Results participants to assess whether they constitute
Agreement with Fuller principles ranged law. By comparing participants’ endorsement
between 53% and 63% in the Actual of abstract principles to their assessments of
condition (M = 0.58, SD = 0.24), and between concrete laws, we aim to conceptually
42% and 54% in the Necessary condition (M replicate the effect of construal level on
= 0.48, SD = 0.26), once again significantly Fullerian intuitions.
below supermajority support in one-sample t- We predicted that the folk would be
tests: Actual t(77) = 3.18, p = .002; Necessary more likely to endorse Fullerian principles
t(77) = 6.33, p < .001. when the principles are stated abstractly than
Indeed, prompting participants to evaluate when grappling with the principles in
Fuller principles simultaneously as empirical concrete situations. This prediction is
and necessary claims reversed the distinction undergirded by the thought, expressed by
we saw under separate evaluation. In a others (e.g. Hart, 1965), that Fuller’s
mixed-effects model, the effect of condition principles express reasonable rules-of-thumb
was highly significant, OR = 0.64 [0.46, 0.89], to make legislating rational and efficient. As
z = 3.00, p = .003. such, it may be hard—when thinking
abstractly—to imagine how one would engage
This time, laws were seen as observing
in lawmaking in any other way. However, if
Fullerian principles de facto (by a simple
one is invited to consider concrete cases of
majority), but not necessarily in a
lawmaking that run afoul of the Fullerian
hypothetical legal system—as we originally
principles, this difficulty in imagining
predicted.
dissipates, which should lead to lower rates of
Table 1 summarizes Fuller principles by
endorsement.
endorsement and compares the results of
Finally, we also investigate whether
Studies 1 and 1b, through additive (Model 1)
judgments on either task, the concrete or the
and interactive (Model 2) models with
abstract, are impacted by the order in which
evaluation mode and statement modality as
the tasks were presented. In our opening
fixed effects. The Necessity×Joint Evaluation
study, we found evidence that participants
interaction represents the judgment reversal
across conditions: Overall, participants were treated their judgments at different construal
levels as contradictory. Specifically, they
more likely to treat Fuller principles as
appeared to ‘correct’ their spontaneous
necessarily (but not actually) true when
Fullerian intuition—that hypothetical laws
judged in isolation, and as actually (but not
necessarily observe Fuller principles—when
necessarily) true when making both
prompted to consider also whether actual
judgments at once.
laws in fact observe them. Analogously, we
might expect that beliefs about the essence of
Study 2: The abstract essence versus law, stated in abstract terms, might depend on
concrete instances of law whether participants previously considered
The previous study focused on attitudes specific violations of Fuller principles (i.e., an
toward Fullerian principles when stated in effect of order on judgments in the abstract
abstract terms. Next, we introduce concrete condition).
violations of Fullerian principles, and ask

10
Procedure speeds under 85 kilometers per hour is
In a 2 (construal: abstract, concrete) × 2 forbidden and that anyone found driving at
(order: abstract-first, concrete-first) mixed speeds under 85 kilometers per hour on
factorial design, 104 participants were Highway 1 will be ticketed. As a result of
randomly assigned to one of two orders. the two bills, many tickets are issued and
Every participant viewed two tasks—an the state revenues increase dramatically.
abstract task and a concrete task—in a In the above example, we then asked “Are
counterbalanced order across participants. these two bills truly laws” Fullerian
In the abstract section, participants were judgments (that they are not laws) were
asked whether laws ‘must’ observe a given coded as 1s, while non-Fullerian judgments
Fuller principle P or if they ‘can’ violate P, for that they are laws despite violating the
example: consistency principle were coded as 0s.
Can there be laws that contradict one
another or must laws be consistent? Results
As predicted, we observed an effect of
The dependent measure in the abstract
construal level, OR = 7.51 [3.75, 15.03], z =
condition was participants’ endorsement of
5.69, p < .001. Participants were much more
one of two statements:
likely to endorse Fuller principles in the
There can be laws that contradict one abstract. When stated abstractly, participants
another in a single jurisdiction (0: non- endorsed Fullerian principles approximately
Fullerian), 67% [64%, 69%] of the time. When assessing
or concrete violations of Fuller principles,
participants largely reported that they were
There must not be any laws that contradict
truly laws nonetheless, with only 21% [19%,
other laws in a single jurisdiction (1:
24%] reporting Fullerian judgments.
Fullerian).
Unexpectedly, there were no effects of
In the concrete section, participants read order in either condition, |z| < 1, ps > .50.
about a city ordinance, policy proposal or bill Exposure to violations of Fuller principles did
that violated a certain Fuller principle P and not affect beliefs about the inner morality of
were asked whether it was ‘truly a law’ or not, law, and reflection on the essence of law in the
for example: abstract did not promote Fullerian reactions
to concrete violations of procedural
In a hypothetical country, a state principles.
legislature passes two bills that the
governor eagerly signs. The first bill is a
speed limit bill. It says that driving along Study 3: The expertise defense
Highway 1 at speeds over 80 kilometers per So far we have assessed views about the
hour is forbidden and that anyone found procedural morality of law in a sample of
driving at speeds over 80 kilometers per participants who lack technical knowledge of
hour on Highway 1 will be ticketed. the law. In reaction to past folk psychological
The second bill is a speed minimum bill. It evidence, philosophers have sometimes
says that driving along Highway 1 at argued against drawing any major

11
conclusions from laypeople’s use of technical simple effects of expertise emerged in either
concepts (Sosa, 2007). On this view, evidence modality: Professionals were no more likely to
of experts’ beliefs is needed to understand judge that Fuller principles are actually
whether law truly observes Fuller’s inner observed, OR = 0.81 [0.33, 1.97], z = -0.51, p
morality of law. In Study 3, we examine = .61, or that they are necessarily observed by
whether professionals with legal training and hypothetical legal systems, OR = 1.86 [0.84,
experience reveal distinct intuitions about the 4.28], z = 1.57, p = .12.
nature of law. Much like lay respondents, experienced
Procedure lawyers exhibited the core intuition that
For this study, lawyers were contacted Fuller’s procedural principles are necessary
through their bar association mailing lists and for law, while at the same time believing that
assigned to one of two conditions, Actual or laws in practice fail to observe them.
Hypothetical, as in Study 1a. The materials
were identical to Study 1a, except we added General discussion
specific questions about participants’ In three studies, we found limited support for
experience in the legal profession to the Fuller’s (1969) procedural natural law theory.
demographic information section. As we noted at the outset, in the best case for
Results Fuller, we would see widespread and reliable
Averaging across principles, overall folk endorsement for his principles. This is
agreement with Fullerian views ranged not what we see.
between 39% and 54% in the Actual First we consider the widespread front.
condition (M = 0.47, SD = 0.22), and between Though some individual principles were
57% and 78% in the Necessary condition (M widely endorsed by the folk, others were not,
= 0.67, SD = 0.32). Like lay participants, legal and as a set, the inner morality of law did not
professionals did not tend to think that actual garner 2:1 supermajority level support from
laws observe Fuller principles at the 2:1 the folk. Insofar as Fuller aimed to capture
supermajority level, Actual, t(34) = 5.26, p < ‘our’ concept of law, his theory misses the
.001. However, they did tend to judge that mark at least in part. Because many of his
hypothetical legal systems would necessarily principles garner a slim majority support
observe Fuller principles at approximately a (when construed the right way), worries
2:1 ratio, t(37) = -0.08, p = .93. about the presumption against error theories
Replicating the results of Study 1a, law probably do not obtain. Thus, if Fuller’s
professionals tended to demonstrate the effect venture is what we called descriptive analysis,
of construal level observed in laypeople, OR = he may be largely safe. However, some of his
4.05 [1.15, 15.08], z = 2.29, p = .022. When principles, particularly the consistency
thinking about hypothetical legal systems, principles which has 2:1 supermajority level
Fuller principles were viewed as necessary negative support, perhaps that needs to be
properties although they were not viewed as modified.
properties of actual law. There are larger problems on the reliability
We then compared the responses of legal front. In conjunction, Studies 1a and 1b show
professionals to those of lay participants. No participants’ views about Fullerian principles

12
shift depending on the conditions in which the philosophical debate concerning the role
they are evaluated. Instability of this kind is of morality in law may in some arise from the
problematic for Fuller, because, as we argued psychological capacity to oscillate between
above, when there are two conflicting reports two conflicting concepts of law (see also
of the level of endorsement, Fuller’s defenders Struchiner, Hannikainen & Almeida, in prep.).
are now saddled with data to explain away. Our results also speak to two common
This general problem looks particularly objections levied against folk psychological
worrying given the precise way that results evidence on philosophical issues: the expertise
turned out, since non-Fullerian reactions look defense and the reflection defense.
like they emerge in the epistemically Regarding the former, did experienced
preferable circumstance, i.e., joint evaluation legal professionals reveal different intuitions?
in Study 1b. In joint evaluation, as opposed to They did not; legal professionals were also
separate evaluation, arguably one’s views are divided with regard to the truth of Fuller
more likely to reflect one’s more settled principles and susceptible to the effect of
opinion. Study 2 looks similar, for it shows construal level. If anything, under separate
that when we vary construal levels from high evaluation, legal professionals were
to low, participants are more likely to doubt somewhat more likely to treat Fuller
Fullerian principles. Again, Fuller is saddled principles as necessary properties of
with something to explain away; and again, hypothetical laws despite recognizing that the
there is room to argue that the non-Fullerian principles are flouted by actual legal systems.
response pattern is formed in the more One may wish to push back at this point by
epistemically ideal setting. Such an argument contending that legal professionals are not the
might begin by noting that our intuitions are relevant sort of experts for the expertise
sharpest when considering more everyday defense. On this refurbished version of the
things. expertise defense, legal philosophers, not
On closer inspection, our experiments also lawyers, are the true experts. We do not and
point toward effects of construal level on the need not deny that our attack on the expertise
propensity toward Fullerian views. When defense would be better if we also surveyed
asked to reason about the law at a higher legal philosophers. Nevertheless, trained
construal level, a majority of respondents lawyers do not have untutored minds about
demonstrated Fullerian intuitions. This was the law, such that one can just dismiss their
true when participants reasoned about intuitions. These professionals have expertise
hypothetical legal systems instead of actual vis-à-vis the folk regarding a wide range of
legal systems (Studies 1 and 3), and when they norms that purport to be law, and frankly,
described the abstract essence of law instead many trained lawyers have expertise vis-à-vis
of concrete instances of law (Study 2). legal philosophers.
Taken together, the evidence we presented Regarding the reflection defense, did
casts doubt upon the notion that we have a conditions favoring more careful reflection
stable and univocal concept of law. Rather, influence beliefs about the inner morality of
our evidence suggests that naturalist and law? Indeed, our evidence indicated that,
positivist concepts of law are supported by when prompted to resolve the tension
thinking at different levels of construal. If so, between their conflicting intuitions,

13
individuals were more likely to conclude that intuitions are the very thing they aim to
Fuller principles are contingent, not discover. Experimental jurisprudence will
necessary, properties of law. provide more reliable access to the truths they
However, we must draw attention to seek. Other philosophers contend that we
important limitations of our studies. First, our have no shared concept of law (Murphy,
sample of legal professionals was smaller than 2005); for them, access to good data about
one would hope. As a consequence, our claims folk intuitions could help to decide that
regarding the expert concept of law should be matter. Our data might be suggestive on this
treated as provisional and subject to front, but much more evidence is needed. Still
confirmation in future research. Second, we other philosophers argue that our task as
did not succeed in eliciting a distinction philosophers of law should include (or even
between necessary and contingent truth wholly comprise) advocating that people
overall, which may somewhat compromise accept particular conceptions of law for
our conclusions regarding the modality of practical reasons (Murphy, 2005; Stoljar,
Fuller principles. 2012; Donelson, forthcoming); for them, data
about which views already have currency
We close by reemphasizing the broad
might influence the views that these
ambition of this essay. As the article actually
philosophers recommend. These are just
proceeded, it was largely a piece which offered
some of the theorists who stand to gain from
new reasons to doubt Fuller’s procedural
more of these projects. We can only hope that
natural law theory. As such, one might be led
others will continue in our stead and that this
to believe mistakenly that the interest of this
will yield a new, experimental jurisprudence.
paper lies in solely in point-scoring for
particular sides in a narrow debate. One of our
broader ambitions was to demonstrate that, Acknowledgements
by using empirical methods, we can We thank Guilherme Almeida, Joshua Knobe,
contribute to core debates in jurisprudence. Noel Struchiner, Dietmar von der Pfordten
Thus, this work hopes to make a significant and three anonymous reviewers for feedback
methodological point about jurisprudence, on earlier versions of this manuscript.
that experimental methods are viable. We also
hope that this essay provides a blueprint to
References
others (to revise and improve!) on gathering
information about folk intuitions about the Aquinas, T. (1994). The Treatise on Law. Ed. R.J.
nature of law. At present, little of such Henle. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame
Press.
evidence is available (e.g., MacLeod,
Austin, J. (1998). The Province of Jurisprudence
forthcoming; Tobia, forthcoming). Thus, this Determined. Indianapolis: Hackett.
venture and others it inspires will be helpful Bazerman, M. H., Gino, F., Shu, L. L., & Tsay, C. J.
to many philosophers. (2011). Joint evaluation as a real-world tool for
To see this, we mention just three groups managing emotional assessments of morality.
that stand to benefit from more experimental Emotion Review, 3(3), 290-292.
jurisprudence projects. There are D’Amato, A. (1981). Lon Fuller and substantive
philosophers of law engaged in conceptual natural law. American Journal of
Jurisprudence, 26(1), 202-18.
analysis of law (Raz, 2009); for them, folk

14
Donelson, R. (2018). Describing law, in Knobe, J., Prasada, S., & Newman, G. E. (2013).
preparation. Dual character concepts and the normative
Dworkin, Ronald. (1986). Law’s Empire. dimension of conceptual representation.
Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Cognition, 127(2), 242-257.
Finnis, J. (1980). Natural Law and Natural Rights. MacLeod, J. (2018). Ordinary causation. Indiana
Oxford: Oxford University Press. Law Journal, forthcoming.
Frances, B. (2013). Philosophical renegades. In Murphy, C. (2005). Lon Fuller and the moral value
The Epistemology of Disagreement: New of the rule of law. Law and Philosophy 24, 239-
Essays, 121-166. Eds. Jennifer Lackey and 62.
David Christensen. Oxford: Oxford University Murphy, L. (2005). Concepts of law. Australian
Press. Journal of Legal Philosophy, 30(1), 1-19.
Fuller, L. L. (1969). The Morality of Law, rev. ed. Murphy, M. (2011). The explanatory role of the
New Haven: Yale University Press. weak natural law thesis. In Philosophical
Hart, H. L. A. (1965). Review of The Morality of Foundations of the Nature of Law, 3-21. Eds.
Law. Harvard Law Review 78(6), 1281-96. Wil Waluchow & Stefan Sciaraffa. Oxford:
Hart, H. L. A. (1994). The Concept of Law, 2nd ed. Oxford University Press.
Eds. Penelope A. Bulloch and Joseph Raz. Priel, D. (2013). Is there one right answer to the
Oxford: Oxford University Press. question of the nature of law? In Philosophical
Haslanger, S. (2012a [1999]). What Knowledge Is Foundations of the Nature of Law, 322-50. Eds.
and What It Ought to Be: Feminist Values and Wil Waluchow & Stefan Sciaraffa. Oxford:
Normative Epistemology. In Resisting Reality, Oxford University Press.
341-64. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Raz, J. (2009 [2004]). Can there be a theory of
Haslanger, S. (2012b [2005]). What Are We law? In Between Authority and Interpretation,
Talking About? The Semantics and Politics of 17-46. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Social Kinds. In Resisting Reality, 365-80. Shapiro, S. J. (2011). Legality. Cambridge: Harvard
Oxford: Oxford University Press. University Press.
Hsee, C. K. (1996). The evaluability hypothesis: An Sosa, E. (2007). Experimental philosophy and
explanation for preference reversals between philosophical intuition. Philosophical studies,
joint and separate evaluations of alternatives. 132(1), 99-107.
Organizational behavior and human decision Stoljar, N. (2012). In praise of wishful thinking. A
processes, 67(3), 247-257. critique of descriptive/explanatory theories of
Hsee, C. K., Loewenstein, G. F., Blount, S., & law. Problema: Anuario de Filosofía y Teoría
Bazerman, M. H. (1999). Preference reversals del Derecho 6, 51-79.
between joint and separate evaluations of Struchiner, N., Hannikainen, I. R., & Almeida, G.
options: A review and theoretical analysis. An experimental guide to vehicles in the park,
Psychological bulletin, 125(5), 576. in preparation.
Jackson, F. (1998). From Metaphysics to Ethics: A Tobia, K. (2018). How people judge what is
Defence of Conceptual Analysis. Oxford: Oxford reasonable. Indiana Law Journal, forthcoming.
University Press. Waluchow, W. J. (1994). Inclusive Legal
Kelsen, H. (1967). Pure Theory of Law. Trans. M. Positivism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Knight. Berkeley: University of California Winston, K. (2005). The internal morality of
Press. Chinese legalism. Singapore Journal of Legal
King, M. L. (1986 [1963]). Letter from Studies, 2005(Dec), 313-47.
Birmingham City Jail. In A Testament of Hope, Wright, C. (1994). Response to Jackson.
289-302. Ed. James M. Washington. New York: Philosophical Books, 35(3), 169-75.
Harper & Row.

15

You might also like