You are on page 1of 19

This article appeared in a journal published by Elsevier.

The attached
copy is furnished to the author for internal non-commercial research
and education use, including for instruction at the authors institution
and sharing with colleagues.
Other uses, including reproduction and distribution, or selling or
licensing copies, or posting to personal, institutional or third party
websites are prohibited.
In most cases authors are permitted to post their version of the
article (e.g. in Word or Tex form) to their personal website or
institutional repository. Authors requiring further information
regarding Elsevier’s archiving and manuscript policies are
encouraged to visit:
http://www.elsevier.com/copyright
Author's personal copy

New Ideas in Psychology 29 (2011) 80–97

Contents lists available at ScienceDirect

New Ideas in Psychology


journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/newideapsych

A model of art perception, evaluation and emotion in transformative


aesthetic experience
Matthew Pelowski*, Fuminori Akiba
Nagoya University, Graduate School of Information Science, Furo-cho, Chikusa-ku, Nagoya 464-8601, Japan

a b s t r a c t

PsycINFO classification: While accounts of “aesthetic” experience inspire art study and drive its cognitive goals the
2610 current modeling of art perception, based on the analytic tradition emphasizing successful
2820 assimilation of art information, is unable to truly address this phenomenon, leaving us
2340
without means of accounting for disruption and fundamental changedeither perceptual
Keywords: or self-referentialdas well as epiphany and insight, within the experience of art; and no
Aesthetics means of addressing ’art’s ability to mark and change lives. To address this, we introduce
Emotional response a five-stage model of art-perception, organized around initial disruption and subsequent
Perceptual development meta-cognitive reflection and self-transformation, which allows for this needed discussion
Cognitive processes of perceptual and conceptual change, and a connection of art-viewing to viewer person-
Cognitive dissonance
ality. Based on this, we consider belletristic accounts of aesthetic experience, and discuss
the inter-relation of emotional, cognitive and appraisal factors that may be important for
objective research.
! 2010 Published by Elsevier Ltd.

For centuries viewers have been struck, moved and Freedberg (1989, p. 60) argues that it is these experi-
changed by their encounters with art, documenting ences that provide art with its ongoing mystery, and
accounts of transformation and epiphany throughout art’s universality, throughout human anthropology. People, he
history, which have come to be known collectively as notes, are “stirred” by works of art, they “expect to be
“aesthetic experience.” Proust (1981/1954, p. 48) memori- elevated by them. They have always responded in these
alized a disruptive “pleasure invading [his] senses” from ways; they still do.” These reactions can be traced
a tea-soaked Madeleine. Kandinsky recorded being throughout diverse mediadfrom painting to music, theater
“stopped short” by “an indescribably beautiful picture”dhis to poetry. They quickly spill beyond the gallery, offering
own painting, on its sided“pervaded by an inner glow” (in compelling connections between the arts and general
Weiss, 2005, p. 145). In contemporary examples, the un- conceptions of enlightenment and insight. And, when we
played piano in the work 4’33 by John Cage, the ‘empty’ look to the specific study of art itself, it is this phenomenon
canvases of Rothko, and Nam Jun Paik’s blank filmstrips that sits at the heart of art’s scholarship, inspiring
routinely deliver insight and “transcendence” (Belting, conceptions of what art can do, what art-viewing might
2002; Pelowski, 2007). As a viewer recently wrote in a visi- lead to; even, at its best, what art might be.
tor’s book after an experience with a Rothko (in Elkins, p.11), Despite differences in historical period, terminology and
adding his comment to a long tradition of meetings between objects of perception themselves, when writers describe
viewer and artwork, “This makes me fall down.” aesthetic experience, as Shusterman (1997; also Fenner,
1996) has argued in his review of these accounts, they
show fundamental agreement, and central emphasis on the
* Corresponding author. Tel.: þ81 90 3583 1355; fax: þ81 52 789 4800. importance of disruption and transformation. Aesthetic
E-mail address: mpelowski@yahoo.com (M. Pelowski). experience “breaks in upon us” (Fenner, p. 108), and serves

0732-118X/$ – see front matter ! 2010 Published by Elsevier Ltd.


doi:10.1016/j.newideapsych.2010.04.001
Author's personal copy

M. Pelowski, F. Akiba / New Ideas in Psychology 29 (2011) 80–97 81

as a “check of our daily activities” (Ingarden, 1961, p. 300; Focusing almost exclusively on a third factor mentioned in
also Dickie, 1974). It constitutes a state of heightened anecdotal accounts, they posit a state of selfless, pleasur-
awareness (Ferree, 1968), leading to self-confrontation, able and harmonious mastery, involving the successful
relieved tension, resolved conflicts (Crittenden, 1968), reception and assimilation of art information, that might be
consummation (Maslow, 1959); enlightenment equated to a peak moment of epiphany or insight itself.
(Shusterman, 1997) and cognitive development (Dewey, When considered in isolation however, as has been the
1980; Goodman in Shusterman, 1997; Petts, 2000). It is practice since its Kantian inception, this “aesthetic” in
this phenomenondwhereby we see something new, experience tends to preclude the possibility for art to mark
question our conceptions and transform our world- and transform lives.
viewdthat provides art’s ontological (e.g., Blanchot, 1997/ As this has come to form the basis for the modeling of
1971; Danto, 1986) and social (Becker, 1982) definition. art perception, it has led to a current approach which
When considered as a progression of meetings between presupposes successful reception and understanding at the
viewer and artist, between expectations and new art- expense of the antecedent, and often negative, movement to
worksdwhat Gadamer (in Roald, 2007, p. 78) has called moments of insight, pleasure and conceptual or perceptual
a “reciprocal game”dthese experiences drive art’s history transformation; and we are left without a means of
(e.g., Dufrenne, 1973). In a recent example, the ur experi- accounting for fundamental change within art experience.
ence for post-modern art, an aesthetic experience had by This, in turn, has led to a flattened conception of the
Danto (1992) in front of Warhol’s Brillo Box fundamentally experience of art itself, often divorced from a viewer’s
altered and re-defined his, and art’s, entire philosophy. And personal beliefs and identity, limiting our ability to divide
it is assumptions about this phenomenon that determine and order perception, as well as to explain and unite
conceptions of how viewers should perceive art, how they cognitive, emotional and evaluative benchmarks. And as
should be prepared to look at art, and how cognition of art Funch (1997, p. 42) has concluded, within his survey of the
should be evaluated. Berlyne (1974) argued for novelty, present psychological analysis of art, “if appreciation of
surprise and arousal as the goals of art interaction. “People a specific work of art really has an impact on the viewer’s
are looking for challenge in art,” Leder, Belke, Oeberst, and life. it would be difficult, if not impossible, to give
Augustin (2004, p. 2) recently surmised for art apprecia- evidence of such influences through empirical studies.”
tion. “Art,” Blanchot (p. 18) concluded, “and by this should This paper represents our attempt to re-address this
be understood the entirety of works and that which makes topic. We first consider the present discussion of aesthetic
each one a work of art,” and therefore aesthetic experience, experience and modeling of art perception, discussing its
“is in essence anxiety and movement.” current limitations, and then introduce an alternative
It is this phenomenon, then, that begs vital questions for approach, based on the pioneering work of John Dewey, who
psychology. How does art “break in upon us?” How do argued, rather than success, that a model stressing initial
viewers come to see something new in art? How do they disruption, based not on analysis of specific information but
change their conceptions, deepen their evaluation and on the application of the self-image to the perception of
achieve insight and epiphany? Given the historical information, and disruption-driven meta-cognitive self
evidence for the ability of simple stimuli, often without reflection and self-change, may introduce this needed
physical change, to create this outcome (e.g., Freedberg, element of change into the modeling of art perception, as
1989), how does this occur within the act of perception well as explain how aesthetic experience itself is achieved
itselfdhow do objects become “transformed” (Fenner, and how it might be recorded. We offer a five-stage model
1996)? How is cognition within this process tied to for this process, clarifying the steps leading up to trans-
emotion and evaluation? And ultimately, as argued by formation, and therefore calling for an expansion of many of
Levi-Strauss (1982, p. 151; also Osborne, 1979) to be the the current approaches to aesthetic study.
fundamental question, not only for art, but for human
interactions with their environmentsdhow might these 1. “Aesthetic” success and current limitations in the
experiences of disruption, change and insight be modeled, modeling of art-perception
empirically recorded and identified “in real life?”
However, it is these very questions, and this “aesthetic Before considering our model, it is first necessary to
experience,” that have not been addressed, or more often consider the existing approach to art, noting what is
are beyond the scope of consideration, in art’s psycholog- addressed, and more importantly, what is currently outside
ical study. While inspiring the study of art, aesthetic of present discussion. As noted above, while the conception
experience also embodies a longstanding disconnect in the of art and aesthetic experience as a disruptive/trans-
conception and modeling of art perception. When asked to formative phenomenon represents a long tradition, the
describe what is important in art, how art might affect actual conception of aesthetic experience, and the subse-
usdessentially, how aesthetic experience is manifest in quent focus of art study, tends to focus exclusively on the
real lifedwe find this marked agreement among moment of “aesthetic” insight, or peak of harmonious
researchers highlighting the disruptive and trans- pleasure and contemplation itself. This can be traced to
formational nature of the phenomenon. When asked to Baumgarten’s initial founding of the field of aesthetics, and
explain what aesthetic experience is, and therefore how definition of “aesthetic experience,” as the “perfection of
this might be achieved, however, art philosophy, and sensate cognition” (e.g., Osborne, 1979, p. 136), continuing
subsequently art’s psychology, which is largely built upon into the subsequent Kant (1978/1790) harmony of
the analytic tradition, give a quite different answer. “aesthetic judgment.” It is this harmonious state that was
Author's personal copy

82 M. Pelowski, F. Akiba / New Ideas in Psychology 29 (2011) 80–97

originally linked to explanations for beauty as well as disruption, this approach presupposes moments of success,
hedonic valuedas that which is “agreeable” or that which requiring, for a viewer to meet their parameters, that he or
can be contemplated free from thoughts of utility (Walton, she employ an observational strategy or set of pre-expec-
1993). Often, it is this state that was given as the means of tations sufficiently compatible with, or sufficiently
identifying works of art, as those objects that allow malleable so as to accommodate, a specific artwork. Look-
a viewer to enter, or are intended to be perceived in, this ing back to the qualities of aesthetic experience posited in
mode of detached pleasure (Fenner, 1996). This then the introduction, scholars question how, given correspon-
extends into the analytic tradition (Beardsley, 1969; Eaton, dence between expectations and perception, “aesthetic”
1995; Fenner, 1996) of “aesthetic attention,” a form of mastery can lead to heightened awareness, novel percep-
perception in which one moves past worldly disruptions, tion (e.g., Carroll, 1986; Dickie in Petts, 2000), new
one’s desires, and negative emotions to a heightened state knowledge (Smith, 1996), or enlightenment (McDowell in
of pleasurable scrutiny. And, it is this state, which Petts); or how we might account for art’s ability to surprise
Shusterman (1997, p. 30) has called aesthetic experience’s us or to break in upon us. In fact, with the elimination of
“evaluative dimension,” and this pursuit of harmonious disruption, it is these very qualities that would also be
reception of art’s information, that has then come to form eliminated in the present approach. As Csikszentmihalyi
the implicit goal for current psychological models. and Rochenberg-Halton (1981; also Duval & Wicklund,
Building on this tradition, current models equate art- 1972; Smith) note, to the extent that viewer action comes
perception to either an emotional/empathic alignment of to match current models of art perception, culminating in
viewer to artist or artwork, as in the psychoanalytic and moments of selfless “aesthetic” harmony, art experience
psycho-physical conceptions (e.g., documented by Funch, itself would create no impetus to change one’s analysis or
1997; Roald, 2007); or, more recently, a cognitive ques- perception because it would create no “checks” in the flow
tion of the assessment of an artwork’s formal or semiotic of perception. Instead, “by providing a familiar symbolic
information via the matching of perceptual schema to the context [it would] reaffirm” existing conceptions and
object of perception, as in Norman’s (2004) “intuitive” identity (p. 187).
understanding, Berlyne’s (1974) appraisal theory, and Even models that do account for re-assessment (e.g.,
recently Leder et al.’s (2004) “cognitive mastery.” Aesthetic Goodman in Shusterman, 2006; Leder et al., 2004),
perception and aesthetic experience are fit into a frame different complexities of perception (Parsons, 1987), or
whereby, it is argued, the more successful an individual is those that explicitly single out disruptive and trans-
at “grasping the meaning” of an artwork (Leder et al., 2004, formative qualities (Lasher, Carroll, & Bever, 1983), focus
p. 178; also Walton, 1993), or assimilating oneself to art, the exclusively on successful assessment of art’s formal infor-
more ease with which they can perceive and the more mationdoften following Berlyne’s (1974, p. 6) four chan-
pleasurable or rewarding the outcome (Mitias, 1982). When nels of semantic, expressive, cultural and syntactic
one’s perception and evaluation is sufficiently unified or analysisdflattening the perception of art viewing into this
harmonious, it is then assumed, a viewer may experience eventual assimilation without a means of considering
an escape from self-awareness (e.g., Ferree, 1968; Smith, fundamental changes in viewer expectations or schema
1996). And it is to these ultimate moments of success, themselves. By focusing exclusively on informational
typified by Bullough’s “psychical distance” (see Funch, assessment, the significance, or “meaning,” of an artwork
1997), Maslow’s (1959) “peak experience” and recently becomes implicitly located outside of the viewer, where it
Csikszentmihalyi’s (1990) “flow” stated“a special, can be received and assessed but is itself “fixed and
detached state of consciousness, in which you are aware unchangeable” (Dewey, 1929, p. 23). This leaves no opening
only of the moment, of the activity, and of the sheer for considering the role that self-identity plays in shaping
enjoyment” (Norman, 2004, p. 125)dthat writers look as information, or the role that artwork plays in questioning
the archetypal explanation of aesthetic experience (e.g., expectations. Rather, as noted by Müller-Freienfels (in
Leder et al., 2004). In turn, “aesthetic” experiences, within Funch, 1997), personal associations and, often, complete or
art-philosophy and psychology, pertaining to both genuine examples of artworks themselves (see also
mundane art perception and transformative accounts, Berlyne), are often omitted from consideration because
become those situations where, in Leder et al.’s (2004, p. they represent disturbances in the ability to generalize the
493) words, a viewer can “classify, understand and cogni- reception of information. Instead, both artwork and viewer
tively master [an] artwork successfully; ” and this becomes tend to become inert actors in this informational assess-
the goal and basis for understanding and assessment of art. ment process (considered in detail by Dewey, 1951, 1980).
While this approach represents essential work on an Because aesthetic mastery presumes the elimination of
important aspect of the experience of artdindeed, it self-reflection, there is also no means of linking aesthetic
focuses on one of the most compelling components of experience to personal growth or cognitive development
aesthetic experiencedas has long been argued against the (Carver, 1996). Rather these qualities too must be posited to
analytic tradition, this exclusive emphasis on informational occur sometime after, or to have already occurred before,
mastery introduces numerous limitations when applied to the actual perception of art.
the “real life” experience of art. Essentially, there is no Even if we do look to this selfless harmony as the
means of accounting for how individuals arrive at these “aesthetic” experience, distinguishing this state from
attunements to their environment within the act of cognitive processes (e.g., discussed by Funch, 1997), we are
perception. Rather, following the philosophical focus on still left with the question of why a viewer is able to suddenly
assimilation via the minimization of self-awareness and find harmony or epiphany with a previously inert work or
Author's personal copy

M. Pelowski, F. Akiba / New Ideas in Psychology 29 (2011) 80–97 83

what this consummation occurs in reference to. In order to things” Artists, when producing art, and viewers when
identify this state, Dewey (1980) noted, would require that perceiving, “must violate standards more or less deeply
aesthetic epiphany be explained by finding an imagined internalized.” Leder et al. (2004) have noted that one of the
threshold for harmony. More often, this state is specifically qualities of much contemporary art that makes it troubling
linked to underlying cognitive interactiondDickie (in Petts, for both viewer and researcher is the fact that it often does
2000, p. 64) made this same argument from within the not even make use of the old tropes of beauty or mimetic
analytic tradition, noting that when philosophers speak of depiction in questioning standards and ideas. Instead, as
“detached” aesthetic appraisal, what they in fact appear to noted by Bourdieu (1984/1979) the post-modern era
mean is “paying attention.” Again we return to the need for demands that art be interpreted via its effect on one’s
a discussion of change either in artwork or viewer, and the worldview. However, while “ambiguity” is acknowledged
disruption in perception or experience that might drive this as an important factor in art perception (e.g., Berlyne,
change. This becomes more problematic when coupled with 1974), it is precisely this negative quality of collative
information-processing research, discussed below, breakdown and fundamental change in the mastery
revealing the fundamental influence that pre-expectations process that violates current models (e.g., Carroll, 1986;
and self-protectionary filters have on what viewers are or McDowell in Petts, 2000). And again, personal relation to
are not initially able to perceive. Writers question whether stimuli and changes in viewer mode of assessment that
selflessness is not really self-protection (Wenzel, 2005), or might explain art’s ability to “die,” or a string to question
how to distinguish between inattentive and attentive one’s existencedand the epiphanic/self-transformative
perception without arbitrarily creating a “correct” meaning reaction this might createdlie outside informational
for an artwork (e.g., Merleau-Ponty, 1962/1945). Without consideration.
a means of discussing the overcoming of initial expectations Because of this emphasis on selfless informational
and perceptual schema, there is the question of whether mastery, emotion too tends to be entirely separated from
“aesthetic” success, would not actually signal a “facile” or the cognitive consideration of art (e.g., Roald, 2007); or,
premature reaction to art (e.g., Donoghue, 1983), marking other than pleasure, which is presumed to fit into a one-to-
what Dewey (1980, p. 24) termed “a dead spot in experience one relationship with assimilation (Berlyne, 1974; Funch,
that is merely filled in.” There arises the question of whether 1997), following the original Kantian conception of non-
aesthetic experiences themselves can be measured (Fenner, cognitive “aesthetic” pleasure (Pouivet, 2000), omitted
1996; Osborne, 1979; Shusterman, 1997), or can even be said altogether (noted by Eaton & Moore, 2002). However,
to exist (Kennick in Beardsley, 1969). empirical studies by Russell and Milne (1997) have seri-
At the same time, when we do look to transformative ously questioned this tie between basic hedonic response
examples, it is the very qualities that are currently elimi- and selfless assessment. Cupchik (1994) has questioned the
nated from the study of art perception that might give tie between pleasure and non-discrepant understanding.
shape to this phenomenon. According to Tucker (2004), Here too, Arnheim (1966) as well as Pouivet argue that
viewer accounts of their experiences and of the significance discussion of cognitive change, within personal relation to
of artworks often have little to do with informational or an artwork, is necessary in order to create a means of dis-
formal assessment, instead focusing expressly on their cussing arousal of emotion, including pleasure (see also
cognitive and emotional experience surrounding their Scherer, 1999). And, as might be expected from the
interpretation, its effect on deeply held conceptions and discussion above, when Steele, Spencer, and Lynch (1993;
identity, and fundamental changes in their relation to also Ingram, 1990) did explore emotion and trans-
artworks. The 20th century work allegedly responsible for formation, outside of art, they argued for a progression of
the most aesthetic epiphanies (Elkins, 2001) for example, emotions, specifically including negative affect, which
the Rothko Room mentioned above, consists of an octag- themselves may be a necessary antecedent to final
onal space and 14 black and purple rectangles that explic- epiphany and pleasure. As is discrepancy however, these
itly reject mimesis, coming to be viewed not as paintings antecedent responsesdanxiety, confusion and self-focused
but as ‘just paint’. Danto’s aesthetic encounter led him to attentiondare in direct opposition to current conceptions
declare the “death” of art (1992, p. 8). “If art is impossible,” of aesthetic and epiphanic experience (Csikszentmihalyi,
Fraser (2006, p. 42) recently wrote of an epiphanic 1990; Torrance, 1979).
encounter with sculpture, composed only of string, strung This same limitation can be traced into the analysis of
floor to ceiling, “then artists are also impossible, and I art appraisal. Again, while there is specific acknowledge-
myself am impossible.” ment of the importance that arousal and challenge play in
Freedberg (1989) has extensively documented this coloring art assessment (Berlyne, 1974), there is no means
consistent, yet “ignored,” “strain of antagonism” between of considering why, in fact, viewers are aroused, surprised
self-conception and artwork that underlies profound or pleased by art, and therefore how self-identity and
encounters (p. 11). Levi-Strauss (e.g., 1982, p. 144) as well expectations might shape our assessment of beauty and
as Gadamer (1984) and Dewey (1951, 1980) have gone so worth. Ellsworth and Scherer (2003, p. 574) have gone so
far as to argue that aesthetic experience/transformation is far as to note that conscious appraisal often begins when
best understood, not in terms of what is represented, but “something in the environment (physical, social, or mental)
via what is “denied” by a specific artwork. This is reiterated changes.” However, it is this change that is outside current
by Becker (1982, p. 204) for the basic mechanism of art, discussion. Because viewer experience must inevitably
who argued “to produce unique works of art. artists must involve the resolution of uncertainty through assimilation,
unlearn a little of the conventionally right way of doing there is no means of distinguishing between “agreeable”
Author's personal copy

84 M. Pelowski, F. Akiba / New Ideas in Psychology 29 (2011) 80–97

art and appraisal reflecting profound encounters (e.g., represents the successful matching of pre-expectations to
Becker, 1982; Harrington, 2004). perception through the elimination of discrepancy, assim-
Finally, this situation can be traced into the outcomes of ilation of discrepant information into pre-existing schema,
institutional/museum programs for art appreciation. While or self-protectionary escape, the latter represents a “new
championing the challenge of art, the current pedagogical organization” of a viewer’s expectations and schema
approach, following the analytic focus on assimilation, themselves. This results from cases in which initial failure,
attempts to increase selfless mastery by placing viewers in in the application of pre-expectations to perception, forces
comfortable environments and by giving them contextual a viewer out of informational mastery and induces this
information (Haanstra, 1996; Tucker, 2004). Yet, while easy meta-cognitive mode of self-reflection and self-change.
mastery does lead viewers to feel that they “understand,” it When successful, it is this linked mechanism of discrepancy
tends to preclude enjoyment of art experience itself (e.g., and self-change, embedded in a viewer’s personal self
noted in empirical study by Leder, Carbon, & Ripsas, 2006). image, that allows us to account for growth, novelty and
Writers argue that a pedagogical emphasis on informa- insight in art experience, and changes of kind in artworks
tional mastery, in tandem with the goal of the elimination (Dewey, 1951; also Doll, 1972).
of discrepancy, may actually diminish the possibility for Because this approach is built around the overcoming of
insight or self-transformation (Adorno, 1984/1970; natural strategies for the reinforcement of the self or self-
Bersson, 1982; Dewey, 1956; Dufrenne, 1973; Tucker, protection in the experience of discrepancy, it also gives us
2004) As artworks themselves become increasingly more a means of dividing cognition of environmental stimuli in
refractory, writers argue that this may contribute to an terms of their relation to a specific viewer’s self-identifi-
increasing alienation, and sense among the public that the cation. Discussion of art perception becomes, not a discus-
arts themselves have no connection to their own lives (e.g., sion of specific art information, but a discussion of how
argued by Bersson; Bourdieu, 1984/1979; Tucker, 2004). viewers transform themselves through engaging with art.
This might be ascertained, as noted by Eaton (2000), by the Finally, this approach offers a means of reconciling the
declining support of the National Endowment for the Arts. three factors noted in the anecdotal description of aesthetic
This then leaves us with several key points that a model experience, grounding the peak of selfless pleasure and
of art experience, augmenting existing discussion, needs to mastery within this cognitive progression, occurring last
address. Specifically, there is need for consideration of 1) and marking the consummation of this process of ante-
how mastery or “aesthetic” epiphany/flow is achieved from cedent failure and self-transformation. It is this entire
within experience itself; 2) expanding the conception of art process then, wherein a viewer returns to cognitive
perception beyond informational assessment; 3) incorpo- mastery with a new set of expectations or schema as
rating a mechanism for local growth and expectational a direct result of their perception of art, that Dewey argued
modification that can account for fundamental changes in should be considered an “aesthetic experience.” And it is
viewer perception and relationship to art, as well as 4) the implicit focus on disruption, whereby we look for
accounting for the role that viewer self-identity plays in art change before assimilation, that should provide the
perception. essential focus for the modeling of art.
In this way, we may provide a means of explaining how The remainder of this paper presents a cognitive model
we might “transcend” the process of cognitive or aesthetic for this process, fleshing out this conception of Dewey, and
mastery itself, and may provide the study of art with considering a large body of existing scholarly work on its
a frame for the consideration of emotion and changes in various aspects. This model (shown as a cognitive flow
appraisal. Essentially, as noted by Tucker (2004, p. 85), this diagram in Fig. 1 and broken into a detailed description of
requires a “radical change” in the basic conception of its stages in Table 1) serves as an extension to the current
aesthetic experience; from the peak moments of informa- conception of cognitive mastery, beginning with 1)
tional assimilation, to an “experience-based” discussion of a discussion of viewer pre-expectations, self image and
a viewer’s relation with art; focusing on the process of perceptual schema, and then considering four phases
arriving at new insight and transformation. involving: 2) the initial application of these schema within
the cognitive mastery process; 3) subsequent attempts at
2. An alternative model of art perception and self-protectionary reconciliation or escape given the
transformative aesthetic experience arousal of discrepancy; 4) transformations of viewer
expectations or schema in meta-cognitive re-assessment,
John Dewey offered the basis for such a discussion. culminating in 5) an “aesthetic” outcome of epiphany,
“Instead of denying the importance of conflict in aesthetic cognitive development and pleasurable harmony. While
experience,” he argued, “I have emphasized its indispens- this discussion is adapted for the specific case of objects
able function (1951, p. 552).” Dewey (1980) argued that it is perceived to be “art,” this model readily applies to any
disruption in viewer interaction with art, and subsequently perceptual activity, and, as we discuss below, may offer
viewer response to disruption, which both provides a means of equating multiple forms of transformative/
a mechanism for substantial change in the experience of insightful experience.
art, and a means of organizing this experience. Rather than
a one-to-one match between artwork and perceptual 2.1. Stage 1: pre-expectations and the self-image
schema, he posited that art perception and evaluation be
organized around two distinct states: facile “recognition” First, before perceptual experience, viewers already
and meta-cognitive “perception.” Whereas the former hold a set of postulates directing behavior, expectations for
Author's personal copy

M. Pelowski, F. Akiba / New Ideas in Psychology 29 (2011) 80–97 85

Self-Image
Pre-state
Classification
Cognitive Mastery
Match self-image to perception?

Yes Recognition

High Flow state

No

Confident?

Wait for more


info
Yes No

All expected info


available
Secondary
Control
Re-classify?

Yes No

Physical escape?

Yes No

Mentally withdraw?

Yes No

Behavior/
Meta-cognitive Expectations can be
changed? (give up)
reassessment

Depression No

Yes

Reassess

Aesthetic Phase/ Schema-change

New Cognitive Mastery


New Schema/Self Image

Fig. 1. Cognitive flow model of aesthetic experience.

interacting with the environment, and their likely response perception, as well as what individuals can perceive or
to possible outcomes (e.g., Epstein, 1973). Interaction with understand, are a result of this postulate system. Epstein
stimulidand interaction with “art”dentails the application notes the need for self-esteem, for fulfilling needs while
of some prior, hypothetical postulates to the reality or avoiding disapproval and anxiety; as well as strategies for
scrutiny of the environment, and success or failure in navigating the environment, understanding and control;
86

Table 1
Major stages and contextual factors in transformative model of aesthetic experience.

Physiological responsea Emotion/affecta Cognitive activityb Self-image involvementb Art evaluationb


1. Pre-encounter Possess hierarchical Regard art as either
self-image/conceptual self-reinforcing (high
perceptual schema self-involvement/high
regarding art viewing, importance/potency) or
tie to self self-protectionary (low
self-involvement/
importance etc.) task
2. Cognitive mastery Sympathetic arousal: if discrepancy Success: pleasure, Semiotic or informational/ Structure art perception as Assessment of artist motive
is present: heightened electrodermal anticipation, excitement, tension historical assessment, self-reinforcing task, utilize and subsequent meaning.
response/heart rate, decreased Failure: anxiety, tension, threat attempted assimilation into cognitive and social filters Assimilation of meaning into
peripheral temperature classification, assessment of class. Correspondence
motive, evaluation between artwork and artist in
evaluation. Assessment of
meaning based on informational/
formal/historical elements. High
understanding leads to
positive assessment
3. Secondary control Heightened sympathetic arousal Self-awareness, tension, anxiety, Self-focused attention, Protect self-involvement and Accusatory evaluation of
need to leave or abort, maintain semiotic/informational “be goals”: devaluation of art/artist, devaluation of
anger, sadness assessment. Art is meaningless artwork/context, increased artwork, art/artist concept or
valuation of self/alternative situational context. Evaluation
activities of art that reduces potency,
seriousness. Negative
evaluation as bad or ugly
4. Meta-cognitive Sympathetic and parasympathetic Temporary intensification of Meta-cognitive analysis of activity, Modify “be goals” of
Author's personal copy

Assessment arousal: increased heart rate/ tension/anxiety. Acute expectations, acknowledgement hierarchical
electrodermal response, decreased self-focused attention. and acceptance of failure, self image, resulting
Unsuccessful examination of motives, self-transformation
M. Pelowski, F. Akiba / New Ideas in Psychology 29 (2011) 80–97

finger temperature/respiration
schema-change: depression schema-change
5. Schema-change/ Parasympathetic latency Relief, pleasure, happiness, New cognitive mastery, Self evaluation as less Evaluation of artwork
Aesthetic Outcome period, tears epiphany reengage perceptual task potent meaning/artist motive in terms
of previous meta-cognitive
experience/induced
self-reflection. Positive
evaluation of artwork
as beautiful, good
a
Accumulate throughout experience.
b
Determined by stage in which experience terminates.
Author's personal copy

M. Pelowski, F. Akiba / New Ideas in Psychology 29 (2011) 80–97 87

Fig. 2. The hierarchical self-image (adapted from Carver, 1996).

and the need to be a part of society and to act in a non- distinguishing oneself from ‘others’ who are not members;
deviant manner. Individuals also hold a set of “funda- and enjoyment (Goulding, 2000; Hendon, Costa, &
mental” meanings regarding themselves, other persons, Rosenberg, 1989; Jansen-Verbeke & van Rekom, 1996).
objects or behaviors (Lawler & Thye, 1999, p. 228)di.e., These are accompanied by specific cultural expect-
who am I; what, in the case of meetings with artworks, is ationsdthe prohibition against touching art, or against
“art,” and how does “art” relate to me. Together, these improper actions in the museum (e.g., Goffman, 1974). It is
postulates constitute an individual’s “ideal self-image” important to note here that, although much previous study
(Carver, 1996), and the specific hierarchical arrangement of of art experience has noted pre-expectations in art
postulates within the self-image, as in Fig. 2, drives indi- perception (reviewed by Leder et al., 2004), this has only
vidual behavior. focused on “aesthetic preferences,” past knowledge about
At the highest level of importance are what Carver art, level of past exposure, and cultural expectations
(1996) termed “Be goals,” a collection of ideal traits and (Berlyne, 1974). It is this deeper tie between stimuli and
concepts such as ‘be creative’ that the individual aspires to. self, as well as expectations for the self in the perception of
Be goals are pursued and reinforced through actions, stimuli, which forms the basis of this model, that has not
controlled by “do goals”de.g., understand artdwhich are typically been included.
then subdivided into specific tasksdclassify, find meaning,
etc. The higher the level of control utilized for a task, the 2.2. Stage 2: cognitive mastery and introduction of
more relevance to the ideal self and the greater the discrepancy
potential threat to the self-image should a discrepancy
arise; while low level goals that directly link to high level Upon encountering a stimulus in the environment,
concepts are difficult to change without modifying the individuals make an initial identification or classification,
higher concept. Lawler and Thye (1999, p. 228) note, based upon their pre-expectations and conceptual image in
“individuals seek consistency between fundamental what Leder et al. (2004) recently called the process of
meanings (i.e., that which they believe to be true), and “cognitive mastery”. Because they have extensively docu-
transient meanings (i.e., that which they experience at mented this, we will only refer to specific elements
a given moment).” Individuals avoid discrepant situations if important to this model. Once a classification is made,
possible, actively work to escape from situations that pose given an “art” situation, viewers make an attributional
a threat to the self-image, and are more likely to attend to inference regarding the basic motive or purpose behind the
information that fits their hypothetical model and rein- object (Gilbert, McNulty, Giuliano, & Benson, 1992).
forces their existing self-image (Swann & Read, 1981). Humans are preconditioned to employ this perceived
Taylor and Brown (1988, p. 201) also note the presence of “a motive in order to assess an artwork’s meaning (Bloom &
series of social and cognitive filters [that] make information Markson, 1998; From, 1971/1953; Gelman & Ebeling,
disproportionately positive” while “negative information 1998; Parsons, 1987), which is then used to structure
that escapes these filters is represented in as unthreatening interaction, evaluation and re-evaluation. However, again,
a manner as possible.” motive is not specifically necessary when considering this
In the specific case of art, while individuals for whom art mechanism itselfdone could just as well substitute the
perception is tied to higher order self-relevant concepts framing question, ‘why is this here?’ (e.g., From; Norman,
may have specific goals for art encounters, in most cases 2004). Once classification and mode of evaluation are set,
art-viewing expectations are structured toward general the viewer attempts to locate and combine all information
self-reinforcement and control (Leder et al., 2004): in order to form one coherent meaning, matching the initial
knowledge acquisition and “stimulation”; involvement or classification/motive, and then may attempt to formulate
membership with a respected element of culture, an appropriate evaluative or physical response.
Author's personal copy

88 M. Pelowski, F. Akiba / New Ideas in Psychology 29 (2011) 80–97

According to Leder et al. (2004), mastery is a circular noting, given information that is discrepantdor from
process, reflecting Gadamer’s (discussed in Parsons, 1987) another perspective, perception that is ‘imper-
notion of the accumulation and understanding of parts in fect’dassimilation requires that we ignore some informa-
terms of a projected sense of the hypothetical whole, and tion that might disrupt our experience. Frazier and Clifton
revising the latter in the light of an investigation of the (1998) note that the cognitive mastery process follows
parts. This assumes a temporal nature. “There [is] the “Minimal Revisions Principle” maintaining as much of
a successive cyclic interpretation check after each new the initial classification as possible. Viewers spend more
piece of syntactic structure is built” (Ferreira, Christianson, time attending to the earliest information in an encounter
& Hollingworth, 2001, p. 14). Importantly for this discus- (Morgan & Schwalbe, 1990). In situations of contradictory
sion, this cyclicality within the cognitive mastery stage initial and subsequent information, initial information is
implies that, barring perfect receptivity, there will always given more value; and viewers often fail to correct an initial
be discrepanciesdinformation that does not fit the present classification given new evidence (Gilbert et al., 1992;
classification or motive; elements that do not readily Greenwald, 1980). The longer that a subject has success-
combine. Conceptually speaking, any novel element, to the fully employed an initial classification before discrepancy,
extent that it is perceived, is prima facie a ‘discrepancy’. the less likely they are to change (Ferreira et al., 2001); and
Discrepancies may also arise between perceived informa- as adults, viewers become progressively less able to
tion and its relevance to the self or to other important abandon existing schema and classifications when
concepts, or between one’s actions or response and one’s perceiving novel objects (Gutheil, Bloom, Valderrama, &
expectations for action etc. In each case, as noted by Freedman, 2004). When this process of assimilation is
Festinger (1957), discrepancy involves two cognitions, one connected to the selective pre-filtering of information
involving one’s hypothetical model, the other involving mentioned above, Dewey’s notion of the difference
actual behavior or perception. between recognition and perception becomes pertinent. In
Typically, in the case of informational discrepancy, order to accommodate new information that does not fit
resolution is possible from within the cognitive mastery one’s present self-image, viewers must work against this
processdeither through ignoring the discrepancy or gradient of self-protection that would diminish or dismiss
through assimilation into a classification (Festinger, 1957). the novel in perception; and following the argument laid
If individuals are confident that a discrepancy can be out by Becker (1982) above, it might be said that much art is
overcome, or will soon be explained, they will wait and specifically designed to accomplish this.
attempt to take in more information in order to achieve
clarification (Goethals & Cooper, 1975). In art situations, 2.3. Stage 3: secondary control and escape
Bloom and Markson (1998) note that viewers afford
a certain leeway to an artist. Parsons (1987, p. 74) adds, “the When discrepancy cannot be assimilated or ignored,
thought of the artist’s intentions allows us to believe that [a while it appears that no subsequent information will resolve
work] has a subjective meaning even when we cannot the discrepancy and an individual is confident that they
grasp what it is,” encouraging viewers to persist when have not made a mistake, we move to the next phase of
otherwise they might be tempted to move on. As argued interaction. Steele et al. (1993) note that at this point
above, researchers typically view this process of mutual discrepancies appear as such to the individual, self-protec-
reinforcement and assimilation itself as the archetypal tion, as opposed to self-reinforcement, begins to play an
conception of art-evaluation (e.g., reviewed historically by overt role, and elements such as tension and anxiety become
Berlyne, 1974, p. 9; Haworth in Mitias, 1982). Gadamer prevalent. This also entails a switch from “lower order and
concludes that it has as its goal the “achieving of a unity of often unconscious” perception to a “higher order process
sense: an interpretation of the whole (in Parsons, p. 81).” involving conscious assessment” and greater cognitive
And Leder et al. (2004, p. 493) add, “it is this entire process involvement.
that we call an aesthetic experience.” Particular mastery Interaction becomes a balancing act between elements
may even induce pleasurable flow-type states involving the self-image. According to Folkman, Lazarus,
(Csikszentmihalyi, 1990). Dunkel-Schetter, DeLongis, and Gruen (1986, p. 1000), the
However as this occurs from within the process of subject has “appraised [the] encounter as having to be
informational evaluation itself, it is essentially an act of accepted,” yet acceptance would impact the self negatively.
circularity, requiring a viewer to expand his/her classifica- In order to escape discrepancy, the individual must alter
tion or break off perception rather than modify pre- one of the two cognitions so that the relative impact on the
expectations to accept a discrepant element. Viewers may self is lessoned (Bem, 1967; Festinger, 1957). Viewers are
of course be bemused by art, pleasantly stimulated, or find left with a choice between the importance of maintaining
a work beautifuldaccounting for a great majority of art a sense of control and mastery and the relative importance
interactionsdhowever, if we restrict our analysis of art of the object, task or contextual elements. Because
perception to only this stage, it is essentially an act of what contextual factors are not typically important to the self-
Rothbaum, Weisz, and Snyder (1982) call “changing the image, while motor control and action expectations do
world,” so that current ideals and expectations might be impact comparatively higher “do goals” regarding efficacy
preserved. In fact, successful assimilation reinforces the and ability, viewers discard or diminish the environment.
existing self-schema (e.g., Csikszentmihalyi, 1990). While it In so doing they preserve the integrity of their own, failed,
becomes suspect to the criticisms laid out above, typified interaction. However this does not lead to a confrontation
by the conundrum Ingarden (1961) made explicit by of the self that might result in a true resolution. This phase
Author's personal copy

M. Pelowski, F. Akiba / New Ideas in Psychology 29 (2011) 80–97 89

represents what Rothbaum et al. (1982) call “secondary Efran and Spangler (1979; also Miceli & Castalfranchi,
control,” the attempt to covertly change the conditions of 2003) note that this movement is often aided by an
the environment so that a discrepancy can ultimately be external “trigger”da formal climax (discussed in Frey &
assimilated or ignored. Langseth, 1985; Sloboda, 1991), a mirror, camera, audi-
First, viewers attempt re-classification. In the case of ence, or the sound of ones own voice (Rothbaum et al.,
man-made stimuli, From (1971/1953; Norman, 2004) notes 1982); even a painting ‘watching you’ (Duval & Wicklund,
that this often utilizes the existence of motive, taking an 1972)dthat consummates an irresolvable conflict or
accusatory tonedthe artwork is a bad or meaningless induces this self-awareness. Dissonant events may also
example, i.e., the artist made a mistake, and therefore there slowly wear a viewer down over a length of time.
is no need for interpretation. A viewer may also misat- Rothbaum et al. (1982, p.28) note, “when the obstacle and
tribute discrepancy to an uncontrollable external sour- the resulting failure are salient and of lengthy duration.
cednatural phenomena, divine intervention, “an individuals’ resources are depleted and they are forced to
insurmountable task, chance, or a powerful other” give up.”
(Rothbaum et al., 1982, p. 8)dthereby absolving him/ It is viewers in this position that we can attach to
herself from culpability. From (p. 122) concludes that it is a discussion of transformation. In order to resolve this
only in rare cases that the viewer is not able to adequately position, viewers must reframe their own involvement
assign blame to an external source and fully escape from with the problem situation, seeking, what Torrance (1979,
the proceeding involvement. It is only in cases where “we p. 182) has called a “second-order change” whereby they
participate in such a manner that our personal status is “look outside” the problem to “the system” itself. This
affected,” where negative reclassification “is of importance occurs through viewers switching to a meta-cognitive
to our self-esteem.” Failing re-classification, viewers approach to their interpretation: acknowledging discrep-
attempt escape. Physically, they may leave the situation, ancy, revisiting their previous expectations or perceptual/
block out dissonant stimuli, or undertake action shifting conceptual schema, and eventually discarding or changing
attention away from the dissonant cognitiondclap, fidget, these schema or “do goals” themselvesdoften, essentially
talk to one’s neighbor (Rothbaum et al.). Individuals next “giving up” their attempt at direct control (Miceli &
attempt to escape mentally (e.g., Steele et al., 1993). Roth- Castalfranchi, 2003). Thereby viewers alter their own
baum et al. (p. 10) label this act “cognitive withdrawal,” hierarchical self-image, achieving a relative “self-trans-
which can be accomplished by raising the relative impor- formation” (Rothbaum et al., 1982).
tance of the individual’s ideal-selfdfocusing on other
positive self qualities not impacted by the discrepancy (e.g., 2.5. Stage 5: aesthetic outcome and new mastery
Hill & Martin, 1997)dor lowering the importance of the
discrepant eventdi.e., “it’s only art” (From). These It is this schema change or self-transformation that we
outcomes result in Dewey’s (1980, p. 52) second form of can then reunite to the current conception of aesthetic
“recognition,” “perception arrested at the point where it experience. As noted by Duval and Wicklund (1972) this
will serve some other purpose”dthe self is protected at the change allows a viewer to reset their interaction and re-
expense of the artwork. engage with a stimuli, employing a new set of schema that
may then allow renewed/deepened cognitive mastery (e.g.,
2.4. Stage 4: meta-cognitive re-assessment Sarason, Pierce, & Sarason 1996), and the ability to attend to
or understand previously discrepant elements (Dewey in
When assimilation and subsequent escape mechanisms Petts, 2000). This successful completion of schema change
are unsuccessful or are bypassed, however, and viewers is also explicitly tied in the literature to epiphanic emotions
become trapped in an intractable situation where the associated with aesthetic experience da feeling of
abortive alteration of either discrepant cognition is not “cathartic” release, epiphany, enlightenment, harmony,
possibledone can neither escape from perception nor pleasure and, often, tears (Efran & Spangler, 1979; Frijda,
change its repercussionsdviewers may instead enter into 1988; Labott & Martin, 1988; Miceli & Castalfranchi, 2003;
a period of active experiential and expectational re- Vingerhoets, Van Geleuken, Van Tilburg, & Van Heck,
assessment. This event is often accompanied, or preceded, 1997). It is also within the latency period following
by acute self-focused attention (Steele et al., 1993), which schema-change that viewers may return to a harmonious/
appears to serve as a catalyst for inducing an outcome in selfless contemplation of these new elements or the
discrepant encounters. While self-focused attention forces physical qualities of a stimuli that allowed for their
subjects who anticipate doing poorly to abort (Ingram, preceding experience (e.g., Dewey, 1980). And therefore it is
1990; Steenbarger & Aderman, 1979), through reclassifica- this outcome, brought about through previous discrepancy
tion and escape, it induces individuals who cannot abort to and schema-change, that Dewey (1950, p. 56) termed the
revisit and revise their expectations (Duval & Wicklund, “aesthetic phase” of experience.
1972; Greenwald, 1980; Steenbarger & Aderman, 1979).
Self-focus leads to the feeling of “increased submissive- 3. Art-perception and aesthetic experience
ness” and “individuation,” causes the individual to “focus reconsidered via disruption and transformation
attention on personal limitations and to increase perceived
uncontrollability” (Rothbaum et al., 1982, p. 23), increases Returning to the psychological/philosophical discussion
negative affect and anxiety (Mor & Winquist, 2002); and of art, it is this progression through disruption, to meta-
induces expectational re-assessment (Ingram, 1990). cognitive reflection, acceptance and self-change, rather
Author's personal copy

90 M. Pelowski, F. Akiba / New Ideas in Psychology 29 (2011) 80–97

than assimilation or escape, that introduces a vital element discrepancy, choosing instead to protect their own self-
of distinction in art experience. Adorno (1984/1970, p. 25) identities. “The [gallery] director. felt absolutely betrayed
put this best when he argued that aesthetic experience, by the Brillo Box. She hated them. she was livid at the
or enlightenment through art involves “the individual opening.” “People laughed. An artist friend of mine wrote
effect[ing] his identification with art not by assimilating the SHIT across the guest book.” They “were clearly not ready
work of art to himself,” as would occur in the initial for [an artwork] which put no premium whatever on the
cognitive mastery and secondary control stages, “but by romantic. imperatives that defined painting.”
assimilating himself to the work.” By introducing a means The epiphanic response to the works of Rothko follows
of breaking from the mastery process, through the intro- a similar progression. According to Nodelman (1997, p.
duction of meta-cognitive assessment and schema-change, 333), the paintings, monumental black and purple color
and then re-engaging in final mastery/assimilation with fields representative of mid-twentieth century abstract
a new set of schema/expectations, we introduce a means of expressionism, are “cunningly designed to incite” the
explaining the transcendental quality of artdreflecting attempt at direct mimetic interpretationdbegging viewers
a relative adjustment in a viewer’s self-image or relation- to find a message or meaning from the artistd“while at the
ship to the worlddas well as a means of connecting the same time rendering it untenable.” Elkins (2001, p. 11)
existing conception of mastery to insight, novelty and continues, viewers are forced into a turning point, “the
personal growth. moment when they have seen everything they can, and
This then also offers a means of explaining the arousal of they sense its time to look away.” It is viewers who do not
“aesthetic” harmony, pleasure and emotion itself. While flee at this point who are likely to have a moving experi-
this model may end with mastery and aesthetic emotions, ence. This in turn comes to fit into this model’s description
these responses are explicitly connected to this antecedent of meta-cognitive reflection. “Frustrated and thrown back
cognitive progression of discrepancy, overcoming self- to yourself,” Nodelman (p. 330) argues, “you become the
protectionary strategies and achieving self-transformation. center of the room. You think about your conduct, your
In this way, this final “aesthetic phase,” of experience, is body.” The art “forces disturbing questions about the
given grounding and purpose. Rather than being champ- nature of the self and its relation to the world.” One realizes
ioned for its own intrinsic value or the pleasure it entails, that the real is only “a system of signs constructed
these emotions become “signs. that point to a cognitive or continuously by and for the viewer” (p. 342). And this self-
psychological reorganization” (Efran & Spangler, p. 68), or confrontation and meta-cognitive assessment induces an
as noted by Bohart (1980, p. 199), “sign[s] that one is expectational change in the viewer, who “may emerge on
allowing oneself to actively experience and perceive.” In a new plateau” of understanding where “the experiential
turn, as Dewey argued, it is as much this antecedent structure of the installation [itself] is transformed.” “Rothko
disruption, as well as subsequent self-reflection, as it is final makes a “transcendental promise,” Dutoit and Bersani (in
harmony and pleasure, that should be regarded as an Elkins, p. 16) conclude, “but he breaks it and gives us
“aesthetic experience” and should be considered when ourselves.”
examining the perception of art. However, it is these It is by considering this tie to self-image, and the meta-
antecedent stages that are typically overlooked. cognitive nature of viewer assessment in the schema-
When we return to literary examples, however, we can change process, that we can account for these fundamental
trace this process. Danto’s account of transformation changes in a viewer’s relation to stimuli; and explain the
through viewing Warhol’s Brillo Box, for example, details “negative” quality of aesthetic transformation. The re-
a discrepancy between his pre-expectations and percep- assessment process may often explicitly take on a negative
tion, self-reflection and self-change. He recalls that he, tone, deeply tied to the defeat of a viewer’s personal
a philosopher interested in the ontological meaning of art, expectationsd“what did I expect?”; “what am I doing?”
was confronted with an artwork designed as an exact copy However, in all cases, schema-change requires a viewer to
of a commercial shipping container for soap, leaving him “give up” a previous, personally important, expectation or
(1992, p. 3) “struck by the question of how it was possible” desire for action (Miceli & Castalfranchi, 2003). The
for the Brillo Box to be a work of art. He recalled that this resulting transformation, in turn, creates a fundamental
placed him in the intractable position noted in this model, change in the viewer’s relation to the stimuli; a switch from
where either the work was not art, which, because it was positive informational analysis, or direct attempt to control
placed in an art gallery, called into question the very exis- their situation, to essentially an aniconic assessment of
tence of art itself; or it was art, but, because it was designed their own, “failed,” participation with art. This in turn
to not be beautiful or meaningful, was un-interpretable. reunites the outcome of art perception to the specific
This in turn challenged his previous philosophical basis for qualities of an artwork itself, which, by questioning vital
interpreting art (his “do goals”), and therefore his self- elements of a viewer’s self-image, creates the opportunity
identity as a philosopher. His aesthetic experience came for this self-reflection; and, when a viewer is able to ach-
when he realized that it was his own expectations for the ieve self adjustment, may be evaluated expressly for its
interpretability of art itself that were incorrect, and that ability to provide this enlightenment. Much like Rothko
this in fact was the intention of the artist; leading to above, Belting (2002, p. 391) notes of the epiphanic
epiphany and the famous “death” of artworks, as he had response to the empty films of Nam Jun Paik and the silent
known them. piano of John Cage, the artists “devised zones of silence as
Also recalled that many of his colleagues did not make it zones of freedom where the audience was expected to
past the “secondary control” stage when confronted by this become creative in the face of nothing.”
Author's personal copy

M. Pelowski, F. Akiba / New Ideas in Psychology 29 (2011) 80–97 91

This however, should not be thought of as a recent action is socially discouraged (e.g., Lutz, 1999; Vingerhoets
development, or a new kind of interaction, but rather can et al., 1997). Art history recounts these responses indicative
be traced throughout art experiences. Rollins (2004, p. 182) of “secondary control”: the desire to clap or yell (Elkins,
notes that this response is fundamental to paintings that 2001), the need to “do something with itdto run through
are often tied to conceptions of beauty and mimesis. He it, or eat it, or tear it apart (Beckley & Shapiro, 2001, p.
offered as an example Monet’s painting Springtime through 360).” The inability to do so, because of social constraints, is
the branches, arguing that it represented leaves so that it is deeply dissonant, and giving up this need or accepting the
impossible to combine them together in order to resolve impossibility of a correct response leads to intense emotion
their depth, leading to a forced, and eventually pleasurable, (Elkins, 2001; Goffman, 1974; Magherini, 1989). In these
re-assessment of the “way the visual system ordinarily cases, the particular discrepant cognitions in the model for
works.” This can also occur via discrepancy between what arriving at an “aesthetic phase” concern not the evaluation
is mimetically depicted in art and its relevance to a viewer. of the artwork itself, but the evaluation of one’s response
Magherini (1989; also Elkins, 2001) has documented while perceiving the artwork. However the progression
numerous intense responses to pre-modern works, from primary to secondary control to acceptance remains
involving for example a discrepant relation between fundamentally the same.
a “repressed” gay male viewer, a troublingly titular Rubens While each account, and the specific combination of
painting of a young man, and transformative confrontation events that conspire to create transformation and the
of the viewer’s self-expectations. As she concluded, while specific relevance of this outcome to a viewer are of course
“different people have strong reactions to the same works different in each case, this model gives us a means of
of art,” response ultimately comes down to “the [viewer’s] considering these elements via this underlying progres-
history and personal experience” (in Elkins, p. 47), and self- sion, and a key elementdthis self or schema changedthat
adjustments therein. unites them. This allows us to expand this model beyond
In his empirical studies of music, Sloboda (1991, p. 120) art, providing a basic mechanism for self-transformations
notes this same mechanism, arguing that emotional or in the relation to environmental stimuli, without need for
aesthetic responses are linked to “creation and violation of a definition of “artworks”. This also draws together both
expectancy. within musical structures.” In opera, Poizat man-made and natural stimulidi.e., those with an absence
(1992/1986) notes that aesthetic emotions occur when or presence of perceived underlying intentionalitydas well
viewers “dimly sense that the singer is trying to free as objects not intended to be art. Again, as was discussed
themselves from the prison of words. at the point when above, objects that are perceived as “artworks” certainly
a voice has almost made it, but gives out” (in Elkins, 2001, p. invite a set of pre-expectations that play an important role
146) forcing a viewer to give up their prior expectation. in information processing, and may determine the specific
Burch-Brown (1983, p. 122) argues that transformational or means of escape in secondary control, however, the basic
epiphanic experience from reading poetry results from mechanism of self-change itself remains the same. As noted
a “metaphoric process” that alters one’s expectations in above, great deal of 20th century art, notably the Brillo Box,
such a way as to engage and change their “whole self.” created disruption and reflection in viewers by presenting
This process can also be traced in accounts that corre- objects not intended to look like “art.” More recently,
spond directly to the classical conception of aesthetic exhibitions, such as the 1998 Guggenheim exhibition of
experience. Cases of extremely resonant stim- Harley Davidson motorcycles, created disruption and
ulidexperiences beauty or harmony (e.g., documented by reflection through the appropriation, into the “art” context,
Elkins, 2001)dor “sublime,” overwhelming natural of objects expressly not intended to be art. And with post-
phenomena, when considered in the broadened viewpoint modernism and performance art, “artists” have moved past
of this model, are often marked by discrepancy between even this trope, using design to question elements of life
one’s expectations for understanding the significance of having nothing to do with “art” at all. We would argue, it is
what they have perceived and their actual response. Elkins this procession, regardless of the specific stimuli, that
(p. 20) argues that, while the examples above are “painfully writers implicitly refer to when speaking of ”challenge” of
vacant,” these cases are “overfull”. Miceli and Castalfranchi art. And it is art’s ability to act, in whatever form, as an
(2003, p. 260) add, viewers experience a “sense of contrast impetus of this process, again, that is given as the historical
between one’s experience. and one’s perceived ‘small- basis and definition of art itself (Becker, 1982).
ness’, ordinariness, and imperfection. together with one’s In turn, Dewey (1929, 1956) explicitly argued for
helpless need to comprehend and express the whole a fundamental equivalence between artworks and educa-
experience.” “Viewers see more [,or experience more,] than tional materials, and for basic equivalence between this
they expect” (Elkins, p. 20). And, again, it is self-awareness, conception of “aesthetic experience” and everyday acts of
acceptance, and final forfeiture of one’s expectations for growth and insight. And this model can be readily con-
control that leads to pleasure and epiphany. As Frijda (1988, nected to numerous such conceptions. Gadamer (1984, p.
p. 351) concludes, these instances result from meta- 317), writing of knowledge acquisition, much like Dewey,
cognitive “awareness of [one’s] state of action readiness” noted two types of experience: an initial facile interaction
and, ultimately, “some change” in one’s expectations for with the environment that “fit[s] in with our expectation
this state. Koestler (in Frey & Langseth, 1985, p. 92) adds; and confirm[s] it,” and “real” experience “[whereby] we
these experiences too are always “self-transcending.” gain through it better knowledge, not only of itself, but of
Viewers may also be presented with a powerful stim- what we thought we knew before.” This is reiterated by
ulus in a situation, such as a museum, where an overt Heidegger in his notion of “destructive hermeneutics,”
Author's personal copy

92 M. Pelowski, F. Akiba / New Ideas in Psychology 29 (2011) 80–97

requiring for the discovery of something new, that the discussion in the introduction. Following the typical
“traditional interpretive instrument breaks down” and an conception of the arts as affording detached moments of
individual be forced to evaluate their schema for “being in contemplation, we are lead to assume that the role that art
the world” (Spanos, 1993, p. 55). Torrance (1979), in his might play in human existence is as a form of “rehearsal,”
review of insight and “aha moments” in education, notes with the consequences of interaction somehow removed
this same process of antecedent disruption and decon- from a viewer’s real life. It is assumed that “aesthetic”
struction of initial schema and ideas leading to meta- interaction fits into this cognitive mastery process where
cognitive reflection and acquisition of new knowledge. viewers test their conceptions and seek challenge, being
This model can also be connected to conceptions of careful not to go too far so as to find themselves in an
transformative experience in religion or spiritual contexts. intractable position. And the idea of “aesthetic” evaluation,
Notably, James (1958) description of religious experience as detached analysis of an object’s informational qualities,
noted“to get to it, a critical point must usually be passed, itself informs this conception. This paper, however, argues
a corner turned within one. Something must give way,” just the opposite. Truly detached “aesthetic” contempla-
explicitly linking this progression to negative emotions, tion, as noted above, would signal a self-defense/rein-
a “change in terms of the old self” and a final feeling of forcement mechanism, allowing a viewer to escape
“conversion” (pp. 169–175). This “negative” nature of reli- personal involvement with their environmentdleading to
gious transformation is reiterated by Kierkegaard (in the discomfort of many writers when this conception of
Spanos, 1993). Stoudenmire (1971, p. 254) adds that the aesthetics is extrapolated to the ‘aestheticization’ of war
initial contradiction of one’s religious beliefs elicits and tragedy (e.g., Arendt, 1958). This, however, exemplifies
“significantly more emotion” than expectational affirma- the basic disconnect with the current approach to art,
tion. And the phenomenon of “satori” or enlightenment in where despite the effort of artworks to force intractable
Zen Buddhism explicitly follows this failure-based disruption, it is this process that is dissuaded by the focus
progression. Suzuki (1950, p. 87; also Torrance, 1979) notes on physical/mimetic evaluation. Jagodzinski (1981, p. 29)
that “a psychological impasse” and a “highly wrought-up makes this explicit when he laments; “by fiat, new art
state of consciousness” are “the necessary antecedent of forms are critical and reflective of existence” [demanding]
satori.” Sogen Hori (2000) adds that Zen masters, playing “please don’t relax and have an aesthetic experience.”
the role of artist, and using the religious context of However, what this paper calls for is an entirely
Buddhism as their medium, violate the basic rules of different conception of aesthetic experience, equated to
interaction, creating a discrepancy between students’ cognitive schema-change rather than a particular manner
expectations and their perception, inducing reassessment, of perception, because such labels become meaningless as
schema-change and epiphany. they shade into other psychological/contextual disciplines.
This then suggests a potential universal nature to these In turn, this expressly requires a viewer/artwork to over-
accounts, able to explain the equivalence of small acts of come the human instinct of escape or assimilation through
insight and “big” aesthetic experiences. Essentially, as surface evaluation or self-withdrawal and instead enter an
Carver (1996; also Festinger, 1957) has argued, regardless of intractable position whereby one might use their own
what the specific stimuli and means of arousing discrep- disruptive encounter as a means of self-reflection and
ancy are, the more fundamental an affected schema or transformation, and therefore come to believe or see
concept is to the core self-image, the greater the magnitude something new, as well as feel pleasure, epiphany and
of potential dissonance, the greater the difficulty in over- harmony.
coming self protection, and therefore the greater the final Finally, while there are examples of art experience that
transformation of the hierarchical self; and the more do seem to break suddenly upon viewers (see
profound the experience. Csikszentmihalyi, 1990), their distinction from the above
We might even connect this process to shocking events accounts highlights this important cognitive distinction.
such as war, natural disaster or the World Trade Center Without this process of disruption, reflection and meta-
tragedy.1 Virilio and Lotringer (2002) note that, while for cognitive change, in which a viewer is able to process their
many, overwhelming violence and its aftermath constitute experience and make it a part of their life, these events do
a simply horrifying experience, for some, these events, not contain a cognitive resolution, they do not change
what Virilio (p. 147) called “negative historical monu- future behaviordsave for possibly motivating a viewer to
ments,” act, just as artworks, as a “rite of passage,” try again to duplicate the feeling. They do not include
becoming “the means by which you connect creatively to a component of self-modification and leave the viewer
the world” or “touch base with reality” itself (p. 9). This is of without any understanding of the significance of the
course not to champion the transformative potential of preceding event (e.g., Carver, 1996; Csikszentmihalyi, 1990;
disaster, but to equate it, as one more potential stimuli, in Smith, 1996). These accounts often appear to be the result
this basic mechanism of disruption and change. of the application of a classification that is so broad, or
This reiterates one more important note about this flawed, so as to allow for wonderment and contemplation;
model’s discussion, connecting back to the educational and examples from the arts often suggest that the viewer
entered the experience in an already altered state of fatigue
or dreams, returning to question of facile assimilation.
1
These examples were raised in the peer review of this paper.
Often they share a sense of lost opportunity. Kandinsky
However, the specific interpretation of these examples is that of the lamented that he tried to recreate his impression and “only
authors. half succeeded” (Weiss, 2005, p. 145). Proust (1981/1954, p.
Author's personal copy

M. Pelowski, F. Akiba / New Ideas in Psychology 29 (2011) 80–97 93

48) diminished his madeleine experience, summing up the that that the artist’s intention for the artwork, rather than
problems with “isolated, detached” moments of success, transmitting signs, may have been the creation of the
“with no suggestion of origin”d“Whence did it come? viewer’s preceding experience itself. For example, Danto
What did it mean? How could I seize and apprehend it?” (1992), when assessing the meaning of the Brillo Box
surmised that what it was “about” was its ability to ques-
4. Factors for empirical study: interrelation between tion his attempt to answer that very question. The
emotion, appraisal and viewer experience through the descriptions of Rollins (2004) and Fraser (2006) above offer
stages of aesthetic experience similar examples. It is this personalized, experience-based
interpretation of art that Dewey (1980) and Tucker (2004)
Whether talking of peak accounts or the basic mecha- argue constitutes the goal of a deepened art experience.
nism of change in art perception, this then leaves one final And it is this form of interpretation that Bourdieu (1984/
question for this paperdthe empirical study of this process. 1979) claims is expressly demanded by post-modern and
As noted above, if we focus only on the peak conclusion of much contemporary art.
epiphany or assimilation of art information, we are left with This progression might be assessed by having viewers
no means of assessing art experience other than pleasure or keep a log of their interactions with an artwork, or asking
formal assessment. And as Osborne (1979) notes, there is viewers to walk a researcher through their interaction after
probably then no individual measure that could determine the fact, as in the work by Roald (2007), looking for these
the occurrence of an “aesthetic” experience. changes. Alternatively, Pelowski (2007) has asked viewers
However, if we approach art perception not as a distinct to describe the “meaning” of an artwork, as well as the
moment of assessment, but rather, following the discussion “artist’s motive,” after a viewing experience, assessing their
of this paper, as a progression of stages whereby the viewer answer via these three stages. We are essentially then
matches and adjusts their self-schema against an artwork, calling for an analysis of art perception, if at all possible, in
we can connect a great deal of existing work on the various a “natural” setting, in which a viewer is allowed to interact,
stages discussed herein. By using this model as a frame, and without intrusion, with a complete work of art. From (1971/
introducing this process of self-change, we can then 1953), and Bloom and Markson (1998), on the other hand,
introduce a means of considering the interrelation of have explored this isolated progression in the laboratory,
emotion, appraisal, understanding and viewer self- presenting viewers with an artwork or stimuli and then
conception through each stage of this model. By consid- purposefully introduced a discrepancy, typically by calling
ering the elements most likely to arise throughout an into question the existence of artist motive or a work’s
experience culminating in this schema-change (detailed in classification as a meaningful object, tracking viewer
Table 1), we can then propose a means of identifying this response through these stages.
outcome and making a distinction from facile acts of It is also important to note that this final experiential
assimilation or abortive secondary control. While it is assessment proposed as the end-state of a transformative
certainly true that schema-change itself may occur over outcome should not be confused with what Leder et al.
a long period of time, involving multiple stimuli, because of (2004) have described as self-related interpretation, refer-
the distinct nature of most meetings with art, we can argue ring to a form of art assessment often equated with facile
that this full progression might be looked for in a specific understanding. While the latter involves assessment of
encounter. formal qualities in relation to existing schema that a viewer
may holddi.e., “that character looks like my cousin”dthe
5. Art evaluation and assessment of meaning experiential interpretation reflects the viewer’s own art
experience itself and the role the artwork plays in this
This model posits three general outcomes to art view- experience.
ingdinitial self-reinforcing mastery, abortive self-protec-
tionary escape in secondary control, and final “aesthetic” 6. Appraisal and self-conception
meta-cognitive schema-change. When looking at the
evaluation of art and the assessment of meaning, we would When looking to appraisal of art, again, much useful
expect to track an evolution in viewer understanding work has been done which might be applied to this
through these stages within a distinct art encounter: discussion; specifically, the work of Berlyne (1974), Vitz
beginning with 1) direct evaluation of art in the cognitive (reviewed in Funch, 1997), or approaches considered by
mastery stage, involving appraisals of the formal elements Scherer (1999), which consider a multivariate analysis of
of an artwork such as those qualities noted by Berlyne appraisal terms. As these authors note, following the initial
(1974)dits semiotic or conceptual meaning, its historical work of Osgood, Suci, and Tannenbaum (1961), who also
or cultural significance, as well as syntactic and expressive applied this analysis to art, appraisal typically can be
qualities transmitted via the art form. Given discrepancy divided into the three factors of an evaluative or hedonic
that cannot be assimilated, this should then be followed by response, as well as evaluations of potency and activity.
2) a period of meaninglessness and loss of understanding of While much work has gone toward the consideration of,
artist motive in the secondary control stage; concluding predominantly hedonic, factors in aesthetic experi-
with 3) a fundamental shift in assessment from the infor- encedspecifically the tie between complexity or challenge
mational plane to a meta-cognitive mode of “experiential” posed by art and hedonic value/beauty, relation between
interpretation. In the case of plastic arts, viewers may understanding and positive or negative hedonic evaluation,
revise their analysis of the artwork’s significance, deciding and the agreeable “collative” application of art to one’s self
Author's personal copy

94 M. Pelowski, F. Akiba / New Ideas in Psychology 29 (2011) 80–97

in the assimilation process (e.g., Berlyne)dthere has not as well as Cupchik (1994), have questioned this assump-
been consideration of the underlying role that self-image, tion, suggesting that initial difficulty may instead lead to
and threats to this self, play in determining viewer a deepened hedonic response. This in turn may be tied to
response to, and assessment of, art (e.g., Scherer). Nor has this epiphanic/schema-change progression proposed
there been a consideration of assessment following major herein, suggesting that the final stage in this model may
changes in viewer relationship to artworks. result in a more profound hedonic appraisal. By tying
When we return to the three stages proposed for viewer appraisal to the other factors of evaluation and emotion, we
interaction moving to schema-change, it is this role of might shed light on this distinction. These proposed
self-protection, self-reinforcement, and final self-trans- changes in viewer evaluation of artist and “art,” which may
formation that might give further shape to many assess- represent either self-protection or self-transformation, also
ments of art appraisal. Evaluation ending in initial cognitive call for future exploration.
mastery, according to Garfinkel (1967) and Goffman (1974), Miceli and Castalfranchi (2003) also argue that this
should likely reveal appraisals that aid in ignoring or progression from secondary control to schema-change
assimilating discrepancy, thereby aiding self-reinforce- should manifest in re-evaluation of a viewer’s own self-
ment, diminishing the potential threat to the individual by image, revealing, in the case of the transformation posited
reducing art’s potential meaningfulness and importance in this model, increased personal impotence as a viewer
(also Rothbaum et al., 1982). We might expect these low- acknowledges discrepancy and gives up attempts at
ered measures in baseline evaluation of the general cate- control. This might be assessed by issuing matched pre-
gory of “art”. When experience ends in the secondary and post-tests evaluating a viewer self-image following
control stage, on the other hand, we would expect self- Osgood et al. (1961). Bem (1967) notes that changes in self
protectionary strategies to play an important role in appraisal using multivariate analysis may prove a ready
appraisal. This might be revealed through an analysis of indicator of this cognitive self transformation.
terms corresponding to potency or activity. Carroll (1959, p.
113) notes that these factors of appraisal suggest 7. Emotion, physiological response and experiential
a measurement of the amount of adjustment that “must be factors
made” to a stimulus. Berlyne (1974) too has noted the
ability of these regions to measure “collative uncertainty” Finally, a review of literature on the major cognitive
or tension between pre-expectations and perception in art elements of this modeldcognitive dissonance studies,
assessment. We would expect a correlation between secondary control and schema changedalso offers a means
secondary control and negative evaluations in these scales, of ordering and incorporating numerous emotions and
reducing the “need” for evaluation from an individual and physiognomic responses, as well as specific experiential
therefore reducing the threat art plays to the self. Viewers factors, to this discussion.
may also evaluate the artist in equally negative terms, Discrepancy in the cognitive mastery stage should
reflecting the accusatory or dismissive tone noted above by correspond physiologically to sympathetic arousal of the
From (1971/1953). Matched pre and post testing may also autonomic nervous system (Frey & Langseth, 1985; Gross,
show a re-evaluation of general categories of art and artist Fredrickson, & Levenson, 1994). Whereas successful assim-
reflecting this lowered importance and potency. In addi- ilation of discrepancy results in a “positive” feeling of
tion, Becker (1974, p. 773; also Harrington, 2004), adds, an “anticipation or excitement,” unsuccessful assimilation
“attack” on the self, “becomes an attack on the aesthetic results in confusion, anxiety and tension (Epstein, 1973), as
related to it,” and for viewers who end with escape, we well as loss, failure and threat (Efran & Spangler, 1979).
expect a negative hedonic evaluation of the artwork as Movement to secondary control results in heightened
“distasteful,” “ugly” and bad. Finally, with schema-change, tension, anxiety and professed desire to leave or abort an
the work may be again evaluated positively, as evaluation interaction (Steele et al., 1993). Viewers may note elements
moves from self-protectionary impotence and lack of seri- tied to self-awarenessdawareness of others, feeling of being
ousness to evaluations revealing heightened potency watched, awareness of one’s body and actions. And for those
(Becker, 1982), affecting both specific artwork and re- who do not escape, but continue on to the meta-cognitive
evaluation of the general category of art. In this way, as re-assessment, we should find a switch from outward
noted by Bourdieu (1984/1979) this final schema-change “subjective awareness” to inward “self-awareness” (Duval &
with a specific artwork may also create a deepened rela- Wicklund, 1972), and specific awareness of “triggering”
tionship between viewer and the category of art itself. elements, marking a distinction between these stages.
This of course, leaves many questions for future study, Schema-change itself, then, appears to temporarily
such as the relation that this model proposes between intensify the preceding tension and emotion (e.g., Miceli &
impotence of artworks, negative hedonic assessment and Castalfranchi, 2003). The moment of schema change
threat to the self, or potency and positive assessment of appears to result in both sympathetic and parasympathetic
beauty and worth given “aesthetic” outcome. This also response. Gross et al. (1994, p. 466) conclude, “it may be
raises the question of possible differences between initial precisely this coordinated activation of parasympathetic
assessments of beauty or hedonic evaluation and that and sympathetic [response] that makes [it] such a potent
following a schema-change. While it is generally assumed physiological state.” This is accompanied by meta-cognitive
that initial assimilation or understanding of art results in analysis of the previous activity, analysis of one’s motives,
reward/relief and therefore positive assessment (e.g., changing one’s mind; and reported epiphany. As the indi-
Berlyne, 1974), recent studies by Russell and Milne (1997), vidual moves past the height of schema change into
Author's personal copy

M. Pelowski, F. Akiba / New Ideas in Psychology 29 (2011) 80–97 95

a period of latency, parasympathetic response is expected, their experience may include pleasure and “mastery,” too
as is reported relief, happiness and pleasure (Efran & should lack important factors in this full pro-
Spangler, 1979; Labott & Martin, 1988; Miceli & gressiondspecifically, self-focus and expectational change.
Castalfranchi, 2003). This outcome may also be accompa- Just as this cognitive progression underlying this progres-
nied by tears, which, according to Frey and Langseth (1985), sion is argued to be universal, so too should be these
represent a physical indicator of schematic change. Martin appraisals and emotions in each stage. As Ellsworth and
and Labott (1991) also note a correlation between this final Scherer (2003, p. 584) have argued, the relationship
aesthetic emotion/tears and superior recall of the between these factors, considering their tie to self-protection,
preceding experience. Physiological factors might be “is culturally general, perhaps even universal.”
measured by galvanic skin response, following Ram-
achandran and Hirstein (in Leder et al., 2004). In turn, 9. General conclusion
emotional/experiential factors might be assessed by ques-
tionnaire or through interviews (e.g., Pelowski, 2007; This paper argued for an alternate approach to the
Roald, 2007). traditional conception of aesthetic experience, and the
current modeling of art perception. Instead of initial
8. Specific combination of factors in empirical study assimilation of viewer to artwork, and an exclusive analysis
of aesthetic experience of art’s formal information, we argued that a model focused
on discrepancy, and subsequent processes of overcoming
When we consider the above elements in combination discrepancy through meta-cognitive analysis and expecta-
(Table 1), following the underlying progression to schema- tional or schema change may allow us to account for those
change discussed herein, we can begin to organize art- disruptive and transformative aesthetic experiences in art’s
experience based upon the combination of factors reported. history. In addition, we argue that this basic mechanism for
Viewer experiences of emotion and experiential factors schema change itself should not be thought of as mystical
should reflect their historical movement through each or once in a lifetime event, although when it involves
subsequent stage of this model, while art appraisal, self- fundamental aspects of the self it certainly can be, but
evaluation and understanding should show a correlation rather may be an everyday occurrence. This in turn calls for
with the stage at which experience ends. When looking to much future work considering the aspects raised by this
the transformative outcome, we can argue that those model.
viewers who do achieve schema-change should report this Essentially, this calls for a broadening of what we
entire progression of experiential terms, including: anxiety, consider to constitute an aesthetic experience itself, and
tension and confusion from failed cognitive mastery, self- what researchers include in their study of art perception. It
awareness and meta-cognitive re-assessment, as well as may be that what is considered to constitute cognitive
happiness, relief, tears and epiphany, which may serve as mastery in the present conception is actual deepened
a central marker of transformation. Viewers may also report mastery following this model proposed herein, where
specific changes, reflecting lowered personal potency, in a viewer, in a single encounter with art, both leaves the
their own self-image, and increased importance and mastery process due to failure, and returns with a new
potency in art. Epiphany and schema-change should be tied means of addressing, and new relationship to, the artwork
to a movement from direct informational evaluation to an itself. This in turn calls for a renewed focus on the rela-
experiential evaluation of art, as well as final assessments of tionship between viewer and artwork. By dealing with this
beauty and quality. As argued above, this makes an explicit combination in terms of viewer processes for self-protec-
tie between emotion and cognitive appraisal/evaluation, tion rather than the specific meaning of art, this model may
and a natural progression to emotions themselves. In addi- provide a means of generalizing and discussing this
tion, following Steele et al. (1993), the antecedent emotions phenomenon. Ultimately, the most fruitful question may
of anxiety, confusion, as well as self-focused attention, become, what environmental and psychological combina-
become important elements of both an art encounter and tions allow viewers to move beyond assimilation/escape to
final, often selfless, aesthetic epiphany. Cupchik and this aesthetic outcome, and how can this be enhanced?
Gebotys (1988) too have suggested the importance of
discrepancy and the overcoming of disruption as a vital
References
component of insight and mastery of art. However, this
model provides a frame for understanding this process. Adorno, T. W. (1984). Aesthetic theory (C. Lenhardt, Trans.). London:
When we talk of a unique art encounter, Arnheim (1966) has Routledge & Kegan and Henley. (Original work published in 1970).
given the rough estimate of 10 min necessary for this Arendt, H. (1958). The human condition. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
complete progression. Arnheim, R. (1966). Toward a psychology of art. Berkeley: University of
On the other hand, viewers who show discrepancy, California Press.
anxiety and confusion but lack this full progression, should Beardsley, M. C. (1969). Aesthetic experience regained. The Journal of
Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 28(1), 3–11.
show negative appraisals, reflecting the influence of abor-
Becker, H. S. (1982). Art worlds. Berkeley: University of California Press.
tive self-protection. They should remain on the informa- Beckley, B., & Shapiro, D. (Eds.). (2001). Uncontrollable beauty: Toward
tional plane of assessment, or evaluate art as meaningless. a new aesthetics. New York: Allworth Press.
In addition they should not report self-focused attention or Belting, H. (2002). Beyond iconoclasm: Nam June Paik, the Zen gaze and
the escape from representation. In B. Latour, & P. Weibel (Eds.),
epiphanic emotions, and should show no self-trans- Iconoclash: Beyond the image wars in science, religion and art (pp. 390–
formation. While those who lack discrepancy, although 401). Cambridge, MA.: MIT Press.
Author's personal copy

96 M. Pelowski, F. Akiba / New Ideas in Psychology 29 (2011) 80–97

Bem, D. J. (1967). Self-perception: an alternative interpretation of Elkins, J. (2001). Pictures and tears; a history of people who have cried in
cognitive dissonance phenomena. Psychological Review, 74(3), 183– front of paintings. New York: Routledge.
200. Ellsworth, P. C., & Scherer, K. R. (2003). Appraisal processes in emotion. In
Berlyne, D. E. (1974). Studies in the new experimental aesthetics: Steps R. J. Davidson, K. R. Scherer, & H. H. Goldsmith (Eds.), Handbook of
toward an objective psychology of aesthetic appreciation. Washington, affective sciences (pp. 572–595). Oxford, England: Oxford University
DC: Hemisphere. Press.
Bersson, R. (1982). Against feeling: aesthetic experience in technocratic Epstein, S. (1973). The self-concept revisited; or a theory of a theory.
society. Art Education, 35(4), 34–39. American Psychologist, 28, 404–414.
Blanchot, M. (1997). Friendship (E. Rottenberg, Trans.). Stanford, CA: Fenner, D. E. W. (1996). The aesthetic attitude. Atlantic Highlands, NJ:
Stanford University Press. (Original work published in 1971). Humanities Press.
Bloom, P., & Markson, L. (1998). Intention and analogy in children’s Ferree, G. (1968). The descriptive use of "aesthetic experience". Journal of
naming of pictorial representations. Psychological Science, 9(3), 200– Aesthetic Education, 2(2), 23–35.
204. Ferreira, F., Christianson, K., & Hollingworth, A. (2001). Misinterpretation
Bohart, A. C. (1980). Toward a cognitive theory of catharsis. Psychotherapy: of garden-path sentences: implications for models of sentence pro-
Theory, Research, Practice, 17(2), 192–201. cessing and reanalysis. Journal of Psycholinguistic Research, 30(1),
Bourdieu, P. (1984). Distinction: A social critique of the judgment of taste (R. 3–20.
Nice, Trans.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. (Original Festinger, L. (1957). A theory of cognitive dissonance. London: Travistock.
work published in 1979). Folkman, S., Lazarus, R. S., Dunkel-Schetter, C., DeLongis, A., & Gruen, R. J.
Burch-Brown, F. (1983). Transfiguration; poetic metaphor and the language (1986). Dynamics of a stressful encounter: cognitive appraisal, coping,
of religious belief. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press. and encounter outcomes. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
Carroll, J. B. (1959). Review of the measurement of meaning. In J. G. 50(5), 992–1003.
Snider, & C. E. Osgood (Eds.), Semantic differential technique; Fraser, A. (2006). Why does Fred Sandback’s work make me cry? Grey
a sourcebook (pp. 58–77). Chicago: Aldine Publishing Company. Room, 22, 30–47.
Carroll, N. (1986). Art and interaction. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Frazier, L., & Clifton, C., Jr. (1998). Sentence reanalysis and visibility. In J.
Criticism, 45(1), 57–68. D. Fodor, & F. Ferreira (Eds.), Reanalysis in sentence processing (pp.
Carver, C. S. (1996). Cognitive interference and the structure of behavior. 143–176). Dordrecht: Kluwer.
In I. G. Sarason, G. R. Pierce, & B. R. Sarason (Eds.), Cognitive inter- Freedberg, D. (1989). The power of images. Chicago: University of Chicago
ference; theories, methods, and findings (pp. 25–46). Mahwah, NJ: press.
Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Frey, William H., II, & Langseth, M. (1985). Crying; the mystery of tears.
Crittenden, B. S. (1968). From description to evaluation in aesthetic Minneapolis: Winston Press.
judgment. Journal of Aesthetic Education, 2(4), 37–58. Frijda, N. (1988). The laws of emotion. American Psychologist, 43, 349–358.
Csikszentmihalyi, M. (1990). Flow; the psychology of optimal experience. From, F. (1971). Perception of other people (B.A. Maher & E. Kvan, Trans.).
New York: Harper Perennial. New York: Columbia University Press. (Original work published in
Csikszentmihalyi, M., & Rochenberg-Halton, E. (1981). The meaning of 1953).
things; domestic symbols and the self. Cambridge, England: Cambridge Funch, B. S. (1997). The psychology of art appreciation. Copenhagen:
University Press. Museum Tusculanum Press, University of Copenhagen.
Cupchik, G. C. (1994). Emotion in aesthetics: reactive and reflective Gadamer, H. (1984). Truth and method. New York: Crossroad.
models. Poetics, 23, 177–188. Garfinkel, H. (1967). Studies in ethnomethodology. Englewood Cliffs, NJ:
Cupchik, G. C., & Gebotys, R. J. (1988). The search for meaning in art: Prentice-Hall.
interpretive styles and judgments of quality. Visual Arts Research, 14, Gelman, S. A., & Ebeling, K. S. (1998). Shape and representational status in
38–50. children’s early naming. Cognition, 66, B35–B47.
Danto, A. C. (1986). The philosophical disenfranchisement of art. New York: Gilbert, D. T., McNulty, S. E., Giuliano, T. A., & Benson, J. E. (1992). Blurry
Columbia University Press. words and fuzzy deeds; the attribution of obscure behavior. Journal of
Danto, A. C. (1992). Beyond the brillo box; the visual arts in post-historical Personality and Social Psychology, 62(1), 18–25.
perspective. New York: Farrar, Straus, Giroux. Goethals, G. R., & Cooper, J. (1975). When dissonance is reduced: the
Dewey, J. (1929). The quest for certainty: A study of the relation of knowl- timing of self-justificatory attitude change. Journal of Personality and
edge and action. New York: Minton, Balch & Company. Social Psychology, 32(2), 361–367.
Dewey, J. (1950). Aesthetic experience as a primary phase and as an artistic Goffman, E. (1974). Frame analysis; an essay on the organization of expe-
development. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 9(1), 56–58. rience. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Dewey, J. (1951). Experience, knowledge and value: a rejoinder. In P. A. Goulding, C. (2000). The museum environment and the visitor experi-
Schilpp (Ed.), The philosophy of John Dewey (pp. 515–608). New York: ence. European Journal of Marketing, 34(3), 261–278.
Tudor Publishing Company. Greenwald, A. G. (1980). The totalitarian ego; fabrication and revision of
Dewey, J. (1956). The child and the curriculum, and the school and society. personal history. American Psychologist, 35(7), 603–618.
Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. Gross, J. J., Fredrickson, B. L., & Levenson, R. W. (1994). The psychophys-
Dewey, J. (1980). Art as experience. New York: Perigee. iology of crying. Psychophysiology, 31, 460–468.
Dickie, G. (1974). Beardsley’s theory of aesthetic experience. Journal of Gutheil, G., Bloom, P., Valderrama, N., & Freedman, R. (2004). The role of
Aesthetic Education, 8(2), 13–23. historical intuitions in children’s and adults’ naming of artifacts.
Doll Jr., W. E. (1972). An analysis of John Dewey’s educational writings Cognition, 91, 23–42.
interpreted with reference to his concept of change (Doctoral disserta- Haanstra, F. (1996). Effects of art education on visual-spatial ability and
tion, The John Hopkins University, 1972). Ann Arbor, MI: University aesthetic perception: a quantitative review. Studies in Art Education,
Microfilms International. 37(4), 197–209.
Donoghue, D. (1983). The arts without mystery. Boston: Little Brown and Harrington, A. (2004). Art and social theory: Sociological arguments in
Company. aesthetics. Cambridge, England: Polity Press.
Dufrenne, M. (1973). The phenomenology of aesthetic experience. Chicago: Hendon, W. S., Costa, F., & Rosenberg, R. A. (1989). The general public and
Northwestern University Press. the art museum: case studies of visitors to several institutions iden-
Duval, S., & Wicklund, R. A. (Eds.). (1972). A theory of objective self tify characteristics of their publics. American Journal of Economics and
awareness. New York: Academic Press. Sociology, 48(2), 231–243.
Eaton, M. M. (1995). The social construction of aesthetic response. British Hill, P., & Martin, R. B. (1997). Empathic weeping, social communication,
Journal of Aesthetics, 35(2), 95–107. and cognitive dissonance. Journal of Social and Clinical Psychology, 16
Eaton, M. M. (2000). A sustainable definition of “art”. In N. Carroll (Ed.), (3), 299–322.
Theories of art today (pp. 141–155). Madison: University of Wisconsin Ingarden, R. (1961). Aesthetic experience and aesthetic object. Philosophy
Press. and Phenomenological Research, 21(3), 289–313.
Eaton, M. M., & Moore, R. (2002). Aesthetic experience: its revival and its Ingram, R. E. (1990). Self-focused attention in clinical disorders: review
relevance to aesthetic education. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art and a conceptual model. Psychological Bulletin, 107(2), 156–176.
Criticism, 36(2), 9–23. Jagodzinski, J. (1981). Aesthetic education reconsidered or please don’t
Efran, J. S., & Spangler, T. J. (1979). Why grown-ups cry; a two-factor have an aesthetic experience! Art Education, 34(3), 26–29.
theory and evidence from The Miracle Worker. Motivation and James, W. (1958). The varieties of religious experience: A study in human
Emotion, 3(1), 63–72. nature. New York: New American Library.
Author's personal copy

M. Pelowski, F. Akiba / New Ideas in Psychology 29 (2011) 80–97 97

Jansen-Verbeke, M., & van Rekom, J. (1996). Scanning museum visitors. Rollins, M. (2004). What Monet meant: intention and attention in
Annals of Tourism Research, 23(2), 364–375. understanding art. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 62(2),
Kant, I. (1978). The critique of judgment (J.C. Meredith, Tans.). Oxford, 175–187.
England: Oxford University Press. (Original work published in 1790). Rothbaum, F., Weisz, J. R., & Snyder, S. (1982). Changing the world and
Labott, S. M., & Martin, R. B. (1988). Weeping: evidence for a cognitive changing the self: a two-process model of perceived control. Journal
theory. Motivation and Emotion, 12(3), 205–216. of Personality and Social Psychology, 42(1), 5–37.
Lasher, M. D., Carroll, J. M., & Bever, T. G. (1983). The cognitive basis of Russell, P. A., & Milne, S. (1997). Meaningfulness and hedonic value of
aesthetic experience. Leonardo, 16(3), 196–199. paintings: effects of titles. Empirical Studies of the Arts, 15(1), 61–73.
Lawler, E. J., & Thye, S. R. (1999). Bringing emotions into social exchange Sarason, I. G., Pierce, G. R., & Sarason, B. R. (Eds.). (1996). Cognitive
theory. Annual Review of Sociology, 25, 228. interference; theories, methods, and findings. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence
Leder, H., Belke, B., Oeberst, A., & Augustin, D. (2004). A model of aesthetic Erlbaum Associates.
appreciation and aesthetic judgments. British Journal of Psychology, Scherer, K. R. (1999). Appraisal theory. In T. Dalgleish, & M. Power (Eds.),
95, 489–508. Handbook of cognition and emotion (pp. 637–663). Hoboken, NJ: John
Leder, H., Carbon, C., & Ripsas, A. (2006). Entitling art: influence of title Wiley and Sons.
information on understanding and appreciation of paintings. Acta Shusterman, R. (1997). The end of aesthetic experience. The Journal of
Psychologica, 121, 176–198. Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 55(1), 29–41.
Levi-Strauss, C. (1982). The way of the masks. Seattle: University of Shusterman, R. (2006). Aesthetic experience: from analysis to Eros. The
Washington Press. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 64(2), 217–229.
Lutz, T. (1999). Crying; the natural & cultural history of tears. New York: W. Sloboda, J. A. (1991). Music structure and emotional response: some
W. Norton & Co. empirical findings. Psychology of Music, 19, 110–120.
Magherini, G. (1989). La Sindrome di Stendhal. [The Stendhal syndrome]. Smith, R. E. (1996). Performance anxiety, cognitive interference, and
Firenze: Ponte alle Grazie. concentration enhancement strategies in sports. In I. G. Sarason, G. R.
Martin, R. B., & Labott, S. M. (1991). Mood following emotional crying: Pierce, & B. R. Sarason (Eds.), Cognitive interference; theories, methods,
effects of the situation. Journal of Research in Personality, 25, 218–244. and findings (pp. 261–284). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Maslow, A. H. (1959). Cognition of being in the peak experiences. The Sogen Hori, G. V. (2000). Koan and kensho in the Rinzai Zen curriculum.
Journal of Genetic Psychology, 94, 43–66. In S. Heine, & D. S. Wright (Eds.), The Koan: Texts and contexts in Zen
Merleau-Ponty, M. (1962). Phenomenology of perception (C. Smith, Trans).. Buddhism (pp. 280–309). Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.
London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. (Original work published in 1945) Spanos, W. V. (1993). Heidegger and criticism; retrieving the politics of
Miceli, M., & Castalfranchi, C. (2003). Crying: discussing its basic reasons destruction. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota.
and uses. New Ideas in Psychology, 21, 247–273. Steele, C. M., Spencer, S. J., & Lynch, M. (1993). Self-image resilience and
Mitias, M. H. (1982). What makes an experience aesthetic? The Journal of dissonance: the role of affirmational resources. Journal of Personality
Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 41(2), 157–169. and Social Psychology, 64(6), 885–896.
Mor, N., & Winquist, J. (2002). Self-focused attention and negative affect: Steenbarger, B. N., & Aderman, D. (1979). Objective self-awareness as
a meta-analysis. Psychological Bulletin, 128(4), 638–662. a nonaversive state: effect of anticipating discrepancy reduction.
Morgan, D. L., & Schwalbe, M. L. (1990). Mind and self in sociology: linking Journal of Personality, 47, 330–337.
social structure and social cognition. Social Psychology Quarterly, 53 Stoudenmire, J. (1971). On the relationship between religious beliefs and
(2), 148–164. emotion. Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion, 10(3), 254.
Nodelman, S. (1997). The Rothko Chapel paintings: Origins, structure, Suzuki, D. T. (1950). The complete works of D.T. Suzuki: Essays in Zen
meaning. Austin: University of Texas Press. Buddhism. second series. London: Rider and Company.
Norman, D. A. (2004). Emotional design; why we love (or hate) everyday Swann, W. B., & Read, S. J. (1981). Self-verification processes: how we
things. New York: Basic Books. sustain our self-conceptions. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology,
Osborne, H. (1979). Some theories of aesthetic judgment. The Journal of 17, 351–372.
Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 38(2), 135–144. Taylor, S. E., & Brown, J. D. (1988). Illusion and well-being: a social
Osgood, C. E., Suci, G. J., & Tannenbaum, P. (1961). The measurement of psychological perspective on mental health. Psychological Bulletin, 103
meaning. Champaign: University of Illinois press. (2), 183–210.
Parsons, M. J. (1987). How we understand art; a cognitive developmental Torrance, E. P. (1979). The search for satori & creativity. New York: The
account of aesthetic experience. Cambridge, England: Cambridge Creative Education Foundation.
University Press. Tucker, M. (2004). No title. In J. Baas, & M. Jacob (Eds.), Buddha mind in
Pelowski, M. (2007). Incontinent thaumaturgy; tears, the fetish, and the contemporary art (pp. 75–86). Berkeley: University of California Press.
aesthetic experience: a critical-empirical study of viewer affect and Vingerhoets, A. J. J. M., Van Geleuken, A. J. M. L., Van Tilburg, M. A. L., &
the philosophy and significance of the aesthetic experience. Unpub- Van Heck, G. L. (1997). The psychological context of crying episodes:
lished master’s thesis, Nagoya University, Japan. towards a model of adult crying. In A. J. J. M. Vingerhoets, F. J. Van
Petts, J. (2000). Aesthetic experience and the revelation of value. The Bussel, & A. J. W. Boelhouwe (Eds.), The (non)expression of emotions in
Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 58(1), 61–71. health and disease (pp. 323–336). Tilburg: Tilburg University Press.
Poizat, M. (1992). The angel’s cry: Beyond the pleasure principle in opera (A. Virilio, P., & Lotringer, S. (2002). Crepuscular dawn (M. Taormina, Trans.).
Denner, Trans.). Ithica, NY: Cornell University Press. (Original work Cambride, MA: MIT Press.
published in 1986). Walton, K. L. (1993). How marvelous! Toward a theory of aesthetic value.
Pouivet, R. (2000). On the cognitive functioning of aesthetic emotions. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 51(3), 499–510.
Leonardo, 33(1), 49–53. Weiss, Je (2005). Dis-orientation: Rothko’s inverted canvases. In G. Phil-
Proust, M. (1981) (C.K. Scott-Moncrieff, Trans.)Remembrance of things past, lips, & T. Crow (Eds.), Seeing Rothko (pp. 135–158). Los Angeles: Getty
Vol. 1. London: Chatto & Windus. (Original edition published in 1954). Research Institute.
Roald, T. (2007). Cognition in emotion: An investigation through experiences Wenzel, C. H. (2005). An introduction to Kant’s aesthetics: Core concepts
with art. Amsterdam: Rodopi. and problems. Malden, MA: Blackwell.

You might also like