You are on page 1of 7

786312

research-article2018
QIXXXX10.1177/1077800418786312Qualitative InquiryRobinson and Kutner

Original Article - Graduate Student


Qualitative Inquiry

Spinoza and the Affective Turn: A Return


1­–7
© The Author(s) 2018
Reprints and permissions:
to the Philosophical Origins of Affect sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav
DOI: 10.1177/1077800418786312
https://doi.org/10.1177/1077800418786312
journals.sagepub.com/home/qix

Bradley Robinson1 and Mel Kutner1

Abstract
In their introduction to a recent special issue of Qualitative Inquiry, Taguchi and St. Pierre observed that Foucault’s
notion of “fruitful disorientation” seemed to circulate throughout the included articles. Embracing this fruitfully
disorienting impulse, the authors of this article provide a detailed reading of Baruch Spinoza’s ontological concept
of affect as he articulated it in the Ethics. Through this return, the authors consider the implications of affect for
qualitative and postqualitative inquiry and offer an example of how a return to the philosophical origins of a theory can
produce new lines of thinking and inquiry.

Keywords
affect theory, Spinoza, postqualitative inquiry

In their introduction to a recent special issue of Qualitative Megan Boler succinctly captured a core tension regarding
Inquiry focused on concept as method, Taguchi and St. the use of Spinozan affect in education:
Pierre (2017) observed that Foucault’s notion of “fruitful
disorientation” seemed to circulate throughout the included The affective turn has done us the major service of popularizing
articles. Scholars “who take up the idea of working with the study of emotion and affect. To date, however, this now
concept as method in inquiry,” they wrote, “will not think fashionable arena relies heavily on a couple of oft-cited
the same way about either concepts or how to use them as readings/uses of Spinoza, and thus a great deal of what counts
as “affect theory” is not even secondary but tertiary readings or
methods so they won’t ‘do’ the same things” (p. 644).
even further removed, from original sources. This also results in
Embracing this fruitfully disorienting impulse, in this arti- confusions such as presuming that the hypothesized “autonomy
cle we provide a detailed reading of Baruch Spinoza’s of affect” is a concept foundational to all “affect theory” or to
(1677/1996) ontological concept of affect as he articulated Spinoza’s philosophy (Boler & Zembylas, 2016, p. 22).
it in the Ethics. Through this return, we consider the impli-
cations of affect for qualitative and postqualitative inquiry We would like to emphasize two of Boler’s ideas. First,
(St. Pierre, 2011) and offer an example of how a return to she highlighted both the importance of Spinoza’s philoso-
the philosophical origins of a theory can produce new lines phy to affect theory and the dearth of direct engagement
of thinking and inquiry. with his work. Second, Boler mentioned both emotion and
The last decade or so of research in the social sciences affect as separate ideas that are invoked within the affective
has brought with it renewed attention to affect, and this turn, but she does not reduce either to one another. It is nota-
development has been a part of a larger shift in ontological ble that the volume’s title does not make this distinction,
orientations that emphasize immanence, indeterminacy, and which highlights how these concepts have been conflated
relationality à la Deleuze (1970/1988), Deleuze with with, or reduced to, one another as scholars have attempted
Guattari (1980/1987), and Barad (2007). And despite the to capture affect through research.
work of affect theorists such as Manning (2013), Massumi What is at stake when emotion and affect are conflated is
(2002), and Thrift (2004), questions continue to linger about the very notion of subjectivity. After all, the term emotion
the conceptual and ontological nature of affect itself. What implies the existence of a singular human subject who expe-
is it? What, if anything, can it be said to do? And, critically riences feelings that can be located, isolated, reflected on,
for qualitative researchers, how can it be accounted for?
Such questions are at the heart of the debate over effective 1
University of Georgia, Athens, USA
methodologies for studying affect in the field of educational
Corresponding Author:
research, as demonstrated in Zembylas and Schutz’s (2016)
Bradley Robinson, University of Georgia, 315 Aderhold Hall, 110
edited volume, Methodological Advances in Research on Carleton Street, Athens, GA 30602, USA.
Emotion and Education. In the volume’s second chapter, Email: t.brad.robinson@gmail.com
2 Qualitative Inquiry 00(0)

and measured. This emotion-experiencing subject is the through which posthuman affect becomes thinkable. We, of
Cartesian cogito—the I, the rational, essential self. In this course, recognize that our reading of Spinoza is not and
system of thought, affect can only be synonymous with cannot be functionally equivalent to reading the Ethics one-
human emotion, and researchers who attempt to map a self—which we highly recommend, by the way—but we
Spinozan conception of affect onto this system of thought still hope that our description will help readers think differ-
are likely to experience unfruitful disorientation. A concep- ently about affect theory in qualitative and postqualitative
tion of affect derived from Spinoza’s work, is only think- inquiry.
able in a relational ontological arrangement in which affect
emerges as necessarily entangled with memories and mate- The Origins of Affect in Spinoza’s
rials, sensations and spaces. This Spinozan conception of Ethics
affect subsumes emotion and cannot be reduced to specific
feelings of happiness or sorrow. If we were forced to use the Written in the mid-17th century, Spinoza’s Ethics is a chal-
word “emotion,” we might say that affect is, in this way, lenging read for a number of reasons. First, the text is con-
posthuman emotion. ceptually dense, and because Spinoza is largely cutting
These are difficult concepts to wrap one’s head around, from whole cloth, many of those dense concepts are new to
and in response, some may critique Spinozan affect’s onto- readers (e.g., adequate and inadequate ideas). Second,
logical assumptions, claiming that any such notion of affect Spinoza’s argument takes the form of a geometric proof
must necessarily escape discursive capture and would with definitions, axioms, postulates, propositions, and dem-
therefore be irrelevant and inaccessible to inquiry. Such onstrations—a rhetorical move, perhaps, intended to ele-
charges, we argue, may result from misconceptions over vate his philosophy to the status of Euclidean geometry. For
what posthuman subjectivity is. Crucially, posthuman sub- readers, however, Spinoza’s geometric method challenges
jectivity is not the denial of subjective experience—yes, us to track all the definitions etcetera, which he references
you are interacting with this text right now—but rather it by parenthetical abbreviations throughout the text to syn-
acknowledges the dispersal of subjectivity across indeter- thesize various components of his broader argument. Third,
minate assemblages of human and nonhuman material—no, as it was originally written in Latin—yet another rhetorical
it is not only you intra-acting with this text right now. As move, likely—readers of English translations must linger in
Deleuze and Guattari (1980/1987) noted, “There is no lon- the uncertainty inherent to translated texts.
ger a tripartite division between the field of reality (the Reading the Ethics, we found it useful to entangle our
world) and a field of representation (the book) and a field of own experiences with the text, to lodge ourselves in its
subjectivity (the author)” (p. 23). In this way, the “I” is a obtuse angles, and then to work ourselves out of them. For
production, not simply a producer. Such posthuman orienta- example, Brad found it useful to think about his experience
tions work not to deny subjective experiences, or the expe- moving to Georgia, where the heat of the sun led him to
rience of subjectivity, but rather to argue that they are suspect it might actually be closer to the earth than it was in
produced by dispersed and dynamic, not fixed and static, his previous home of North Carolina. Indeed, Spinoza used
affective flows. In other words, to move past the cogito is such an example in the Ethics to demonstrate his conception
not to reject the existence of emotion; instead, such a move of inadequate ideas:
suggests that emotions never spring from within a body but
are produced through a circulating relationality between Similarly, when we look at the sun, we imagine it as about two
and among bodies. This is affect—dispersed subjectivity, hundred feet away from us, an error which does not consist
simply in this imagining, but in the fact that while we imagine
posthuman emotion so diffuse it travels through crowds, up
it this way, we are ignorant of its true distance and of the cause
mountains, and down spines. of this imagining. For even if we later come to know it is more
This conception of affect only became thinkable for us than six hundred diameters of the earth away from us, we
after deep engagement and struggle with the Ethics, in nevertheless imagine it as near. For we imagine the sun so near
which Spinoza articulates his notion of affect and its role in not because we do not know its true distance, but because an
his overall ontological arrangement. As Boler suggested in affection of our body involves the essence of the sun insofar as
her interview with Zembylas, however, few scholars work- our body is affected by the sun. (p. 59)
ing with affect theory appear to have engaged with Spinoza’s
texts directly, even if through translations. And it seems to In other words, that the sun may have seemed—to Brad,
us that to the extent Spinoza’s name has been invoked in at least—closer to the earth in Georgia than in North
affect theory scholarship, it is often in reference to Carolina was due to the intensity of its effects on his body
Deleuze’s, and Deleuze with Guattari’s, invocations of him. to the extent that his mind understood them. Indeed, for
In the sections that follow, we aim to move the discussion Spinoza, at the moment in time when Brad’s body experi-
around affect theory closer to its primary source by provid- enced an intensity leading him to imagine something false,
ing a description of the Spinozan ontological framework he was blind to the fact that the sun is, according to Spinoza,
Robinson and Kutner 3

around 600 diameters away from the earth. Despite Brad’s be easy to align Spinoza’s thought and extension with
knowledge that the sun is not actually any closer to the earth Descartes’s mind and body. To do so, however, would be to
in Georgia, it felt to him that way, Spinoza explained, conflate two incommensurable ontological frameworks.
“because an affection of [his] body involves the essence of For his part, Spinoza insisted that “the thinking substance
the sun insofar as [his] body was affected by the sun” (p. and the extended substance are one and the same substance,
54). What Brad was left with, then, were what Spinoza which is now comprehended under this attribute, now under
called inadequate ideas of both the sun and his body. But that” (p. 35). In fruitfully disorienting terms, Spinoza’s
what is an inadequate idea? What would an adequate idea notions of mind and body are different, yet the same. To
look like? What does Spinoza mean by affection? Finally, think posthuman subjectivity, then, it is useful to reckon
what does all this have to do with affect theory? To answer with the implications of both Spinoza’s substance and his
these questions, one must first come to some understanding distinction between thought-as-substance and extension-as-
of Spinoza’s ontology. And, it all comes from substance. substance. If it is the case that posthuman subjectivity is
dispersed and dynamic, not localized and static, one can see
how Spinoza’s conception of substance allowed him to lay
Substance
out a plane of immanence upon which posthuman subjec-
For Spinoza, substance is “that whose concept does not tivity could circulate and unfold.
require the concept of another thing, from which it must be
formed” (p. 1). Substance, then, is that which cannot be
divided and which constitutes all things which can be
Mode
divided. The immanence of substance is fundamental to Spinoza populated his plane with many other concepts,
Spinoza’s ontological monism, and it stands in contrast to including that of mode, a concept which allowed him to
Descartes’s conception of dual substances: mind and body. describe specific manifestations of substance-as-thought
Beginning from substance, Spinoza goes on to describe his and substance-as-extension. And it is worth repeating here
new, anti-Cartesian system of thought that is only thinkable that thought and extension are the only two attributes of
in monist terms. Consequently, we, the authors, must be substance the human intellect can comprehend. “By mode,”
careful in how we describe this system of thought, and our Spinoza wrote, “I understand the affections of substance, or
readers must be careful as well, making sure we all think that which is in another through which it is also conceived”
substance. (Perhaps this will not be too difficult, however, (p. 1). To understand this, it helps to understand first what
given the influence of quantum and particle physics on Spinoza meant by affection, or affectio in Latin. An affec-
modern conceptions of reality.) tion is a mode of substance—either one of thought or one of
A reader of the Ethics might object to our characteriza- extension—as it entangles with other modes of substance.
tion of Spinoza’s substance, arguing that he made it clear The term affection emphasizes how modes of thought
that God is immanent, that God is the true, infinite cause of encounter and co-constitute one another, and also how
all things. It is true that Spinoza used the word “God” modes of extension encounter and co-constitute one another.
throughout the Ethics, but he explained his unique concep- To return to Brad’s experience with the sun, when it occurred
tion of God in Part I, Proposition 11: “God, or a substance to him that the sun might be closer to the earth in Georgia,
consisting of infinite attributes, each of which expresses he was reckoning with the intensity of the relation between
eternal and infinite essence, necessarily exists” (p. 41). God his body and the sun, both of which are modes of extension,
is substance, and Substance is God. (Readers of the Ethics, and this interaction constitutes a relation of affection.
and of this article, may find it helpful to replace the word Although Spinoza collapsed this relation into the phrase
“God” with “substance” anytime they encounter it.) “affection of our body,” it is crucial to keep in mind the
Furthermore, substance is only understood by the intel- active, relational quality of affections. For Spinoza, this
lect through its attributes, or characteristics, and God’s infi- entangling of modes of substance was quite literal—the
nite intellect can comprehend infinite attributes of substance. sun’s substance entangled with the substance that is Brad’s
The human mind, however, can only comprehend two attri- body—and this relation of affection was so intense that he
butes of substance: thought and extension (i.e., matter). became blind to true causes and was momentarily tempted
Consequently, the infinite nature of substance always- to conclude that the sun may in fact be closer to Georgia.
already exceeds the human mind’s ability to apprehend it. The second half of Spinoza’s definition of mode, indeed
Thought is an attribute of substance that manifests only in the trickier half, defines mode as “that which is in another
the mind, whereas extension is an attribute of substance that through which it is also conceived” (p. 1). This paradoxical
manifests only in space, individuating bodies through rela- phrase may seem more obfuscating than clarifying, but it is
tions of “speed and slowness” (p. 41). It is in this division nevertheless important to understanding Spinoza’s concept
between two different attributes of the same substance that of mode. How can a mode be “in another”? Indeed, in
we, the authors, and our readers must be careful as it would another what? And how can a mode be “in another” and
4 Qualitative Inquiry 00(0)

“conceived” through it? Here, we offer two interpretations, remain inadequate so long as he remains a thinking thing.
each of which depends on how one understands “con- Yes, he can be reasonably sure there is a sun as a result of
ceived,” or concipitur in Latin. If “conceived” means the relations of affection between substantive bodies, but
“becomes,” then Spinoza was suggesting that modes exist his idea of both bodies is necessarily inadequate. Indeed,
within the same substance through which they come to be, Spinoza was not immune to such inadequate ideas himself,
an interpretation which highlights their entangled, co-con- as his reference to the sun’s distance from the earth (over
stitutive nature. Alternatively, or perhaps complementarily, 600 diameters of the earth, he claimed), while technically
if “conceived” means “comprehended” (i.e., understood), and minimally correct, understated the distance by approxi-
then Spinoza was suggesting that the processes by which mately 88,209,500 miles based on our calculations.
the mind experiences modes of thought and extension are
functions of relations of affection. Both interpretations
assume the immanence of substance, and we suggest that is
Adequate Ideas
the crucial takeaway. Spinoza’s modes are unique manifes- So far we have discussed the relations among Spinoza’s
tations of substance as they exist in relations of affection concepts of substance, attributes, affections, and modes,
between bodies and other bodies, between thoughts and explaining how they inevitably lead to inadequate ideas.
other thoughts. But all this begs another question: What constitutes an
All the discussion so far begs a vexing question: How adequate idea? Assuming it is possible to do so—and per-
can relations of affection between extensive modes (e.g., haps it isn’t—how might Brad arrive at an adequate idea
bodies) be apprehended by the human intellect, itself a of the relation between his body and the sun? It is here
mode of thought? How does the mind develop an idea of the that we turn to Spinoza’s concept of affect, or affectus in
body if they are each different modes of substance under Latin, which Spinoza defined as follows: “By affect I
different, mutually exclusive attributes? How was Brad’s understand affections of the body by which the body’s
mind able to develop an idea of the sun’s effect on his body? power of acting is increased or diminished, aided or
These questions point to the mind–body problem, the restrained, and at the same time, the ideas of these affec-
Cartesian split. Spinoza’s solution to the problem is this: tions” (p. 70). Here Spinoza seems to equate “affect” with
“The object of the idea constituting the human mind is the “affections of the body” inasmuch as they both can
body, or a certain mode of extension which actually exists, increase or decrease the “body’s power of acting.” Note,
and nothing else” (p. 39). That is to say, although the human however, that in the first half of the definition, the human
mind is itself a mode of thought, it can only experience mind is not to be found; it is all about bodies, about rela-
itself as a mode of extension (e.g., a body) entangled with tions of affection that either elevate or depress a body’s
other modes of extension because the body is the object of conatus—that is, its striving, its ability to maintain those
the mind’s thought. Put differently, thought is necessarily individuating relations of “speed and slowness” that hold
embodied. Ultimately, then, the physical body is a mode of it together. Affect, then, is both dispersed and dynamic,
extension, the idea of the physical body is a mode of not located in or reducible to the cogito. It is only toward
thought, and these two modes are united as the same sub- the end of the definition that we encounter the mind: “and
stance under different attributes. at the same time, the ideas of these affections” (emphasis
added). Spinoza made an important distinction here, one
that laid out the plane of immanence within which post-
Inadequate Ideas human subjectivity could emerge and circulate. Although
Crucially, however, because the mind and body are mutu- affects are precisely those relations of affections that
ally exclusive modes of the same substance, Spinoza either strengthen or weaken bodies, they are simultane-
claimed that “the ideas of the affections of the human body, ously the human mind’s idea of those relations of affec-
insofar as they are related to the human mind, are not clear tions. And such ideas will be either adequate or inadequate
and distinct, but confused” (p. 51). They are inadequate to the extent that the mind is, respectively, either acting or
ideas. That is, the mind can by its nature only have inade- being acted on.
quate ideas of modes of extension, including the physical
body which is the mind’s object of thought. Spinoza added
Affect
that “the human mind does not perceive any external body
as actually existing, except through the ideas of the affec- Returning to Brad and that blazing Georgia sun, then, one
tions of its own body” (p. 50), which again are necessarily can see both dimensions of affect at work. First, the relation
inadequate and confused ideas. Perhaps one can now under- of affection between the sun and his body was affective in
stand how Brad’s superficial idea of the sun’s proximity to that the sun lowered his body’s power of acting, but that
the earth was clearly inadequate, but more importantly, per- affective response existed in a dispersed, dynamic, noncon-
haps one can understand how Brad’s idea of the sun will scious arrangement between physical bodies. As Spinoza
Robinson and Kutner 5

explained, however, because “the object of the idea consti- mind is their cause, can lead us toward true knowledge.
tuting the human mind is the body” (p. 39), after a few Given such nuance, when researchers position their work in
moments of insufferable heat Brad’s mind entered into a a philosophical lineage of affect that includes both Spinoza
relation of affection between that of his body and the sun— and Massumi—even Massumi himself—it is easy to see
and other bodies, too—which is to say his mind conceived how things can become confused, how inadequate ideas can
an idea of the sun’s power on his body. It was an inadequate abound. In her interview with Zembylas, Boler highlighted
idea that prompted him to suspect the sun was closer to the one such confusion, namely that Massumi’s “‘autonomy of
earth in Georgia. Only a moment later, however, his mind affect’ is a concept foundational to all ‘affect theory’ or to
understood that this was, of course, not true. It only seemed Spinoza’s philosophy” (p. 23). As Spinoza makes clear,
that way, perhaps, because he had just stepped from an air- affect, or affectus, is not an entirely prepersonal intensity
conditioned vehicle onto pavement radiating intense waves that always-already exceeds our capacity to engage it with
of heat. For Spinoza, such rational engagement between the it. Instead, Spinozan affect is a suprapersonal intensity, one
mind and its ideas of relations of affection can lead to more amenable not only to discursive capture but also to rational,
adequate ideas of those relations of affection. He wrote, productive, and ethical engagement within a posthuman
“Our mind does certain things [acts] and undergoes certain conception of subjectivity.
things, namely insofar as it has adequate ideas, it necessar-
ily does things, and insofar as it has inadequate ideas, it
necessarily undergoes things” (p. 70). Clearly, then, Brad’s Spinoza and Deleuze With Guattari
wrong-headed impression of the sun was a result of “under- Importantly, we do not claim that Spinoza’s ontological arrange-
going,” or enduring, the power of the sun, and he was there- ment necessarily implied posthuman subjectivity and did so
fore limited to an inadequate idea of it. But Spinoza added about three centuries ago. Rather, we claim that Spinoza’s
that “if we can be the adequate cause of any of these affec- monist ontology laid out a plane of immanence within which a
tions, I understand by the affect an action; otherwise, a pas- thinkable conception of posthuman subjectivity could take
sion” (p. 70). As a pure mode of substance-as-thought, shape. And thanks to the work of Deleuze (1970/1988) and
Brad’s rational mind possessed the agentive power to Deleuze with Guattari (1980/1987), Feminist New Materialists
become the adequate cause of the relation of affection like Braidotti (2006) and Barad (2007), it has and continues to
between his mind and his inadequate idea of the sun, and take shape. However, the nuanced ontological arguments in
this adequate idea enhanced his power to act. He continues Spinoza’s Ethics are essential to engage with in any account of
living in Georgia, after all. Central to Spinoza’s Ethics, affect theory that traces its philosophical lineage to Deleuze and
then, is the call to active, relational ways of being in the Guattari, who themselves profess the importance of Spinoza.
world that strive to rise above the passions, those external For example, in What is Philosophy? Deleuze and Guattari
forces that obscure rather than clarify understanding. (1991/1994) anointed Spinoza as the “‘prince’ of philosophers”
Indeed, that the words “passion” and “passive” both derive (p. 49)—“the only philosopher never to have compromised
from the Latin pati, meaning to suffer, calls our attention to with transcendence and to have hunted it down everywhere,”
the ethical force of Spinoza’s philosophy. adding that “he discovered that freedom exists only within
Spinozan affects can get in the mind’s way of under- immanence” (p. 48). Braidotti (2006) too returned to Spinoza’s
standing true causes, which is why Spinoza encouraged us conception of conatus to explore the political ethical impera-
to “separate emotions, or affects, from the thought of an tives of nomadic philosophy.
external cause, and join them with other thoughts” (p. 163). It is Deleuze and Guattari’s description of affect in A
When we are successful, “the love, or hate, toward the Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia that
external cause is destroyed, as are the vacillations of mind seems to dominate conceptions of affect in inquiry after the
arising from these affects” (p. 163). For Spinoza, then, an ontological turn. That in mind, now that we have worked
affect can be a sort of problem, one only the rational mind through Spinoza’s ontological arrangement, we will turn to
can solve as it makes its way through the levels of knowl- one of Deleuze and Guattari’s most cited passages, one of
edge, working toward true knowledge of God, of Substance, just two instances where they offer something close to a
of Nature. This is an important point, as affect sometimes definition of affect. This reading will indicate what new
carries a more positive valence in the work of contemporary potentialities can emerge from affect theory following a
affect theorists. Massumi (2002), for example, associates return to Spinoza’s original philosophical origins. Deleuze
affect with the “perception of one’s own vitality, one’s sense and Guattari write
of aliveness, of changeability (often signified as ‘free-
dom’)” (p. 36). For Spinoza, however, there are affects of We know nothing of the body until we know what it can do, in
sadness, which decrease our power of acting and lead us other words, what its affects are, how they can or cannot enter
away from true knowledge, and there are affects of joy, into composition with other affects, with the affects of another
which increase our power of acting and, when our rational body, either to destroy that body or be destroyed by it, either to
6 Qualitative Inquiry 00(0)

exchange actions and passions with it or to join with it in so-called “force” on the other. By laying out a plane where
composing a more powerful body. (p. 257) posthuman subjectivity becomes thinkable, Spinoza showed
how affect can exist in a discursively accessible state of
A few things to note about this passage. First, it opens excess to the body–mind.
with a line that echoes Deleuze’s (1970/1988) book A We also suggest that our return to Spinoza might be con-
Practical Philosophy, in which he discusses the work of sidered an act of inquiry itself, a postqualitative inquiry in
Spinoza. In A Practical Philosophy, Deleuze (1988) com- which we delved into the origins of the philosophical con-
ments that one of Spinoza’s greatest philosophical insights cept of affect and in so doing were able to think something
was that “no one has yet determined what the body can do” new (St. Pierre, 2017). There are two primary ways in which
(p. 72). This is important to note because it indicates the affect is discussed in education. First, research on affect
extent to which Spinoza’s philosophy was foundational for with a posthuman inflection often leaves behind the indi-
Deleuze and Guattari’s constructions, although they do not vidual student-subject or teacher-subject to investigate the
state so explicitly. Second, Deleuze and Guattari implied school or classroom in terms of rhizomatic assemblages, or
that knowledge of the body and its affects is possible, if bodies with without organs. Second, research on affect in
aspirational. As we saw earlier, the epistemological distinc- education often involves analyses that frame educational
tion between adequate and inadequate ideas is a key feature environments, practices, or moments in terms of lines of
of Spinoza’s Ethics, and while Deleuze and Guattari are not flight, or conditions of emergent becoming. Our reading of
as proscriptive, there is a clear epistemological implications Spinoza led us to think about the ethical force of Spinozan
to their ontological arguments. Third, their attention to the affect in education, which we will relate here to curriculum
potential for affects to “enter into composition with other theory.
affects” seems to rely on Spinoza’s conception of modes, In Latin, the word curriculum refers to the running of
particularly their capacity to enter into co-constitutive rela- a course, or a race. Some curriculum theorists have noted
tions of affection. This emphasizes the more-than-individ- how this metaphorical course has become increasingly
ual relationality aspect of affect. Fourth, Deleuze and literal—“Race” to the top, for example—with regimented
Guattari preserved Spinoza’s distinction between affective curricular maps and standards. Such theorists note, too,
actions and passions, whereby actions strengthen bodies’ how social and physical environments are not separate
strivings to cohere, to maintain their relations of “speed and from, but rather are a part of, those curricular courses.
slowness” (p. 41), while passions weaken bodies’ strivings Drawing on our reading of Spinoza, it occurred to us that
to cohere, destroying them in the process. That is, affect is an alternative way to consider curriculum—a way more
not simply a poetic descriptive. Affect does, and does dif- in the spirit of its etymology—is to emphasize the move-
ferently in its onto-epistemic relations among bodies. ment toward which it hints, the act of running. By these
In this way, Deleuze and Guattari called upon Spinoza lights, we came to consider the possibility of a curriculum
because he raised the status of the body to that of the mind, of affective joy. Such a curriculum would attend to the
thereby complicating them in compelling ways. However, how assemblages cultivate increasingly adequate, ethical
what is left out of this invocation of Spinoza is the ethical ideas of the world in educational spaces through rhizom-
and epistemological force of his project. Those who would atic, not utilitarian, action. This example is provided not
grasp onto a Spinozan–Deleuzoguattarian ontology of the to argue specifically for this construction but rather to
body without directly engaging with Spinoza’s Ethics—not present just one possibility of how inquiry into the
to mention Deleuze’s and Deleuze with Guattari’s large cor- Spinozan philosophical origins of affect theory allowed
pora, as well—may miss opportunities to experience the us to think of something new.
fruitful disorientation produced by his ideas of what the will In Thinking with Theory in Qualitative Research,
and the mind can do, thereby allowing affect to slip from Youngblood Jackson and Mazzei (2012) showed how dif-
their hands, which are left holding just a body. ferent theoretical and philosophical orientations could be
“plugged in” to the same set of interview data to produce
different—but not better or worse—analyses. Our return to
Implications for Inquiry Spinoza provided a different type of thinking with theory,
Importantly, by our reading of Spinoza we do not mean to one that used theory to drive potential questions for inquiry.
suggest that a return to the Ethics is all affect theory needs. For example, one could imagine projects to investigate the
Spinoza has his own problems—strict determinism, for curricular and instructional implications of affect as they
example. What he offers, however, is the possibility of relate to Spinoza’s concepts of adequate and inadequate
negotiating between two seemingly contradictory impulses ideas or of the connections between affective joy and action
for engaging with affect theory through inquiry. Which is to all within the Deleuzoguattarian assemblage. These were
say that Spinoza helps us avoid reducing affect to humanis- not questions that we were capable of considering ahead of
tic emotion on one hand or some inevitably inaccessible our reading of Spinoza’s Ethics.
Robinson and Kutner 7

Conclusion Boler, M., & Zembylas, M. (2016). Interview with Megan Boler:
From “feminist politics of emotions” to the “affective turn.”
The notion that affect always-already exceeds subjective In M. Zembylas & P. Schutz (Eds.), Methodological advances
experience may represent both the theory’s greatest strength in research on education and emotion (pp. 203-214). Basel,
and its greatest limitation. Affect theory is an attempt to Switzerland: Springer.
give voice to a crucial something, a haunting that is trace- Braidotti, R. (2006). The ethics of becoming imperceptible. In
able but always slipping. This is a problematic paradox for C. Boundas (Ed.), Deleuze and philosophy (pp. 133-159).
researchers, especially researchers working in humanist Edinburg, UK: Edinburgh University Press.
social sciences such as education, where “useful” concepts Deleuze, G. (1988). Spinoza: Practical philosophy (R. Hurley,
Trans.). San Francisco, CA: City Lights Books. (Original
are those amenable to methodological application. As Boler
work was published 1970)
suggested in her interview with Zembylas (2016), scholars
Deleuze, G., & Guattari, F. (1987). A thousand plateaus:
want to be put affect theory “to work” (p. 23). The chal- Schizophrenia and capitalism (B. Massumi, Trans.).
lenge is how to put affect theory to work in ways that fulfill Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. (Original work
its theoretical potential without either reducing it to psycho- published 1980)
logical conventions that focus on individual feelings and Deleuze, G., & Guattari, F. (1994). What is philosophy? (H.
emotions or dismissing it as free-floating signification. In Tomlinson & G. Burchell Trans.). New York, NY: Columbia
this article, we have argued that one way to meet this chal- University Press. (Original work published in 1991)
lenge is through a re-engagement with the primary philo- Jackson, A. Y., & Mazzei, L. A. (2012). Thinking with theory in
sophical origins of affect in Spinoza’s Ethics. qualitative research: Viewing data across multiple perspec-
Our re-engagement with the Ethics called our attention to tives. New York, NY: Routledge.
various conceptual tools that may support fruitfully disori- Manning, E. (2013). Always more than one: Individuation’s
enting inquiry with affect theory: adequate and inadequate dance. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
ideas, affections, modes, substance, joy, sadness, and so on. Massumi, B. (2002). Parables for the virtual: Movement, affect,
Our reading of Spinoza also helped make affect theory sensation. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
thinkable by clarifying the philosophical origins of posthu- Spinoza, B. (1996). Ethics. New York, NY: Penguin. (Original
work published 1677)
man subjectivity, which would be crucial for any scholar
St. Pierre, E. A. (2011a). “Post qualitative research: The cri-
attempting to engage in inquiry in a posthuman ontological
tique and the coming after”. In Sage handbook of qualitative
turn. Furthermore, inquiry is not only about how we ask it
inquiry, 4th ed., Edited by: Denzin, N. K. and Lincoln, Y. S.
but also about what we ask. Our return to Spinoza suggested 611–625. Los Angeles, CA: Sage.
to us that inquiry related to affect is not only about the pos- St Pierre, E. A. (2017). Haecceity: Laying Out a Plane for Post
sibilities of capturing affect through research but also about Qualitative Inquiry. Qualitative Inquiry, 23(9), 686-698.
returning to affect theory to ask something different, to think Taguchi, H. L., & St Pierre, E. A. (2017). Using concept as method
and create something different. To do so, a return to the phil- in educational and social science inquiry. Qualitative Inquiry,
osophical origins of theory is essential. Make no mistake, 22, 643-648.
this is difficult work, but as we continue reading, thinking, Thrift, N. (2004). Intensities of feeling: Towards a spatial politics
and writing our way around affect theory, we like to keep in of affect. Geografiska Annaler: Series B, Human Geography,
mind one of Spinoza’s pithier constructions: “But all things 86, 57-78.
excellent are as difficult as they are rare” (p. 181). Zembylas, M., & Schutz, P. A. (Eds.). (2016). Methodological
advances in research on education and emotion. Switzerland:
Declaration of Conflicting Interests Springer.
The author(s) declared no potential conflicts of interest with respect
to the research, authorship, and/or publication of this article. Author Biographies
Bradley Robinson is a doctoral student in the Department of
Funding Language and Literacy Education at the University of Georgia. He
is a National Board certified teacher in English Language Arts with
The author(s) received no financial support for the research,
over a decade of experience in North Carolina’s public schools. His
authorship, and/or publication of this article.
research explores the intersections of literacy, technology, and neo-
liberalism in formal and informal educational spaces.
ORCID iD
Mel Kutner is a doctoral student and graduate research assistant
Bradley Robinson https://orcid.org/0000-0002-2983-0206 in the Department of Education of Education Theory and Practice
at the University of Georgia. They have a master’s degree in
References Conflict Analysis and Resolution and eight years experience in
Barad, K. (2007). Meeting the universe halfway: Quantum physics educational policy and research. Mel’s work explores theoriza-
and the entanglement of matter and meaning. Durham, NC: tions of temporality and movement in inquiry and ethics, as well
Duke University Press. as the circulation of conflict in educational spaces.

You might also like