You are on page 1of 27

doi 10.4436/JASS.

91009 JASs Invited Reviews


Journal of Anthropological Sciences
Vol. 91 (2013), pp. 63-89

Biolinguistics: forays into human cognitive biology


Cedric Boeckx

ICREA (Catalan Institute for Advanced Studies), University of Barcelona, Department of General
Linguistics, Gran via de les Cortes Catalanes 585, 08007 Barcelona, Spain
e-mail: cedric.boeckx@ub.edu

Summary - The present article surveys the field of biolinguistics. It revisits the roots of the field’s core
research agenda, then turns to the various factors that led to its recent re-emergence, and finally offers
suggestions for future inquiry. The essay also serves to highlight certain conceptual issues that should be
addressed if the field is to bear its interdisciplinary fruits.

Keywords - Anthropology, Development, Evolution, Genetics, Linguistics, Neuroscience.

Introduction The significant change caused by Chomsky’s


review was to reorient scientific studies of lan-
Biolinguistics refers to a branch of the cogni- guage towards more internalist issues, revolving
tive sciences that focuses on uncovering the bio- around the cognitive capacity that human beings
logical underpinnings of the human capacity to bring to the task of language acquisition, interpre-
acquire at least one natural language. As such, tation, and production—what Chomsky (1965)
and despite its name, it departs sharply from the dubbed “linguistic competence”. Chomsky went
many subdisciplines of linguistics, which focus on to formulate a set of central, field-defining
on how human languages are put to use in various questions, all of which led logically to the realm
socio-cultural contexts. That such uses require a of biology, converging with the range of evidence
(possibly complex and multi-faceted) biological revealed by Lenneberg (critical period, creoli-
foundation cannot be seriously put into doubt, zation, language impairments, etc.) This was
and biolinguistics takes that fundamental aspect in fact to be expected, as both Lenneberg and
of human biology as its subject matter. Chomsky took as their point of departure the
The biolinguistic enterprise grew out of the classic ethology literature (Konrad Lorenz, Niko
concerted efforts of several individuals, most nota- Tinbergen, Karl von Frisch, and others), where
bly Noam Chomsky and Eric Lenneberg, in the (animal) behavior was studied “biologically”.
1950s to overcome the overwhelmingly behavior- The success of what is often called the “cog-
ist framework dominating psychology and lin- nitive revolution” naturally led to the organiza-
guistics in the USA at the time. Although the term tion of interdisciplinary meetings, where lin-
‘biolinguistics’ did not emerge in its current sense guists, biologists, neuroscientists, anthropolo-
until the 1970s, the roots of biolinguistics are to gists, and experts in other disciplines such as
be found in Chomsky’s 1959 review of Skinner’s Artificial Intelligence, convened to shed further
book Verbal Behavior, which effectively put an end light on the biological nature and evolution of
to the dominance of the behaviorist paradigm in the human language faculty. Historically speak-
psychology, and Lenneberg’s comprehensive col- ing, the most prominent of these meetings was
lection of evidence in favor of a biological sub- the “Chomsky-Piaget” encounter in Royaumont
strate for the uniquely human capacity for lan- in 1975. It was, in fact, during a prequel of
guage acquisition, which culminated in his classic this encounter, in Massachusetts in 1974, that
1967 book, “Biological foundations of language”. Massimo Piattelli-Palmarini (the mastermind

the JASs is published by the Istituto Italiano di Antropologia www.isita-org.com


64 Linguistics and human cognitive biology

behind this and many subsequent meetings on enterprises, it suffers from the many differences
biolinguistics; witness Piattelli-Palmarini, 1980; that exist among perspectives, methodologies,
Piattelli-Palmarini et al., 2009) came up with the and even discrepancies in terminology. Too
term ‘biolinguistics’. Interestingly for readers of many scholars still put forth rather naive hypoth-
this journal, in the transcript of the 1974 meet- eses about language, ignoring the substantial
ing to which I have had access, both the terms progress regarding the computational nature of
‘biolinguistics’ and ‘bioanthropology’ were used human language over the past 50 years—a pro-
interchangeably to refer to the same enterprise. gress unmatched in the context of cognition
It was indeed clear back then, as it is clear now, (with the possible exception of early vision).
that, given the centrality of language for modern There is a serious need for linguists to make the
human cognition, a field focusing on the biologi- essential aspects of this progress available, in an
cal foundations of human language amounts to accessible form, to other fields. To achieve this, it
one intent on uncovering what one might call is necessary for linguists to engage substantially
“the human mind’s body plan”, which I take to with the biology literature, something which I
be the ultimate subject matter of bioanthropol- recognize has not yet happened enough, hence
ogy. But while biological anthropology achieved the feeling among some biologists that little has
independence from cultural anthropology and been achieved in terms of concrete results in bio-
flourished, biolinguistics did not. Biological con- linguistics. The overall message of this review is
cerns remained confined to introductory sections that there are grounds for renewed optimism in
of linguistics papers, and substantive engagement this area.
with the biology literature on the part of linguists
remained scarce. This is in part because at the
end of the 1970s theoretical linguistics developed Factors that led to the comeback
successful models of cross-linguistic comparisons
(Chomsky, 1981; Baker, 2001), and biological The return of ‘biolinguistics’ is due to a vari-
concerns were relegated to the background. It ety of factors, which I would like to first list and
is only recently—about ten years ago—that the then elaborate on in this section. The factors are:
term ‘biolinguistics’ resurfaced, and with it, the 1) The progress made possible by the genomic
interdisciplinary concerns that were at the heart revolution in genetics, which led to the
of the cognitive revolution in the 1950s. discovery of FOXP2, insights into its evo-
In this overview article I examine the factors lutionary history, and its interactome (Lai
that led to this biolinguistic revival, discuss the et al., 2001; Enard et al., 2002; Konopka et
progress made since then, and highlight both al., 2009) and which promises much more
prospects and challenges raised by recent studies. in the coming years;
Towards the end of the article, I also formulate 2) The rise of a bottom-up perspective in
some personal suggestions intended to advance comparative psychology, and its increased
the field, incorporating important results from appreciation that the basic building blocks
the anthropological sciences that linguists have of cognition might be shared across a wide
perhaps not yet assimilated fully. (Readers wish- range of species, in line with Darwin’s no-
ing to learn more about the early history of the tion of descent-with-modification (De Waal
field succinctly addressed in this introduction & Ferrari, 2010; Hauser et al., 2002), which
section are encouraged to consult Jenkins, 2000; opens up the possibility of constructing
Boeckx, 2009a; Di Sciullo & Boeckx, 2011; ‘cognitive phylogenies’ (Fitch et al., 2010);
Boeckx & Grohmann, 2013.) 3) A reduction of the theoretical machinery
I should stress that the field of biolinguistics needed to account for the fundamental
is still in its infancy. Although its major goals properties of grammar within linguistics—
are clear, like many similar interdisciplinary a theoretical trend known as ‘linguistic
C. Boeckx 65

minimalism’ (Chomsky, 1995, 2007a; serve as illustrations of some of the conceptual


Boeckx, 2006, 2011d), which renders the barriers faced by biolinguists.
study of the language faculty more feasible The first one is that in order to link genes
biologically speaking, both in terms of its (‘bio-’) and mind (‘ling’), it is imperative to
emergence, as it minimizes the cognitive develop linking hypotheses involving the brain,
boundaries across species, and in terms of for there is no direct road from genes to cogni-
its neural implementation; tion. As Marcus (2004) aptly put it, “genes build
4) A decidedly pluralist agenda in biology: neural structures, not behavior”. In fairness,
‘evo-devo’ and its ‘extended synthesis’ (Pig- even this statement is too simplistic, as genes do
liucci & Müller, 2010), which provides nothing on their own. To get to neural struc-
enough theoretical flexibility to handle a tures, epigenetic processes must be taken into
complex bio-cognitive object like the hu- account. But Marcus’s assertion certainly goes
man language faculty. in the right direction, as it highlights the dis-
tance between genes and cognition. And there’s
Molecular windows the rub: linguists, and cognitive scientists more
The logical deduction that the faculty of lan- generally, still don’t have a good understanding
guage is somehow part of our biological endow- of how brain and mind relate to one another. In
ment cannot match the excitement of actually recent years, several important reflections have
discovering genes more or less directly related to appeared concerning why this is so (Poeppel
linguistic behavior. It is for this reason that the & Embick, 2005; Gallistel & King, 2009 are
discovery of the link between a specific muta- outstanding), to which I will come back in this
tion of the FOXP2 gene and a linguistic disor- article, but for now, let me make clear that until
der (attested in the now well-known KE family) we fix this problem, we have little hope to inter-
played a crucial role in revitalizing the study of pret properly the information that comes out of
the genetics of language. The point, of course, genetics labs.
is not to look for ‘language genes’ or ‘grammar The second lesson to draw from inquiries
genes’, but to uncover the molecular basis of into the role of FOXP2 is that valuable as the
what ultimately makes typical language devel- information concerning the evolutionary of the
opment possible. A healthy dose of skepticism gene is (as is well known, FOXP2 is a highly
towards geno-centrism notwithstanding, the conserved gene, with only two amino acids sepa-
genomic revolution makes available new tools rating the human version from the chimp ver-
and new pools of data whose relevance for bio- sion, and only three amino acids separating the
linguistics cannot be overstated. human version from the mouse version), it will
There are several excellent reviews of the be extremely hard to draw inferences from it con-
steps that led to the discovery of the relevance cerning the evolution of the language faculty. For
of the FOXP2 gene, and of the implications that example, attempts have been made to establish
the early results raise for the relationship between recent selective sweeps (Enard et al., 2002), but
genetics and linguistics. I say ‘early results’ they remain extremely controversial, both con-
because scarcely a month goes by without new cerning the timing of the sweep (Coop et al.,
information about the gene and its interactome, 2008) or the very nature of the sweep itself (Ptak
but Marcus & Fisher (2003), Ramus (2006), et al., 2009; Berwick, 2011; Benítez-Burraco et
Fisher & Scharff (2009), Piattelli-Palmarini & al., 2008), due to inherent methodological rea-
Uriagereka (2011), Berwick (2011), Scharff & sons (the choice of initial conditions to detect
Petri (2011) and Benítez-Burraco (2012, 2013) the sweep; cf. Lewontin, 2002; Garrigan et al.,
provide excellent overviews. Here I would like 2010), and also because it is hard to be sure
to focus on what I take to be some of the most about selective pressures given the many sites of
important lessons learned so far. These will also FOXP2 expressions beside the brain (lung, heart,

www.isita-org.com
66 Linguistics and human cognitive biology

etc.) and the possibility of free-riding functional very recently was discarded, given the uniformity
effects in the context of pleiotropy. of language development.
It’s also been claimed that Neanderthals Let me elaborate on each of these points,
(and Denisovans) had “language” because their beginning with the last one. In the course of
genomes contained the modern human version unravelling neurogenetic networks implicated
of the gene (Krause et al., 2007; Reich et al., in developmental language disorders, we have
2010), but again linking genes and cognition learned that certain genes regulated by FOXP2,
without solid intermediary hypotheses involving such as CNTNAP2, are polymorphic, even in the
the brain is at this point a risky and largely spec- normal population. Some of these variants have
ulative endeavor, as Longa & Benítez-Burraco, been shown to affect early language development
2012 convincingly demonstrate. In addition, no in the general population (Whitehouse et al.,
gene acts on its own, and recent studies (Meyer 2011), and to also underlie differences detected
et al., 2012; Maricic et al., 2012) strongly sug- by various psycholinguistic measures in adults
gest that the context of expression of FOXP2 was (Kos et al., 2012). Studies of this kind (see also
rather distinct in our extinct cousins, given our Pinel et al., 2012 directly implicating FOXP2)
current understanding of the FOXP2 interac- cast doubt on the longstanding assumption that
tome in modern human (Konopka et al., 2009, the “linguistic genotype” is going to be uniform
2012; Vernes et al., 2008, 2009). across the species in the absence of a fairly severe
None of these difficulties are specific and specific pathology. Indeed, they suggest that
to FOXP2 (in fact, as Piattelli-Palmarini & a continuum may exist between these patholo-
Uriagereka, 2011 rightly emphasize, some gies and normal interindividual variability (an
aspects of the FOXP2 gene comes close to what idea Antonio Benítez-Burraco and I are currently
a geneticist would dream to find, so future can- exploring) and that there may be more than one
didate genes are likely to be even messier!), it’s “normal” neurological organization for language
just that biology is a messy business, as Richard (Hancock & Bever, 2013).
Lewontin never tires of writing (Lewontin, The discovery of the linguistic relevance of
1993, 2000). Although one may find aspects FOXP2 also led to a renewed appreciation for
of Lewontin’s skepticism extreme (see, e.g., the role of subcortical structures such as the
Lewontin, 1998), and indeed hope that “fossil basal ganglia, the thalamus, and the cerebellum
genes” will shed light where more traditional in language (and cognition more generally). It
kinds of fossils are missing (Carroll, 2006), no is fair to say that neurolinguistics is still on the
one should expect the story to be linear, easy, or whole rather corticocentric, but tracing the neu-
intuitive. Certainly, there is no clear lead in this ral expression of FOXP2 during embryological
domain at the moment. development, and tracking the effects of FOXP2
I also don’t want to give the impression that the mutations on brain structure and function has
value of everything we have learned about FOXP2 contributed to reverting this trend (see Vargha-
is unclear. Apart from having made it obvious that Khadem et al., 2005), and lent credence to mod-
the link between FOXP2 (genotype) and language els that attribute a key role to subcortical struc-
(phenotype) is very indirect, solid progress has tures (e.g., Lieberman, 2006). Recent knock-in
been made in at least three areas. First, it has pro- experiments in mice reinforce this conclusion, as
vided a significant boost to cross-species compari- significant structural changes are observed in cor-
son, and helped shed light on the neurobiology of tico-thalamo-basal ganglia circuits in mice carry-
vocal learning. Second, it has highlighted the rel- ing the humanized version of FOXP2 (Reimers-
evance of subcortical neural structures in under- Kipping et al., 2011; Enard et al., 2009); leading
standing the neural basis of language. Third, it has to the conclusion that FOXP2 has contributed
opened up the possibility of intra-species genetic to tuning cortico-basal ganglia circuits (Enard,
variation in the normal population, which until 2011). Other knock-in experiments in mice
C. Boeckx 67

(Fujita et al., 2008; Fujita & Sugihara, 2012; need for rule learning is most obviously attested
Fujita et al., 2012) have shown FOXP2 targets (Boeckx, 2011a; Berwick & Chomsky, 2011).
such as CNTNAP2 to exhibit distinct expres- Cortico-basal ganglia circuits, including their
sion patterns in the cerebellum, another brain dopaminergic modulations, are also crucial for
structure that is often missing from standard song learning in birds (Jarvis, 2006), and this
neurolinguistic models, despite its undeniable brings me to the third positive effect of FOXP2
relevance (Murdoch, 2010; Barton, 2012; Deniz studies in biolinguistics: the parallels between
Can et al., 2013; Saldaña Gascon, 2012). human language and bird song. Darwin (1871)
To be clear, the cortex remains relevant. As a had already recognized the relevance to language
matter of fact, Tsui et al. (2013) conclude from evolution of birdsong, which he considered the
new experiments in mice that FOXP2 regulates “nearest analogy to language”. Like humans,
genesis of some intermediate progenitors and many birds have fully instinctive calls, and an
neurons in the mammalian cortex, and suggest instinct to sing. But the songs themselves are
that the evolution of the gene may be associated learned. Darwin recognized the parallel between
with the expansion of the human cortex. But the infant babbling and songbird “subsong”, and
relevance of cortico-thalamo-cerebello-basal gan- recognized the key fact that cultural transmission
glia loops for some aspects of language should ensures the formation of regional dialects in both
now be clearer than ever. The big question, of birdsong and speech. Finally, he recognizes that
course, is, which aspects of language? The brain physiology is not enough for learned song: crows
structures just mentioned may give us a clue. In have a syrinx as complex as a nightingale’s but
a recent review, Jürgens (2009) proposed two use it only in unmusical croaking. All of these
separate pathways involved in the control of parallels have been amply confirmed, and further
vocalizations. The first runs from the anterior explored, by modern researchers (Doupe & Kuhl,
cingulate cortex via the midbrain periaqueductal 1999; Marler, 1970; Nottebohm, 1970), but it
gray into the reticular formation of pons and was not until the FOXP2 discovery that such par-
medulla oblongata and from there to the pho- allels were exploited by biolinguists (see Bolhuis
natory motoneurons. The second vocalization et al., 2010). Today, this is one of the most pro-
control pathway described by Jürgens runs from ductive areas of research in biolinguistics, as song
the motor cortex via the reticular formation to birds offer a model organism for vocal learning
the phonatory motoneurons. This pathway has (the only one, so far, but see Arriaga et al., 2012
been shown to include two feedback loops, one for the claim that mice also possess the basic
involving the basal ganglia and the other involv- neuroanatomy for vocal learning, opening up
ing the cerebellum. A comparison of vocaliza- the possibility of a neurobiological continuum in
tion pathways among terrestrial mammal species this behavioral domain, as mooted in Arriaga &
has revealed that only humans exhibit a direct Jarvis, 2013). In addition, the structural variety
pathway from the motor cortex to the motoneu- of bird songs offers the beginning of genuine for-
rons controlling the larynx muscles. In contrast, mal comparison with human language (Berwick
connections between the limbic cortex and the et al., 2011, 2012).
motoneurons constitute an ancestral trait found Looking back at what FOXP2 has taught us
in many non-human species. so far (no doubt, but a fraction of what it will
From this we could conclude that FOXP2 teach us in the future), I am tempted to say that
acts on structures involved in the externaliza- this gene made it plain to us that the distance
tion of language, morpho-phonological pro- from genes to mind cannot be underestimated,
cessing, and the mapping from hierarchical to but it also helped made us aware that something
linear structures (see Kurt et al., 2012 for rel- like “comparative biolinguistics” (focused on the
evant material). Interestingly, this is the area of inter- and intra-species variation that lies well
language where cross-linguistic variation and the beneath the surface variation that is the bread

www.isita-org.com
68 Linguistics and human cognitive biology

and butter of comparative linguistics—the com- 3) “In fact, we propose in this hypothesis that
parison of languages) may be in the making. FLN comprises only the core computation-
al mechanisms of recursion as they appear
Innovation and specificity in narrow syntax and the mappings to the
Perhaps no paper symbolizes the return of interfaces” (p.1573, column 2-3)
biolinguistics as well as Hauser, Chomsky, and 4) “At minimum, then, FLN includes the ca-
Fitch (2002). The paper is famous for introduc- pacity of recursion” (p.1571, column 3)
ing the Faculty of Language in the Broad [FLB]/
Narrow [FLN] sense distinction, and notorious Unfortunately, this infelicity attracted most of
for suggesting that the content of FLN is “recur- the attention in the subsequent literature. This,
sion”. In an attempt to reconcile what makes the in my opinion, was doomed to be unproductive
language faculty unique (human specific) and because “the core computational mechanisms of
properly Darwinian descent-with-modification recursion as they appear in narrow syntax and
scenarios (a program aimed “at uncovering both the mappings to the interfaces” alluded to by
shared (homologous or analogous) and unique Hauser, Chomsky and Fitch were never explic-
components of the faculty of language”), Hauser, itly stated in that paper (nor in the 2005 sequel),
Chomsky & Fitch (2002) distinguished between making the claim about “recursion” too vague to
FLB and FLN, with the latter being defined be falsified. Because of this focus on “recursion”,
essentially as what makes language human- most of the literature has tried to determine “what
specific. As Fitch, Hauser & Chomsky (2005) is in FLN”, but I think that this was the wrong
characterize it, “[i]t seems likely that some sub- strategy: the emphasis should have been on FLB,
set of the mechanisms of FLB is both unique to for the recognition that a significant amount of
humans, and to language itself. We dub this sub- the language faculty could be neither specific to
set of mechanisms the faculty of language in the language nor unique to humans marked a rather
narrow sense (FLN).” sharp departure from the standard position in the
Hauser, Chomsky and Fitch went on to dominant biolinguistic paradigm in its early days.
implicate “recursion” in trying to add content As Chomsky (2007a) has observed, “[t]hrough-
to FLN. I use words like ‘implicate’ and put out the modern history of generative grammar,
‘recursion’ in quotes for, as readers of Hauser, the problem of determining the character of [the]
Chomsky & Fitch (2002) will immediately F[aculty of ] L[anguage] has been approached
notice, the exact position defended in the paper “from top down”: How much must be attributed
is not clear. Consider the following passages, all to U[niversal] G[rammar] to account for lan-
taken from the same paper: guage acquisition? The M[inimalist] P[rogram]
seeks to approach the problem “from bottom
1) “We hypothesize that FLN only includes up”: How little can be attributed to UG while
recursion and is the only uniquely human still accounting for the variety of I-languages
component of the faculty of language” attained?” This significant shift of perspective in
(p.1569, abstract) linguistics is, in fact, part of a sea-change within
2) “We assume ... that a key component of the cognitive sciences that makes what I have
FLN is a computational system that gener- called “comparative biolinguistics” possible. This
ates internal representations and maps them is well-captured in the following passage from De
into the sensory-motor interface by the Waal & Ferrari (2010):
phonological system, and into the concep-
tual-intentional interface by the (formal) “Over the last few decades, comparative
semantic system. ... All approaches agree cognitive research has focused on the pinnacles
that the core property of FLN is recursion” of mental evolution, asking all-or-nothing
(p.1571, column 1) questions such as which animals (if any) possess
C. Boeckx 69

a theory of mind, culture, linguistic abilities, evolution to be included in FLB or in FLN.


future planning, and so on. Research programs Take FOXP2. While highly conserved, the gene
adopting this top-down perspective have often has undergone two mutations in our lineage.
pitted one taxon against another, resulting in Say, for the sake of the argument, that we suc-
sharp dividing lines. Insight into the underlying ceed in establishing that these mutations led to
mechanisms has lagged behind ... specifically (and uniquely) linguistic changes.
A dramatic change in focus now seems to be Would the role of FOXP2 be a component
under way, however, with increased appreciation of FLB, or of FLN? FLN, it seems to me, but
that the basic building blocks of cognition might not according to Fitch, Hauser, and Chomsky
be shared across a wide range of species. We argue (2005), who take the highly conserved nature of
that this bottom-up perspective, which focuses the gene to automatically make it part of FLB.
on the constituent capacities underlying larger At the heart of the FLN/FLB distinction is
cognitive phenomena, is more in line with both the attempt on the part of Hauser, Chomsky
neuroscience and evolutionary biology”. & Fitch (2002) to grapple with the problem of
innovation and novelty in biology. This problem
Put succinctly, the more we attribute to FLB, is currently attracting a lot of attention in the
the more biologically feasible FL becomes. “evo-devo” literature, after having been badly
Having said this, I should hasten to add that neglected in the context of the modern synthesis
the whole FLB/FLN distinction may not have (as Mayr, 1960 readily acknowledged.) As is well
been the most felicitous way of redirecting atten- known, while biologists have made great progress
tion to the need for a comparative, as opposed over the past century and a half in understand-
to a contrastive, biolinguistics. Although Hauser, ing how existing traits diversify, relatively little
Chomsky, and Fitch wrote that “[l]inguists and progress has been made in understanding how
biologists, along with researchers in the relevant novel traits come into being in the first place.
branches of psychology and anthropology, can To remedy this explanatory deficit, Evo-Devo
move beyond unproductive theoretical debate practitioners have first attempted to define what
to a more collaborative, empirically focused and counts as a novelty (here the work of Gerd Müller
comparative research program” by adopting the has been especially illuminating; see especially
FLN/FLB distinction (“The FLB/FLN distinc- Müller (2010) and Müller & Newman 2005).
tion is critical for productive discussion of lan- In this context, it is worth noting the similarity
guage evolution”, according to Fitch, Hauser, between how Fitch, Hauser & Chomsky (2005)
and Chomsky (2005)), I find the very B/N define FLN (“that which is specific to language
dichotomy dubious, for reasons that deserve to and unique to humans”) with the definition put
be elaborated on. forth in Müller & Wagner, 1991: “a structure that
Hauser, Chomsky & Fitch are certainly right is neither homologous to any structure in the ances-
in saying that “[s]omething about the faculty of tral species nor homologous to any other structure of
language must be unique in order to explain the the same organism”.
differences between humans and the other ani- Say that FLN counts as such a novel structure
mals”, but as Jackendoff & Pinker (2005) cor- (I think this is the unstated intention of Hauser,
rectly point out, “the Narrow/Broad dichotomy Chomsky, and Fitch (2002)). If one turns to the
[...] makes space only for completely novel relevant evo-devo literature, one finds a consen-
capacities and for capacities taken intact from sus regarding how such novel structures arise.
nonlinguistic and nonhuman capacities, omit- The consensus position is what Müller (2010)
ting capacities that may have been substantially characterizes as “Type II” or “emergent” nov-
modified in the course of human evolution”. elty. For Müller, and for many other biologists
Indeed, there are capacities that may have been that worry about such novelties (see Wagner &
substantially modified in the course of human Müller, 2002; Moczek, 2008; Moczek & Rose,

www.isita-org.com
70 Linguistics and human cognitive biology

2009; Prud’homme et al., 2011; who provide clearly defined, and thus the distinction itself is
several concrete examples of novelties), “pheno- of little use in furthering our understanding of
typic novelty is largely reorganizational rather the mechanisms”. (Fitch, 2011, p.384)
than a product of, say, innovative genes” (West-
Eberhard, 2003) (cf. the notion of “deep homol- On the basis of this, I am led to conclude,
ogy” in Shubin et al., 2009, see also Balari & with Bloomfield, Gentner, and Margoliash
Lorenzo, 2013). In other words, novelty arises (2011), that “[p]erhaps this is a good time to
from the combination of generic mechanisms, reconsider whether attempting to distinguish
whose collective effects give rise to what appears between qualitative and quantitative differences
to be de novo characters (phase transitions). is helpful if the quantitative advantage is vast.”
Interestingly, the possibility of emergent nov- It is indeed puzzling that so many researchers
elty is alluded to in Fitch, Hauser, and Chomsky still cling to the FLN/FLB distinction when the
(2005, p.182): “Something about the faculty of rationale behind the distinction given at the out-
language must be unique in order to explain the set of Hauser, Chomsky, and Fitch (2002) is to
differences between humans and the other animals reject the notion of the faculty of language as a
if only the particular combination of mechanisms in monolithic object: how can we identify if some
FLB”. But they fail to note that this puts in jeop- mechanism is ‘specific to language’ if ‘language’
ardy the very FLN/FLB distinction (with FLN itself is not a well-defined, unique object. Perhaps
taken to be a subset of FLB, as made clear in it is for this reason that the phrase “unique/
Hauser, Chomsky & Fitch 2002). Incidentally, specific to language” does not appear in the origi-
the possibility of emergent novelty is present nal 2002 paper (Joana Rosselló, pers. comm.),
in some of Chomsky’s own works (Chomsky, but only appear as such in Fitch, Hauser, and
1980, 2000), but is always put in doubt (“Now Chomsky (2005), who take it from Pinker &
a question that could be asked is whether whatever Jackendoff (2005), where FLN is characterized
is innate about language is specific to the language in those terms for the first time (contrary to the
faculty or whether it is just some combination of the literature that routinely attributes it to Hauser,
other aspects of the mind. That is an empirical ques- Chomsky & Fitch, 2002).
tion and there is no reason to be dogmatic about it;
you look and you see. What we seem to find is that Grammatical downsizing
it is specific.”). This is unfortunate, for Chomsky’s The most promising aspect of Hauser,
stance (which boils down to the FLN/FLB dis- Chomsky & Fitch (2002) is the idea that much
tinction) indeed “mak[es] some hypotheses — in of what linguists have attributed to the language
our view the most plausible ones — impossible to faculty falls in the broad characterization of
state” (Jackendoff & Pinker, 2005). Not surpris- it; that is, many properties of the human lan-
ingly, one finds the following statement in Fitch’s guage faculty are neither specific to language
recent writings (in direct contradiction from the nor specific to humans. This conclusion con-
affirmation in Fitch, Hauser & Chomsky (2005) verges with the ‘minimalist’ project that many
and already quoted above that the FLN/FLB dis- formal linguists embarked on in the 1990s (see
tinction is “critical for productive discussion of Chomsky, 1995; Boeckx, 2006, 2010, 2011d,
language evolution”): among many others). Linguistic minimalism
is an attempt to minimize the role of system-
“What all of these examples make clear is specific assumptions to account for properties of
that the distinction between general and natural language grammars.
linguistically specialized mechanisms is hard to Over the years it has become clear that the
draw, even in those cases where the mechanisms success of this minimalist enterprise depends on
themselves seem fairly clearly defined. Most areas several factors that mesh well with biolinguistic
of language are not, and will not soon be, so concerns. First, it must rely on—and therefore
C. Boeckx 71

assume the existence of—a rich cognitive appa- This effectively means that the success of this
ratus with which the (minimal) specifically lin- ‘Chomskyan’ enterprise depends on the correct-
guistic apparatus interfaces to yield the substan- ness of approaches that have (erroneously, in my
tive universals that previous linguistic research opinion) traditionally been put in opposition with
had (somewhat blindly) attributed to a highly ‘Chomskyan’ linguistics (e.g., Kirby, 2001; Kirby
structured and specifically linguistic “Universal & Hurford, 2002; Kirby et al., 2008). As Boeckx
Grammar”. (In other words, the success of the et al. (in press) stress, building on Deacon’s (2006)
minimalist project depends on the success of orders of emergence, such approaches—typically
comparative biolinguistics.) couched in terms of ‘grammaticalization’ and
The rich cognitive apparatus in question cov- imperfect learning across generations—must be
ers both systems of interpretation (‘meaning’) correct when it comes to accounting for the sort
and of externalization (‘sound/sign’). This has of cumulative complexity that characterizes mor-
effectively led to a model of the language faculty phophonological systems of specific languages
where many semantic and phonological aspects (the systems of regularities and exceptions that
of language find their roots in capacities inde- lay people often take to exhaust what linguists
pendently attested in other species. For phonol- mean by ‘grammar’; “third-order emergence” in
ogy, I recommend Yip (2006), Samuels (2011), Deacon’s typology).
Samuels et al. (in press); for semantics, Hurford The conclusion just reached is typically
(2007) is outstanding, but the following are also resisted in ‘Chomskyan’ circles, but it is, I think,
excellent sources of information: Burge (2010), inescapable. (If I am right, this illustrates how
Carey (2009), Carruthers (2006), Hauser (2001), biolinguistics forces one to transcend the tradi-
Cheney & Seyfarth (1990, 2007), Jackendoff tional ‘ideological’ boundaries that populate lin-
(1990, 2010). guistic circles.) As Hall (2012) correctly observes,
This is not to say, of course, that there is “pursu[ing] a biolinguistic approach to ... lan-
nothing specific about human language seman- guage, ... [i]n one sense means that the field of
tics or phonology. Rather, the emerging con- inquiry becomes broader.” A successful biolin-
sensus is that specificity arises when ancient guist must know enough about the cognitive sys-
mechanisms are placed in a new context. In par- tems of other species and about the properties of
ticular, the dominant view in minimalism ought non-linguistic cognitive domains in humans to
to be that the emergence of a capacity to form be able to make reasonable inferences about what
potentially unbounded hierarchical structures each of them contributes towards the shape of
of a particular sort, characteristic of human lan- the modern language faculty. But “[i]n another
guage (technically known as ‘headed’ or ‘endo- sense, the central object of study becomes much
centric’ phrases, i.e. groupings organized around smaller” for Chomskyan linguistics, for many of
a prominent element, such as a verb in a verb the grammatical details that were often attributed
phrase) significantly reshaped the semantic and to some rich innate component specifically dedi-
phonological components inherited by descent. cated to language (‘Universal Grammar’) is to be
Such a possibility is defended in Samuels (2011), understood in terms of cultural evolution. The
Boeckx & Samuels (2009) for phonology and empirical and explanatory success of approaches
in Uriagereka (2008), Hinzen (2007, 2011), like Blevins (2004) reinforces this conclusion,
Pietroski (2011, to appear), Boeckx (2009b, to and I anticipate that this trend will become more
appear a) for semantics. prominent in the field in years to come, espe-
It is also becoming extremely clear that the cially in the context of cross-linguistic variation
success of the minimalist project will depend on (Newmeyer, 2005; Boeckx, to appear b).
recognizing that the emergence of many gram- In a certain sense, the offloading of grammati-
matical properties of natural languages is the prod- cal properties onto external factors converges with
uct of social transmission and cultural evolution. the claim advanced by Deacon (2010) that aspects

www.isita-org.com
72 Linguistics and human cognitive biology

of language should be understood not as the result Evolutionary pluralism


of selection pressures (that often lead to the inter- In its 60 years of history the biolinguistic
nalization or genetic assimilation of certain traits), program has developed under the influence or
but in terms of relaxed selection. The net effect inspiration of several biological paradigms. For
of relaxed selection is for speakers to have to rely instance, the role of ethology in the early days
on social transmission to reliably develop com- of biolinguistics has been well-documented
plex grammatical systems, and to possess a plastic, (Chomsky, 1972; Boeckx, 2009a). Later on,
underspecified (i.e., minimally specified) ‘innate’ in the course of the first biolinguistic meetings
initial state of the language faculty (“Universal of the 1970s, Chomsky familiarized himself
Grammar”). with the work of François Jacob and Jacques
As I have discussed at length elsewhere Monod on genetic regulation (Jacob & Monod,
(Boeckx, 2012b), the picture of the language fac- 1961), which provided the conceptual model
ulty that emerges from minimalist guidelines rig- for his parametric approach to cross-linguistic
orously pursued is one where the aspects of lan- variation (as acknowledged in Chomsky, 1981,
guage geared towards externalization are much 2007b, 2009). More recently, several biolinguists
more complex and varied than those aspects ded- have acknowledged the role of recent develop-
icated to meaning. For the latter, the minimally ments in evolutionary-developmental biology
specified structural properties of the language (“EvoDevo”) in their writings (Balari & Lorenzo,
(what linguists often call ‘narrow syntax’) appear 2013; Chomsky, 2010; Hauser, 2009a).
to be sufficient to exploit the rich conceptual The rise of Evo-Devo is, indeed, an impor-
resources inherited by descent to yield the range tant factor in the characterization of the revival
of rich interpretations that characterize human of biolinguistics, for the field of Evo-Devo offers
thought. Put succinctly, the contribution of the a new space of conceptual options to understand
internal structural component of the language the origin, evolution, and development of the
faculty is asymmetric; it appears to be better language faculty that is at once broader than,
designed for meaning than for articulation (on and more congenial to long-standing themes in
this point, see also Berwick et al., 2013). (bio)linguistics, than the neo-darwinian mod-
As should be obvious, if something like what ern synthesis (see Boeckx, 2011c) on this point;
I have touched on in this section is on the right remember also the discussion above concern-
track, the modern human language faculty is a ing evolutionary novelties, and also concerning
mosaic, with old, inherited parts put together the relevance of fossil, highly-conserved genes).
in a new context (which boils down to the pres- With its emphasis on gradualism and selection-
ence of a mechanism for generating unbounded ism, the latter was the perfect incubator for evo-
hierarchical expressions), and further modified lutionary psychology (see, e.g., Pinker & Bloom,
(complexified) by external influences (the exter- 1990). But the difficulties of strict, or exclusively
nal context of cultural, imperfect transmission). selectionist approaches to language evolution
(On the non-uniform character of the language (Piattelli-Palmarini, 1989; Uriagereka, 1998)
faculty, see also Heinz & Idsardi, 2013). It turns made it look like linguistic investigations were
out, then, that debates about saltation vs. grad- out of tune with mainstream biology. At times,
ualism surrounding the language faculty as a this led to non-sensical claims that “Chomsky”
whole, though extremely common (see Pinker had to be “reconciled” with “Darwin”—claims
& Bloom, 1990; Jackendoff, 2002) are mis- that can only be made if the richness of Darwin’s
placed and misleading (see also Clark, 2013), for (and Chomsky’s) writings is ignored.
the modern language faculty is not a uniform, Not surprisingly, when a more extended
monolithic object: some parts have fairly direct synthesis is pursued in biology (see Pigliucci &
homologs while other parts are likely the result Müller, 2010), it becomes much easier to relate
of abrupt phase transitions. biolinguistic proposals to the biology literature.
C. Boeckx 73

As a matter of fact, several authors have pointed the linguistic capacities of other species. In the
out that Lenneberg’s research program was very wake of Hauser, Chomsky & Fitch, (2002) and
much evo-devo avant la lettre (Boeckx & Longa, the shift of emphasis in comparative psychol-
2011; Balari, 2012); indeed, Lenneberg’s writ- ogy, Fitch & Hauser (2004) sought to assess
ings display an awareness of the need to adopt the cognitive capacities of cotton-top tamarins
a pluralist attitude towards the complex nature by (and compare them to humans), using as a
of the language faculty that is more in line with scale the formal language hierarchy (commonly
evo-devo calls in favor of an extended synthesis known as the “Chomsky hierarchy”). Building
in biology than recent biolinguists’ appeal to evo- on Chomsky’s (1956, 1957) foundational
devo, since these retain a more limited, molecu- results concerning the limitation of finite-state
lar understanding of evo-devo (Benítez-Burraco machines to capture natural language gener-
& Longa, 2010, on this point; see also Müller alizations, Fitch & Hauser (2004) claimed that
(2008) on why molecular evo-devo, of the sort cotton-top tamarins, unlike humans, could not
popularized by Carroll (2005), is not the most detect structures in stimuli that went beyond the
distinctive feature of the evo-devo paradigm). computational capacity of finite-state automata.
This is all to say that a complete assimila- The results proved controversial in more than
tion of everything that evo-devo has to offer to one way, but so have the results suggesting that
biolinguistics is still very much a task for the some songbirds performed beyond the finite-
future, but one that promises a lot, not only in state boundaries (Gentner et al., 2006; Abe &
the context of language evolution studies (and Watanabe, 2011). (For review, see Berwick et al.,
the evo-devo emphasis of the centrality of the 2012, and also Van Heijningen et al., 2009.)
problem of phenotypic innovations, already dis- The overarching problem, it seems to me,
cussed in the previous subsection in the context is the adequacy of the Chomsky hierarchy in
of Hauser, Chomsky, and Fitch, 2002), but also assessing cognitive profiles. Although formal
in the context of language development (Longa language theory can certainly help in designing
& Lorenzo, 2008, 2009, 2012), and in the con- experiments shedding light on mental abilities
text of what I have called comparative biolinguis- (see the papers collected in Fitch & Friederici,
tics. If it is indeed the case that we find intra- 2012), it suffers from a major problem in the
species variation involving genes that have a role context of biolinguistics. As is well-known, the
to play in language, it is necessary to adopt a less Chomsky hierarchy is of limited use in char-
geno-centric, and more epigenetic/dynamic per- acterizing human linguistic competence. As
spective (of the sort evo-devo favors) to have any Berwick et al. (2012) correctly observe, the hier-
hope to account for why, despite genetic varia- archy is both “too weak and too strong”, failing
tion, language development is uniform across the as it does to cut natural language at its joints
species (barring severe pathology). (see also Heinz & Idsardi, 2011; Boeckx &
Uriagereka, 2011).
Emerging trends Finding a substitute to the Chomsky hier-
To conclude this section, I’d like to mention archy to construct cognitive phylogenies will
two additional important considerations ani- be a serious challenge for the years to come.
mating current biolinguistic research. Although It is a challenge that ought to be of interest to
these two factors have not led to the revival of the anthropologists as well, given recent attempts
field, unlike those discussed so far in this section, to use the Chomsky hierarchies to draw cogni-
they are poised for dominance in years to come, tive inferences from artifacts in the fossil record
given the frequency with which they figure in (Camps & Uriagereka, 2006; Balari et al., 2011;
recent papers. and Lobina, 2012; Balari et al., 2012; Lobina &
The first of these two factors is the role the Brenchley, 2012 for an intense debate on the fea-
“Chomsky hierarchy” is to play in assessing sibility of this approach).

www.isita-org.com
74 Linguistics and human cognitive biology

The second topic I want to touch on in this not explanation (this is Poeppel’s “map” prob-
subsection pertains to how productive linking lem). What is needed instead is a set of mecha-
hypotheses between theoretical linguistics and nistic hypotheses to which findings in linguistic
neuroscience could be formulated. As I indicated theory (or cognitive science more generally)
above, this is a necessary step towards linking could relate. This is, in some respect, the same
mind and genes, but also mind and the range concern voiced by Gallistel & King (2009), who
of anatomical evidence drawn from the fossil point out that neurosciences (and, I might add,
records (e.g., skull size and shape). David Poeppel many fields of cognitive science) ought to take
has written eloquently and accessibly about the the notion of “computation” far more seriously
challenges neurolinguistics faces (Poeppel & than they have done so far.
Embick (2005), Poeppel (2005, 2011, 2012). Finally, both Deacon (2005) and I (Boeckx,
The heart of the matter, according to Poeppel, 2012a, to appear a) have suggested, coming from
is the “granularity mismatch” (or “mapping”) different perspectives, that the failure to develop
problem: the objects of study in theoretical lin- fruitful linking hypotheses in neurolinguistics
guistics and in neuroscience don’t match. As a may be the result on the part of linguists of hav-
result, mapping one onto the other has proven ing pursued an exclusively ‘engineering’ or ‘lexi-
impossible. Accordingly, Marr’s (1982) vision of cocentric’ logic regarding how language works,
cognitive neuroscience based on linking levels of as opposed to an ‘embryonic’ or ‘syntactocentric’
analyses, to which biolinguistics should aspire, logic. The main difference between the two logics
remains distant. is that the former starts with small units of com-
Both theoretical linguistics and the neuro- putation (say, words) and from there construct
sciences are to blame for this sorry state of affairs. whole structures (say, phrases or sentences),
For all the “bio” talk in linguistic circles, linguists whereas the latter takes the small units of compu-
have so far failed to distill what is known from tation to be the end products of a differentiation
linguistic theory into a set of computational process starting from a much more generic, and
primitives, and try to link these with models underspecified whole. The main drawback of the
and specific principles of neural computation. As engineering/lexicocentric perspective is that it
Poeppel points out, “we need linguistic models invariably leads to starting assumptions that are
that are explicit about the computational primi- so field-specific (e.g., the features of words in lin-
tives (structures and operations) they require, guistics) as to be untranslatable (hence, useless)
and that attempt to define linguistic problems at for researchers in other fields. As a result, all the
a fine enough grain that one can discuss algorith- generalizations based on these starting assump-
mic and implementational approaches to their tions are lost in translation. A change in perspec-
solution. We need a list of computations that lin- tive (along the lines of how development is con-
guistic theorists deem indispensable to solve their strued in embryology)—indeed, an inversion of
particular problem (e.g., in phonology, syntax, reasoning—may prove far more productive.
or semantics).” Put another way, “[l]inguists and A recent example of the rampant lexicocen-
psycholinguists owe a decomposition (or frac- tric fallacy I have in mind (one which will be
tionation) of the particular linguistic domain in accessible to many readers, as it figures in an
question (e.g. syntax) into formal operations that article targeting a wide audience) is to be found
are, ideally, elemental and generic. ... Generic in the treatment of the differences between bird-
formal operations at this level of abstraction can song and human language offered by Berwick
form the basis for more complex linguistic repre- et al. (2012). (The lexicocentric stance is even
sentation and computation.” made clearer in a follow-up paper: Miyagawa et
On the neuroscience side, the problem has al., 2013).
been the emphasis on localization and spatial Berwick et al.’s discussion bears on the
characterization of function. But localization is influence of the lexicon because they take as
C. Boeckx 75

their point of departure famed ethologist Peter of more complex birdsong syntax. Rather, this
Marler’s well-known contrast between “pho- gap is due to a fundamental deficiency in a very
nological syntax” and “lexical syntax” (Marler, particular computational ability, namely, the lack
1970). On Marler’s account, songbirds exhibit of the combinatorial operation of the sort found
only phonological syntax, that is, the stringing in human language [what is often called “Merge”
together of elements, sounds, according to some in the theoretical linguistics literature—CB]”.
well-defined pattern, but without the meaning However, Berwick et al. end up partially
of the resulting sequence as a whole dependent agreeing with Marler (and many others, e.g.,
on the meaning of its individual parts. In con- Pinker & Jackendoff, 2005), because the notion
trast, Marler argues that only human languages of combinatorial operation/Merge they advocate
exhibit lexical syntax, that is, changes in mean- is not the mere act of combining, but a lexico-
ing resulting from different combinations ele- centric version of it, as the following passage
ments such as word parts, words, or phrases. makes clear.
Put another way, Marler notes that while both
birdsong and human language are combinato- “The key difference is the use of a verb or nouns
rial, in the sense that they both assemble larger features to label an entire word sequence with
structures out of more basic parts, only human a single label, ... the selection of a privileged
language is compositional, in the sense that the element in this way renders the underlying
meaning of a word or sentence changes as we structure fundamentally asymmetric. Note that
change its component parts. Marler’s use of the there is no analog to this in birdsong ... . Consider
term “lexical syntax” may cause one to think that as an example the birdsong motif described
the key difference lies in the existence of lexical earlier, consisting of seven particular syllables.
items (“words”). And indeed Marler’s view leads This motif is not labeled by selecting just one
to lexicocentrism, even if Berwick et al. (2012) of these syllables and its properties to name the
appear to claim the contrary. entire motif; none of the syllables takes priority
Thus, Berwick et al. (2012) note that “Marler’s ... Neither is the resulting structure asymmetric
notion that it is “lexicoding” —words— that as it is in human language. This is true precisely
completely characterizes the division between because birds apparently do not have words or
human language and birdsong captures part, but manipulate word features at all. This is one
not all, of the necessary distinctions.” In par- difference between the human language syntactic
ticular, “[i]t does not account for the inherent system and birdsong. We noted earlier that
asymmetry of human language structure, and this does not in principle bar the possibility of
falls short when it comes to describing human birdsong making use of features of song elements,
language structures that have no associated lexi- for example, syllables and their acoustic features,
cal meanings, such as the metrical or prosodic and assembling them in a similar hierarchical
structure associated with human language.” fashion. However, current evidence suggests
Elsewhere, they write, “we should emphasize that this does not occur in birdsong. Rather, the
that it would be a mistake to conclude that all combinatorial operator itself is absent”.
birdsong-human differences result simply from
the lack of words in birdsong, ... . For example, By stressing the notion “labeling dependent
even though birds lack words, there is nothing on word features”, Berwick et al. effectively end
that logically blocks birdsong syntax from rely- up “anchor[ing]” the combinatorial operator “on
ing on syllable groupings or other features that words or more precisely, word features”, and con-
could themselves be labeled by properties of their clude that
constitutive parts”.
Berwick and colleagues conclude that “it is not “It is this operation [lexicocentric Merge—
the lack of words alone that blocks the possibility CB] that is apparently absent in birds, so

www.isita-org.com
76 Linguistics and human cognitive biology

far as we know. However, even though birds of human thought/activity, where words are far
seemingly lack words, it does not follow that the less central; think of music and mathematics).
combinatorial operator is necessarily absent in
birds. For example, the combinatorial operator
could still work on other elements, for example, Where to go from here: some
syllables, in this way yielding the distinctive personal suggestions
metrical patterning of sound melodies, rhythmic
patterns, ... . However, for whatever reason, the As I have stressed on several occasions in
operator does not appear to have been exploited this review, a productive biolinguistics must be
this way in birds. It remains an open question brain-based. It seems to me that much work in
as to whether a similar analysis would apply this area remains bound to ideas ultimately going
to birdsong metrical patterns; this then is a back to Paul Broca, ideas that are in serious need
possibly crucial open research question where a of reconsideration. I am not here referring just
non-human model might (speculatively) provide to the classical model of language areas (with
insight into its counterpart in human language. Broca’s area and Wernicke’s area occupying pride
If birdsong were found to operate in a similar of place) —a model that numerous studies have
way to human metrical structure, this might shown to be hopelessly simplistic (see Hickok &
provide precisely the required evolutionary Poeppel, 2007, to cite but one study), I am also
“bridge,” in the sense that the combinatorial referring to the idea, often attributed to Broca,
operator was present in the common ancestor of that the defining characteristic of the human
both species, but full-fledged language required brain is its asymmetric character.
in addition words and their features, an ability Timothy J. Crow is perhaps the most promi-
present in the human lineage, but not in any nent advocate of the importance of brain asym-
bird species. It follows that it is precisely here that metry in the emergence of language and our
one might look for key evolutionary innovations species. Crow (2008, p.43) has indeed written
that distinguish humans from birds ...”. that “If the innovation that allowed the evolu-
tion of language was genetic [...] lateralization of
As I will discuss in the next section, my own function in the brain (Broca’s hypothesis) is the
view (defended in Boeckx, 2011b, c, to appear a) only current candidate mechanism.” What Crow
is quite different. For me, it’s not the projection refers to as “Broca’s hypothesis” is rooted in the
of (word) features, but the presence of an unre- following passage from Broca’s writings (from
stricted combinatorial operator (corresponding Harrington, 1987, pp.65-66):
to the notion of ‘unrestricted Merge’) that was
the big evolutionary breakthrough. It was the “Man is, of all the animals, the one whose brain
possibility of ignoring word/conceptual features in the normal state is the most asymmetrical.
that made it possible for humans to make infinite He is also the one who possesses most acquired
use of finite means, and construct “finite-yet- faculties. Among these faculties-which experience
unbounded” systems (in the sense of systems and education developed in his ancestors and of
yielding endlessly many complex expressions which heredity hands him the instrument but
that can be characterized recursively), which which he does not succeed in exercising until
encompass language, mathematics, and music. after a long and difficult education-the faculty
Rather than seeing the evolutionary break- of articulate language holds pride of place. It is
through as a constraint on merge (asymmetric this that distinguishes us the most clearly from
labeling), we should think of it as the lifting of the animal”.
a constraint—the removal of selectional restric-
tions that block systematic combination of the But I think that a close reading of this pas-
sort we find in language (and in other domains sage, and of Broca’s other writings, reveals a
C. Boeckx 77

somewhat different (and ultimately, I believe, supported genetically by FOXP2 and its interac-
more accurate) picture. Note that in the pas- tome, which provide the basis for externalization
sage just quoted, Broca talks about “the faculty systems (see Matsunaga et al. (2013) for data
of articulate language”. This is, by no means, an pointing in this direction), and may well be sex-
innocent phrase. Elsewhere, Broca (1861, p.334) ually selected for via ProtocadherinXY, as Crow
writes (about aphasia) has argued in numerous publications. It may
even be the case that we may find FOXP2 dif-
“What is missing in these patients is only the ferences when sexes are compared (see Bowers et
faculty to articulate the words; they hear and al., 2013 for potentially relevant data). But, cru-
understand all that is said to them, they have cially, lateralization would not be the key to what
all their intelligence and they emit easily vocal one might call the “interpretive brain”, where
sounds. What is lost is therefore not the faculty language appears to play its most distinctive role.
of language, is not the memory of the words To understand the latter, we must, I think, turn
nor is it the action of nerves and muscles of away from lateralization, and focus on a perhaps
phonation and articulation, but something else so far neglected aspect of H. sapiens’ brain in the
... the faculty to coordinate the movements which context of language, an aspect that is perhaps
belong to the articulate language, or simpler, it is even more characteristic of our species than the
the faculty of articulate language”. structural asymmetries that have been the focus
of so many studies: globularity.
In others words, Broca is distinguishing It is now well-established that modern humans
between the faculty of language and the faculty show a species-specific “neomorphic hypertro-
of articulate language. I believe that the dis- phy of the parietal volumes, leading to a dorsal
tinction is important, and in fact relates to the growth and ventral flexion (convolution) and
asymmetric contribution of the internal struc- consequent globularity of the whole structure”
tural component of the language faculty (the (Bruner, 2004), well reflected in the archeological
idea, already discussed above, that language record (Bruner et al., 2003; Bruner, 2004, 2010;
appears to be better designed for meaning than Lieberman, 2011). Significantly, globularity is a
for articulation, and quite possibly more robust trait absent in Neanderthals. I say significantly
to deviations and deficits in the former domain because the brain size range of modern humans
than in the latter). Broca may well be right about and Neanderthals overlap, which has led many
brain asymmetry being related to ‘articulation’ researchers to assume that the cognitive capabili-
(externalization of linguistic expressions). After ties of these two species were similar. But we know
all, brain asymmetries are also found in other that among humans the internal organization
vocal learners, where semantics is missing (see of the brain is far more important for cognitive
Moorman et al. (2012) on lateralization is birds). abilities than its absolute size is. In other words,
And it would make a lot of sense to tie the exter- shape (wiring topology) may be far more signifi-
nalizing, referential, communicative component cant than size is. We also know that the brain’s
of language and sexual selection via brain asym- internal organization depends on the ‘tempo and
metry (Crow’s hypothesis concerning the human mode’ of brain development. And, interestingly,
torque), if sexual selection is to be understood the attained globularity appears to take shape at a
in terms of mate recognition mechanisms, which particularly significant point in development.
must then refer to overt behavior (and commu- As Gunz et al. (2010, 2012) have shown,
nication surely is one). based on detailed measurements of internal
Brain asymmetry, then, following Broca, shape changes of the braincase during indi-
would be a tell-tale structural sign of the “com- vidual growth, there are differences in the pat-
municative brain”, as William Marslen-Wilson terns of brain development between humans and
has called it. The communicative brain would be Neanderthals during what everyone believes is a

www.isita-org.com
78 Linguistics and human cognitive biology

critical phase for cognitive development. Gunz Numerous comparative studies in psychology
et al. (2010, 2012) reveal that when we compare reveal that mature linguistic creatures transcend
the skulls of a Neanderthal and a modern human many cognitive limits seen in animals and prelin-
newborn, the Neanderthal’s face is already larger guistic infants (infants whose linguistic capacity
at the time of birth. However, most shape dif- has not matured yet). Such limits are the signa-
ferences of the internal braincase develop after ture limits of what Elizabeth Spelke has called
birth. Both Neanderthals and modern human core knowledge systems, which correspond to
neonates have elongated braincases at the time of primitive knowledge modules in roughly the
birth, but only modern human endocasts change sense of Fodor (1983). Such systems (for space,
to a more globular shape in the first year of life. numbers, actions, objects, social interactions,
This strongly suggests that modern humans and and perhaps a few more) suffer from informa-
Neanderthals reach large adult brain sizes via dif- tional encapsulation and quickly reach combina-
ferent developmental pathways. (Neubauer et torial limits (see Spelke, 2003 for a survey; see
al., 2010 show that the developmental patterns also Carruthers, 2003, 2006; Pietroski, 2007).
of the brain were remarkably similar between By contrast, linguistically mature individuals
chimpanzees and humans after the first year of regularly go beyond the computational bounda-
life, but differed markedly directly after birth. ries of core knowledge systems to yield markedly
Quite plausibly, this means that those aspects different modes of conceptualization. As Spelke
of development that are shared between mod- stresses, such new modes of thought often cor-
ern humans, Neanderthals, and chimpanzees respond to what would result from the combi-
as conserved, with modern humans, but not nation of otherwise encapsulated concepts; for
Neanderthals, depart from this ancestral pattern example, the ability to think of sets of individuals
of brain development in the first year of life.) plausibly results from the conjunction of think-
As Gunz et al. (2010, 2012) observe, given ing about sets and thinking about individu-
that the differences between modern humans and als in the same conceptual space. (Incidentally,
Neanderthals are most prominent in the period this characterization matches that of cognitive
directly after birth, they likely have implications fluidity in Mithen (1996), which is reflected in
for the neuronal and synaptic organization of the the archeological record, e.g., terianthropes.)
developing brain. The development of cognitive Spelke is, I think, right in taking language to
abilities during individual growth is standardly provide the key combinatorics to make this pos-
linked to the maturation of the underlying wiring sible. But it would be a mistake in my opinion
pattern of the brain; and we know that around to conclude from this that the key evolutionary
the time of birth, the neural circuitry is sparse in event was a completely new mode of combina-
humans. We also know from clinical studies that tion, given that the combination in question
even subtle alterations in early brain development (“Merge”) is as primitive as one can get: it boils
lead to changes in the neural wiring patterns that down to set-formation. The key event, rather,
affect behavior and cognition. It is therefore must have been the ability to combine virtu-
plausible to claim, as Gunz et al. (2010, 2012) ally any concept (from whatever (core) knowl-
do, that the connections between diverse brain edge system) with any other concept (from the
regions that are established during this period same or another knowledge system). That is,
in modern humans are significant for cognition. the key event was the lifting of a constraint.
That is to say, it is unlikely that Neanderthals had This alone gives us our unique cognitive profile,
the same cognitive profile as H. sapiens. what Hauser (2009b, pp.192-193) has dubbed
Indeed, I suggest that the mechanisms giving ‘humaniqueness’, which he characterizes in part
rise to globularity provide the basis for the dis- as the ability to ‘create and easily understand
tinctive mode of thought displayed by our spe- symbolic representations of computation and
cies, which I’d like to call cross-modular thinking. sensory input’, to ‘apply the same rule or solution
C. Boeckx 79

to one problem to a different and new situation’, be simply related to the fraction of its pyramidal
and to ‘combine and recombine different types neurons contributing to layers 2 and 3, which
of information and knowledge in order to gain is particularly elevated in dorsolateral prefrontal
new understanding’. and inferior parietal cortical structures.” These
Such a characterization of humaniqueness are particularly relevant regions in the context of
matches fairly well the characteristic of the ‘neu- globularity.
ronal workspace’ model formulated in Dehaene But in addition to these cortical regions, I
et al. (1998) in the domain of consciousness (see believe we must take into account the thalamus.
also Tononi & Edelman, 1998). (It also matches (As Dehaene et al. note, “the pyramidal neu-
the properties of the multiple-demand system of rons from layers 2 and 3 establish, in addition,
Duncan (2010), which relies on the same fronto- vertical and reciprocal connections with layer 5
parietal regions, and those of the ‘connective neurons and thus corresponding thalamic nuclei.
core’ put forth in Shanahan, 2012.) These connections contribute to both the sta-
Inspired by Baars’s (1993) Global Workspace bility and the dynamics of workspace activity,
model for consciousness, the ‘neuronal work- via, for instance, self-sustained circuits, but also
space’ model emphasizes the role of distrib- mediate the direct access to and from the pro-
uted neurons with long-distance connections, cessing networks.”) Although the thalamus has
particularly dense in prefrontal, cingulate, and been implicated in the context of many human-
parietal regions, interconnecting multiple spe- specific traits like intelligence or consciousness
cialized processors and “broadcasting” signals (see Crick, 1984; Steriade & Llinás, 1988; Min,
at the brain scale in a spontaneous and sudden 2010), its role in language (for which we have
manner, forming a ‘global neuronal workspace’. a much more robust theoretical characterization
Through this workspace, Dehaene et al. claim than for the two other traits just mentioned) has
that “modular processors can exchange informa- not been fully exploited (but see Crosson, in
tion very flexibly”, “information can be accumu- press; Hebb & Ojemann, in press).
lated across time and across different processors”, Given its central location and well-estab-
“incoming information arising from analog sta- lished, pivotal relay function, it is likely that the
tistical inputs can be discretized”, and “chains of thalamus found itself affected by this novel glob-
operations and branching can be performed”— ular environment. Indeed, at the raw anatomical
properties corresponding fairly to Hauser’s char- level, the thalamus acts as a necessary relay center
acteristics of humaniqueness. to connect many brain structures that have
Already a century ago Ramon y Cajal had already been implicated in research on language:
underlined the special morphology of the pyram- the cortical areas with the basal ganglia and with
idal cells from the cerebral cortex and suggested the cerebellum. Second, the literature on FOXP2
they might be the “substratum of the highest and its interactome has often mentioned the thal-
nervous activities”. Building on this insight, amus as an important expression site of the genes
Dehaene et al.’s view as key building blocks of the involved (Vargha-Khadem et al., 2005; Reimers-
workspace “a distributed set of cortical neurons Kipping et al., 2011; Enard et al., 2009; Enard,
characterized by their ability to receive from and 2011). Third, despite the cortical focus of many
send back to homologous neurons in other cor- imaging studies and the technical difficulties in
tical areas, horizontal projections through long- getting recordings from the thalamus, this brain
range excitatory axons.” As they point out, “such structures role has been highlighted in neurolin-
long range corticocortical tangential connections guistic studies (see, e.g., Wahl et al., 2008; David
include callosal connections and mostly originate et al., 2011). Finally, outside of language proper,
from the pyramidal cells of layers 2 and 3”, and the thalamus has routinely been assigned a key
propose that “the extent to which a given brain role in controlling attention, regulating oscilla-
area contributes to the global workspace would tions generated in the cortex, etc. (see Saalmann

www.isita-org.com
80 Linguistics and human cognitive biology

et al., 2012, among many others) functions that, et al., 2010), as it will include structures like the
though not specific to language, must surely also basal ganglia, the cerebellum, and the thalamus
be part of a comprehensive neural characteriza- as the coordinator of this orchestra. This in turn
tion of language. will mean that traditional regions like Broca’s
For all these reasons, the ‘triangle’ formed will likely play a less central role, much more
by the fronto-parietal lobes and the thalamus closely related to externalization (see Boeckx &
(with the latter regulating the dynamics of the Martínez-Álvarez, 2013 for a specific proposal
former, as a clock does, possibly along the lines implicating Broca’s region in the action of lin-
of Buzsáki, 1991) are, I think, good focus can- earization, a property that could be related to the
didates of future biolinguistic studies. (As my motor processing of other hierarchical structures,
references to Dehaene et al. (1998) have made such as the action grammar patterns discussed in
clear, the literature on consciousness will prove Fujita, 2009).
particularly useful. This would not have come Third, if cross-modular thinking is such an
as a surprise to Darwin, who wrote in (1871, important feature of the human language capac-
p.126), “If it could be proved that certain high ity, linguists in particular will have to soften their
mental powers, such as the formation of general stance concerning language and modularity (and
concepts, self-consciousness, etc., were abso- specificity), and adopt positions such as the one
lutely peculiar to man, which seems extremely advocated in Newport (2010) or Marcus (2006),
doubtful, it is not improbable that these quali- which converge in interesting ways with that of
ties are merely the incidental results of other Karmiloff-Smith (1992), and indeed, with many
highly-advanced intellectual faculties; and these evo-devo studies on modularity; cf. Callebaut &
again mainly the result of the continued use of Rasskin-Gutman (2005), Schlosser & Wagner
a perfect language.” On the role of language in (2004) - positions that take modularity and
consciousness, see especially Jackendoff, 1987.) specificity to emerge as a matter of development,
If the above remarks are on the right track, in the context of a logic of reciprocal causation of
at least four major consequences are worth the sort emphasized by Lewontin (2000).
pointing out. First, uncovering the molecular Fourth, the reflections in this section are,
underpinnings of the species-specific globulari- obviously enough, only part of the whole story.
zation phase is likely to yield important insights At best, the evolutionary steps leading to globu-
into the genetic basis of language. This is a task larity and anatomically modern humans only
I recently undertook with the help of Antonio led to cognitively modern humans (taking the
Benítez-Burraco incorporating candidates that mind (cognition) to be what the brain (anat-
may not have been included if only speech dis- omy) makes possible), which took place around
orders were taken as point of departure. In this 200KYA. But from there to behaviorally modern
context, it is worth pointing out that a com- humans, there is still a long way, which I assume
parison of Neanderthal and modern human requires a fair amount of cultural evolution, and
genomes revealed several regions with strong a deeper understanding than we currently have
evidence for positive selection within Homo of the social and environmental factors that led
sapiens. Three among these are likely to be criti- to some of the most dramatic signs of modernity
cal for brain development, as they affect mental well over a hundred years after the emergence
and cognitive development. But other genes are of our species (see Sterelny, 2011 for valuable
clearly involved in giving rise to globularity, such remarks). The (social, cultural, demographic)
as RUNX2, which affects the morphology of the factors leading to this niche construction are
cranium. likely to have affected the surface properties of
Second, the brain model for language will languages, and the ways in which language is put
be far more distributed, and less cortico-centric to use. But this is another story, distinct from the
(in line with much recent work, see Fedorenko emergence of the human language faculty.
C. Boeckx 81

Conclusion Baker M. 2001. The atoms of language. Basic


Books, New York.
Back in (1975), Chomsky could write that Balari S. 2012. Up the cudgels for Lenneberg. In
“[w]e know very little about what happens when C. Boeckx, M. Horno & J.L. Mendívil-Giró
1010 neurons are crammed into something the (eds): Language from a biological point of view:
size of a basketball, with further conditions Current issues in biolinguistics, pp. 208-214.
imposed by the specific manner in which the sys- Cambridge Scholars Publishing, Cambridge.
tem developed over time.” We are now in posi- Balari S., Benítez-Burraco A., Camps M., Longa
tion to take advantage of progress in numerous V.M. & Lorenzo G. 2012. Knots, language, and
disciplines to be able to say a bit more about this. computation: A bizarre love triangle? Replies to
Combining information from (paleo)genetics, objections. Biolinguistics, 6: 79-111.
paleoneurology, neuroscience, linguistics, com- Balari S., Benítez-Burraco A., Camps M., Longa
parative psychology, and evolutionary biology, V.M., Lorenzo G. & Uriagereka J. 2011. The ar-
reviewed in this article, offers the contours of a chaeological record speaks: bridging anthropology
new neurobiological architecture supporting that and linguistics. Int. J. Evol. Biol., 2011:382679.
most distinctive trait of our species, the human Balari, S. & Lorenzo G. 2013. Computational phe-
language faculty. notypes: Towards an evolutionary developmental
biolinguistics. Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Barton, R.A. 2012. Embodied cognitive evolution
Acknowledgments and the cerebellum. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond.
B. Biol. Sci., 367: 2097-2107.
For comments and suggestions, I thank Emiliano Benítez-Burraco A. 2012. The “language” genes.
Bruner, two anonymous reviewers, Evelina Leivada, In C. Boeckx, M. Horno & J.L. Mendívil-Giró
Pedro Tiago Martins, Joana Rosselló, Lluís Barceló (eds): Language from a biological point of view:
i Coblijn and especially Antonio Benítez-Burraco. Current issues in biolinguistics, pp. 215-262.
The present work was made possible through a Marie Cambridge Scholars Publishing, Cambridge.
Curie International Reintegration Grant from Benítez-Burraco A. 2013. Genetics of language:
the European Union (PIRG-GA-2009-256413), roots of specific language deficits. In C. Boeckx
research funds from the Fundació Bosch i Gimpera, & K.K. Grohmann (eds): The Cambridge hand-
and a grant from the Spanish Ministry of Economy book of biolinguistics, pp. 375-412. Cambridge
and Competitiveness (FFI-2010-20634). University Press, Cambridge.
Benítez-Burraco A. & Longa V.M. 2010. Evo-
Devo - Of course, but which one? Biolinguistics,
References 4: 308-323.
Benítez-Burraco A., Longa V.M., Lorenzo G. &
Abe K. & Watanabe D. 2011. Songbirds possess Uriagereka J. 2008. Also sprach neanderthalis...
the spontaneous ability to discriminate syntac- or did she? Biolinguistics 2:225–232.
tic rules. Nat. Neurosci., 14: 1067-1074. Berwick R., Beckers G., Okanoya K. & Bolhuis
Arriaga G. & Jarvis E.D. 2013. Mouse vocal com- J. 2012. A bird’s eye view of human language
munication system: Are ultrasounds learned or evolution. Front. Evol. Neurosci., 4:5.
innate? Brain Lang., 124: 96-116. Berwick R.C. 2011. All you need is Merge:
Arriaga G., Zhou E.P. & Jarvis E.D. 2012. Of Biology, computation and language from the
mice, birds, and men: the mouse ultrasonic song bottom-up. In A.M. Di Sciullo & C. Boeckx
system has some features similar to humans and (eds): The biolinguistic enterprise: New per-
song-learning birds. PloS ONE, 7: e46610. spectives on the evolution and nature of the hu-
Baars B.J. 1993. A cognitive theory of consciousness. man language faculty, pp. 461-491. Oxford
Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. University Press, Oxford.

www.isita-org.com
82 Linguistics and human cognitive biology

Berwick R.C. & Chomsky N. 2011. The biolin- (eds): The biolinguistic enterprise: new perspec-
guistic program: the current state of its develop- tives on the evolution and nature of the human
ment. In A.M. Di Sciullo & C. Boeckx (eds): language faculty, pp. 42-64. Oxford University
The biolinguistic enterprise: New perspectives on Press, Oxford.
the evolution and nature of the human language Boeckx C., ed. 2011d. The Oxford handbook of
faculty, pp. 19-41. Oxford University Press, linguistic Minimalism. Oxford University Press,
Oxford. Oxford.
Berwick, R.C., Friederici A.D., Chomsky N. & Boeckx C. 2012a. A missing design perspective in
Bolhuis J.J. 2013. Evolution, brain, and the na- I-linguistics. In S. Ojima, Y. Otsu, J.F. Connolly
ture of language. Trends Cogn. Sci., 17:89-98. & G. Thierry (eds): Future trends in the biology of
Berwick R.C., Okanoya K., Beckers G.J.L. & language, pp. 95-116. Keio University Press, Tokyo.
Bolhuis J.J. 2011. Songs to syntax: the linguis- Boeckx C. 2012b. The I-language mosaic. In C.
tics of birdsong. Trends Cogn. Sci., 15: 113-121. Boeckx, M. Horno & J.L. Mendívil-Giró (eds):
Blevins J. 2004. Evolutionary phonology: the emer- Language from a biological point of view: current
gence of sound patterns. Cambridge University issues in biolinguistics, pp. 23-51. Cambridge
Press, Cambridge. Scholars Publishing, Cambridge.
Bloomfield T.C., Gentner T.Q. & Margoliash D. Boeckx C. To appear a. Elementary syntactic struc-
2011. What birds have to say about language. tures. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Nat. Neurosci., 14: 947. Boeckx C. To appear b. What Principles &
Boeckx C. 2006. Linguistic Minimalism: origins, Parameters got wrong. In C. Picallo (ed):
concepts, methods, and aims. Oxford University Linguistic variation and the Minimalist Program.
Press, Oxford. Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Boeckx C. 2009a. Language in Cognition: uncover- Boeckx C. & K.K. Grohmann. Eds. 2013.
ing mental structures and the rules behind them. The Cambridge handbook of biolinguistics.
Wiley-Blackwell, Malden. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Boeckx C. 2009b. Some notes on the syntax- Boeckx C. Leivada E. & Martins P.T. Language and
thought interface. Proceedings of the Sophia complexity considerations: A biolinguistic perspec-
University Linguistic Society, 24: 92-103. Sophia tive. Llengua, Societat i Comunicació (in press).
University Linguistic Society. Boeckx C. & Longa V.M. 2011. Lenneberg’s
Boeckx, C. 2010. Linguistic minimalism. In B. views on language development and evolution
Heine & H. Narrog (eds): Oxford handbook and their relevance for modern biolinguistics.
of linguistic analysis, pp. 485-505. Oxford Biolinguistics, 5: 254-273.
University Press, Oxford. Boeckx C. & Martínez-Álvarez A. 2013. A mul-
Boeckx C. 2011a. Approaching parameters from ti-step algorithm for serial order: converging
below. In A.M. Di Sciullo & C. Boeckx (eds): evidence from linguistics and neuroscience.
The biolinguistic enterprise: new perspectives on Presented at GLOW 36, Lund.
the evolution and nature of the human language Boeckx C. & Samuels B. 2009. What emerges
faculty, pp. 205-221. Oxford University Press, from merge in phonology. Presented at the 6th
Oxford. Old World Conference on Phonology, Edinburgh,
Boeckx C. 2011b. The emergence of language, UK.
from a biolinguistic point of view. In M. Boeckx C. & Uriagereka J. 2011. Biolinguistics
Tallerman & K. Gibson (eds): The Oxford and information. In G. Terzis & R. Arp (eds):
handbook of language evolution, pp. 492-501. Information and Living Systems: Philosophical
Oxford University Press, Oxford. and Scientific Perspectives, pp. 353-370. MIT
Boeckx C. 2011c. Some reflections on Press, Cambridge.
Darwin’s Problem in the context of Cartesian Bolhuis J.J., Okanoya K. & Scharff C. 2010.
Biolinguistics. In A.M. Di Sciullo & C. Boeckx Twitter evolution: Converging mechanisms
C. Boeckx 83

in birdsong and human speech. Nat. Rev. Cheney D.L. & Seyfarth R.M. 2007. Baboon met-
Neurosci., 11: 747-759. aphysics: the evolution of a social mind. University
Bowers J.M., Perez-Pouchoulen M. Edwards N.S. of Chicago Press, Chicago.
& McCarthy M.M. 2013. FOXP2 mediates Chomsky N. 1956. Three models for the description
sex differences in ultrasonic vocalization by rat of language. I. R. E. Transactions on Information
pups and directs order of maternal retrieval. J. Theory, 2:113-124. Reprinted, with corrections,
Neurosci., 33: 3276-3283. in R.D. Luce, R. Bush & E. Galanter (eds).
Broca P. 1861. Remarks on the seat of the faculty Chomsky N. 1957. Syntactic structures. Mouton,
of articulated language, following an observa- The Hague.
tion of aphemia (loss of speech). Bulletin de la Chomsky N. 1959. Verbal behavior. Language, 35:
Société Anatomique, 6: 330-357. 26-58.
Bruner E. 2004. Geometric morphometrics and Chomsky N. 1965. Aspects of the theory of syntax.
paleoneurology: Brain shape evolution in the MIT Press, Cambridge.
genus homo. J. Hum. Evol., 47: 279-303. Chomsky N. 1972. Language and mind. Harcourt
Bruner E. 2010. Morphological differences in the Brace Jovanovich, New York.
parietal lobes within the human genus. Curr. Chomsky N. 1975. Reflections on language.
Anthropol., 51: S77-S88. Pantheon, New York.
Bruner E., Manzi G. & Arsuaga J.L. 2003. Chomsky N. 1980. Rules and representations.
Encephalization and allometric trajectories in Columbia University Press, New York.
the genus homo: evidence from the neander- Chomsky N. 1981. Lectures on Government and
tal and modern lineages. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. Binding. Dordrecht, Foris.
U.S.A., 100: 15335-15340. Chomsky N. 1995. The Minimalist Program.
Burge T. 2010. Origins of objectivity. Oxford MIT Press, Cambridge.
University Press, Oxford. Chomsky N. 2000. New horizons in the study of language
Buzsáki G. 1991. The thalamic clock: Emergent and mind. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
network properties. Neurosciences, 41: 351-364. Chomsky N. 2007a. Approaching UG from be-
Callebaut W. & D. Rasskin-Gutman. Eds. 2005. low. In U. Sauerland & H.-M. Gärtner (eds):
Modularity: Understanding the development and Interfaces + recursion = language? Chomsky’s
evolution of natural complex systems. MIT press, minimalism and the view from semantics, 1-30.
Cambridge. Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin.
Camps, M. & Uriagereka J. 2006. The Gordian knot Chomsky N. 2007b. Of minds and language.
of linguistic fossils. In J. Rosselló & J. Martin (eds): Biolinguistics, 1: 9-27.
The biolinguistic turn, pp. 34-65. PPU, Barcelona. Chomsky N. 2009. Opening remarks and con-
Carey S. 2009. The origin of concepts. Oxford clusion. In M. Piattelli-Palmarini, P. Salaburu
University Press, Oxford. & J. Uriagereka (eds): Of minds and language.
Carroll S.B. 2005. Endless forms most beautiful: Oxford University Press, Oxford.
The new science of evo-devo and the making of the Chomsky, N. 2010. Some simple evo devo theses:
animal kingdom. Norton, New York. how true might they be for language. The evo-
Carroll S.B. 2006.The making of the fittest: DNA lution of human language. In R. K. Larson, V.
and the ultimate forensic record of evolution. WW Déprez & H. Yamakido (eds.): The Evolution
Norton & Company. of Language: biolinguistic perspectives, 45-62.
Carruthers P. 2003. The cognitive functions of Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
language. Behav. Brain Sci., 25: 657-674. Clark, B. 2013. Syntactic theory and the evolu-
Carruthers P. 2006.The architecture of the mind. tion of syntax. Biolinguistics, 7: 169-197.
Oxford University Press, Oxford. Coop G., Bullaughey K., Luca F. & Przeworski
Cheney D.L. & Seyfarth R.M. 1990. How monkeys M. 2008. The timing of selection at the human
see the world. University of Chicago Press, Chicago. FOXP2 gene. Mol. Biol. Evol., 25: 1257-1259.

www.isita-org.com
84 Linguistics and human cognitive biology

Crick F. 1984. Function of the thalamic reticular Duncan J. 2010. The multiple-demand (md) system
complex: the searchlight hypothesis. Proc. Natl. of the primate brain: mental programs for intel-
Acad. Sci. U.S.A., 81: 4586-4590. ligent behaviour. Trends Cogn. Sci., 14: 172-179.
Crosson B. Thalamic mechanisms in language: A Enard W. 2011. FOXP2 and the role of cortico-
reconsideration based on recent findings and basal ganglia circuits in speech and language
concepts. Brain Lang. (in press). evolution. Curr. Opin. Neurobiol., 21: 415-424.
Crow T.J. 2008. The big bang theory of the ori- Enard W., Gehre S., Hammerschmidt K., Hölter
gin of psychosis and the faculty of language. S.M., Blass T., Somel M., Brückner M.K.,
Schizophr. Res., 102: 31-52. Schreiweis C., Winter C., Sohr R., et al. 2009.
Darwin C. 1871. The descent of man. D. Appleton A humanized version of FOXP2 affects cortico-
and Co, London. basal ganglia circuits in mice. Cell, 137: 961-971.
David O., Maess B., Eckstein K. & Friederici Enard W., Przeworski M., Fisher S.E., Lai C.S.L.,
A.D. 2011. Dynamic causal modeling of sub- Wiebe V., Kitano T., Monaco A.P. & Pääbo S.
cortical connectivity of language. J. Neurosci., 2002. Molecular evolution of FOXP2, a gene
31: 2712-2717. involved in speech and language. Nature, 418:
De Waal F. & Ferrari P.F. 2010. Towards a bot- 869-872.
tom-up perspective on animal and human cog- Fedorenko E., Hsieh P.-J., Nieto-Castañón A.,
nition. Trends Cogn. Sci., 14: 201-207. Whitfield-Gabrieli S. & Kanwisher N. 2010.
Deacon T.W. 2005. Language as an emergent func- New method for fMRI investigations of lan-
tion: some radical neurological and evolution- guage: Defining ROIs functionally in individ-
ary implications. THEORIA. An International ual subjects. J. Neurophysiol., 104: 1177-1194.
Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Fisher S.E. & Scharff C. 2009. FOXP2 as a molec-
Science, 20: 269-286. ular window into speech and language. Trends
Deacon T.W. 2006. Emergence: The hole at the Genet., 25: 166-177.
wheel’s hub. In P. Clayton & P. Davies (eds): Fitch W. & Friederici A.D. 2012. Artificial gram-
The re-emergence of emergence: The emergentist mar learning meets formal language theory: an
hypothesis from science to religion, pp. 111-150. overview. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B. Biol.
Oxford University Press, Oxford. Sci., 367:1933-1955.
Deacon T.W. 2010. A role for relaxed selection Fitch W., Huber L. & Bugnyar T. 2010. Social
in the evolution of the language capacity. Proc. cognition and the evolution of language:
Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A., 107: 9000-9006. Constructing cognitive phylogenies. Neuron,
Dehaene S., Kerszberg M. & Changeux J.-P. 65: 795-814.
1998. A neuronal model of a global workspace Fitch W.T., Hauser M.D. & Chomsky, N. 2005. The
in effortful cognitive tasks. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. evolution of the language faculty: Clarifications
U.S.A., 95: 14529-14534. and implications. Cognition, 97: 179-210.
Deniz Can D., Richards T. & Kuhl P.K. 2013. Fitch W.T. 2011. Unity and diversity in human
Early gray-matter and white-matter concentra- language. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B. Biol.
tion in infancy predict later language skills: A Sci., 366: 376-388.
whole brain voxel-based morphometry study. Fitch W.T. & Hauser M.D. 2004. Computational
Brain Lang., 124: 34-44. constraints on syntactic processing in a nonhu-
Di Sciullo, A.M. & C. Boeckx. Eds. 2011.The man primate. Science, 303: 377-380.
biolinguistic enterprise: New perspectives on the Fodor, J.A. 1983.The modularity of mind. MIT
evolution and nature of the human language fac- Press, Cambridge.
ulty. Oxford University Press, Oxford. Fujita E., Tanabe Y., Imhof B.A., Momoi M.Y. &
Doupe A.J. & Kuhl P.K. 1999. Birdsong and hu- Momoi T. 2012. Cadm1-expressing synapses on
man speech: common themes and mechanisms. purkinje cell dendrites are involved in mouse ultra-
Annu. Rev. Neurosci., 22: 567-631. sonic vocalization activity. PloS ONE, 7: e30151.
C. Boeckx 85

Fujita E., Tanabe Y., Shiota A., Ueda M., Suwa Hauser M.D. 2001.Wild minds: What animals re-
K., Momoi M.Y. & Momoi T. 2008. Ultrasonic ally think. Owl Books, New York.
vocalization impairment of FOXP2 (r552h) Hauser M.D. 2009a. Evolingo: The nature of the lan-
knockin mice related to speech-language dis- guage faculty. In M. Piattelli-Palmarini, P. Salaburu
order and abnormality of purkinje cells. Proc. & J. Uriagereka (eds): Of minds and language, pp.
Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A., 105: 3117-3122. 74-84. Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Fujita H. & Sugihara I. 2012. FOXP2 expres- Hauser M.D. 2009b. The possibility of impossi-
sion in the cerebellum and inferior olive: ble cultures. Nature, 460: 190-196.
Development of the transverse stripe-shaped Hebb A. & Ojemann G.A. The thalamus and lan-
expression pattern in the mouse cerebellar cor- guage revisited. Brain Lang.(in press).
tex. J. Comp. Neurol., 520: 656-677. Heinz J. & Idsardi W. 2011. Sentence and word
Fujita K. 2009. A prospect for evolutionary adequa- complexity. Science, 333: 295-297.
cy: Merge and the evolution and development of Heinz J. & Idsardi W. 2013. What complexity dif-
human language. Biolinguistics, 3: 128-153. ferences reveal about domains in language. Top.
Gallistel C.R. & King A.P. 2009. Memory and the Cogn. Sci., 5: 111-131.
computational brain: Why cognitive science will Hickok G. & Poeppel D. 2007. The cortical
transform neuroscience. Wiley-Blackwell, Malden. organization of speech processing. Nat. Rev.
Garrigan D., Lewontin R. & Wakeley J. 2010. Neurosci., 8: 393-402.
Measuring the sensitivity of single-locus “neu- Hinzen W. 2007. An essay on naming and truth.
trality tests” using a direct perturbation ap- Oxford University Press, Oxford.
proach. Mol. Biol. Evol., 27: 73-89. Hinzen W. 2011. Language and thought. In C. Boeckx
Gentner T.Q., Fenn K.M., Margoliash D. & (ed): The Oxford Handbook of Linguistic Minimalism,
Nusbaum H.C. 2006. Recursive syntactic pattern pp. 499-522. Oxford University Press, Oxford.
learning by songbirds. Nature, 440: 1204-1207. Hurford J.R. 2007. The origins of meaning. Oxford
Gunz P., Neubauer S., Golovanova L., Doronichev University Press, Oxford.
V., Maureille B. & Hublin J.-J. 2012. A Jackendoff R. 1987. Consciousness and the compu-
uniquely modern human pattern of endocra- tational mind. MIT Press, Cambridge.
nial development. Insights from a new cranial Jackendoff R. 1990. Semantic structures. MIT
reconstruction of the Neandertal newborn from Press, Cambridge.
Mezmaiskaya. J. Hum. Evol., 62: 300-313. Jackendoff R. 2002. Foundations of language.
Gunz P., Neubauer S., Maureille B. & Hublin J.-J. Oxford University Press, Oxford & New York.
2010. Brain development after birth differs be- Jackendoff R. 2010. Meaning and the lexicon:
tween Neanderthals and modern humans. Curr. The Parallel Architecture 1975-2010. Oxford
Biol., 20: R921-R922. University Press, Oxford.
Hall D.C. 2012. Bridget D. Samuels, Phonological Jackendoff R. & Pinker S. 2005. The nature of the
architecture: A biolinguistic perspective (oxford language faculty and its implications for evolu-
studies in biolinguistics 2). Oxford: Oxford tion of language (reply to Fitch, Hauser, and
university press, 2011. pp. xii+ 252. Journal of Chomsky). Cognition, 97: 211-225.
Linguistics, 48: 736-741. Jacob F. & Monod J. 1961. On the regulation of
Hancock R. & Bever T.G. 2013. Genetic factors gene activity. Cold Spring Harbor Symposia on
and normal variation in the organization of lan- Quantitative Biology, volume 26, pp. 193-211.
guage. Biolinguistics, 7: 75-95. Cold Spring Harbor Laboratory Press.
Harrington A. 1987. Medicine, mind, and the double Jarvis E.D. 2006. Learned birdsong and the neu-
brain. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. robiology of human language. Ann. N. Y. Acad.
Hauser M.D., Chomsky N. & Fitch W.T. 2002. Sci., 1016: 749-777.
The faculty of language: What is it, who has it, Jenkins L. 2000. Biolinguistics: Exploring the biology of
and how did it evolve? Science, 298: 1569-1579. language. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

www.isita-org.com
86 Linguistics and human cognitive biology

Jürgens U. 2009. The neural control of vocaliza- Lenneberg E.H. 1967. Biological foundations of
tion in mammals: a review. J. Voice, 23: 1. language. Wiley, New York.
Karmiloff-Smith A. 1992. Beyond modularity. Lewontin R.C. 1998. The evolution of cognition.
MIT Press, Cambridge. In. D. Scarborough & S. Sternberg (eds): An
Kirby S. 2001. Spontaneous evolution of lin- invitation to cognitive science: methods, models,
guistic structure-an iterated learning model and conceptual issues, vol. 4, pp. 107-132. MIT
of the emergence of regularity and irregular- Press, Cambridge.
ity. Evolutionary Computation, IEEE Trans. 5: Lewontin R.C. 1993. Biology as ideology: The doc-
102-110. trine of DNA. Harper Perennial, New York.
Kirby S., Cornish H. & Smith K. 2008. Lewontin R.C. 2000.The triple helix: gene, organ-
Cumulative cultural Evolution in the labora- ism, and environment. Harvard University Press,
tory: an experimental approach to the origins of Cambridge.
structure in human language. Proc. Natl. Acad. Lewontin R.C. 2002. Directions in evolutionary
Sci. U.S.A., 105: 10681-10686. biology. Annu. Rev. Genet., 36: 1-18.
Kirby S. & Hurford J. 2002. The emergence of Lieberman, D.E. 2011. The evolution of the human
linguistic structure: An overview of the iterated head. Harvard University Press, Cambridge.
learning model. In A. Cangelosi & D. Parisi (eds): Lieberman P. 2006. Toward an evolutionary biology
Simulating the evolution of language, 121-148. of language. Belknap Press, Cambridge.
Springer, Dordrecht. Lobina, D.J. 2012. All tied in knots. Biolinguistics,
Konopka G., Bomar J.M., Winden K., Coppola 6: 70-78.
G., Jonsson Z.O., Gao F., Peng S., Preuss T.M., Lobina D.J. & Brenchley M. 2012. Knots, lan-
Wohlschlegel J.A. & Geschwind D.H. 2009. guage and computation: More Bermuda than
Human-specific transcriptional regulation of love. Biolinguistics, 6: 176-204.
cns development genes by FOXP2. Nature, 462: Longa V. & Benítez-Burraco A. 2012. On the in-
213-217. ference ‘Neanderthals had FOXP2 = they had
Konopka G., Friedrich T., Davis-Turak J., complex language’. In T.C. Scott-Phillips, M.
Winden K., Oldham M.C., Gao F., Chen L., Tamariz, E.A. Cartmill & J.R. Hurford (eds):
G.Z. Wang G.Z., Luo R., Preuss T.M., et al. The evolution of language. Proceedings of the
2012. Human-specific transcriptional networks 9th International Conference (EVOLANG9),
in the brain. Neuron, 75: 601-617. pp. 50-57. World Scientific Publishing, Hong
Kos M., van den Brink D., Snijders T.M., Kong.
Rijpkema M., Franke B., Fernandez G. & Longa V.M. & Lorenzo G. 2008. What about a
Hagoort P. 2012. CNTNAP2 and language (really) minimalist theory of language acquisi-
processing in healthy individuals as measured tion? Linguistics, 46: 541-570.
with ERPs. PloS ONE, 7: e46995. Longa V.M. & Lorenzo G. 2012. Theoretical
Krause J., Lalueza-Fox C., Orlando L., Enard W., linguistics meets development: Explaining
Green R.E., Burbano H.A., Hublin J.J., Hänni C., FL from an epigeniticist point of view. In C.
Fortea J., De La Rasilla M. et al. 2007. The derived Boeckx, M. Horno & J.L. Mendívil-Giró (eds):
FOXP2 variant of modern humans was shared with Language from a biological point of view: current
Neandertals. Curr. Biol., 17: 1908-1912. issues in biolinguistics, pp. 52-84. Cambridge
Kurt S., Fisher S.E. & Ehret G. 2012. FOXP2 Scholars Publishing, Cambridge.
mutations impair auditory-motor association Lorenzo G. & V.M. Longa. 2009. Beyond gen-
learning. PLoS ONE, 7: e33130. erative geneticism: Rethinking language acqui-
Lai C.S.L., Fisher S.E., Hurst J.A., Vargha- sition from a developmentalist point of view.
Khadem F., Monaco A.P., et al. 2001. A fork- Lingua, 119: 1300-1315.
head-domain gene is mutated in a severe speech Marcus G. 2006. Cognitive architecture and descent
and language disorder. Nature, 413: 519-522. with modification. Cognition, 101: 443-465.
C. Boeckx 87

Marcus G.F. 2004.The birth of the mind: How a 2012. Human-like brain hemispheric domi-
tiny number of genes creates the complexities of hu- nance in birdsong learning. Proc. Natl. Acad.
man thought. Basic Books, New York. Sci. U.S A., 109: 12782-12787.
Marcus G.F. & Fisher S.E. 2003. FOXP2 in focus: Müller G.B. 2008. Evo-devo as a discipline. In A.
what can genes tell us about speech and lan- Minelli & G. Fusco (eds): Evolving pathways:
guage? Trends Cogn. Sci., 7:257-262. key themes in evolutionary developmental biol-
Maricic T., Günther V., Georgiev O., Gehre ogy, pp. 3-29. Cambridge University Press,
S., Ćurlin M., Schreiweis C., Naumann R., Cambridge.
Burbano H.A., Meyer M., Lalueza-Fox C., et Müller G.B. 2010. Epigenetic innovation. In
al. 2012. A recent evolutionary change affects a Pigliucci M. & G. Müller (eds): Evolution -
regulatory element in the human FOXP2 gene. The Extended Synthesis, 307-333. MIT Press,
Mol. Biol. Evol. 30:844-852. Cambridge.
Marler P. 1970. Birdsong and speech development: Müller G.B. & Newman S.A. 2005. The innova-
Could there be parallels? There may be basic rules tion triad: An evo-devo agenda. J. Exp. Zool. B
governing vocal learning to which many species Mol. Dev. Evol., 304: 487-503.
conform, including man. Am. Sci., 669-673. Müller G.B. & Wagner G.P. 1991. Novelty in
Marr D. 1982. Vision. Freeman, San Franscisco. evolution: restructuring the concept. Ann. Rev.
Matsunaga E., Nambu S., Oka M., Okanoya K. Ecol. Syst., 22: 229-256.
& Iriki A. 2013. Comparative analysis of pro- Murdoch B.E. 2010. The cerebellum and lan-
tocadherin-11 x-linked expression among post- guage: historical perspective and re-view.
natal rodents, non-human primates, and song- Cortex, 46: 858-868.
birds suggests its possible involvement in brain Neubauer S., Gunz P. & Hublin J.-J. 2010.
evolution. PloS ONE, 8: e58840. Endocranial shape changes during growth in
Mayr E. 1960. The emergence of evolutionary chimpanzees and humans: a morphometric
novelties. Evolution after Darwin, 1: 349-380. analysis of unique and shared aspects. J. Hum.
Meyer M., Kircher M., Gansauge M.T., Li H., Evol., 59: 555-566.
Racimo F., Mallick S., Schraiber J.G., Jay F., Newmeyer, F.J. 2005. Possible and probable lan-
Prüfer K., de Filippo C., et al. 2012. A high- guages: A generative perspective on linguistic typol-
coverage genome sequence from an archaic ogy. Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Denisovan individual. Science, 338: 222-226. Newport E.L. 2010. Plus or minus 30 years in the
Min B.-K. 2010. A thalamic reticular network- language sciences. Top. Cogn. Sci., 2: 367-373.
ing model of consciousness. Theor. Biol. Med. Nottebohm F. 1970. Ontogeny of bird song.
Model., 7:10. Science, 167: 950-956.
Mithen S.J. 1996. The prehistory of the mind. Piattelli-Palmarini M. ed. 1980. Language and learn-
Thames and Hudson, London. ing: The debate between Jean Piaget and Noam
Miyagawa S., Berwick R.C. & Okanoya K. 2013. Chomsky. Harvard University Press, Cambridge.
The emergence of hierarchical structure in hu- Piattelli-Palmarini M. 1989. Evolution, selection
man language. Front. Psychol. 4:71. and cognition: from ‘learning’ to parameter set-
Moczek A.P. 2008. On the origins of novelty in ting in biology and in the study of language.
development and evolution. BioEssays, 30: Cognition, 31: 1-44.
432-447. Piattelli-Palmarini M., P. Salaburu & J. Uriagereka.
Moczek A.P. & Rose D.J. 2009. Differential re- Eds. 2009. Of minds and language. Oxford
cruitment of limb patterning genes during de- University Press, Oxford.
velopment and diversification of beetle horns. Piattelli-Palmarini M. & Uriagereka J. 2011.
Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S A., 106: 8992-8997. FOXP2: a geneticist’s dream; a linguist’s night-
Moorman S., Gobes S.M.H., Kuijpers M., mare. In A.M. Di Sciullo & C. Boeckx (eds):
Kerkhofs A., Zandbergen M.A. & Bolhuis J.J. The biolinguistic enterprise: new perspectives on the

www.isita-org.com
88 Linguistics and human cognitive biology

evolution and nature of the human language faculty, Ramus F. 2006. Genes, brain, and cognition: A
pp. 100-125. Oxford University Press, Oxford. roadmap for the cognitive scientist. Cognition,
Pietroski P.M. 2007. Systematicity via monadicity. 101: 247-269.
Croatian Journal of Philosophy, 7: 343-374. Reich D., Green R.E., Kircher M., Krause J.,
Pietroski P.M. 2011. Minimal semantic instruc- Patterson N., Durand E.Y., Viola B., Briggs
tions. In C. Boeckx (ed): The Oxford Handbook A.W., Stenzel U., Johnson P.L.F., et al. 2010.
of Linguistic Minimalism, pp. 472-498. Oxford Genetic history of an archaic hominin group
University Press, Oxford. from Denisova cave in Siberia. Nature, 468:
Pietroski, P. M. To appear. Semantics without truth 1053-1060.
values. Oxford University Press, Oxford. Reimers-Kipping S., Hevers W., Pääbo S. & Enard W.
Pigliucci M. & G. Müller. Eds. 2010. Evolution - 2011. Humanized FOXP2 specifically affects corti-
The Extended Synthesis. MIT Press, Cambridge. co-basal ganglia circuits. Neuroscience, 175: 75-84.
Pinel P., Fauchereau F., Moreno A., Barbot A., Saalmann Y.B, Pinsk M.A., Wang L., Li X. &
Lathrop M., Zelenika D., Le Bihan D., Poline Kastner S. 2012. The pulvinar regulates informa-
J.B., Bourgeron T. & Dehaene S. 2012. Genetic tion transmission between cortical areas based on
variants of FOXP2 and KIAA0319/TTRAP/ attention demands. Science, 337: 753-756.
THEM2 locus are associated with altered brain Saldaña Gascon C. 2012. Regiones aceleradas hu-
activation in distinct language-related regions. manas y la facultad del lenguaje en el humano
J. Neurosci., 32: 817-825. moderno. BA thesis, Universitat de Barcelona.
Pinker S. & Bloom P. 1990. Natural selection and Samuels B. 2011. Phonological architecture: a biolin-
natural language. Behav. Brain Sci., 13: 707-784. guistic perspective. Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Pinker S. & Jackendoff R. 2005. The faculty of language: Samuels B., Hauser M.D. & Boeckx C. In press.
What’s special about it? Cognition, 95: 201-236. Do animals have Universal Grammar? A case
Poeppel D. 2005. The interdisciplinary study of study in phonology. In I.G. Roberts (ed):
language and its challenges. Technical report, The Oxford Handbook of Universal Grammar.
Jahrbuch des Wissenschaftskollegs zu Berlin. Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Poeppel D. 2011. Genetics and language: a neuro- Scharff C. & Petri J. 2011. Evo-devo, deep ho-
biological perspective on the missing link (-ing mology and FOXP2: implications for the evo-
hypotheses). J. Neurodev. Disord., 3: 1-7. lution of speech and language. Philos. Trans. R.
Poeppel D. 2012. The maps problem and the Soc. Lond. B. Biol. Sci., 366: 2124-2140.
mapping problem: Two challenges for a cogni- Schlosser G. & G.P. Wagner. Eds. 2004.
tive neuroscience of speech and language. Cogn. Modularity in development and evolution.
Neuropsychol., 29: 34-55. University of Chicago Press, Chicago.
Poeppel D. & Embick D. 2005. Defining the rela- Shanahan, M. 2012. The brain’s connective core
tion between linguistics and neuroscience. In A. and its role in animal cognition. Philos. Trans.
Cutler (ed): Twenty-first century psycholinguistics: R. Soc. Lond. B. Biol. Sci., 367: 2704-2714.
four cornerstones, pp. 173-189. Erlbaum, Hillsdale. Shubin N., Tabin C. & Carroll S. 2009. Deep ho-
Prud’homme B., Minervino C., Hocine M., mology and the origins of evolutionary novelty.
Cande J.D., Aouane A., Dufour H.D., Kassner Nature, 457: 818-823.
V.A. & Gompel N. 2011. Body plan innova- Spelke E. 2003. What makes us smart? Core
tion in treehoppers through the evolution of an knowledge and natural language. In D.
extra wing-like appendage. Nature, 473: 83-86. Gentner & S. Goldin-Meadow (eds): Language
Ptak S.E., Enard W., Wiebe V., Hellmann I., and Mind: Advances in the study of language and
Krause J., Lachmann M. & Pääbo S. 2009. thought, pp. 277-311. MIT Press, Cambridge.
Linkage disequilibrium extends across putative Sterelny K. 2011. From hominins to humans:
selected sites in FOXP2. Mol. Biol. Evol., 26: How sapiens became behaviourally modern.
2181-2184.
C. Boeckx 89

Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B. Biol. Sci., 366: Vernes S.C., Newbury D.F., Abrahams B.S.,
809-822. Winchester L., Nicod J., Groszer M., Alarcón
Steriade M. & Llinás R.R. 1988. The functional M., Oliver P.L., Davies K.E., Geschwind D.H.
states of the thalamus and the associated neu- et al. 2008. A functional genetic link between
ronal interplay. Physiol. Rev., 68: 649-742. distinct developmental language disorders. N.
Tononi G. & Edelman G.M. 1998. Consciousness Engl. J. Med., 359: 2337-2345.
and complexity. Science, 282: 1846-1851. Wagner G.P. & Müller G.B. 2002. Evolutionary
Tsui D., Vessey J.P., Tomita H., Kaplan D.R. & innovations overcome ancestral constraints: A
Miller F.D. 2013. FOXP2 regulates neurogen- re-examination of character evolution in male
esis during embryonic cortical development. J. sepsid flies. Evol. Dev., 4: 1-6.
Neurosci., 33: 244-258. Wahl M., Marzinzik F., Friederici A.D., Hahne
Uriagereka J. 1998. Rhyme and reason: An in- A., Kupsch A., Schneider G.-H., Saddy D.,
troduction to minimalist syntax. MIT Press, Curio G. & Klostermann F. 2008. The human
Cambridge. thalamus processes syntactic and semantic lan-
Uriagereka J. 2008. Syntactic Anchors: On guage violations. Neuron, 59: 695-707.
Semantic Structuring. Cambridge University West-Eberhard M.J. 2003. Developmental plas-
Press, Cambridge. ticity and evolution. Oxford University Press,
Van Heijningen C.A.A., De Visser J., Zuidema W. Oxford.
& Ten Cate C. 2009. Simple rules can explain Whitehouse A.J.O., Bishop D.V.M., Ang Q.W.,
discrimination of putative recursive syntactic Pennell C.E. & Fisher S.E. 2011. CNTNAP2
structures by a songbird species. Proc. Natl. variants affect early language development in
Acad. Sci. U.S.A., 106: 20538-20543. the general population. Genes Brain Behav., 10:
Vargha-Khadem F., Gadian D.G., Copp A. & Mishkin 451-456.
M. 2005. FOXP2 and the neuroanatomy of speech Yip M.J. 2006. The search for phonology in other
and language. Nat. Rev. Neurosci., 6: 131-138. species. Trends Cogn. Sci., 10: 442-446.
Vernes S.C., Fisher S.E., et al. 2009. Unravelling neu-
rogenetic networks implicated in developmental
language disorders. Biochem. Soc. Trans., 37: 1263. Associate Editor, Emiliano Bruner

www.isita-org.com

You might also like