You are on page 1of 7

The General Impossibility of Normative Accounting Standards

Author(s): Joel S. Demski


Source: The Accounting Review, Vol. 48, No. 4 (Oct., 1973), pp. 718-723
Published by: American Accounting Association
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/245294
Accessed: 10-08-2017 20:53 UTC

REFERENCES
Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
http://www.jstor.org/stable/245294?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents
You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms

American Accounting Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and


extend access to The Accounting Review

This content downloaded from 168.176.239.33 on Thu, 10 Aug 2017 20:53:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The General Impossibility of Normative
Accounting Standards

Joel S. Demski

A PRIMARY goal of accounting theory rem. The third section then presents a
is to explain which accounting alter- brief discussion of the result's implications.
native should be used (in some par-
ticular circumstance). Numerous attempts CHOICE AMONG ACCOUNTING
ALTERNATIVES
to develop such a theory have, of course,
been offered through the years. Most of In this initial section we shall explore
these attempts have, in turn, relied on the abstract notions of choice among ac-
standards, such as relevance, usefulness, counting alternatives and the use of stan-
objectivity, fairness, and verifiability to dards to characterize the accounting choice
delineate the desired alternatives. Social process. To begin, suppose some indi-
choice institutions also reflect this reliance vidual is confronted with a defined set of
on standards, with the recently formed accounting alternatives, denoted H, that
Financial Accounting Standards and Cost is neither null nor singular. The former, of
Accounting Standards Boards. course, admits to no problem while the
Moreover, these standards are usually latter admits to a trivial problem. We now
viewed in terms of, or applied to, the ac- invoke the completeness and transitivity
counting measurement process, the en- axioms that are the hallmark feature of
vironment in which the measurements are rational choice theory.'
taken and/or used, and perceptions re- Consider any two accounting alter-
garding that environment. But any such natives, X and AS'EH. Completeness requires
application that is removed from indi- that we be able to ascertain whether in the
vidual preferences-in the slightest man- situation facing us we prefer X to I', I' to 77,
ner-creates an insurmountable diffi- or are indifferent between them. And this
culty. In particular, no normative theory rudimentary comparability must hold for
of accounting can be constructed using all pairs of alternatives that are available.
auy such set of standards; the standards A convenient characterization is that of
are bound incompletely and/or incorrectly "is at least as good as," which we denote
to rank the accounting alternatives-thus by the binary relation R. Then complete-
leading to an incorrect or undefined ac- 1 We could, in fact, develop these axioms from more
counting specification. primitive ones, as in revealed preference theory; but
such development is not germane to our impossibility
The purpose of this paper is to state exploration.
and prove this impossibility result. The
necessary choice theory framework is pre- Joel S. Demski is Professor of Informa-
sented in the first section followed in the tion and A ccounting Systems, Graduate
second section by the impossibility theo- School of Business, Stanford University.

718

This content downloaded from 168.176.239.33 on Thu, 10 Aug 2017 20:53:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Demski: Accounting Standards 719

ness requires Specifically,


that tqRtq', we now adopt the Savage
s'oqRn, o
all q, ?1'EH.2 Axioms4 to ensure that the ordering rela-
Now consider any three alternatives I, tion, R. admits to a subjective belief and
preference factoring such that the ac-
7',7"llH where qRq' and I'RE". Transitivity
requires that, under these conditions, counting alternative providing the maxi-
qR-". If historical cost is deemed at least
mum expected value of utility is the most
as good as current cost and current cost is preferred alternative. Denote the prefer-
deemed at least as good as price level ad- ence, or utility, factoring U(.) and the
justed historical cost, then historical cost belief, or probability, factoring 1(.).
is at least as good as its price level ad- To characterize further this expected
justed counterpart. utility description, we also adopt the con-
If, then, we elect to view accounting ventional specification of an uncertain
issues in terms of selecting or specifying an choice problem. The individual will ulti-
alternative that ought to be used, we must mately select some action aEA and subse-
be able to say which of two alternatives is quently observe consequence xeX. Ini-
the better (or whether they are indiffer- tially, however, he selects accounting al-
ent). Otherwise, we cannot hope to resolve ternative ?7EH; signal yEY is then produced.
accounting issues. These comparisons If, upon receipt of signal y, action aEA is
should also be transitive.3 Otherwise, taken, and state sES actually obtains, the
needless consumption of resources may re- consequence will be x=p(s, a, )), where
sult. Suppose, for example, that qRq', we include X in the outcome function do-
9'R7", but not 27R7". We might, in this main to represent the cost of the account-
intransitive setting, pay z dollars to ing alternative chosen. The p(.) function
switch from I" to I', another z dollars to is, without loss of generality, completely
switch from I' to I, and another z dollars known; and the probability of observing
to switch from X to n". This ensures the state sES given receipt of signal y from ac-
status quo, at a cost of 3z dollars, and counting alternative -q is denoted by
hardly seems satisfactory. I(s I y, I). Also, let 4(y 1 7) denote the prob-
Completeness and transitivity are, in ability of observing signal y if alternative
fact, sufficient to explore a variety of -q is selected. Finally, to avoid regularity
issues, including questions relating to the difficulties, we assume both Y and S to be
existence of at least one most preferred finite.
alternative. But since accounting alter- Now, upon receipt of signal y, the most
natives relate to information system alter- preferred action maximizes conditional
natives, we can develop a far more reveal- expected utility :'
ing framework by invoking additional
axioms sufficient to ensure the expected E(U I y, tq, a,,*) )
utility hypothesis. We shall, that is, make - max E U(p(s, a, A)) f(s I y, nq)
aEA seS
additional assumptions that ensure exis-
tence of utility and probability functions 2 v preferred to -q', then, is -qR-q' but
3 One notable exception here is a mul
such that the ordering relation R can be where we rely on game theory. See R.
represented by the expected utility asso- Theoretic Analysis of Social Choice," in B. Lieberman
Ed., Social Choice (Gordon and Breach, 1971).
ciated with any particular course of ac- 4 L. Savage, The Foundations of Statistics (Wiley,
tion. This has the advantage of being 1954).
6 We naturally assume here and throughout the
specific about the use of accounting infor- paper that all indicated maxima exist. A continuous
mation, with only a minor decrease in expected value of utility function and nonempty com-
pact choice set are, of course, sufficient to ensure
generality. existence.

This content downloaded from 168.176.239.33 on Thu, 10 Aug 2017 20:53:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
720 The Accounting Review, October 1973

The most preferred accounting alterna- keyEY=S and yny'=0 for all y, y'tEY,
tive, in turn, maximizes the expected value where Yv denotes the set of all yeY with
of utility: 4(y ) >0. This has the convenient effect
of placing all recording, transmission, and
E(UI |7*) (2) similar errors in the state partition; and it
- max A E(U I y, 7,
allows ay*)D(y
viewing the information |system
(2)as
X7EXc YEY defining a function from S into Y: y =(s).
Observe that this characterization of Within this framework, the standards
the choice, or specification, of an account- are viewed as defining a function, m, from
ing alternative is but an expected utility H into the real line such that m(8) m(77')
variant of the situation initially discussed. if and only if 77R77'. That is, the standards
We provide for comparison of any pair of are used to single out a most preferred
alternatives; and our comparisons are alternative. Using the standards, we are
transitive. We place these comparisons in able to compare any two accounting alter-
an expected utility format simply because natives and decide which of the two is
it is convenient. superior or whether they are equally de-
Reliance on standards to specify the sirable. Presumably, the comparisons are
most preferred accounting alternative fol-also transitive.
lows a somewhat different tack. The pur- One way of describing such a choice pro-
pose is to select the preferred alternative, cess, which we adopt, is to view the stan-
but the method of analysis does not rely dards as providing a hypothetical numer-
on subjective opinions and preferences re- ical ranking for each of the alternatives.
garding outcomes; rather, it relies on ex- Note, however, that the domain of this
trinsic properties of the accounting alter- ranking function is limited to E itself, with-
natives per se. The authors of ASOBAT, out any reference to the individual's pref-
for example, state: erences and beliefs.
These standards provide criteria to be used in A fundamental question now arises:
evaluating potential accounting information. does any such function, m(.), exist? In
They constitute a basis for inclusion or exclusion of selected settings the answer is, no doubt,
data as accounting information. If these criteria,
affirmative. But, in general, the answer is
taken as a whole, are not adequately met, the
information is unacceptable. On the other hand, negative. This is discussed below.
economic data which adequately fulfill these cri-
THE IMPOSSIBILITY RESULT
teria represent accounting material that must be
considered for reporting.6 In this section we formally state the as-
One way of characterizing this stan- sertion that, in general, no set of standards
dards, or criteria, approach is to regard exists
the that will single out the most pre-
standards as reflecting the basic qualities ferred accounting alternative without spe-
of the accounting alternatives irrespective cifically incorporating the individual's be-
of the individual's beliefs or preferences. liefs and preferences. We shall focus on an
For example, objectivity refers to the ac- arbitrary set of i = 1, , I individuals,
counting measurement process per se; and assume each to be Savage rational.
similarly, usefulness and relevance refer to Then individual i's action choice problem
the partition induced by the system, irre- is described by state set Si, action set Ai,
spective of its cost. outcome function pi(*), utility function
To make this precise, we now assume, Ui(*) and probability measure cIi(.). We
without loss of generality, that each sqlH 6 A Statement of Basic Accounting Theory (American
partitions the state set. That is, for all AScH
Accounting Association, 1966), p. 8.

This content downloaded from 168.176.239.33 on Thu, 10 Aug 2017 20:53:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Demski: Accounting Standards 721

now have the following result, which is that any set of standards will single out
proven in the Appendix. the most preferred accounting alternative.
Moreover, a less stringent interpreta-
THEOREM: Let i= 1, , I index a set tion of standards does not eliminate the
of Savage rational users of information. impossibility result. That is, we might
Further let m(-) denote a mapping from interpret
the the standards as, say, circum-
set of information system alternatives into scribing the feasible list of alternatives.
the real line that is independent of the indi- But this merely amounts to specifying a
viduals and their choice problems. No mea-
set of indifferent alternatives (in a feasible
sure of information quality m(-) exists such
sense); and the Theorem goes through
that m(77)>m(r') if and only if E(Uif77)with equal force.
? E(Ui 7q') for all individuals and choice We can strengthen, in fact, the result in
problems and any arbitrary pair of informa- several respects. Adding beliefs to the
tion system alternatives, vq and ti'. analysis does not circumvent the negative
result. For example, we might apply ob-
DISCUSSION
jectivity only to those situations we
The major significance of this result is to thought might occur with "reasonable
ensure that, generally speaking, we cannot probability." This extends the domain
rely on standards to provide a normative of m(.) to systems and beliefs, with m(,
theory of accounting. No set of standards 1?) being the basic mapping. But the
exists that will always rank alternatives Theorem's proof is totally unaffected
in accordance with preferences and beliefs by such an addition. We could also extend
-no matter what these preferences and the Theorem to ex post performance eval-
beliefs are, as long as they are consistent in uation systems as well, where the measure-
admitting to the expected utility char- ments are designed to motivate subordi-
acterization. This negation is, in fact, far nate decision makers.'0 But the funda-
reaching. It applies to the use of measure mental conclusion remains: no such rank-
or aggregation theory, as discussed by ing function, in general, exists.
Ijiri,7 the use of information theory, as
discussed by Lev,8 as well as the more SUMMARY

typical sets of standards, as in ASOBAT. We have interpreted accounting theory


It also applies with equal force to so-called as providing a complete and transitive
managerial and financial reporting areas. ranking of accounting alternatives at the
Allocation criteria, such as physical iden- individual level. It was then proven that
tification, facilities provided, and benefits 7 Y. Ijiri, "Fundamental Queries in Aggregation
received do not universally work, nor does Theory," Journal of The American Statistical Associa-
tion (December 1971).
a criterion of statistical correlation. 8 B. Lev, Accounting and Information Theory (Ameri-
Further observe that the basic difficulty can Accounting Association, 1969).
9 Indeed, another fundamental difficulty arises in a
does not rest with a multiperson orienta- multiperson setting. There is no way of moving from
tion. We might have a single-person situa- complete and transitive preferences at the individual
level to a group level complete and transitive notion
tion or a multiperson setting in which of preference that satisfies Arrow's conditions. (K.
only a dictator's preferences and beliefs Arrow, Social Choice and Individual Values (Wiley,
1963)). As a result, we expect difficulties in the multi-
counted. Either way, I= 1 and the Theo- person case, using standards or any other formulation
rem remains.9 Without restricting the of the choice process. But standards cannot even be
relied upon in the individual case.
nature of the decision problem faced or 10 See J. Demski, "Optimal Performance Measure-
the nature of the controlling preferences ment," Journal of Accounting Research (Autumn 1972)
for a discussion of the relationship between ex ante and
and beliefs, we simply cannot guarantee ex post information systems.

This content downloaded from 168.176.239.33 on Thu, 10 Aug 2017 20:53:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
722 The Accounting Review, October 1973

no set of standards (applied to the account- LEMMA: Given -l' and -l" are costless in-
ing alternatives per se) exists that will formation systems, E( U. ') > E( U. I ") for
always rank accounting alternatives in all i= 1, , I and all choice problems if
relation to consistent individual prefer- and only if -q' is as fine as -q".II
ences and beliefs. The major import of the
result is to raise a number of questions.
Proof: First suppose -q' is as fine as
Dropping the i subscript, this implies that
We know that standards do not always
work. When, then, do they work? Under ',(Y// I , =y
")Cd/"y
= (Y/ '
what types of conditions will various yl cyl

types of standards work; when they fail, Next, some algebraic manipulation of
how badly do they fail? We know that equation [2 ]establishes the desired result
criteria systems, as in information theory,
ASOBAT, or cost-allocation guides cannot E(U I a")
be relied upon to provide the desired = A, 1(y" 1 7") max E2 U(p(s, a))
V" 'E=-Y aEA 8ES
result in every situation. This does not,
however, necessarily imply that they *?Sy", 1a")
never provide the desired result. Hence, a
= Z, A (y'f |7')
major question in accounting theory must y"EtY y'c>" aEA 8ES
be conditions under which standards do
*4(s I, Y n")
work.
= Z E (y' I ')E(U Iy", ,a d7*)
poeY y'cy"
APPENDIX

Proof of the Impossibility Theorem re- < E E D(y'| I7')E(U I y', n'
ylEY y'cy"l
lies on a fineness Lemma. We say that -q
=E(U 1 7')
is as fine as rq' if every signal from 7 is fully
contained in a signal from -i'. Alterna- Thus, 77' as fine as -q" guarantees E(U
tively, we say that Xq is as fine as -q' when
? E(Uj-q"), given both systems are cost-
knowledge of a signal from Xq is sufficientless.
to
construct the corresponding signal from q'.Now suppose E(U') E(U 17") for
For example, capitalization of human as- all individuals and any choice problem.
set values provides an income measure- Further suppose t7' is not as fine as 7t". We
ment system that is as fine as a conven- proceed by contradiction. Suppose S= { 1,
tional income measurement system; with 2, 3, 4 } and the partitions induced by a'
knowledge of the former measurement one and a", respectively, are {{ 1,3}, { 2, 4 } }
could construct the latter measurement.
and {{ i, 2}, {3, 4} }. Observe that p(I,
Similarly, a more timely measurement sys- a)=p(3, a) and p(2, a)=p(4, a) for all
tem is as fine as a less timely system, again aEA implies, for some settings, that
because the former measurement can be
used to construct the latter. Hence, with 11 This Lemma is quite close to Blackwell's Theorem.
It is, however, more general in that it does not rely on
iq as fine as -q', we know that -q tells us aall
payoff adequate partition of the state space. See D.
that I' tells us, and possibly more. Blackwell and M. Girshick, Theory of Games and Statis-
tical Decisions (Wiley, 1954) and C. B. McGuire
Now consider two costless accounting
"Comparisons of Information Structures," Chapter 5
alternatives, 77' and -q", where by "costless"
in C. McGuire and R. Radner (eds.), Decision and
Organization (North-Holland, 1972) for discussion of
we mean that p(s, a, q) is strictly inde- Blackwell's Theorem. Also see J. Marschak and R.
pendent of I' and I". We now have the Radner, Economic Theory of Teams (Yale University
Press, 1971) for discussion of the Lemma and the fact
following result linking fineness to prefer-
that it ensures that no measure of the quality of infor-
ence between costless information systems: mation exists.

This content downloaded from 168.176.239.33 on Thu, 10 Aug 2017 20:53:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Demski: Accounting Standards 723

E(U 1q')>E(Uj1q"). But


all action choice p(1,
problems (given that a)=
a' p
and p(3, a) = p(4, a) for all aEA implies, for and a" are costless). Hence, in this case,
some settings, that E(U I -q") > E( U|I'). the standards must rank in accordance
This, however, contradicts our assump- with fineness. But, in general, this cannot
tion and we must, therefore, have -q' beasaccomplished because fineness is an
fine as -q". e incomplete relation; it does not always
We now prove the Impossibility Theo- hold. (See, for example, the two partitions
rem. used in proof of the Lemma.) That is, aq'
Proof: Since the Theorem is a negative as fine as ai" is necessary and sufficient to
result, we need only provide one counter ensure that E( Us v7') 2 E( Uj I 77"), regard-
example. Using the Lemma, an entire class less of the individual's preferences, beliefs,
is provided by costless accounting alter- and decision problem. But not all systems
natives. The Lemma establishes the ne- can be compared with respect to fineness.
cessity of I' as fine as -q" for E(Uj7n')
Thus, the m(.) function sought for cannot
exist. This completes the proof. U
> E( Ui I I") to hold for all individuals and

This content downloaded from 168.176.239.33 on Thu, 10 Aug 2017 20:53:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

You might also like