You are on page 1of 9

Lifetime Portfolio Selection By Dynamic Stochastic Programming

Author(s): Paul A. Samuelson


Source: The Review of Economics and Statistics , Aug., 1969, Vol. 51, No. 3 (Aug., 1969),
pp. 239-246
Published by: The MIT Press

Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/1926559

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms

The MIT Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The
Review of Economics and Statistics

This content downloaded from


194.145.103.137 on Sun, 22 Aug 2021 01:03:13 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
LIFETIME PORTFOLIO SELECTION
BY DYNAMIC STOCHASTIC PROGRAMMING
Paul A. Samuelson *

Introduction Third, being still in the prime of life, the


businessman can "recoup" any present losses
M OST analyses of portfolio selection,
in the future. The widow or retired man near-
whether they are of the Markowitz-
ing life's end has no such "second or nth
Tobin mean-variance or of more general type,
chance."
maximize over one period.' I shall here formu-
Fourth (and apparently related to the last
late and solve a many-period generalization,
corresponding to lifetime planning of consump- point), since the businessman will be investing
for so many periods, "the law of averages will
tion and investment decisions. For simplicity
even out for him," and he can afford to act
of exposition I shall confine my explicit dis-
almost as if he were not subject to diminishing
cussion to special and easy cases that suffice to
marginal utility.
illustrate the general principles involved.
What are we to make of these arguments?
As an example of topics that can be investi-
It will be realized that the first could be purely
gated within the framework of the present
a one-period argument. Arrow, Pratt, and
model, consider the question of a "business-
others2 have shown that any investor who
man risk" kind of investment. In the literature
faces a range of wealth in which the elasticity
of finance, one often reads; "Security A should
of his marginal utility schedule is great will
be avoided by widows as too risky, but is highly
have high risk tolerance; and most writers
suitable as a businessman's risk." What is in-
seem to believe that the elasticity is at its
volved in this distinction? Many things.
highest for rich - but not ultra-rich! -
First, the "businessman" is more affluent
people. Since the present model has no new
than the widow; and being further removed
insight to offer in connection with statical risk
from the threat of falling below some sub--
tolerance, I shall ignore the first point here
sistence level, he has a high propensity to
and confine almost all my attention to utility
embrace variance for the sake of better yield.
functions with the same relative risk aversion
Second, he can look forward to a high salary
at all levels of wealth. Is it then still true that
in the future; and with so high a present dis-
lifetime considerations justify the concept of
counted value of wealth, it is only prudent for
a businessman's risk in his prime of life?
him to put more into common stocks compared
Point two above does justify leveraged in-
to his present tangible wealth, borrowing if
vestment financed by borrowing against future
necessary for the purpose, or accomplishing
earnings. But it does not really involve any
the same thing by selecting volatile stocks that
increase in relative risk-taking once we have
widows shun.
related what is at risk to the proper larger base.
* Aid from the National Science Foundation is gratefully
(Admittedly, if market imperfections make
acknowledged. Robert C. Merton has provided me with
much stimulus; and in a companion paper in this issue of
loans difficult or costly, recourse to volatile,
the REVIEW he is tackling the much harder problem of "leveraged" securities may be a rational pro-
optimal control in the presence of continuous-time sto- cedure.)
chastic variation. I owe thanks also to Stanley Fischer.
'See for example Harry Markowitz [5]; James Tobin
The fourth point can easily involve the in-
[14], Paul A. Samuelson [10]; Paul A. Samuelson and numerable fallacies connected with the "law of
Robert C. Merton [13]. See, however, James Tobin [15], large numbers." I have commented elsewhere 3
for a pioneering treatment of the multi-period portfolio
problem; and Jan Mossin [7] which overlaps with the
on the mistaken notion that multiplying the
present analysis in showing how to solve the basic dynamic same kind of risk leads to cancellation rather
stochastic program recursively by working backward from
the end in the Bellman fashion, and which proves the 2 See K. Arrow [1]; J. Pratt [9]; P. A. Samuelson and
theorem that portfolio proportions will be invariant only R. C. Merton [13].
if the marginal utility function is iso-elastic. 3P. A. Samuelson [11].

[ 239 ]

This content downloaded from


194.145.103.137 on Sun, 22 Aug 2021 01:03:13 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
240 THE REVIEW OF ECONOMICS AND STATISTICS

than augmentation of risk. I.e., insuring for prescribed (W0, WT+1). Differentiating
many ships adds to risk (but only as \In); partially with respect to each Wt in turn, we
hence, only by insuring more ships and by derive recursion conditions for a regular inte-
also subdividing those risks among more people rior maximum
is risk on each brought down (in ratio 1/V/n).
However, before writing this paper, I had
(I +P) U wt1 +]
1+r1r
thought that points three and four could be
reformulated so as to give a valid demonstra- =U' Wt - [w + (7)
tion of businessman's risk, my thought being
If U is concave, solving these second-order
that investing for each period is akin to agree-
difference equations with boundary conditions
ing to take a 1/nth interest in insuring n inde-
pendent ships.
(Won WT+1) will suffice to give us an optimal
lifetime consumption-investment program.
The present lifetime model reveals that in-
Since there has thus far been one asset, and
vesting for many periods does not itself in-
that a safe one, the time has come to introduce
troduce extra tolerance for riskiness at early,
a stochastically-risky alternative asset and to
or any, stages of life.
face up to a portfolio problem. Let us postulate
the existence, alongside of the safe asset that
Basic Assumptions makes $1 invested in it at time t return to you
The familiar Ramsey model may be used as at the end of the period $1(1 + r), a risk asset
a point of departure. Let an individual maxi- that makes $1 invested in, at time t, return to
mize you after one period $1Zt, where Zt is a random
T variable subject to the probability distribution
e-Pt U[C(t)]dt (1)
Prob {Zt < z} = P(z). z- (8)
subject to initial wealth WO
Hence, Zt+1 - 1that
is thecan a
perce
invested for an exogeneously-given certain each outcome. The most general probability
rate of yield r; or subject to the constraint distribution is admissible: i.e., a probability
C(t) = rW(t) - W(t) (2) density over continuous z's, or finite positive
probabilities at discrete values of z. Also I
If there is no bequest at death, terminal wealth
shall usually assume independence between
is zero.
yields at different times so that P(zo, z1, ... ,
This leads to the standard calculus-of-varia-
Z ... * , ZT) = P(zt)P(Z1) ... P (zT)
tions problem
For simplicity, the reader might care to deal
T
J = Max e-Pt U[rW - W]dt (3) with the easy case
{W(t)} ? Prob {Z = X} = 1/2
This can be easily related I to a discrete- =Prob{Z=X-}, x> 1
(9)
time formulation
T In order that risk averters with concave utility
Max 1t0 (1+p)-t U[Ct] (4) should not shun this risk asset when maximiz-
subject to ing the expected value of their portfolio, X must
be large enough so that the expected value of
C= W Wt+1 (5) the risk asset exceeds that of the safe asset, i.e.,
1+r
or,
- + A-1 > 1 + r, or
2 2

{w~~~O+ 1+r
MaxEt= (1+p)t U [Wt- W+ ] (6)
X > 1 + r + V2r + r2
Thus, for X = 1.4, the risk asset has a mean
'See P. A. Samuelson [12], p. 273 for an exposition of
discrete-time analogues to calculus-of-variations models. yield of 0.057, which is greater than a safe
Note: here I assume that consumption, Ct, takes place at asset's certain yield of r = .04.
the beginning rather than at the end of the period. This At each instant of time, what will be the
change alters slightly the appearance of the equilibrium
conditions, but not their substance. optimal fraction, Wt, that you should put in

This content downloaded from


194.145.103.137 on Sun, 22 Aug 2021 01:03:13 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
LIFETIME PORTFOLIO SELECTION 241

the risky asset, with 1 - wt going into the safe consider Phelps' 5 wage income, and even in
asset? Once these optimal portfolio fractions the stochastic form that he cites Martin Beck-
are known, the constraint of (5) must be mann as having analyzed.) More recently,
written Levhari and Srinivasan [4] have also treated
the Phelps problem for T = oo by means of
Ct =[Wt - Wt+1]. the Bellman functional equations of dynamic
c[(1-wt) (1 +r) + wtZt]programming, and have indicated a proof that
(10)
concavity of U is sufficient for a maximum.
Now we use (10) instead of (4), and recogniz- Then, there is Professor Mirrlees' important
ing the stochastic nature of our problem, work on the Ramsey problem with Harrod-
specify that we maximize the expected value neutral technological change as a random vari-
of total utility over time. This gives us the able.6 Our problems become equivalent if I
stochastic generalizations of (4) and (5) or
replace W - Wt+1 [(1+r)(1-wt) + wtZtJ-1
(6)
in (10) byAtf(Wt/At) - nWt - (Wt+- Wt)
Max T
let technical change be governed by the prob-
{Ct, wt} E X (1 +p) -t U[Ct] (1
t=O ability distribution
subject to
Prob {At ? At-1Z} = P(Z);
reinterpret my Wt to be Mirrlees' per capita
Ct =[ Wt(1 + r) (- wt) + wtZt] capital, Kt/Lt, where Lt is growing at the nat-
WO given, WT+1 prescribed. ural rate of growth n; and posit that Atf(Wt/
If there is no bequeathing of wealth at death, At) is a homogeneous first degree, concave, neo-
classical production function in terms of cap-
presumably WT+1 = 0. Alternatively, we could
ital and efficiency-units of labor.
replace a prescribed WT+1 by a final bequest
It should be remarked that I am confirming
function added to (11), of the form B(WT+1),
and with WT+1 a free decision variable to be
myself here to regular interior maxima, and
not going into the Kuhn-Tucker inequalities
chosen so as to maximize (11) + B(WT+D).
For the most part, I shall consider CT = WT
that easily handle boundary maxima.

and WT+1 = 0?
In (11), E stands for the "expected value Solution of the Problem
of," so that, for example, The meaning of our basic problem
T

E Zt = fztdP(zt) JT(WO) = Max E X (1+P)-tU[Ct] (11)


{ct,wt} t=O
In our simple case of (9),
subject to Ct = Wt- Wt+1[(1-wt) (1+r)
+ w,Zt]-I is not easy to grasp. I act now at
EZt = 2 A + 1 A-1.
2 2 t = 0 to select C0 and w0, knowing W0 but not
yet knowing how Z0 will turn out. I must act
Equation ( 11 ) is our basic stochastic program-
now, knowing that one period later, knowledge
ming problem that needs to be solved simul-
of Z0's outcome will be known and that W1 will
taneously for optimal saving-consumption and
then be known. Depending upon knowledge of
portfolio-selection decisions over time.
W1, a new decision will be made for C1 and
Before proceeding to solve this problem, ref-
w1. Now I can only guess what that decision
erence may be made to similar problems that
will be.
seem to have been dealt with explicitly in the
As so often is the case in dynamic program-
economics literature. First, there is the valu-
ming, it helps to begin at the end of the plan-
able paper by Phelps on the Ramsey problem
ning period. This brings us to the well-known
in which capital's yield is a prescribed random
variable. This corresponds, in my notation, to 'E. S. Phelps [8].
the {wt} strategy being frozen at some frac- 6 J. A. Mirrlees [6]. I have converted his treatmen
into a discrete-time version. Robert Merton's companion
tional level, there being no portfolio selection
paper throws light on Mirrlees' Brownian-motion model
problem. (My analysis could be amplified to for At.

This content downloaded from


194.145.103.137 on Sun, 22 Aug 2021 01:03:13 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
242 THE REVIEW OF ECONOMICS AND STATISTICS

one-period portfolio problem. In our terms, Substituting (C*T-1, W*T_1) into the expres-
this becomes sion to be maximized gives us J1(WT-1) ex-
JI (WT-1) = Max U[CT-1] plicitly. From the equations in (12), we can,
{CT-1jWT-1} by standard calculus methods, relate the de-
+ E(l+p) 'U[ (WT-1 - CT-1) rivatives of U to those of J, namely, by the
{(1-WT-1) (l+r) envelope relation
+ WT-1ZT-1} 4].* (12) JI'(WT-1) = U' [CT-1]. (13)
Here the expected value operator E operates Now that we know J1[WT_1], it is easy to
only on the random variable of the next period determine optimal behavior one period earlier,
since current consumption CT-1 is known once namely by
we have made our decision. Writing the second
J2 (WT-2) = Max U[CT-2]
term as EF(ZT), this becomes
{CT-21WT-2}
+ E(1 +p) -1JI [ (WT-2-CT-2)
EF(ZT) = J F(ZT)dP(ZTjZT-1,ZT-22 * , Zo)
0 {( 1-WT-2) (1 +r) + WT-2ZT-2}].
(14)
/F (ZT) dP (ZT), by our independence
Differentiating (14) just as we did (11)
postulate. gives the following equations like those of (12)
In the general case, at a later stage of decision O = U' [CT-2] - (1+p) - EJ1' [WT-2]
making, say t = T- 1, knowledge will be avail- { (1-WT-2) (I +r) + WT-2ZT-2} (15')
able of the outcomes of earlier random vari- 0 = EJ1' [WT-1] (WT-2 - CT-2) (ZT-2 - 1-r)
ables, Zt-2, ... ; since these might be relevant
= J fJ1' [ (WT-2 -CT-2) { ( 1-WT-2) (1 +r)
to the distribution of subsequent random vari-
ables, conditional probabilities of the form + WT-2ZT-2}] (WT-2 -CT-2) (ZT-2 - 1-r)
dP(ZT_2).
P(ZT-1IZT-2, .. .) are thus involved. How-
ever, in cases like the present one, where in- (15")
dependence of distributions is posited, condi- These equations, which could by (13) be re-
tional probabilities can be dispensed within lated to U'[CT-1], can be solved simultaneous-
favor of simple distributions. ly to determine optimal (C*T-2, W*T-2) and
Note that in (12) we have substituted for J2 (WT-2) .
CT its value as given by the constraint in (11) Continuing recursively in this way for T-3,
or (10). T-4,...,2, 1, 0, we finally have our problem
To determine this optimum (CT-1, WT-1), solved. The general recursive optimality equa-
we differentiate with respect to each separately, tions can be written as
to get { O = U'[Co] - (1 +p) -1 E'TT1 [Wo]
O = U' [CT-1] - (1+p)P EU' [CT] { (1-wo) (l+r) + woZo}
{(1-WT-1) (l+r) + WT-IZT-l} (12') O = EJI'T-l[Wl] (WO -CO) (ZO -1-r)
O = EU' [CT] (WT-1 -CT_1) (ZT-1-1-r)
O = U'[CT-] - (1+P) EJ'T-t[Wt]
- ,J'U' [ (WT-1 -CT-1)
{ (I 1-wt-1) (I1 +r) + wt_IZt_I} ( 16')
{(1-WT l(1+r) - WT-1ZT-1}] o = ETT-t [Wt-l -Ct-1) (Zt-1 r),
(WT-1-CT-1) (ZT-1 -r) dP (ZT-1) (t =l,I...,IT-1I). (16tt)
(12")
In (16'), of course, the proper substitutions
Solving these simultaneously, we get our must be made and the E operators must be
optimal decisions (C*T-1, W*T_1) as functions over the proper probability distributions. Solv-
of initial wealth WT-1 alone. Note that if ing (16") at any stage will give the optimal
somehow C*T-1 were known, (12") would by decision rules for consumption-saving and for
itself be the familiar one-period portfolio op- portfolio selection, in the form
timality condition, and could trivially be re- C*t = f [Wt; Zt-l, ... , Zo]
written to handle any number of alternative = fT-t[Wt] if the Z's are independently
assets. distributed

This content downloaded from


194.145.103.137 on Sun, 22 Aug 2021 01:03:13 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
LIFETIME PORTFOLIO SELECTION 243

W*t = g[Wt; Zt_, ... *, Zo] Hence, equations (12) and (16')-(16") split
= g-_t[Wt] if the Z's are independently into two independent parts and the Ramsey-
distributed. Phelps saving problem becomes quite indepen-
Our problem is now solved for every case dent of the lifetime portfolio selection problem.
but the important case of infinite-time horizon.
Now we have
For well-behaved cases, one can simply let 0 = (1/C) - (1+p)-1 (W - C)-'or
T -> oo in the above formulas. Or, as often CT-1 = (l+p) (2+p) 'WT-1 (19)
happens, the infinite case may be the easiest of r00

all to solve, since for it C*t = f(Wt), w*t =


o = (Z- 1 r)-[(l w) (l+r)
g(Wt), independently of time and both these + wZ] -1 dP(Z) or
unknown functions can be deduced as solutions WT-1 = W* independently of WT-1. (19")
to the following functional equations: These independence results, of the CT-1 and
0 = U' [f(W)] -(1+p) WT-1 decisions and of the dependence of WT_1
fJ'[ (W - f(W)) {(1+r) on WT_1, hold for all U functions with iso-
elastic marginal utility. I.e., (16') and (16")
-g(W) (Z- 1 -r)}] [ (1+r) become decomposable conditions for all
-g(W)(Z - 1 - r)]dP(Z) (17') U(C) = 1/yCl, y < 1 (20)
00

0= fUu[{W - f(W)} as well as for U(C) = log C, corresponding by


L'Hopital's rule to y = 0.
{1 + r-g(W) (Z- 1 -r)}] To see this, write (12) or (18) as
[Z -1- r] d p (-i) ( 17"f)
Equation (17'), by itself with g(W) pretended J1 (W) = Max C + (1 +p) -1 (W-C)7
to be known, would be equivalent to equation {C, w} Y Y
(13) of Levhari and Srinivasan [4, p. f]. In rx
deriving (17')-(17"), I have utilized the enve- f[(1 -w)(1+r) + wZ]Zi dP(Z)
lope relation of my (13), which is equivalent to
Levhari and Srinivasan's equation (12) [4, = Max-+ (+p)-1 (w-CYx
{C} 'Y 'Y
p.5].
Max [(1-w) (1+r)
Bernoulli and Isoelastic Cases w?

To apply our results, let us consider the in- + wZ] dp(Z). (21)
teresting Bernoulli case where U = log C. This Hence, (12") or (15") or (16") becomes
does not have the bounded utility that Arrow rx
[1] and many writers have convinced them- [ (1 -w) (1+r)
selves is desirable for an axiom system. Since + wZ]Y-l (Z-r- 1) dP (Z) = O, (22")
I do not believe that Karl Menger paradoxes which defines optimal w* and gives
of the generalized St. Petersburg type hold any rx
terrors for the economist, I have no particular Max [(1 -w)(1+r) +wZ]y dP(Z)
interest in boundedness of utility and consider {w}
log C to be interesting and admissible. For this = f (1 -w*) (1 +r) + w*Z]'ydP (Z)
co

case, we have, from (12),


J1(W) = Max logC
= [1 + r*]Y,for short.
{C,w} Here, r* is the subjective or util-prob mean
+ E(l+p)-'log [(W - C) return of the portfolio, where diminishing mar-
{ (l-w) (l+r) + wZ}] ginal utility has been taken into account.7 To
= Max log C + (I +p) log [W-C] get optimal consumption-saving, differentiate
{C} (21) to get the new form of (12'), (15'), or
+ Max log [ (1-w) (1+r) (16')

{w} See Samuelson and Merton for the util-prob concept


+ wZ]dP(Z) (18) [13].

This content downloaded from


194.145.103.137 on Sun, 22 Aug 2021 01:03:13 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
244 THE REVIEW OF ECONOMICS AND STATISTICS

0 = CY-1 _ (1+p)-l (1+r*)y (W-C)'-1. In the limiting case, as y -O 0 and we have


(22') Bernoulli's logarithmic function, a, = (1+p),
Solving, we have the consumption decision rule independent of r*, and all saving propensities
depend on subjective time preference p only,
C*T_1 = T1 1 (23) being independent of technological investment
+ aW
where opportunities (except to the degree that Wt
will itself definitely depend on those opportu-
a, = [(1+r*)Y/(11+p)]/11tl. (24)
nities).
Hence, by substitution, we find
We can interpret 1 +r* as kind of a "'risk-
J1 (WT-1) = blW'YT-11/Y (25) corrected" mean yield; and behavior of a long-
where lived man depends critically on whether
b, = aj'Y(1+aj)-Y
+ (1+p)-l (1+r*)y (1+al)'-y (26) (1+r*)y > ( (l+p), corresponding to a, < 1.
Thus, J,(.) is of the same elasticity form as
(i) For (1+r*)'y = (1+p), one plans always to
U(.) was. Evaluating indeterminate forms for
consume at a uniform rate, dividing current WT-i e
y = 0, we find J, to be of log form if U was. by remaining life, 1/(1+i). If young enough, one saves
Now, by mathematical induction, it is easy on the average; in the familiar "hump saving" fashion,
to show that this isoelastic property must also one dissaves later as the end comes sufficiently close
hold for J2(WT-2), I3(WT-3), ..., since, into sight.
(ii) For (1+r*)7 > (1+p), a, < 1, and investment
whenever it holds for JI(WT_") it is deducible
opportunities are, so to speak, so tempting compared
that it holds for Jn+1(WT -1). Hence, at to psychological time preference that one consumes
every stage, solving the general equations (16') nothing at the beginning of a long-long life, i.e., rigor-
and (16"), they decompose into two parts in ously
the case of isoelastic utility. Hence, Lim c4 = 0, a. < 1
i -- oo
Theorem:
and again hump saving must take place. For (1+r*)y
For isoelastic marginal utility functions, U'(C) > (1+p), the perpetual lifetime problem, with T = oo,
= C-1, 'y < 1, the optimal portfolio decision is divergent and ill-defined, i.e., JI(W) -- oo as i-- oo.
is independent of wealth at each stage and in- For Y - 0 and p > 0, this case cannot arise.
dependent of all consumption-saving decisions, (iii) For (1+r*)Y < (1+p), a,. > 1, consumption
at very early ages drops only to a limiting positive
leading to a constant w*, the solution to
fraction (rather than zero), namely
r0
Lim c4 = 1- l/a1< 1, a> 1.
o= f[(1-w)(l+r)+wZ]T-h(Z-1-r)dP(Z). - 00

Now whether there will be, on the average, initial hump


Then optimal consumption decisions at each
saving depends upon the size of r* - c., or whether
stage are, for a no-bequest model, of the form
C*T-i = CiWT-i r*-- I- > O
where one can deduce the recursion relations
This ends the Theorem. Although many of
a,
Cl = _.SA.l the results depend upon the no-bequest as-
a1 = +W1
sumption, WT+1 = 0, as Merton's companion
a, [ (1+p)1( 1 +r*)'Y] 1/1_7
rX paper shows (p. 247, this Review) we can easily
(1+r*)y = J'[(1 w*)(1+r) generalize to the cases where a bequest func-
+ w* Z]y dP (Z)
tion BT(WT+l) is added to X O (1+p) tU(Ct).
alc_- If BT is itself of isoelastic form,
c1s =-
1+a1jc_j BT- bT(WT+1Y"/y,
the algebra is little changed. Also, the same
1+al+a 21+ ... +ail comparative statics put forward in Merton's
ail (a -1) continuous-time case will be applicable here,
=ai+1- e.g., the Bernoulli y = 0 case is a watershed
between cases where thrift is enhanced by risk-
1+i iness rather than reduced; etc.

This content downloaded from


194.145.103.137 on Sun, 22 Aug 2021 01:03:13 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
LIFETIME PORTFOLIO SELECTION 245

Since proof of the theorem is straightfor- risk-tolerance as toward the end of life! The
ward, I skip all details except to indicate how ''chance to recoup" and tendency for the law
of large numbers to operate in the case of re-
the recursion relations for ci and bi are derived,
namely from the identities peated investments is not relevant. (Note:
b+l1W7/y = J+i(W) if the elasticity of marginal utility, - U' (W) /
= Max {CY/y WU"(W), rises empirically with wealth, and if
C the capital market is imperfect as far as lending
+ bj(1+r*)Y(1+p)-l(W-C)Y/y} and borrowing against future earnings is con-
{c'i+l + bi(l+r*)Y cerned, then it seems to me to be likely
( 1+p) -1 ( 1-Ci+1)_1} WY/y that a doctor of age 35-50 might rationally
and the optimality condition have his highest consumption then, and certain-
0 = CT-1_ b,(1+r*)Y(l+p)-l(W-C)7- ly show greatest risk tolerance then - in other
= (c,+jW)8-1- bj(1+r*)7(1+p)1 words be open to a "businessman's risk." But
( 1-Cj+l ) T- W7-1j not in the frictionless isoelastic model!)
which defines cj+j in terms of bi. As usual, one expects w* and risk tolerance
What if we relax the assumption of isoelastic to be higher with algebraically large y. One
marginal utility functions? Then WT_j be- expects C, to be higher late in life when r and
r* is high relative to p. As in a one-period
comes a function of WT>j1l (and, of course,
of r, p, and a functional of the probability dis- model, one expects any increase in "riskiness"
tribution P). Now the Phelps-Ramsey optimal of Zt, for the same mean, to decrease w*. One
stochastic saving decisions do interact with the expects a similar increase in riskiness to lower
optimal portfolio decisions, and these have to or raise consumption depending upon whether
be arrived at by simultaneous solution of the marginal utility is greater or less than unity in
nondecomposable equations (16') and (16"). its elasticity.8

What if we have more than one alternative Our analysis enables us to dispel a fallacy
asset to safe cash? Then merely interpret Zt that has been borrowed into portfolio theory
from information theory of the Shannon type.
as a (column) vector of returns (Z2,,Z3,, ..)
on the respective risky assets; also interpret Associated with independent discoveries by
wt as a (row) vector (w2t,w3t, ...), interpret J. B. Williams [ 16], John Kelly [2 ], and H. A.
P(Z) as vector notation for Latane [3] is the notion that if one is invest-
ing for many periods, the proper behavior is to
Prob {Z2t _ Z2, Z3t ? Z3,... }
= P(Z2 Z3,...) =P(Z), maximize the geometric mean of return rather
than the arithmetic mean. I believe this to be
interpret all integrals of the form fG (Z) dP (Z)
incorrect (except in the Bernoulli logarithmic
as multiple integrals fG (Z2,Z3, . ..) dP(Z2,Z3,
case where it happens I to be correct for reasons
...). Then (16") becomes a vector-set of
equations, one for each component of the vector 'See Merton's cited companion paper in this issue, for
Zt, and these can be solved simultaneously for
explicit discussion of the comparative statical shifts of (16)'s
the unknown wt vector. C*t and W*t functions as the parameters (p, y, r, r*, and
P(Z) or P(Z1,...) or B(WT) functions change. The same
If there are many consumption items, we results hold in the discrete-and-continuous-time models.
can handle the general problem by giving a 'See Latane [3, p. 151] for explicit recognition of this
point. I find somewhat mystifying his footnote there which
similar vector interpretation to Ct.
says, "As pointed out to me by Professor L. J. Savage (in
Thus, the most general portfolio lifetime correspondence), not only is the maximization of G [the
problem is handled by our equations or obvious geometric mean] the rule for maximum expected utility in
extensions thereof. connection with Bernoulli's function but (in so far as cer-
tain approximations are permissible) this same rule is ap-
proximately valid for all utility functions." [Latane, p. 151,
Conclusion n.13.] The geometric mean criterion is definitely too con-
servative to maximize an isoelastic utility function cor-
We have now come full circle. Our model responding to positive y in my equation (20), and it is
denies the validity of the concept of business- definitely too daring to maximize expected utility when
,y < 0. Professor Savage has informed me recently that his
man's risk; for isoelastic marginal utilities, in 1969 position differs from the view attributed to him in
your prime of life you have the same relative 1959.

This content downloaded from


194.145.103.137 on Sun, 22 Aug 2021 01:03:13 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
246 THE REVIEW OF ECONOMICS AND STATISTICS

quite distinct from the Williams-Kelly-Latane REFERENCES

reasoning). [1] Arrow, K. J., "Aspects of the Theory of Risk-


These writers must have in mind reasoning Bearing" (Helsinki, Finland: Yrj6 Jahnssonin
that goes something like the following: If one Saati6, 1965).

maximizes for a distant goal, investing and [2] Kelly, J., "A New Interpretation of Information
Rate," Bell System Technical Journal (Aug.
reinvesting (all one's proceeds) many times on
1956), 917-926.
the way, then the probability becomes great
[3] Latane, H. A., "Criteria for Choice Among Risky
that with a portfolio that maximizes the geo- Ventures," Journal of Political Economy 67 (Apr.
metric mean at each stage you will end up 1959), 144-155.
with a larger terminal wealth than with any [4] Levhari, D. and T. N. Srinivasan, "Optimal Sav-
other decision strategy. ings Under Uncertainty," Institute for Mathe-
matical Studies in the Social Sciences, Technical
This is indeed a valid consequence of the
Report No. 8, Stanford University, Dec. 1967.
central limit theorem as applied to the addi-
[5] Markowitz, H., Portfolio Selection: Efficient
tive logarithms of portfolio outcomes. (I.e., Diversification of Investment (New York: John
maximizing the geometric mean is the same Wiley & Sons, 1959).
thing as maximizing the arithmetic mean of [6] Mirrlees, J. A., "Optimum Accumulation Under
the logarithm of outcome at each stage; if at Uncertainty," Dec. 1965, unpublished.
[7] Mossin, J., "Optimal Multiperiod Portfolio Pol-
each stage, we get a mean log of m** > m*,
icies," Journal of Business 41, 2 (Apr. 1968),
then after a large number of stages we will
215-229.
have m**T > > m*T, and the properly nor- [8] Phelps, E. S., "The Accumulation of Risky Cap-
malized probabilities will cluster around a ital: A Sequential Utility Analysis," Economet-
higher value.) rica 30, 4 (1962), 729-743.
There is nothing wrong with the logical [9] Pratt, J., "Risk Aversion in the Small and in the
Large," Econometrica 32 (Jan. 1964).
deduction from premise to theorem. But the
[10] Samuelson, P. A., "General Proof that Diversifica-
implicit premise is faulty to begin with, as I
tion Pays," Journal of Financial and Quantitative
have shown elsewhere in another connection Analysis II (Mar. 1967), 1-13.
[Samuelson, 10, p. 3]. It is a mistake to think [11] , "Risk and Uncertainty: A Fallacy of
that, just because a w** decision ends up with Large Numbers," Scientia, 6th Series, 57th year
almost-certain probability to be better than a (April-May, 1963).

w* decision, this implies that w** must yield a [12] , "A Turnpike Refutation of the Golden
Rule in a Welfare Maximizing Many-Year Plan,"
better expected value of utility. Our analysis
Essay XIV Essays on the Theory of Optimal
for marginal utility with elasticity differing Economic Growth, Karl Shell (ed.) (Cambridge,
from that of Bernoulli provides an effective Mass.: MIT Press, 1967).
counter example, if indeed a counter example [13] , and R. C. Merton, "A Complete Model
is needed to refute a gratuitous assertion. of Warrant Pricing that Maximizes Utility," In-
dustrial Management Review (in press).
Moreover, as I showed elsewhere, the ordering
[14] Tobin, J., "Liquidity Preference as Behavior
principle of selecting between two actions in
Towards Risk," Review of Economic Studies,
terms of which has the greater probability of XXV, 67, Feb. 1958, 65-86.
producing a higher result does not even possess [15] , "The Theory of Portfolio Selection,"
the property of being transitive.'0 By that The Theory of Interest Rates, F. H. Hahn and
principle, we could have w*** better than w**, F. P. R. Brechling (eds.) (London: Macmillan,
1965).
and w** better than w*, and also have w*
[16] Williams, J. B., "Speculation and the Carryover,"
better than w***.
Quarterly Journal of Economics 50 (May 1936),
"0See Samuelson [11]. 436-455.

This content downloaded from


194.145.103.137 on Sun, 22 Aug 2021 01:03:13 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms

You might also like