You are on page 1of 16

PAUL GUYER

Free Play and True Well-Being: Herder’s Critique of


Kant’s Aesthetics

The philosophical discipline of aesthetics, as subsequent Scottish writers such as Francis Hutch-
is well known, did not receive its name until eson, Henry Home (Lord Kames), and Alexander
1735, when the twenty-one-year-old Alexander Gerard. It was only slowly received in Germany,
Gottlieb Baumgarten introduced it to mean epis- making its first sustained appearance in the em-
teme aisthetike, or the science of what is sensed and phasis on the pleasure of the unhindered activity
imagined.1 But Baumgarten’s denomination of the of our powers of representation in some of the
field was an adult baptism: without the benefit of entries in Johann Georg Sulzer’s Allgemeine The-
a name, aesthetics had been part of philosophy orie der schönen Künste (1771–1774), for exam-
since Plato attacked the educational value of many ple, the entries on “beauty” and “taste,” but then
forms of art in the Republic and Aristotle briefly quickly becoming central to the aesthetic theories
defended them in his fragmentary Poetics. In par- of Immanuel Kant and Friedrich Schiller in the
ticular, Aristotle defended the arts from Plato’s Critique of the Power of Judgment (1790) and the
charge that they are cognitively useless, trading in Letters on the Aesthetic Education of Mankind
mere images of particulars rather than universal (1795).3
truths, by arguing that it is precisely the arts, or at Johann Gottfried Herder, who had done the
least poetry, that deliver universal truths in a read- bulk of his work in aesthetics long before these
ily graspable form, unlike, for example, history, publications of Kant and Schiller, indeed even be-
which deals merely with particular facts.2 And if fore the publication of Sulzer’s encyclopedia, re-
experience of the arts can reveal important moral acted violently to the new aesthetics of play in his
truths, then it can also be important to the develop- late work Kalligone (1800), that is, “The Birth of
ment of morality, the other pole of Plato’s doubts. Beauty.” This work, published only three years be-
Some variant of Aristotle’s response to Plato was fore Herder’s death and after his renown had been
the core of aesthetics through much of subsequent eclipsed by such new stars as Friedrich Schelling
philosophical history and, indeed, continued to and Johann Gottlieb Fichte, has never received
be central to aesthetics well into the twentieth much attention, but beneath its bursts of ill-temper
century—one need only think of T. W. Adorno. it contains interesting and important criticisms of
In the eighteenth century, however, an alternative Kant. The theme of Kalligone may be summed
response to Plato was introduced, namely, the idea up with this statement from its table of contents:
that our response to beauty, whether in nature or “Nothing harms immature taste more than if one
in art, is a free play of our mental powers that is makes everything into play.”4 Here I shall show
intrinsically pleasurable and thus needs no episte- not only that Kant has no good reply to some of
mological or moral justification, although it may Herder’s criticisms, but also that if Herder had had
in fact have epistemological and moral benefits. more sympathy for Kant’s expository method in
This line of thought was introduced in Britain in the third Critique, he might have realized that on
Joseph Addison’s 1712 Spectator essays on “The some of the central substantive points of his criti-
Pleasures of the Imagination,” and developed by cism the distance between himself and Kant is not

The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 65:4 Fall 2007


354 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

as great as it initially seems. In particular, I want it, that presupposes the sentiment of the beautiful
to argue that Herder’s representation of Kant’s and then analyzes this sentiment, and—no! does
aesthetics as a pure theory of mental play mis- not presuppose a definition, but gathers it both ob-
takes Kant’s initial analysis of the simplest form jectively from the artwork and subjectively from
of natural beauty for his whole theory of natural the sentiment? Is this not one work of one soul, and
and artistic beauty, and that if Herder had recog- why then maliciously separate these ways in or-
nized the importance for Kant of the more com- der maliciously to slander them, when without all
plicated cases of adherent and artistic beauty, he three together there can never be an aesthetics?”
would have seen that there is considerable com- The importance of this criticism is its proof that
mon ground between Kant’s aesthetics of free play from an early stage Herder was suspicious of the
and his own aesthetics of the sensory apprehension use of excessively abstract and a priori methods
of truth. in aesthetics, and although he did not think that
Baumgarten himself, whom he always admired,
i. some critical themes in herder’s early was guilty of this, it will be a recurring charge in his
aesthetics later polemic that Kant had, as it were, forgotten
his earlier suspicion of beginning philosophy from
Herder wrote most of his works on aesthetics early abstractions and instead succumbed to an a priori
in his career, twenty or more years before Kant’s methodology.
third Critique and thirty years before Kalligone. The substance of both the first and the fourth
The heart of this early work lies in the first and of the Groves of Criticism, however, and the main
fourth of the Kritische Wälder, or “Groves of Crit- reason for their enduring interest, is Herder’s cri-
icism,” the first published in 1769 and the fourth tique of Gotthold Ephraim Lessing’s Laocoön,
written around then but published posthumously, or on the Limits of Painting and Poetry.9 Less-
although some of its central arguments did see the ing, in turn responding to the famous claim of Jo-
light in Herder’s Plastik, an essay on sculpture be- hann Jakob Winckelmann that the serenity (sup-
gun in 1770 and finally published in 1778.5 I do posedly) expressed by the face and especially the
not want to spend much of my time here on these mouth of the Trojan priest in the famous epony-
works, but do want to mention two themes that mous statue reflected the “noble simplicity and
anticipate important aspects of Herder’s later cri- sedate grandeur” of the Greeks, had argued that
tique of Kant. this was not the source of Laocoön’s expression.10
The first of these points is methodological. Instead, he argued, visual arts are both confined
Herder cast the fourth Grove in the form of to the representation of a single moment of action
a criticism of the now justly forgotten Theorie and constrained by the necessity of being beauti-
der schönen Künste und Wissenschaften of Frie- ful, and so must depict a momentary state of their
drich Just Riedel.6 Herder particularly objected to object that both intimates an entire sequence of ac-
Riedel’s distinction among three supposedly alter- tion and yet is itself beautiful, while poetry, which
native “methods of aesthetics, which he likes to call deals with a succession of events in time, can de-
the Aristotelian, the Baumgartian, and the Kame- pict an object only by describing the process that
sian, where the Greek is supposed to have derived produced it, but can depict even an ugly or painful
his laws from the works of the masters, the mis- object as long as its own description is beautiful.11
erable, dry Baumgarten from definition, and the Herder applauded Lessing’s attention to the re-
Briton from sentiment.”7 At this stage, influenced quirements of specific media of art, but argued
by Kant’s argument in 1764 that in philosophy def- that he did not go far enough in his analysis. Two
initions always come at the end of inquiry, not at points are central to his extended criticism. In the
the beginning, Herder held that these are not three first Grove, he argued that it is music, not poetry,
alternative methods of aesthetics but, rather, that which is the art of pure succession, and that the
aesthetic theory must begin from both the anal- fact that poetry uses artificial rather than natural
ysis of works of art and the analysis of our own signs, which Lessing did recognize, means that in
responses to them and only then arrive at defini- the right hands poetry is capable of describing any
tions informed by both these sources.8 “Is it not kind of object and expressing any kind of emotion.
the same soul and the same operation of the soul, In the fourth Grove and in the published work
that presupposes a masterwork and observes art in on sculpture, Herder argued that Lessing failed
Guyer Free Play and True Well-Being: Herder’s Critique of Kant’s Aesthetics 355

to make an essential difference between paint- because it uses artificial rather than natural signs,
ing and sculpture among the visual arts, and thus can present both objects and actions to us, and
failed to see that while painting is limited to the in that sense present more truth to us than either
beautiful depiction of surfaces, sculpture appeals painting or music alone.
to our sense of touch, creating three-dimensional The main thrust of the fourth Grove is that
objects that we really want to grasp and explore. recognition of the distinctions among our senses
On Herder’s view, both sculpture and poetry thus will explain the variety of both forms of art
have a relation to truth that is missing from paint- and forms of aesthetic response. The premise of
ing: poetry, precisely because it uses artificial signs, Herder’s argument is that aesthetic response is
can convey any truth rather than being limited to not the disinterested reaction of a special inter-
mere beautiful surfaces, while sculpture, because nal sense to purely formal properties of objects,
it really does not use signs at all, conveys to us the but is really the heightened response of various of
true shape and feel of three-dimensional objects our senses to their appropriate objects. Herder re-
in the physical world, to which we have to learn jects the traditional distinction between mind and
how to correlate the natural but superficial signs body, arguing that mind is essentially connected
delivered by sight. to the bodily organs of sense, as well as rejecting
Thus, in the first Grove, Herder emphasizes the any suggestion that aesthetic pleasures are essen-
broader reach of poetry as compared to both the tially distinct from the other sources of our happi-
visual arts and music. Precisely because in appre- ness and unhappiness. In this connection, Herder
hending artificial rather than natural signs, we typ- scorns Riedel’s thesis that the beautiful is that
ically think immediately of the meaning of those “which can please without an interested aim and
signs rather than focusing on their own physicality, thus also please if we do not possess it”—thus pre-
and thus in taking in poetry we do not focus on the figuring one theme of his later critique of Kant’s
physical or acoustical properties of the signs them- aesthetics.14 Instead, Herder argues that the phe-
selves, but on their meanings, poetry can represent nomenon of distance that Riedel mistakenly char-
anything. In the case of poetry, “it is not the sign acterizes as a general quality of disinterestedness
itself but the sense [Sinn] of the sign that must be in all aesthetic response is a specific feature of the
felt; the soul must not feel the vehicle of the force, visual perception of beauty, indeed that beauty
the words, but the force itself, the sense . . . But is, properly speaking, a property only of the vi-
thereby it also brings every object as it were visibly sual.15 This in turn leads him to distinguish be-
before the soul.”12 Herder then develops his view tween sight as a sense for mere appearance and
by invoking Baumgarten’s characterization of po- touch as the sense for reality, and thus to the es-
etry as “the sensibly perfect in discourse.” What sential distinction between painting and sculpture,
he now argues is that poetry actually achieves its which, he charges, Lessing failed to make. Beauty,
force by exploiting both the depiction of objects Herder writes, appeals to the eye, but insofar as it
as in painting and their energy as represented by does so it is superficial, or even an illusion: “This
music. is in accordance with its etymology: for to intuit
[schauen], appearance [Schein], beautiful [Schön],
Neither of these taken alone is its entire essence. Not beauty [Schönheit] are related offspring of lan-
the energy, the musical in it; for this cannot take place guage: it is here that, if we pay proper attention to
if what is sensible in its representations, which it paints its particular application, that beauty is most orig-
before the soul, is presupposed. But not what is painterly inally found in everything that offers itself pleas-
in it; for it works energetically, in succession it builds the ingly to the eye.” He continues:
concept of the sensibly perfect whole in the soul: only [in]
both together, I can say, the essence of poetry is force, In accordance with this first sense the concept of beauty
which works from space (objects, that it makes sensible) is “a phenomenon” and thus to be treated as if it were an
in time (through a series of many parts in one poetic agreeable delusion [Trug], a delightful illusion [Blendw-
whole); in short, therefore, sensibly perfect discourse.13 erk]. It is properly a concept of surfaces, since we prop-
erly cognize the bodily, the well-formed, and the solidly
Once painting and music have been properly pleasing only with the help of filling, and with sight
distinguished from each other and poetry from can see only planes, only figures, only colors, but not
both, then it can also be recognized that poetry, immediately corporeal spaces, angles, and forms.16
356 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

Here, Herder insists that visible beauty arises artist and the audience can fully feel the emotions
only from the most superficial features of objects, and passions of life that made Pygmalion wish that
not from their full reality, and that only feeling—by his beautiful creation could come alive. This view
which he here means the sense of touch—can put of the power of art is what Herder finds missing in
us into direct contact with reality, or with the Riedel and perhaps even in Lessing himself.
deeper truth about physical reality. He expands These criticisms of Lessing and Riedel prefig-
on this contrast in the essay on sculpture. ure several of Herder’s objections to Kant: he will
object to Kant’s abstract method in aesthetics, to
The living, embodied truth of the three-dimensional his failure to emphasize adequately the role of the
space of angles, of form and volume, is not something we senses and the differences among them in his ac-
can learn through sight. This is all the more true of the count of aesthetic experience and in his classifi-
essence of sculpture, beautiful form and beautiful shape, cation of the arts, to an inadequate recognition
for this is not a matter of color, or of the play of pro- of the importance of truth, indeed truth in several
portion and symmetry, or of light and shadow, but of senses, in our experience of art, and to what he sees
physically present, tangible truth. . . . Consider the lover as Kant’s inadequate emphasis on the way aes-
of art sunk deep in contemplation who circles restlessly thetic experience gives us a feeling of being alive.
around a sculpture. What would he not do to transform But what is missing from Herder’s early critical
his sight into touch, to make his seeing into a form of aesthetics is an objection to the aesthetics of play,
touching that feels in the dark. . . . With his soul he seeks for the simple reason that Kant had not yet made
to grasp the image that arose from the arm and the soul that prominent in German aesthetics. In turning
of the artist. Now he has it! The illusion has worked; the now to Herder’s criticisms of Kant in Kalligone,
sculpture lives and his soul feels that it lives. His soul we will have to add that objection to his list of
speaks to it, not as if his soul sees, but as if it touches, as charges.
if it feels . . .17

This is why Herder subtitles his essay after the ii. herder’s criticisms of kant in KALLIGONE
sculptor Pygmalion, who fell in love with the statue
of the beautiful young woman he had created and Kalligone is a polemic against Kant’s Critique of
was granted his wish that it come alive. the Power of Judgement, or, more precisely, against
Herder’s emphasis on the sense of touch and its its first half, the “Critique of the Aesthetic Power
centrality to the experience of sculpture builds on of Judgment.” The work is loosely structured in
his interpretation of the great eighteenth-century parallel with Kant’s work, although with numer-
debate about the relation between sight and touch, ous digressions, sometimes even in dialogue form,
in which John Locke, George Berkeley, and Denis and statements of Herder’s own positions. Like
Diderot had all argued that we do not correlate the Herder’s polemic with Lessing in the Groves of
deliverances of the two senses innately, but have to Criticism, his response to Kant’s work is longer
learn from experience that an object that looks a than its target, and all its themes cannot be dis-
certain way also feels a certain way, or vice versa.18 cussed here. In ways anticipated in Herder’s ear-
But he takes this thesis a step further by arguing lier work, Kalligone attacks Kant’s methodology
that it is touch that reveals the true form of ob- and his neglect of the concrete role of the senses in
jects, while sight merely reveals or plays with their a discipline that is, as defined by Baumgarten, sup-
superficial appearance. Thus, although sight ini- posed to focus precisely on that. In an expression
tially seemed the paradigmatic vehicle of knowl- of the naturalism that pervades his work, Herder
edge, Herder ultimately concludes that “in paint- also attacks Kant’s appeals to the “supersensible”
ing there is merely beautiful deception” while in in his interpretation of aesthetic experiences, es-
sculpture there is “primary truth.”19 The passage pecially the experience of sublimity. But Herder’s
from Sculpture also displays what Herder thinks is most vehement objections are to Kant’s insistence
the significance of the perception of the true form on the disinterestedness of aesthetic judgment and
of objects through the tactile medium of sculp- his exclusion of a role for determinate concepts in
ture: it communicates to us the feeling of life in the the free play of the mental powers in aesthetic ex-
sculpture and in turn arouses our own feeling of perience, which Herder sees as excluding any role
being truly alive. In the case of sculpture, both the for the knowledge of truth in aesthetic experience.
Guyer Free Play and True Well-Being: Herder’s Critique of Kant’s Aesthetics 357

After a brief comment on Herder’s attack on To this summary, in what is supposed to be Kant’s
Kant’s methodology, I will discuss Herder’s crit- voice, Herder replies in his own voice.
icisms of the disinterestedness and nonconceptu-
That this empty, hollow, pernicious theory, which has
ality of aesthetic judgment in some detail, and then
arisen from necessity, a critique without any critique,
note his criticisms of the nonsensual and transcen-
has not originated in any serious study of the beauti-
dent rather than immanent character of Kant’s
ful, whether in objects or in sentiments thereof, needs
aesthetics more briefly.
no proof. It has come about a priori from a supposedly
Herder prefaces Kalligone with an attack on
empty spot; a play of wit and acuity that is purposelessly-
what he calls “transcendental influenza” and its
purposive and purposively-purposeless.22
infection of the young, thinking no doubt not only
of Kant but also of the influence of Fichte and By saying that Kant’s theory has arisen a pri-
Schelling in Jena, the backyard to Herder’s own ori from “necessity” (Not) and to fill a “suppos-
Weimar. Herder blames Kant for opening the door edly empty spot,” Herder presumably refers to
to “a realm of endless chimerae, blind intuitions, Kant’s suggestion in the introduction to the third
fantasms, empty spelling-words, so-called transcen- Critique that since there are a priori principles
dental ideas and speculations,” a made-up philo- for understanding and (practical) reason, there
sophical language that ignores real human speech should be one for the power of judgment, the
and thus the real structure of human thought, third of the higher powers of cognition as well.23
since, according to Herder’s deepest belief, “[t]he He takes Kant to have decided in advance of and
language of human beings carries their forms of without any serious study of aesthetic objects and
thought in it; we think, sometimes abstractly, only experience—the two prerequisites for any useful
in and with language.”20 In Herder’s view, “[w]e definitions in aesthetics according to Herder’s ear-
should, without all ‘Transcendental taste, whose lier criticism of Riedel—that there is an a priori
principle resides in the supersensible substratum foundation for aesthetics, and that it lies in a free
of mankind in absolute unconsciousness,’ form our play of mental powers that are universal among
taste here below in consciousness, learn to know human beings and therefore yield universally valid
the laws and analogies of nature, and use neither judgments of beauty or other judgments of taste.
the art nor the science of the beautiful for a game Herder scorns Kant’s theory of free play by say-
[Spiel] or for idolatry, but should use them with ing that it is itself a mere play of wit, and jeers at
joyful seriousness for the cultivation [Bildung] of Kant’s claim that this free play is purposive but
mankind.”21 From the outset of his work, Herder without a specific purpose by suggesting that it is
rejects a transcendental method in aesthetics and itself as purposeless as it is purposive.
shows his hostility to any reduction of aesthetic It is no doubt unfair of Herder to accuse Kant of
experience to a form of play rather than to a com- arriving at his theory completely a priori; Kant’s
pletely serious experience of truth that is essential language in his introduction suggests rather that
to human development. he is merely asking whether there is an a priori
In the body of the text, Herder’s rejection principle for aesthetic judgment analogous to the a
of transcendental aesthetics often remains be- priori principles of understanding and reason—he
neath the surface of his specific objections to says that “one has reason to presume, by analogy,
Kant’s various claims. But one place where it that [the power of judgment] too should contain
clearly emerges is at the end of Part I of in itself a priori, if not exactly its own legislation,
Kalligone, which deals with the “Agreeable and then still a proper principle of its own for seek-
the Beautiful.” Here Herder summarizes his ing laws”—and that this question will be answered
polemic by expounding Kant’s “Analytic of the only in the following body of the work.24 As far as
Beautiful” in the form of thirteen “postulates,” Kant’s subsequent attempt to answer his question
and then questioning each. The last of these is concerned, however, it is certainly fair of Herder
postulates sums up Kant’s view in the thesis: to claim that Kant proceeds with little, indeed vir-
“The power of judgment for taste [Geschmacks- tually no, detailed criticism of particular works of
urteilskraft] consists in judgments, rests on the art and of our experiences of them, though it could
common sense, and operates [wirkt] with universal be argued that this is work for critics like Lessing or
validity toward universal communication; other- Herder himself, not for a philosopher like Kant. It
wise, a free play of the powers of the human soul.” is less clear that Kant proceeds without any close
358 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

examination of our sentiments (Empfindungen) sponds: “The correspondence of objects with our
in aesthetic experience, but perhaps this is a fair powers, the harmony of our powers with the ob-
response to Kant’s exposition of his aesthetic the- jects, does not refer us beyond but keeps us firmly
ory in the form of an analysis of the logic of judg- within the boundaries of nature; and where is the
ments of taste rather than in the form of a direct moral in this supersensible-arrogant feeling?”—
description of the feelings or experiences on which that is, within Kant’s “supersensible-arrogant”
such judgments are supposed to be based. interpretation of the moral significance of aes-
Having objected to Kant’s supposedly a priori thetic feeling? In the conclusion of this passage,
method in aesthetics, Herder also objects to Kant’s Herder cannot refrain from reiterating his under-
attempts to read transcendent rather than imma- lying view that Kant’s theory of an “understand-
nent significance into aesthetic experience. This ing and conceptless but yet universally valid judg-
objection is central to Herder’s critiques of Kant’s ing, grounded in an objectless play of imagination
accounts of the sublime and of the beautiful as the and communication,” is the “grave of all genuine
symbol of the morally good. About the sublime, knowledge, critique, and sentiment.”27
Herder writes: Here, I will only say that Herder’s criticism of
Kant’s introduction of the supersensible into his
That this view, this feeling, does not lie in the object but
explication of the moral significance of the expe-
rather in the feeling viewer [fühlenden Anschauer] . . .
riences of the sublime and the beautiful cannot be
no one since the beginning of the world has doubted;
assessed separately from the general critique of
but that the feeling of the sublime is of a supersensible
Kantian moral philosophy that he also intimates
[übersinnlichen] nature, that it rests on a supersensible
in Kalligone.28 Kant certainly thought that in his
reason aiming at an absolute totality, whose feeling does
account of the experiences of the sublime and of
not say something quite different to him? Only an un-
the beautiful as a symbol of the morally good
bounded fantasy steps into the infinite, only a reason that
he had succeeded in describing experiences that
has lost its measure dreams of an absolute totality.25
would have a positive and uplifting, not a cramp-
In his own interpretation of the experience of ing and restricting, effect on our psychology and
the sublime, Herder stresses that what is central moral development because he thought it would
is not the incompletable effort to grasp something be uplifting for us to realize that we have a theo-
that exceeds the boundaries of human imagination retical reason whose ambitions exceed the bound-
and reason alike, but rather the effect on our own aries of our sense-based imagination, a practical
feelings of admiring something high and mighty: reason capable of formulating the moral law in
the “feeling of the sublime” (Gefühl des Erhab- all its purity, and a freedom of the noumenal will
nen) is one of “elevation” (Elevation, Erhebung). that allows us to act in accordance with that moral
“It elevates [us] to the sublime object; lifted above law no matter what our prior history may seem to
ourselves, we become with it higher, more encom- imply. Herder’s objection is not really to Kant’s ac-
passing, wider. This feeling is not a cramp, but the count of the psychological impact of an aesthetic
widening of our breast, raising our view and as- presentation of the elements of this moral the-
piration, elevation of our being.”26 Herder locates ory, but to the moral theory itself. I will hardly
the significance of the experience of the sublime in attempt to adjudicate that dispute here. For now,
the feelings of empowerment it brings to us, not in I will only note that in Herder’s own account of
any intimations of a supersensible realm it might the experience of the sublime, he intimates that
be thought to yield. the observation of something objectively elevated
There is a similar thrust to Herder’s critique of has a subjectively uplifting effect on us, thus that
Kant’s explanation of why the beautiful is a sym- in this aesthetic experience there is a parallel be-
bol of the morally good. Herder interprets Kant tween the structure of the object of the experience
to argue that the beautiful is such a symbol be- and the emotional effect of the experience itself.
cause our experience of it “is related to something This is a crucial premise of Herder’s general theory
in the subject itself and outside of it which is not of aesthetic experience as an experience of well-
nature, also not freedom, but yet connected with being arising from a perception of the true order
the ground of the latter, namely the supersensible, of nature, which he opposes to Kant’s theory of
in which the theoretical faculty is unified with the the disinterestedness of aesthetic experience and
practical in a common and unknown way.” He re- attachment.
Guyer Free Play and True Well-Being: Herder’s Critique of Kant’s Aesthetics 359

Before I turn to that issue, however, which is cer- though Herder does not mention Schiller by name
tainly at the heart of Herder’s response to Kant, I anywhere in Kalligone, he does begin the work by
will say just a word about Herder’s objection that bemoaning the influence of Kant’s third Critique
Kant’s aesthetics does not pay sufficient attention on his followers, and Schiller might be supposed to
to the concrete role of the senses in aesthetic expe- be the foremost among these, although one with
rience. The charge of insensitivity to the specificity whom Herder had to maintain cordial relations in
of the senses, as I have already mentioned, was at Weimar and perhaps spared for this reason.
the heart of Herder’s early aesthetics, beginning There is much more that could be said on this
with his critique of Lessing, and it manifests it- subject, but I now want to turn without further
self in various ways in his critique of Kant. One delay to the two main topics of Herder’s criticism,
point at which it is particularly clear is in his ob- Kant’s theory of the disinterestedness of aesthetic
jection to Kant’s scheme for the classification of judgment and of the concept—and purposeless
the fine arts, a scheme based on the differing ca- play of imagination and understanding as the basis
pacities of different media for meaning, tone, and of such judgment. Since Kant introduces disinter-
gesture, which Herder claims “throws us back into estedness in the first “moment” of the judgment of
the old chaos.” Kant’s basic division is between taste and his theory of free play in the second and
the verbal (redende) and the formative or visual third moments, and Herder’s discussion follows
(bildende) arts, and Herder says that Kant’s ac- the order of Kant’s, I, too, will discuss Herder’s
count of the “so-called verbal arts [is] built upon a attack on disinterestedness first and his attack on
word-play, which makes them both into play, and concept-less free play second.
not in the technical sense of this word; and about Herder had in fact already expressed doubt
the formative arts as well as about the arts that ef- about disinterestedness as a fundamental aesthetic
fect sentiments nothing is said that serves for the category in his polemic with Riedel in the fourth
essence of each and the essence of all.”29 In con- Grove. Here, he rejected Riedel’s definition of
trast, Herder argues that any division of the arts, as the beautiful as “that which can please without
well as any account of the way in which different an interested aim [interessierte Absicht] and which
arts need to be cultivated and contribute to our also can please if we do not possess it.”31 At this
overall cultivation and development, must attend point, however, Herder’s objection seemed to be
to the specificity of our senses. only that the concept of disinterestedness is not
“original,” that is, that disinterestedness by itself
The noble senses of mankind, eye, ear, hand, and tongue, cannot explain our pleasure in the beautiful and
need cultivation [Ausbildung]; sciences and arts that cul- thus could at best be a consequence of some more
tivate [kultivieren] them are called fine [schöne] sciences fundamental explanation of beauty. In Kalligone,
and arts. What gives the eye a proper measure, a quick however, he argues much more broadly that our
judgment about correct, fitting, beautiful figures, and pleasure in beauty is not disinterested but, rather,
forms the eye through the hand, the hand through the that it is intimately connected with our most funda-
eye; what accustoms the ear to hear with understanding, mental interest, our interest in life itself. He does
not only the tones but also the thoughts of human speech; this by rejecting Kant’s rigid distinction between
what accustoms the tongue to express these thoughts, as the agreeable, the beautiful, and the good, argu-
its nature and its purpose demand; that is fine art and ing that all these notions are intimately connected
cultivates human beings.30 and that they all reflect our fundamental interest
in enjoying a harmonious, well-adapted life.
For Herder, any classification of the arts, as well The first step in Herder’s argument is to re-
as any theory of aesthetic education and the contri- ject Kant’s identification of agreeableness with
bution of aesthetic education to general education, sensory gratification narrowly understood. For
must be based on a firm grasp of the differences Herder, the agreeable (angenehm) is what “ex-
as well as the similarities among sight, hearing, pands our existence, what makes us free, what
touch, speech, and song (for that, too, is among makes us rejoice. The poets of paradise, the
the arts of the tongue), and in his view Kant does painters of that Elysium, what do they offer for
not have that grasp. Nor does it seem too much our feeling? Agreeable breezes cosset the blessed;
of a stretch to think that Schiller’s theory of aes- their elastic existence, without illness, without
thetic education is deficient in this regard also. Al- anxiety, lives and moves joyfully and freely.”32
360 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

Alternatively, “[t]he agreeable does not merely [Annehmliche], the well-pleasing [Wohlgefällige], rejoic-
gratify, rather the inmost-agreeable expands, em- ing, gratifying, blessing lies at the basis of all of them.
powers, strengthens my existence; the inmost The end of our existence is well-being; how it is to be
agreeable is my living felt existence itself.”33 The attained, how limited, how its different branches are to
agreeable is what actually liberates and strength- be subordinated to one another, that is the task, easier or
ens me and gives me a feeling of liberation and harder (depending on how one approaches it) in theory,
strength, of not merely being alive but of living as in practice.36
freely and strongly. This feeling can come through
the engagement of any or all of my senses: “what- While the agreeable, the beautiful, and the good,
ever preserves, promotes, expands, in short is har- which Kant construed as three fundamentally “dif-
monious with the feeling of my existence, each ferent relations of representations to the feeling
of my senses gladly accepts that”—Herder’s verb of pleasure and displeasure,” do have to be dis-
here is nimmt . . . an, for he derives angenehm tinguished in certain contexts, they nevertheless
from annehmen, and thus equates the “agreeable” are all expressions of our pleasure in a free and
with that which we “accept”—“appropriates that healthy life.37 Given this assumption, it is not hard
to itself, and finds it agreeable.”34 What gives us for Herder to argue that so far from being disin-
such feelings is, moreover, universally pleasing, terested, our pleasure in beauty is necessarily of
because “well-being, welfare, health” (Wohlsein, the greatest interest to us:
Heil, Gesundheit) are the “ground and end of the
existence of every living thing . . . We all desire Beauty however has interest; indeed everything good has
well-being, and whatever promotes this well-being interest only through it. For what does the word mean?
in any way is agreeable.”35 Interest is quod mea interest, what concerns [angeht] me.
With the agreeable so broadly conceived, it is If something does not concern [betrifft] me, how could
then easy for Herder to suggest that the beautiful I find satisfaction in it? In order to please, the poet, the
cannot be rigidly separated from it, but must be artist, indeed nature itself must first be interesting to us;
more like a species of it, namely, that which gives otherwise everything that they offer us goes past us like
us such agreeable feelings of well-being through unseasoned fare, like empty husks.
the “noble senses,” through figures, colors, tones,
and the re-creation of all of these through the ar- Interest is the soul of beauty as it is of the good and the
tificial signs of literary language. To be sure, there true. Take away from it that through which it attracts
are specific contexts in which we might call some- and binds us, or, what is the same, that through which it
thing that is disagreeable good, or something that communicates to us; what then do you have to do with
is beautiful disagreeable, but these are the excep- it? Give it interest, and a tale of Mother Goose pleases
tions, not the rule. more than a boring epic of heroism.

Interest in the beautiful; is there a purer interest? In con-


Nobody doubts that in language different concepts are trast to that, what is cold self-interest [Eigennutz], philo-
designated with the words “agreeable, beautiful and sophical pride, arrogant self-love [Selbstliebe]?
good.” A disagreeable medicine can be very good, while
the most beautiful cane is never agreeable to the head- No beautiful work of art or of nature shall therefore be
strong child. That much that seems beautiful to us is not without interest for us.38
good is confirmed by the sad proof of the tree of knowl-
edge in the history of mankind. But since our nature in all Now in this passage, while arguing that the
of its concepts and feelings is one nature, which thinks beautiful necessarily interests us, Herder also in-
and comprehends, which feels, wills, and desires, these sists that the beautiful does not appeal to self-
related concepts must all border one another, and how interest or self-love: pleasure and interest in the
they border one another? how they are to be separated or genuinely beautiful as well as the agreeable and
connected?—that is the question. Mere contrasts do not good is universal, not personal or idiosyncratic. It
solve the riddle, even less so arbitrarily set verbal limits. could well be argued that this is all that Shaftes-
Cold approval, for example, is not adequate to genuine bury meant when he introduced the concept of
beauty, as little as mere esteem and respect is adequate for disinterestedness into modern moral and aesthetic
the truly good. This will also be desired, the beautiful also discourse—for him, the opposite of disinterested
known and loved; the agreeable finally or the acceptable is mercenary, that which one wants or does just
Guyer Free Play and True Well-Being: Herder’s Critique of Kant’s Aesthetics 361

for a personal reward—and it is arguably all that and indeed please universally, is contrary to nature
Riedel meant when he said that the beautiful is and experience.”41 He subsequently expands his
that which can please us “without possession.”39 point by saying that what “is to be felt [empfun-
It would not be reasonable, however, to claim that den] must be something, i.e., something substan-
all that Kant meant by saying that the pleasure tial [Bestandheit], an essence [Wesen] that mani-
in beauty is disinterested is that it must be able fests itself to us; hence something true lies at the
to please anyone apart from personal possession ground of everything that is agreeable or disagree-
and use or consumption of the beautiful object; able for us. Sensation without object and its con-
he certainly seems to insist that the source of our cept is a contradiction in human nature, therefore
pleasure in the beautiful has nothing to do with the impossible.”42
sources of our pleasure in the agreeable and the Depending on how we take this claim, of course,
good, and thus to be open to Herder’s criticism if Herder may not be saying anything with which
Herder’s claim is that our pleasures in the agree- Kant would disagree: Kant more than anyone else
able, the beautiful, and the good all ultimately rest argued that all experience of an object requires
on our pleasure in the feeling of a free and healthy consciousness of a concept as well as of empirical
life. Before we consider whether the distance here intuitions of that object, the matter of which is
between Kant and Herder is as great as Herder sensation. But he did hold that we could have a
thinks, however, let us consider one last charge on feeling of pleasure in an object without considering
Herder’s indictment of Kant, namely, his objection what concepts apply to it and, on the basis of such
to Kant’s theory that the experience of beauty is a feeling, make the judgment that it is beautiful.
an experience of a free and concept-less play of the Herder is specifically rejecting that claim. On what
mental powers of imagination and understanding. basis does he do so?
As I mentioned earlier, Herder’s antipathy to He does so by means of the more particular ar-
Kant’s central notion of the free play of our cogni- gument that our pleasure in beauty is in fact a plea-
tive powers is evident from the outset of Kalligone. sure in our sensed or felt recognition of an object’s
In his preface, Herder writes bitterly: adaptation to its environment, and the premise
that such a pleasure cannot be felt without a recog-
Isn’t it tragic that the self-named only possible philos- nition of the application of a relevant concept to
ophy should end up by taking from our sentiment all the object. Herder argues for this by going through
concepts, from the judgment of taste all grounds for a series of cases, precisely the kinds of particular
judgment, from the arts of the beautiful all purpose, and examples that he accuses Kant of neglecting. First
transforming these arts into a short or long, boring ape- he considers figures (Gestalten), then colors and
like play, that critique into a universally valid, dictatorial tones, and then a series of kinds of natural things,
sentence without ground and cause? Critique and philos- ranging from nonliving stones and crystals to living
ophy are thereby at an end.40 flowers to human beings themselves. In all these
cases, he argues, we respond to a recognition of
In the body of the text, Herder argues both gen- the character of a thing and its relation to its en-
erally that all responses to objects, feeling and sen- vironment that is necessarily mediated by our ap-
timent as well as judgment, are accompanied with plication of a concept to it. For example, he argues
a concept of the object, and more specifically that that a child’s pleasure in a colorful pebble and a
our pleasure in beautiful objects is always a plea- mineralogist’s pleasure in stones and crystals are
sure in a sensed or felt recognition of their adap- not different in kind, but only in degree, that con-
tation to their environment, whether natural or cepts lie at the basis of all these pleasures, and that
artificial, that is impossible without the applica- “each of these concepts contains something pur-
tion of a concept to the object. Herder launches posive, for the apparent excellence or perfection
his general attack immediately following his cri- of the thing in a harmonious relation to the per-
tique of Kant’s first moment. Kant’s second mo- ceiver.”43 “The beauty of flowers,” further, “is thus
ment, Herder says, asserts that the “beautiful is (to stay with our language) the maximum of their
what pleases without a concept,” and the third particular existence and well-being [Daseins und
speaks of a “[f]orm of purposiveness without rep- Wohlseins]; they are beautiful to us, if our feeling
resentation of an end.” In Herder’s view, however, appropriates this maximum to itself harmoniously
“[t]hat something could please without a concept, and gladly. As with flowers, so with trees.”44 He
362 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

goes on to argue that we find animals beautiful world of good order and good form [Wohlordnung und
when we find them “in a way that is intuitable [an- Wohlgestalt], where all results of the laws of nature in
schaulich] for us, to be gifted with an undamaged gentle forms reveal to us as it were a band of rest and
natural perfection, to live happily, harmoniously motion, an elastic-effective constancy of things, in short
with themselves in their particular way.”45 Finally, beauty as the bodily expression of a corporeal perfection
a human being is found to be beautiful “when he that is harmonious both within itself and to our feeling?
shows himself in his figure and in his gestures as . . . Our sense feels this; we enjoy the fruits of this har-
active to whomever may perceive him.”46 All these monious nexus of order; everything disagreeable and re-
perceptions, Herder argues, depend on perceiving pulsive, all suffering makes us attentive to it even against
the object through or under an appropriate con- our will.48
cept, indeed a concept of its purpose, whether that
is the concept of a child or an expert. The key idea here is not that we take pleasure
in the direct consumption of the fruits of a har-
The result of our conversation is therefore this, that monious nature, but that there is a kind of reso-
without concepts and the representation of an end the nance between harmony and well-being in nature
word[s] beautiful and beauty are never in place. The flat- and our own sense of well-being: the perception of
ter the concept of the thing that we use is, the more harmony in nature makes our own being feel well-
childish it is called. The more essential it is, therefore ordered, just as the perception of disharmony in
the more accurate is our concept of its beauty. To think nature inevitably although painfully attracts our
of a sum of properties of the object without the object, attention. Herder uses physical language, suggest-
i.e., to think of beauty without everything beautiful, is a ing strings vibrating in harmony with each other,
dream; a feeling without any concept an illusion; and a a page later:
philosophy which by its own account is built upon such
an illusion is the most concept- and purposeless that has The being or the constancy of a thing depends upon its ac-
ever presumed to this name.47 tive forces being in equilibrium, hence on its being within
limits. Motion and rest constitute a maximum in it, and in
Before we consider whether this is a fair objec- several members or aspects several maxima, exponents
tion to Kant, more generally whether there is as of its constancy. If this confirmation to an enduring whole
much distance between Kant’s views and Herder’s is palpably sensible [sinnlich empfindbar] to us, and if
as Herder himself believes, let us ask why Herder this found maximum is harmonious with my own feel-
thinks such perception of an object’s essence and ing, then the constancy of thing, as such, is agreeable to
its well-being in its environment is so pleasing to us us; if not, then it is ugly, fearsome, repulsive. The self-
and so important for our own sense of well-being. constancy, i.e., the well-being of the thing thus stands in
The answer to this question is what we might relation to my own well-being, whether as friend or foe.49
call a harmonic or sympathetic theory of the con-
nection between pleasure in well-being and truth: This is the underlying vision of Herder’s aes-
Herder thinks that the perception of true harmony thetics: our feeling of beauty does not arise from
and well-being in the things around us generates a a free play with forms that might be triggered by
parallel harmony and feeling of it in ourselves. He something in the objective world but is not con-
expounds this vision, which is the basis for his en- strained by it; rather, the feeling of beauty is a sub-
tire argument, at a number of places in Kalligone; jective response to the perception of objective har-
we can take a few examples from his initial discus- mony, a subjective feeling of well-being triggered
sion of the agreeable. For example, he describes by empathy with the well-being of other things in
our perception of a beautiful tree: the world. Let us now see if the difference between
this vision and Kant’s is as insuperable as Herder
This tree, so upright in its growth, in its branches and supposes.
twigs so varied and yet so harmoniously bowed—

In the structure and outline of its leaves, blossoms, and


iii. closing the gap between kant and herder
fruits so manifold and yet so harmonious with itself.

From the highest to the lowest, from palm tree to moss, In this section, I argue that on three central points
to mold, to lichen. May we not rejoice that we live in a the differences between Kant and Herder are not
Guyer Free Play and True Well-Being: Herder’s Critique of Kant’s Aesthetics 363

quite as great as the latter supposed. First, I sug- free play and the feeling of life when he describes
gest that Kant himself interprets the feeling of the the condition of the imagination and understand-
free play of the cognitive powers in aesthetic ex- ing as one of the “animation” (Belebung) of both
perience as a feeling of life, and thus that at the faculties.51 This is still quite gnomic, though, and
deepest level his conception of the source of aes- it would not have been unreasonable of Herder
thetic pleasure is not that different from Herder’s. not to have paid much attention to it. However, in
Second, I argue that while Kant begins his anal- his lectures on anthropology—which, to be sure,
ysis with the simplest case of the free judgment he began offering only in 1772–1773, a decade af-
of natural beauty, which is supposedly not depen- ter Herder had studied with him—Kant makes the
dent on our conceptualization of its object, as he connection between the free play of the faculties
complicates his analysis of aesthetic experiences to and the feeling of life clear and central to his aes-
include the cases of the adherent beauty of works thetic theory, and indeed to his moral theory as
of nature as well as of human art in the general well. In the Friedländer lectures of 1775–1776, for
sense and of fine art in particular, he clearly rec- example, Kant argues that “[g]ratification or plea-
ognizes the role of conceptualization in our re- sure is the feeling of the promotion of life,” in-
sponse to the work, and in the case of art, in the deed that life itself “is the consciousness of a free
production as the well the reception of the work, and regular play of all the powers and faculties of
and transforms his conception of free play with human beings.” He equates the free play of our
the mere form of an object into a conception of powers and faculties with their unhindered activ-
felt harmony between the form and the concept ity, and thus finds the ultimate source of all plea-
of the object that is not so different from Herder’s sure in the unhindered activity of our powers: “The
conception of the harmony in a beautiful object. play of the powers of the mind [Gemüths Kräfte]
Finally, I argue that when Kant complicates his must be strongly alive and free if it is to animate.
initial conception of the disinterestedness of aes- Intellectual pleasure consists in the consciousness
thetic judgment to take account of our intellectual of the use of freedom in accordance with rules.
interest in the existence of natural beauty, he rec- Freedom is the greatest life of the human being,
ognizes that our experience of beauty is an experi- through which he exercises his activity without
ence of well-being and being at home in the world hindrance.”52 Indeed, Kant completes this discus-
that is not unrelated to Herder’s conception of our sion, which opens his lectures on the second part of
experience of beauty, although as Kant’s terminol- psychology, on the faculties of approval and disap-
ogy suggests, his conception of this interest may re- proval with the remark that “[a]ll gratifications are
main more intellectual and moralistic than Herder related to life. Life, however, is a unity, and in so
himself would prefer. far as all gratifications aim at this, they are all ho-
First, then, the feeling of life: Kant mentions mogeneous, let the sources from which they spring
the feeling of life explicitly only twice in the third be what they are.”53 Herder could have included
Critique, each time suggesting that all feelings of these sentences in the footnote from Kalligone in
pleasure or displeasure are related to the subject’s which he objects to Kant’s supposedly complete
feeling of life, indeed that representations please separation of the beautiful from the agreeable and
or displease because of how they affect the feeling the good.54
of life.50 These remarks leave any connection be- To be sure, in the passages from the Friedländer
tween the free play of the cognitive powers and the lectures thus far quoted, Kant connects “activity
feeling of life completely unexplained. In the cen- without hindrance” with “the use of freedom in
tral passage on the free play of the faculties, which accordance with rules,” and says that he is explain-
he calls the “key to the critique of taste,” how- ing “the intellectual pleasure that tends toward the
ever, in which he argues that only the explanation moral.”55 It might therefore be thought that this
of the experience of beauty as due to the free play connection between life and the unhindered activ-
of imagination and understanding stimulated by a ity of our mental powers has nothing to do with the
given representation can justify the claim of the case of aesthetic pleasure. However, in his earlier
judgment of taste to be disinterested, not based discussion of “the concept of the poet and of the
on a concept, and yet universally and necessar- art of poetry” in these lectures, Kant uses the same
ily valid, Kant does suggest a connection between language.
364 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

The harmonious play of thoughts and sentiments which Herder thought inadequate. I suggest that
[Empfindungen] is the poem. The play of thoughts and although Herder was in many ways a penetrat-
sentiments is the correspondence [Übereinstimmung] of ing reader of Kant, he was not attentive to Kant’s
subjective laws: if the thoughts correspond with my sub- expository method in the “Critique of the Aes-
ject then that is a play thereof. Second, it is to be observed thetic Power of Judgment,” which starts by an-
of the thoughts that they stand in relation to the object, alyzing only the simplest case of aesthetic judg-
and the thoughts must be true, and that the course of ment, that of the free judgment of natural beauty,
thoughts must correspond with the nature of the mental but then progressively complicates the analysis
powers, thus with the subject and thus the succession of of aesthetic experience and judgment by showing
thoughts with the powers of the mind.56 precisely that in more complicated cases concepts
can enter into our experience without undermin-
In the case of the experience of poetry, the feel- ing what makes it distinctively aesthetic. Kant’s
ing of the free play and unhindered activity of the strategy is to start with this simplest case, in which
mental powers is consistent with the existence of concepts are not supposed to be involved at all,
laws for both the contents of the poetry and the so that he can isolate the free play of mental pow-
workings of the mind. Here, Kant clearly intends ers as that which is essential to aesthetic experi-
his explanation of our pleasure in poetry to be ence, and then to find the free play of mental pow-
a special case of his general explanation of plea- ers even in cases of aesthetic experience in which
sure as the feeling of free play, which is nothing concepts are clearly and heavily involved, such as
less than the feeling of life itself. I suggest that the experience of works of fine art. In this regard,
this connection between free play and the feel- Kant’s expository method in the third Critique is
ing of life was a constant in Kant’s thought. To similar to his method in moral philosophy. In the
be sure, in his mature theory of the free play of Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals, Kant
imagination and understanding he will emphasize starts with cases where moral motivation is most
that this harmony cannot manifest itself in the ap- evident, such as cases of good will in the absence
plication of determinate laws to beautiful objects, of all favorable inclination, like the case of the
but only in a general sense of the lawfulness of the miserable philanthropist, in order to identify the
forms designed or apprehended by the imagina- fundamental principle of morality, but when he
tion.57 But this does not change the basic point that develops the theory of the highest good in the Cri-
Kant thought that the feeling of pleasure in the tique of Practical Reason and his theory of virtues
free play of the mental powers is a feeling of free, in the Metaphysics of Morals, he shows how in fact
unhindered life itself. In this regard, Herder’s the- the purity of moral motivation is consistent with
ory is not as different from Kant’s as he thought, the presence and, indeed, cultivation of various
though I should add that there does remain a dif- inclinations and with an interest in happiness, al-
ference between Herder’s and Kant’s conceptions though, of course, not merely one’s own happiness
of the role of the imagination in generating this but universal, unselfish happiness.
feeling of life: for Herder, as we saw, the subjec- On Kant’s account, our judgments of adherent
tive faculty of the imagination is like a string that beauty, artistic beauty, and, for that matter, the
vibrates in harmony with some objective harmony sublime can all be regarded as aesthetic judgments
outside itself, while for Kant the imagination, cer- that are more complicated than the initial case of
tainly of the artist but even of the spectator, is a the pure judgment of natural beauty, but that re-
more creative faculty that creates its own forms tain what Kant has inferred from his analysis of
in lawful harmony with the understanding’s gen- the latter is essential to all aesthetic experiences,
eral requirement of unity, and therefore is actively namely, a free play of cognitive capacities. I will
rather than passively responsible for the feeling of not discuss the sublime, although as I mentioned
life. Nevertheless, both theories certainly suppose earlier, Kalligone contains a criticism of Kant’s ac-
that pleasure arises from the feeling of free yet count of that, too. So I begin with adherent beauty.
harmonious activity and that objects of aesthetic Kant’s discussion of that topic is short—just one
pleasure must in some way stimulate this feeling section—and problematic. The problem is that he
of life. says that adherent beauty presupposes a concept
I turn now to the question of the role of concepts of what the object ought to be and “the perfection
in Kant’s account of our experience of beauty, of the object in accordance with it,” although the
Guyer Free Play and True Well-Being: Herder’s Critique of Kant’s Aesthetics 365

preceding section of the “Analytic of the Beau- argues that a work of fine art must be the prod-
tiful” has just asserted that beauty “is entirely uct of intentional human activity, thus must always
independent of the representation of the good, have “a determinate intention of producing some-
since the latter presupposes an objective purpo- thing,” and yet that what it aims to produce must
siveness,” but that “by beauty, as a formal sub- be nothing other than a free and pleasurable play
jective purposiveness, there is not conceived any of the faculties of mind that is not constrained by
perfection of the object.”58 If the judgment of ad- a determinate concept. Kant initially tries to re-
herent beauty presupposes a concept of what an solve this apparent paradox by saying that “[i]n
object ought to be and what it takes for it to be the product of art one must be aware that it is art,
perfect, how can it be a judgment of beauty at all? and not nature; yet the purposiveness of its form
The answer to this puzzle, I suggest, and have ar- must still seem to be as free from all constraint
gued elsewhere, is that the experience of adherent by arbitrary rules as it were a mere product of na-
beauty is a genuinely aesthetic experience because ture.”60 This makes it sound as if in the experience
the concept of the perfection of the object never- of a work of art we must somehow both be aware
theless leaves room for the free play of the imagi- of and yet suppress our recognition of its artifactu-
nation and understanding in response to the form ality and therefore intentionality, or even as if the
of the object, or even enters into the free play of work of art must induce that state in us, deceiv-
the mental powers with the form, but does not fully ing us about its own intentionality. Kant’s theory
determine the response to the object.59 For exam- of genius and of aesthetic ideas as the characteris-
ple, our conception of the proper floor plan for a tic product of genius immediately supersedes this
cathedral limits what forms we can find acceptable initial impression, however. For what Kant argues
for such a building, but does not fully determine here is precisely that a work of art must have a
them, and a cathedral that we find beautiful is one conceptual content or leading idea, but that what
whose floor plan and other mandatory features makes it a successful work of art is the way this
leave room for the free play of our mental powers idea is expressed in a “presentation . . . which by
with its form or can even become part of the mate- itself stimulates so much thinking that it can never
rial with which the imagination and understanding be grasped in a determinate concept, hence which
play, when we feel that there is a harmony between aesthetically enlarges the concept itself in an un-
these mandatory features of the building and the bounded way”; “in this case the imagination is
other features that contribute to our aesthetic ex- creative, and sets the faculty of intellectual ideas
perience of it, but a harmony that cannot itself be (reason) into motion, that is, at the instigation of
derived from any rule. In fact, in his brief account a representation it gives more to think about than
of adherent beauty, Kant suggests three different can be grasped and made distinct in it (although it
ways in which the concept of the object and its pur- does, to be sure, belong to the concept of the ob-
pose can affect our aesthetic response to the ob- ject).”61 In other words, a work of art expresses a
ject: it can merely constrain what forms we could concept, but that concept does not fully determine
find beautiful in the object without positively con- our experience of the object; rather, it enters into a
tributing to our experience of beauty; the object’s free play of our cognitive powers—here clearly in-
satisfaction of the conditions of its objective pur- cluding the faculty of reason as well as imagination
posiveness could be the source of a pleasure that and understanding—that cannot be grasped by a
is additional to our purely aesthetic pleasure in it; determinate concept, or be seen as determined by
or we could feel a harmony between the object’s that concept. For this reason, the experience of
objective purposiveness and all the rest of its fea- art is a genuinely aesthetic experience although it
tures that gives rise to a single experience of free is not a “pure” aesthetic experience like the sim-
play and a single feeling of its beauty. All these ple experience of a beautiful form in nature that
would be genuinely aesthetic experiences. Kant initially analyzed and through which he dis-
Concepts of the object also play a central role covered the role of the free play of the faculties in
in Kant’s theory of fine art, which is expounded in all aesthetic experience.
three stages, the first his analysis of the concept of How does this account of Kant’s concepts of
fine art, the second his theory of genius and aes- adherent and artistic beauty narrow the gap be-
thetic ideas, and the third his classification of the tween Herder and himself? Herder seems to sug-
fine arts. In the first stage of his exposition, Kant gest that all experiences of beauty presuppose a
366 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

concept of what their objects ought to be and how that pleasure is a ground “for producing its ob-
they ought to fit into their natural or human envi- ject.”62 There are technical reasons why Kant does
ronment, and Kant would not concede that point. not want to speak here of an interest in the con-
But, although Kant does not say this explicitly, it tinuation of pleasure and/or the production of its
would seem that the pure case of the experience of object, but it is certainly reasonable to say that on
natural beauty that he initially analyzes is only a Kant’s own account any pleasure, including even
small part of our experience of beauty, and that the purest pleasure in beauty, is accompanied with
the experiences of adherent beauty and artistic some form of attachment to the possibility of its
beauty actually comprise a very large part of our own continued and future experience, and there-
aesthetic experience. If this is so, then on Kant’s fore ordinarily to the availability of the objects that
own view a large number of our actual cases of trigger that pleasure.63
aesthetic experience involve a free play between Further, Kant explicitly argues that the prop-
the concepts of, or in, their objects and the rest erly aesthetic pleasure in beautiful objects enters
of the form and attributes of those objects, a play into combination with interests, also properly so
that is free because it involves the relevant concept called, in the existence of those objects. Under the
but is not determined by that concept functioning rubric of the “empirical interest” in the beauti-
as a rule; and this, I suggest, brings Kant’s phe- ful, he argues that there are societal reasons for
nomenology and psychology of aesthetic experi- taking interest in the availability and possession
ence close to Herder’s. For the heart of Herder’s of beautiful objects; and although he denies that
account of beauty is that our feeling “appropri- there is any a priori relation of these reasons to
ates” itself to the concept of the object’s perfec- the experience of beauty, this is not to deny the
tion that he claims is essential to the experience of existence of such attachments.64 Under the rubric
beauty “harmoniously and gladly.” I interpret this of the “intellectual interest in the beautiful,” Kant
to mean that for Herder, as for Kant, the concept describes a reason for attachment to the beautiful
of the perfection achieved by a beautiful object is that is apparently supposed to be a priori, namely,
more like a necessary than a sufficient condition that the existence of beauty is a “trace” or “sign”
for our experience of its beauty, and that for the that nature is amenable to the satisfaction of our
latter we must also have an experience of a free moral interests.65 Kant’s conception of an intel-
harmony of the object in all its particularity with lectual interest in the beautiful does not seem en-
its purpose, thus a harmony that cannot itself be tirely remote from Herder’s view that our sense
derived from any mere concept of the object. of well-being in an object is accompanied with a
Finally, the most deeply felt and perhaps the corresponding sense of our own well-being, which
deepest of Herder’s criticisms of Kant is his attack I have suggested is the core of Herder’s mature
on the disinterestedness of aesthetic judgment, his aesthetic theory, although there are two key dif-
insistence that there is a continuum rather than ferences. For one, Herder insists on a recognition
discontinuity between our responses to the agree- of an objective well-being to which our subjective
able, the beautiful, and the good. I suggest that feeling of well-being is a response, while for Kant
on the matter of disinterestedness, too, Kant be- well-being is always subjective, that is, our own,
gins with a simple statement of a position that and the satisfaction of our aesthetic aims and of
then turns out to be more complicated than it our moral aims may be parallel, but both are sub-
initially appears. There can be no question that jective. Our aesthetic pleasure in natural beauty
Kant wants to distinguish genuinely aesthetic ex- is a sign of the possibility of our moral well-being
perience from merely physiological gratification in nature, not a response to a harmony in nature
of the senses, from the approval of utility, or from that has nothing to do with us. Second, Kant clearly
moral approval, and that he does this by saying wants to keep the connection between the satisfac-
that aesthetic judgment neither presupposes nor tion of our aesthetic aims and the satisfaction of
gives rise to any interest in the existence of its our moral interests separate although connected,
object. But numerous factors complicate this pic- thus not collapsing aesthetic pleasure into moral
ture. First, Kant always defines pleasure as a state satisfaction and, further, Kant seems to suggest
of mind that is connected with a disposition to- that a sound moral interest in nature’s amenability
ward its own continuation, and in the first draft to our objectives is a condition of the intellectual
of the introduction to the third Critique he adds but aesthetic interest in the existence of (natural)
Guyer Free Play and True Well-Being: Herder’s Critique of Kant’s Aesthetics 367

beauty. From Herder’s point of view, that might 7. Herder, Viertes Kritisches Wäldchen, in Herder,
seem to be an excessive moralization of an inter- Werke, vol. 2 of Schriften zur Ästhetik und Literatur 1767–
1781, ed. Günter Grimm (Frankfurt am Main: Deutscher
est in the beautiful that should be entirely natu-
Klassiker Verlag, 1993), pp. 262–263, both current and fol-
ral, although from Kant’s point of view Herder’s lowing quote. In the first extract, I translated Herder’s
insistence on the continuity of the beautiful and Homischen as “Kamesian” since Henry Home is now usu-
the good might actually run the risk of an exces- ally referred to by his judicial title, Lord Kames. The 1764
sive moralization of aesthetic experience. So no work of Kant to which I refer in this paragraph is the prize
essay “Enquiry concerning the Distinctness of the Principles
doubt there are differences between them, but it of Natural Theology and Morality.”
is misleading of Herder to suggest that Kant simply 8. See Kant, “Enquiry concerning the Distinctness of
fails to recognize that we have a real attachment to the Principles of Natural Theology and Morality,” especially
the interest in the beautiful. Kant does recognize Second Reflection, 2:283–286, in Immanuel Kant, Theoret-
ical Philosophy, 1755–1770, ed. David Walford (Cambridge
that, but wants to keep that attachment somewhat
University Press, 1992), pp. 256–259.
complicated and indirect in order to avoid the 9. The second and third of the Groves, not reprinted
risk of an excessive moralization of the aesthetic in the modern edition of Herder, are a polemic against the
but at the same time, I might suggest, also avoid Leipzig rhetorician and philologist Christian Adolph Klotz.
the risk of an excessive aestheticization of the 10. Winckelmann, Reflections on the Painting and
Sculpture of the Greeks, trans. Henry Fusseli (London: A.
moral. Millar, 1765), p. 30.
I conclude, then, that while there is considerably 11. That visual arts are confined to the representation
more common ground between Kant and Herder of a single moment of action is a premise that goes back at
than might initially appear, and certainly than ap- least to Jean-Baptiste Du Bos’s Critical Reflections on Poetry,
Painting, and Music (1719), trans. Thomas Nugent (London:
peared to Herder in 1800, there is also some good
John Nourse, 1748), vol. I, pp. 71–72.
reason for preserving Kant’s sense of the indirect- 12. Herder, first Grove, p. 195.
ness and complexity of the relation between the 13. Herder, first Grove, pp. 195–196.
aesthetic and the moral rather than making the 14. Herder, fourth Grove, p. 291n.
connection as direct and simple as Herder risks 15. Again a well-established idea in the eighteenth cen-
tury; see Joseph Addison, Spectator 411 (June 21, 1712);
doing. Henry Home, Lord Kames, Elements of Criticism, (1762),
ed. Peter Jones (Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, [1762] 2005),
PAUL GUYER vol. I, pp. 141–142.
16. Herder, fourth Grove, pp. 289–290.
Department of Philosophy 17. Herder, Sculpture, pp. 39–41.
University of Pennsylvania 18. See Herder, Sculpture, pp. 33–38.
Philadelphia, Pennsylvania 19104 19. Herder, fourth Grove, p. 314.
20. Herder, Kalligone, pp. 644, 647.
internet: pguyer@nous.phil.upenn.edu 21. Herder, Kalligone, pp. 653–654.
22. Herder, Kalligone, pp. 747–748.
23. See Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgment, Intro-
1. Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten, Meditationes duction, § III, 5:177. Citations from Kant will use the volume
philosophicae de nonnullis ad poema pertinentibus/Philoso- and page number from Kant’s gesammelte Schriften, ed. the
phische Betrachtungen über einige Bedingungen des Ge- Royal Prussian (later German, then Berlin-Brandenburg)
dichtes, ed. Heinz Paetzold (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, Academy of Sciences (Berlin: Georg Reimer, later Wal-
1983), §CXVI, pp. 86–87. ter de Gruyter, 1900–). Translations will be from Immanuel
2. See Aristotle, Poetics, ch. 9, 1451a37–1451b10. Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgment, ed. Paul Guyer,
3. See Johann Georg Sulzer, Allgemeine Theorie der trans. Paul Guyer and Eric Matthews (Cambridge Univer-
schönen Künste, expanded 2nd ed., four vols. (Leipzig: sity Press, 2000).
Weidmann, 1792–1794), “Geschmack,” vol. II, p. 371, and 24. Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgment, Introduc-
“Schön (Schöne Künste),” vol. IV, p. 307. tion, § III, 5:177.
4. Johann Gottfried Herder, Kalligone, in Johann 25. Herder, Kalligone, pp. 882–883.
Gottfried Herder, Werke, ed. Günter Arnold et al., vol. 8 of 26. Herder, Kalligone, pp. 893–894.
Schriften zu Literatur und Philosophie 1792–1800, ed. Hans 27. Herder, Kalligone, pp. 954–955.
Dietrich Irmscher (Frankfurt am Main: Deutscher Klassiker 28. See Herder, Kalligone, pp. 908–912.
Verlag, 1998), p. 660. 29. The referent of Herder’s ‘both’ is unclear; he could
5. Johann Gottfried Herder, Sculpture: Some Obser- be referring to Kant’s division of the verbal arts into poetry
vations on Shape and Form from Pygmalion’s Creative and oratory. Herder, Kalligone, p. 939.
Dream, trans. Jason Gaiger (University of Chicago Press, 30. Herder, Kalligone, p. 944.
2002). 31. Herder, fourth Grove, p. 291.
6. Friedrich Just Riedel, Theorie der schönen Künste 32. Herder, Kalligone, p. 665.
und Wissenschaften (Jena: Cuno, 1767). 33. Herder, Kalligone, p. 667.
368 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

34. Herder, Kalligone, p. 667. 56. Kant, Vorlesungen über Anthropologie, pp. 525–526.
35. Herder, Kalligone, p. 668. 57. Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgment, General
36. Herder, Kalligone, pp. 672–673n. Remark on the first section of the Analytic, following § 22,
37. Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgment, § 5, 5:209 5:240–241.
38. Herder, Kalligone, p. 730. 58. Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgment, § 16, 5:229;
39. See Anthony Ashley Cooper, Third Earl of Shaftes- § 15, 5:226, 228.
bury, “Sensus Communis,” in Characteristicks of Men, Man- 59. Paul Guyer, “Beauty and Utility in Eighteenth-
ners, Opinions, Times, ed. Philip Ayres (Oxford: Clarendon Century Aesthetics,” Eighteenth-Century Studies 35 (2002):
Press, 1999), vol. I, p. 55. 439–453, and “Free and Adherent Beauty: A Modest Pro-
40. Herder, Kalligone, p. 648. posal,” The British Journal of Aesthetics 42 (2002): 357–366,
41. Herder, Kalligone, p. 675. both reprinted in Paul Guyer, Values of Beauty: Histori-
42. Herder, Kalligone, p. 688. cal Essays in Aesthetics (Cambridge University Press, 2005),
43. Herder, Kalligone, pp. 710–711. pp. 110–140.
44. Herder, Kalligone, p. 712. 60. Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgment, § 45, 5:306.
45. Herder, Kalligone, p. 719. 61. Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgment, § 49, 5:315.
46. Herder, Kalligone, p. 721. 62. First Introduction to the Critique of the Power of
47. Herder, Kalligone, p. 722. Judgment, § VIII, 20:230–231.
48. Herder, Kalligone, pp. 687–688. 63. On the reasons why Kant does not want to speak here
49. Herder, Kalligone, pp. 688–689. of an interest in the continuation of pleasure and/or the pro-
50. Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgment, § 1, 5:204, duction of its object, see Paul Guyer, “Disinterestedness and
and General Remark following § 29, 5:270. Desire in Kant’s Aesthetics,” The Journal of Aesthetics and
51. Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgment, § 9, 5:219. Art Criticism 36 (1978): 449–460, reprinted in Perspectives
52. Kant, Vorlesungen über Anthropologie, pp. 559–560. on Kant, ed. Ruth Chadwick and Clive Cazeaux (London:
53. Kant, Vorlesungen über Anthropologie, p. 561. Routledge, 1992), vol. 4, pp. 232–248.
54. Herder, Kalligone, pp. 672–673. 64. Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgment, § 41, 5:297.
55. Kant, Vorlesungen über Anthropologie, p. 560. 65. Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgment, § 42, 5:300.

You might also like