You are on page 1of 15

The Final Theory of Physics - a Tautology?

C. Baumgarten1
5244 Birrhard, Switzerlanda)
(Dated: 7 February 2017)
We acuminate the idea of a final theory of physics in order to analyze its logical implications and consequences.
It is argued that the rationale of a final theory is the principle of sufficient reason. This implies that a
final theory of physics, presumed such a theory is possible, does not allow to incorporate substantial (non-
trivial) propositions unless they are logically or mathematically deduced. Differences between physics and
mathematics are discussed with emphasis on the role of physical constants. It is shown that it is logically
arXiv:1702.00301v2 [physics.gen-ph] 6 Feb 2017

impossible to introduce constants on the fundamental level of a final theory. The most fundamental constants
emerging within a final theory are constants of motion.
It is argued that the only possibility to formulate a final theory is necessarily a tautology: A final theory of
physics can only be derived from those presumptions about reality that are inherent in the idea and practice
of physics itself. It is argued that a final theory is based on the notion of objectivity, but it is logically
impossible that an ideal final theory supports realism.

PACS numbers: 01.70.+w,02.10.-v,03.65.Ta,03.65.Ca


Keywords: Philosophy of science, Logic, Measurement Theory, Formalism of Quantum mechanics

I. INTRODUCTION known fundamental particles and forces, it neither im-


plies simplicity, nor a deep or even final level of under-
In his book Dreams of a Final Theory Nobel laureate standing, nor a high degree of explanatory power. A
Steven Weinberg wrote1 : “It is difficult to imagine that GUT could be ugly and incomprehensible. The form of
we could ever be in possessions of final physical principles a GUT - if we extrapolate the prominent tendencies in
that have no explanation in terms of deeper principles.” theoretical physics - will likely consist of a set of mathe-
But Weinberg (of course) did exactly this: he described matical structures that allow to summarize the structure
the idea of a final theory in his book. Not all physicists, of the standard model of particle physics. But the very
not even all Nobel laureates, share Weinbergs expecta- idea of a GUT does not include explanations why na-
tion that such a theory might be possible2 . Nevertheless ture should prefer a specific mathematical structure and
we shall pick up and discuss various aspects of Wein- not some other. Or, in other words, a GUT would -
bergs dream. Specifically we shall use the idea of the in contrast to the ideal FiT - not exclude the possibil-
final theory to discuss the relation between physics and ity that different universes with different laws of nature
mathematics. Whether we believe or not that a final is might exist at least in principle.
possible in principle, both cases have their specific im- However, we shall argue that the conjectured finality
plications 1 . Weinberg’s dream concerns a theory that is of a FiT follows a different logic than the assumed com-
final because no deeper theory is possible. The concept of pleteness of the GUT . Furthermore we shall argue that
a final theory (FiT ) understood in this way differs con- and why Weinberg’s specifications can, if at all, only be
siderably from that of a grand unified theory (GUT ) or met by a theory that is based on trivial premises. The
a theory of everything. A GUT aims to provide a unified finality and inevitability that Weinberg expects from a fi-
description of all fundamental forces of nature. However nal theory implies that it is similar to pure mathematics.
revolutionary this would be, it remains within the scope This has a number of consequences 2 .
of already existing theories; the concept of a GUT does Weinberg wrote “But (I repeat and not for the last
not necessarily imply finality, but completeness with re- time) I am concerned here not so much with what sci-
spect to known experimental facts. entists do [...] as I am with the logical order built into
The conjectured finality results, as Weinberg explains, nature itself”. We we shall argue that a final theory (if
from “the beauty of simplicity and inevitability, the possible at all) will be based exactly on this: on what
beauty of perfect structure, the beauty of everything physicist do, what they have to do, in order to formulate
fitting together, of nothing being changeable, of logical a quantitative and objective description of nature.
rigidity.” The keyword here is inevitability: Though the In this essay we further elaborate the premises that
idea of a GUT implies completeness with respect to the we used in two preceeding publications20,21 in which the

2 One implication of the inevitability seems to be that the final the-


a) Electronic mail: christian-baumgarten@gmx.net ory is incompatible with the “Mathematical Universe Hypothe-
1 It might be the historical fate of physics to fail providing a final sis” in Tegmark’s sense of enumerable possible universes5 : If
theory, it might end up with a last instead of a final theory - but many worlds are possible, then none of them can be regarded as
we will not consider this possibility. inevitable.
2

author sketched a logical line of reasoning that allows to didates on the market like quantum gravity or the various
derive relativity, electrodynamics and the Dirac equation string theories. It is sufficient to notice that these theo-
from (almost) trivial principles. Here we shall argue that ries aim to be unified theories. But a final theory is more
these principles are a promising starting point of a final than just a unification, it is a theory which leaves no ques-
theory - not because we are able to deduce a GUT from tions open. It not only allows to derive all known types
it, but because they scetch a possibility to achieve the of particles and interactions, but also the dimension of
required logic of a FiT . space-time. But even this is not sufficient to provide fi-
We shall argue that specifically the inevitability and nality: As we shall argue, the finality implies that it even
finality of a physical theory can only be derived from a provides a formal derivation of the fundamental concepts
systematic analysis of the form or method of physics itself: of physics.
Since the theory has to demonstrate that any physical This specification might seem exaggerated and the idea
world inevitably has the form of our universe, then it of the possibility of a FiT hubristic, however this is not
can not be purely empirical: it has to demonstrate logical necessarily the case. The idea of a FiT only exemplifies
necessity. And since we do (like Weinberg) not believe the ratio behind the scientific project itself: Weinberg’s
that it can be derived “from pure thought”, then it can dream is a consequence of the well-known “principle of
only be derived as an tautology, i.e. from a description sufficient reason” (PSR) and it claims nothing more than
of physics itself. that everything in nature should have a reason7 . Indeed
In Sec. II we will try to precisely specify what we con- it is difficult to imagine and to argue that some fact,
sider to be a final theory of physics. We do not know if or law, or relation in nature might have no reason at all,
our definition is in full agreement with Weinbergs idea that it might be based on pure contingency, that the mass
of a FiT and his attitude towards such a theory. We ratio of proton and electron is unexplainable. It would
will acuminate the idea to an extend that allows to draw simply be unreasonable and alien to science to claim that
conclusions. Insofar it is a thought’s experiment. physical relations or some law might have no reason. Be-
In Sec. III we discuss aspects of the relation and the dif- cause - if something in nature has no reason, why should
ferences between mathematics and physics and the conse- anything have reason? Hence science has to presume rea-
quences for a FiT . Here we put special emphasis on the son, and that is why it is reasonable to consider that a
difference in the methods of concept formation between FiT could be within reach some day - since anything that
mathematics and physics and what can be concluded for is reasonable can, by definition, be understood 3 . Tech-
a final theory. nical or financial limitations might prevent physics from
In Sec. III A we investigate the role played by the so- performing the required experiments, or the mathemat-
called “physical constants”, both, dimensional and di- ics might become so difficult, that we will never be able
mensionless. We shall discuss where and how such con- to solve all riddles of physics. But to question the PSR
stants may be introduced or derived within a final the- would go beyond that - to some degree it would mean to
ory. The specific meaning of natural units is considered in question the scientific project itself.
Sec. III B, their role within physical laws in Sec. III C and Gerard t’Hooft expressed his attitude towards the idea
their importance with respect to the concept of objectiv- of a FiT as follows2 : “[...] in particular string theorists
ity in a final theory, in Sec. III D. In Sec. IV we draw first expect that the ultimate laws of physics will contain a
conclusions and discuss their implications, mainly that kind of logic that is even more mysterious and alien than
the foundation of a final theory can only be formulated that of quantum mechanics. I, however, will only be con-
as a tautology. In Sec. IV A we describe the tautology, tent if the logic is found to be completely straightfor-
namely we provide a simple description of the premises ward.” Or Leonhard Susskind (ibd.): “Not only would
of physics. the theory explain why the proton and neutron are about
In Sec. IV B we scetch some consequences concerning 1,800 times heavier than the electron, but the theory
the attitude of science towards reality. We shall argue would also explain itself: no other theory is possible.”
that the formulation of a FiT first of all requires to with- If we include these requirements in the specifications of
draw all metaphysical presuppositions. In Secs. IV C,V a FiT , then the theory has to carry the evidence for its
we scetch the conclusions for the form of a final theory. truth in itself. This means that a FiT has to demon-
In Sec. VI we shall argue that there is an intrinsic incom- strate that the laws governing physical reality could by
patibility of rationalism with realism. no means be different than those formulated by the FiT
Finally we shall summarize our considerations in . Then of course the FiT has to provide a formal cer-
Sec. VIII. tainty and “logical rigidity” as otherwise only known in
mathematics.
Stanley Goldberg characterized the logic of mathemat-
II. THE SPECIFICATIONS OF A FINAL THEORY ics as follows18 : “Different branches of mathematics have

The current idea of a GUT is that of a theory which


3
unifies all forces of nature into a common conceptional This does not imply that everything must have an intelligible
framework. We do not intend to discuss the various can- cause, though.
3

different rules but in all branches, since the rules are pre- III. WHAT DISTINGUISHES PHYSICS FROM
determined, the conclusion is actually a restatement, in MATHEMATICS?
a new form, of the premises. Mathematics, like all formal
logic, is tautological. That is not to say that it is uninter- Since the final theory is constructive, it can not sim-
esting or that it doesn’t contain many surprises.“ Hence ply presume concepts like mass or velocity that originate
a FiT might be possible if it is formally equivalent to from experience. The required inevitability implies that a
mathematics. This raises the question of the differences final theory has to demonstrate how quantities like mass,
between mathematics and physics and if and how they energy, charge and field emerge within a mathematical
could be overcome. We shall come back to this in Sec. III. framework that is developed on the basis of self-evident
The required self-evidence of a final theory (considered abstract principles. However there is at least one con-
that such a theory is possible) does not allow to base cept that has to be presumed: Time. The reason (and
the theory on substantial propositions, since substantial legitimization) is the inevitability of this concept. There
propositions are not self-evident. Using Goldbergs phrase is not way to describe the meaning of physics without
we might say that substantial propositions are those that presuming the notion of time in some way.
are not predetermined. All propositions that can be de- Goldberg described this in his book on relativity18 as
rived within the FiT must be inherent in some form in follows: “The undefined terms for the dimensional sys-
the premises of physics or they must be derivable math- tem we will be using are ”length,” ”time” and ”mass.”
ematically. To substantiate the meaning of this idea, let These are the common, undefined primitives of physics.
us consider some examples of what propositions might Although I can tell you how to measure a length, or a
be regarded as substantial. It is a substantial claim that time, or a mass by a formula, the concepts themselves are
space-time must have 3 + 1 dimensions and to believe undefined. Either you know or you don’t know what I
that space is fundamental. Though it is clear that our mean when I use a phrase like ”time passes.” The dimen-
world appears to have this form, it is not evident why this sions of all other quantities in physics can be expressed in
should be the case - why any physical world should have terms of these fundamental quantities.” This means that
3 + 1 dimensions. One might have doubts that physics the “understanding” of certain concepts can only be ob-
will ever be able to give clear and distinct reasons why tained by personal experience. If all substantial concepts
any possible physical world must have 3 + 1 dimensions, of physics have to emerge within the final theory then
but one can not deny that the question “why 3+1 dimen- a FiT is formally equivalent to mathematics. And then
sions?” itself is legitimate and meaningful. Therefore a the “mapping” between mathematical form and physical
statement that the physical world has (or must have) meaning is reversed with respect to the usual method of
3+1 dimensions, is substantial and requires a derivation physics. If substantial physical concepts like “mass” and
within a FiT . Hence, if we believe that a FiT should “energy” or “spin” can not be presumed, these notions
be possible and that it has to provide such explanations, have to be identified from pure mathematical form.
then any physical world must have 3 + 1 dimensions. Usually the arrow that describes the formation of con-
A GUT might be based on substantial assumptions cept in physics, points from the phenomena to the equa-
and postulates, for instance a specific dimensionality of tions. In mathematics one also finds the opposite di-
space-time or some special general group structure or on rection: Abstract concepts that have been invented on
the postulation of some type of string: A GUT could be the basis of pure formal considerations and then obtain
formulated as a theory of postulates. However, Einstein a name from conventional language like “fiber” or “pen-
remarked that “When we say that we understand a group cil”. To establish a relationship between the mathemat-
of natural phenomena, we mean that we have found a ical form and its physical content is called interpreta-
constructive theory which embraces them”3 . Following tion. And in contrast to mathematics, the interpreta-
Einstein, a GUT might as well be a theory of principle, tion charges variables with physical meaning: the math
but a FiT has to be anticipated as a purely constructive of physics refers to things outside mathematics. It would
theory: It has to explain the 3+1 dimensional space-time be meaningless to ask whether names given to purely
by construction, it has to explain, why and what physi- mathematical objects or functions are “correct”. Math-
cal significance specific groups have, why there must be ematical objects do not refer to anything else outside
a maximal velocity of massive objects, why Maxwell’s mathematics. But a FiT has to identify mathematical
equations have their specific form and so on. This im- structures with physical objects. There is no formal way
plies that a FiT (if possible at all) also has to reformu- to prove the truth of this mapping. We can only verify
late relativity; it has to replace all of its postulates by a (or falsify) its experimental predictions. But the vari-
reasonable construction. The same would hold for quan- ables that correspond to these predictions are a subset
tum mechanics. A final theory has to explain why we of all variables of the model: We measure mean values
(have to?) use complex numbers in quantum mechanics - even in the microscopic case. Phenomenological phys-
and why the momentum should be equal to the spatial ical models that describe specific physical problems are
derivative of the wave function (times the unit imagi- to a large degree self-sufficient. It is their purpose to
nary). A FiT is a deductive theory in which all elements provide predictions. But a FiT has a different purpose,
are deduced from unquestionable first trivial principles. namely to provide the bridge between phenomenological
4

theories. It must be complete and convincing, though it mathematics. Without the knowledge of the empirically
is questionable, whether the required interpretations can developed physical concepts and notions it is hardly pos-
be unique: the effectiveness of physical models is that sible to recognize the physical meaning of the variables
they are applicable to a variety of phenomena. appearing in the supposed final theory and to find inter-
If the phenomena (the meaning) has not been estab- pretations that provide a physically meaningful theory
lished within physics beforehand or if the FiT would de- from purely formal (mathematical) relations. If a FiT is
scribe completely unknown phenomena of nature, then able to deduce equations from abstract principles, then
the attempt of interpretation might be a serious chal- the “correct” interpretation is not included for free.
lenge: The meaning of variables can (safely) only be ob-
tained from already known physical concepts. That is, Physics and mathematics require certain notational
conventions, a nomenclature, that assigns symbols to cer-
the path of reasoning within a FiT can not start at the
phenomena and end in equations, but vice versa. The tain quantities and relations. For instance, a2 + b2 =
c2 is associated with the Pythagorean theorem, while
equations have to be derived on the basis of the abstract
principles and the resulting variables in these equations m2 + p2 = E 2 , though of identical form, reminds us
of the relativistic energy formula in units where c = 1.
have to be identified with physical quantities. This is a
task of pattern recognition or - as Walter Smilga named A purely formal derivation of equations within a FiT
as suggested by an analogy with pure mathematics does
it - “reverse engineering”6.
This is a characteristic difference between mathemat- neither provide the correct symbols nor the correct inter-
pretation: it only provides mathematical relationships,
ics and the classical method of physics: Mathematicians
the form. If concepts like “mass” and “energy” are sup-
define or derive abstract objects which are invented in a
purely formal way, as a kind of game, a game of thought. posed to emerge from the formalism then, at some stage,
the FiT must provide an equation that matches, for in-
Then, in a second step, the forms obtain their names,
which are essentially arbitrary. Physics however picks stance, the mentioned form of the relativistic energy for-
mula. However the FiT can not provide a proof that
properties known from everyday experience on the basis
of common language. These properties have to be defined the derived formula really means the relativistic energy
formula. A formally derived FiT does not automatically
scientifically but this should not alter their meaning, it
should just render their meaning scientifically, i.e. quan- provide physical but rather mathematical relationships.
The form provides information only in the eye of the
titatively. The meaning of the “mass” of a material body
is essentially the same in physics and in common sense, well-prepared observer. The transformation of a mathe-
matical form into a physical meaningful law requires an
or at least it is very close.
When the physical significance of some symmetries identification of the terms appearing in equations with
physical quantities. This process is to some degree heuris-
have been understood, then physical theory might pre-
dict new particles because the specific symmetry prin- tic: It is an interpretation. Therefore it is unlikely that
equations that emerge within a final theory can be in-
ciple suggests the particle for its completeness. But to
invent a new symmetry principle without any prior ex- terpreted correctly by pure thought. The formulation
of the correct principles alone is not sufficient to obtain
perimental knowledge can be regarded as almost impos-
sible. Hence the FiT requires for its formulation that physical meaning: Physical laws have to be known and
proven meaningful in advance, before a FiT can be for-
most pieces of the final puzzle are already known 4 .
Elementary particle physics is a special case in this mulated. Modifying Goldberg’s insight, we might say
that we already have to know the form and relevance of
respect and its methods are closer to those of mathemat-
the Lorentz group in order to recognize its significance
ics: Most properties (or components) of particles are ab-
stract and have no counterpart in the macroscopic world, within the mathematical framework of a FiT . Therefore
it is unlikely that a FiT could be formulated “from pure
like for instance (iso-) spin or parity or helicity. In this
case physicists have to invent new, essentially arbitrary, thought” before physics sufficiently progressed towards a
fundamental level of physical reality: We can only rec-
names for particle substructures (“quarks”) and proper-
ties (“strangeness”, “charme”). The deeper physics dives ognize known patterns; the pure form does not generate
meaning. When the abstract inevitable principles of a
into the micro-cosmos, the closer it seems to be to pure
FiT are found, and a mathematical formalism has been
developed then one still has to establish the mapping be-
tween an abstract mathematical form and known physi-
4 Neither Leibniz nor Platon nor Newton could have derived a cal laws. This step in the formulation of the FiT might
final theory from pure thought, simply because the phenomena be summarized as “function follows form”. Though the
to be explained where not known precisely enough. Platons list principles of the FiT must be trivial (“self-evident”), this
of solids insofar proves the impressive power of pure thought as does not necessarily hold for the formulation of the the-
Platon obviously understood the importance of symmetry prin-
ory. Therefore it seems unlikely that a FiT will - from
ciples. But Platon could not have arrived by any means at the
gauge group SU (3) × SU (2) × U (1), not even if the mathematics beginning on - be recognized as a possible candidate for a
would have been available: Without the knowledge of the phe- theory of everything. This seems to be sufficiently proven
nomena, i.e. the list of particles, there would be no indication of by contemporary candidates like string theory: The ini-
its physical significance. tial ideas of theories might be simple, but the resulting
5

structures and mathematical forms must (by definition) The latter could, at least in principle, be the result of
be rich and complicated enough to allow for the descrip- mathematical relations. A final theory has to provide
tion of a large number of particles and fields. But if they the values of these dimensionless constants - which im-
are rich and complicated enough, then they are difficult plies that they can be derived.
to interpret.
The basic system of “undefined” quantities, that Gold-
berg mentioned, is still debated, but it appears obvious A. Measurement Standards And Physical Constants
that certain quantities can not be defined by other means
than by a description of their respective measurement Physics used arbitrary measurement standards in its
method or directly by reference to experience. This is history. There is the tale about Galileo, who measured
for instance the case for the notion of time. We can not the frequency of swinging oil lamps in church using his
“explain” time to someone who does not know what it pulse as frequency standard12 . The use of the own body
is because it is unique. A unique concept can not be ex- as a basic standard is a natural and obvious thing to do,
plained by other similar concepts since it is unique. But as the size of an object relative to ourselves is exactly
though clocks don’t explain or define what time is, clock’s what we naturally want to know. The number of steps
define how we measure time. And this is all that is re- on the way between point A to point B is exactly the
quired: Physics is neither able nor obliged to tell what type of practical knowledge that one may assume as the
things are, but physics can tell us how things behave. origin of measurement. And quite naturally, distances
It could be argued that, from the complete knowledge can be and likely have always been measured in units of
of how things behave, we finally obtain an idea of what time: A to point B might be a three day walk or a single
things are. At least one might finally say, “A” and “B” day horse ride. The use of the own body as a reference to
behave as if they were “X” and “Y”. The quantum me- measure length is nearby, because the scale of our body
chanical wavefunction behaves as if it was a probability defines the scale of our world.
density, but we can’t tell seriously that it really is (and It is well within proportion that the meter is roughly
nothing else). And it is not even obvious what difference the size of a footstep. The unit of a foot testifies this
it makes. finding and shows that measurements started with scien-
The impossibility to define the concept of time is in- tifically arbitrary units - standards that are defined prag-
sofar unproblematic in this context as the concept of matically. The first modern scientists like Galileo picked
physics itself presupposes time: The formulation of the phenomenological properties like length or duration of
“laws of nature” is meaningful because laws allow to pre- something in motion and measured dynamical properties
dict measurement results. Physics is and always was of swinging pendula and falling stones. Consequently
more than an intellectual excercise. It is a science that the first “laws” are mere (idealized) descriptions of pro-
aims to provide new technologies, new methods that al- portions13 . First scientific observations were of the sort,
low to manipulate objects. that the frequency of a swinging pendulum does (in first
A physical prediction is in several ways related to time: approximation) not depend on its amplitude. This con-
First of all, predictions enables to know the value of a tinued with Keplers and Newton’s laws: Physical laws
measurable quantity before the measurement has been were rarely formulated as equations, but as statements of
done, or, as in quantum mechanics, it at least enables to proportionality. It should be noted that laws of propor-
predict the possible measurement results and their proba- tionality allow to circumvent the definition of universal
bilities. And secondly there is an indirect relationship by units. If we say that the frequency of a swinging pen-
the presumptions that are required to make a measure- dulum is inversely proportional to the square root of its
ment meaningful, namely, that we have reference objects length, then the experimental confirmation requires (if at
with constant properties (a clock, the prototype meter, all) rulers and clocks. The law itself is correct no matter
etc) and variable properties that are to be predicted. No what units are choosen and hence a universal system of
measurement without a reference. Hence the form of units is not required to confirm them experimentally. De-
physics implies and presupposes that there is time, i.e. spite the fact that it is possible to formulate objectively
that the same type of quantity is allowed to appear in correct laws of proportion without explicit reference to
two forms, as a variable and as a constant reference. specific objects as measurement standards, the measure-
Therefore we shall next discuss the role of units and of ments that are used to find these laws, of course require
so-called “physical constants” in Sec. III A. Inherent in rulers and clocks. But they do not need a universal gauge.
the notion of time is also the concept of constancy and the As technology evolved it became unavoidable to define
specific role of constants is an important difference be- systems of units: laws of proportionality do not suffice for
tween physics and mathematics. Some of these constants the construction of a pendulum with a specified period.
are called “physical constants” because they do not ap- A consequence of the formulation of the laws of nature by
pear in mathematics. These are first of all the constants the use of equations instead of mere laws of proportions
with dimension, i.e. those that have units, like the speed is the appearance of conversion factors like the Avogadro
of light c or the Planck’s constant h̄. Then there are constant or the gravitational constant. Often these con-
dimensionless constants like the fine-structure constant. stants are named physical constants. Wikipedia explains
6

the term physical constant as follows: “A fundamental replace the contingent historical units with “objective”
physical constant is a physical quantity that is gener- units, i.e. the corresponding constant properties of fun-
ally believed to be both universal in nature and constant damental objects 5 . One of the first known natural units
in time.”14 . This, however, does not reflect the under- was the elementary charge e and it is indeed remarkable
standing of the physical significance of physical constants that any amount of charge in nature can be expressed by
in theoretical physics. Dirac wrote: “The information an integer number. If quarks are considered, the natural
that experimentalists obtain provides us with a number unit charge is e/3, but still any natural amount of charge
of constants. These constants usually have dimensions, is quantized and can be expressed as in the natural unit
and then of course, they depend on what units one uses, represented by some fundamental object that serves as
whether centimetres or inches. Then they are not of reference.
theoretical interest.”15 . Dimensionful physical constants Natural units refer to the properties of fundamental
bear no physical significance. This point of view has not (stable) objects (or processes) of nature. If matter would
changed significantly until today16 - even the idea that not be composed of atoms, e.g. if matter would not be
Planck’s constant is physically significant was questioned quantized in some way, such fundamental objects could
with some convincing arguments17 . not be explained within a FiT . It was a common idea
This situation might appear paradoxical: Those physi- in the history of physics that matter would be something
cal constants that can expected to be the result of purely that completely and continuously fills up space, pretty
mathematical considerations, are supposed to be those much as it appears to the eye. This idea is nearby, directly
with physical significance and a FiT would eventually derived from the “empirical evidence”. Today we know
have to provide their values, while those with a physical that the nucleus is very small compared to the atom’s
dimension, are considered to be physically meaningless. dimensions, which are defined by the electronic orbitals,
But though the numerical values of dimensionful physi- so that matter is far from filling up space.
cal constants are meaningless, as Dirac explained, their However, if matter would really be a continuous some-
constancy is not. For instance, the numerical value of thing that fills up space-time in a way that could not
the speed of light is meaningless as it depends on the be derived from a more fundamental theory, then a
choice of units. But the fact that a maximal velocity for FiT would be impossible, because this would imply that
massive objects exists, is of course meaningful, it is even space-time is fundamental and hence unexplainable. It
of fundamental importance. However, since a FiT must has been suggested that the antropic principle might
be formally derived from abstract principles, the values serve as an explanation. But it hardly explains anything;
of dimensionful constants can not be the result of such a it does not generate the kind of reason that the principle
theory. And since their values are not significant, there is of sufficient reason recomments.
no reason why these constants should emerge from fun-
Without a description of the internal dynamics of such
damental equations. In theoretical physics, the system
a material, we could by no means argue that and why
of units is often chosen in a way that the dimensionful
a specific radius should appear. The only way to obtain
constants like c and h̄ can be replaced by unity, i.e. they
a granular structure of matter would then be to postu-
do not appear in the equations and we can expect the
late some kind of quantization. Otherwise there would
same for a FiT .
be no means to replace the arbitrary units of mass and
For instance, it can be shown that the group velocity charge by natural units and a final theory in the sense of
vgr of wave-packets is given by vgr = ∇k ω(k). In quan- Weinberg would be impossible. Without quantization we
tum mechanics (QM) and quantum field theory (QFT), could not refer to the respective properties of an electron
wave packets represent particles and therefore the veloc- and it seems clear, that a FiT would be unthinkable in
ity of these particles is derived from the respective disper- such a world as there would be no way to get rid of the
sion relation. For massless particles this yields ω(k) = |k| arbitrariness of dimensionful units. This implies that a
such that |vgr | = 1. If frequency and wave vector have the classical FiT (i.e. a FiT without some type of quantiza-
same unit, there is no theoretical need for a dimensional tion) is logically impossible. And vice versa: If we spec-
constant called “speed of light”. This means that a FiT ulate that the formulation of a final theory is possible,
constructed from formal principles can not provide equa- then the FiT has to contain quantization in some way.
tions in which the so-called “physical constants” c, h̄, ε0 Otherwise we could not derive the objects that provide
automatically appear. In a FiT such constants have to the required natural units.
be introduced artificially simply because these constants
are artificial.

5 We emphasize the importance of reference standards within the


B. The Significance of Natural Units
logic of physics: objectivity is based on the use of reference ob-
jects. Let us expand the notion of objects and include properties
Dimensional physical constants loose their contingent of reference processes, despite the fact that we will later conjec-
status only if natural units like the elementary charge ture that objects can - within a final theory - only be understood
e or the electron mass me can be found which allow to as processes.
7

C. The Form of Physical Equations If the values of these constants would be independent
such that we could not find a mathematical law that al-
Given two physical quantities E and p of different di- lows for their derivation, then such a law needed an in-
mension are supposed to be related by a physical law in finite number of dimensionless physical constants that
the form would have to be the result of a FiT . But since the FiT
must itself be analogue to mathematics, this would be a
E = f (p) . (1) contradiction in itself. As we specified that a FiT must
derive all dimensionless physical constants mathemati-
Maybe we derived this law by a sequence of measure- cally, then the most fundamental laws may not contain
ments Ek in dependence of pk . The range within which meaningful dimensionless physical constants. The idea of
one can experimentally prepare p and measure E is cer- a FiT implies that the dimensionless physical constants
tainly finite, such that one can always approximate f (p) are effectively mathematical constants. Hence the Tay-
by a polynomial of finite degree. In the simplest case, lor series is a short polynomial or it is a transcendental
we find that f (p) is proportional to p or p2 . If f (p) is a function. Since the most fundamental equations of a FiT
steady function, this has to be expected for small enough may not include dimensionless constants, these most fun-
ranges of p, as one may always write a continuous func- damental laws have to be simple. Not because physicist
tion f (p) of a continuous variable p as a Taylor series: prefer simplicity, but because the laws are assumed to be
∞ fundamental. Nature might turn out to be different, but
P df (k) (p) (p−p̃)k
f (p) = dp k! if it is, then the specified FiT is logically impossible.
k=0 p̃
(2) Let us assume the true law would be
= C0 + C1 (p − p̃) + C2 (p − p̃)2 + · · ·
f (p) = E0 (exp (p/p0 ) − 1) , (6)
However, we can only add physical quantities of the same If p0 is very large compared to the experimentally real-
unit. Since p has a dimension, then all coefficients Ck izeable range of p, then the first experimentally verified
have different dimensions, C0 the dimension of E, de- law might be
noted by [E], C1 has dimension [E]/[p], C2 the dimension
[E]/[p2 ] and so on. This would lead to an infinite number f (p) = C1 p . (7)
of dimensional constants. However, as only two dimen-
This law would neither be absolutely right nor absolutely
sionful quantities are related in Eq. 1, it is sufficient to
wrong. It would be adequate within a certain range of p
establish two dimensionful non-zero constants p0 and E0
and increasingly inaccurate and finally useless, if the p of
and to express f in the form
interest is not within or not even close to the mentioned
E = E0 f (p/p0 ) , (3) range. It is possible to determine C1 by the measure-
ments within a limited range of p, but not E0 and p0
where now f (x) can have any mathematical form since separately. With progress of the experimental technol-
x = p/p0 is dimensionless. These two dimensionful con- ogy one might be able to extend the range of p towards
stants would fall into one, if the Taylor series had just a and beyond p0 , such that we would be able to find
single term, i.e. if the true law would be  2 !
p 1 p
E = E0 (p/p0 )n , (4) f (p) = E0 + , (8)
p0 2 p0
where we assume n 6= 0 to obtain a non-trivial equation.
However, in this case, we could not determine two con- and maybe with further experiments (or with a deeper
theoretical insight) we might conclude that the true law
stants p0 and E0 separately, but only the proportionality
constants C = E0 /pn0 . would have to be Eq. 6. It is obvious that the first dimen-
sionful constant C1 has, as such, no fundamental mean-
This example demonstrates that the mathematical
form of physical laws and the number of physical con- ing. But what about E0 and p0 ?
stants are indeed related. If a physical relation is contin- Such constants have fundamental physical significance
given that they represent natural units E0 and p0 or that
uous and can be written as a Taylor series (Eq. 2) and
the required number of natural units E0 and p0 can be they can be expressed by other natural constants. In the
relativistic energy-momentum relation
found, then one can rewrite Eq. 2 in the form
p
x = p/p0 E = m2 c4 + p 2 c 2 (9)

P dE (k) (x) (x−x̃)k these two constants are m and c, such that with E0 =
E(x) = E0 dx k! (5)

k=0 p̃ m c2 and p0 = m c one may write instead of Eq. 9
= E0 (1 + D1 (x − x̃) + D2 (x − x̃)2 + · · ·) p
E/E0 = 1 + (p/p0 )2 . (10)
with an (potentially) infinite number of dimensionless The mass m is then a property of the electron (for in-
constants Dk . stance).
8

As a final theory may not contain arbitrary units but they have to vary at all times. Secondly, since constants
only natural units as references, these units play a fun- are required to enable for measurements, then the most
damental role for the way, in which physical laws are fundamental level obviously does not allow for a direct
and can be formulated within a FiT . The natural units measurement. However, there must be a one or several
however are properties of reference objects. The FiT can functions of the fundamental variables that generate con-
not derive the value of the mass of a reference object: stants of motion and therefore the reference constants
The FiT expresses the mass of other objects in units of must be constants of motion. If all fundamental vari-
the reference object. The FiT can also not explain the ables continuously vary, the constants of motion must
stability of the reference object: The FiT instead uses at least be of second order in terms of the fundamental
the stability of the object as a self-sufficient fact: In an variables.
objective reality we must have stable objects. Constants of motion appear in all dynamical laws of
However, the FiT may not presume dimensionless con- physics. The best known constants of motion are energy,
stants since the derivation of dimensionless constants was momentum and angular momentum and a FiT has to
one of the requirements for a final theory. The conclu- provide a mechanism from which these COMs emerge.
sion of these considerations is that a FiT can not refer From Noether’s theorems we know that constants of mo-
to any physical constant at the most fundamental level. tion and invariance properties are closely connected. As
Nevertheless it is supposed to provide objects with con- described in Ref.20,21 the suggested trivial principles al-
stant properties which may then serve as references and low to derive Hamiltons equations of motion (EQOM).
that provide natural units. This apparent paradox can But the fundamental variables are not “coordinates of
(only) be solved, if the constant properties of the objects mass points”, but purely abstract variables that can not
are constants of motion (COMs) as we shall explain in be directly measured. This is a logical implication of the
Sec. V. idea of a FiT and if we interpret fundamental variables
Only the existence of fundamental objects allows to as (components) of quantum mechanics wave functions,
refer to fundamental quantities. This in turn allows to then we found a reason why the wave function itself can
express physical quantities by real (or even by natural) not be directly measurered: Quantum mechanics has the
numbers. The final theory became thinkable only by the task to analyze the behavior of ensembles solely on the
discovery of the sufficient number of physical constants, basis of their observables. But the fundamental objects,
e.g. by the invention of relativity and quantum mechan- represented by the wave function, can not be directly
ics. Without the natural objective constants c and h̄, a measured: There is no direct unit for the wave function,
final theory can not be formulated due to the lack of ref- because the (components of the) wave function vary at
erence quantities. Again: The values of these constants all times.
are not meaningful, but their constancy is. This is the A consequence of this argument is that truely funda-
modern understanding of physical units and constants: mental quantities can never be subject of a direct mea-
A final theory contains no arbitrary units, because every surement. This is the trivial and evident reason, why we
quantity can be expressed by the corresponding property can not measure (components of) ψ and claim that “the
of some fundamental object of nature. first component of the wave function at position x is five
Dimensionless constants like the fine-structure con- pumis” 6 , while there is no (principle) problem to obtain
stant α ≈ 1/137 or the mass ratio of electron and pro- the value of a magnetic field B(x) at some position in
tron me /mp ≈ 1/1836 represent proportions between the units of Gauss or Tesla. Then, however, it follows that a
properties of fundamental objects or processes. A FiT magnetic field value can not be regarded as a fundamen-
should provide the mathematical arguments that allow to tal quantity: no directly measureable physical quantity
derive these proportions and in case of success these con- can be regarded as fundamental.
stants are effectively mathematical constants like π, which
represents an extremal proportion between circumference
and diameter. IV. WHAT COULD PROVIDE THE TRIVIAL EVIDENCE
OF A FINAL THEORY?

D. Reference Objects and Constants of Motion If we apply Goldbergs characterization of mathematics


to physics, then a FiT has to be a tautology. As men-
On the most fundamental level, a FiT may neither tioned in the introduction, we suspect that a FiT might
refer to dimensional constants nor to dimensionless con- be formulated on the basis of what we do when we per-
stants, because the former are arbitrary and the latter form physical experiments, physical measurements, i.e.
have to be derived within the FiT . But on the other what we have to assume unless our experiments and mea-
hand objects with constant properties are required as surements are meaningless. Here we might also find the
references in order to allow for measurements. This ap-
parent contradiction can be resolved if we draw the fol-
lowing conclusions: Firstly, all quantities that belong to
6 A pumi is a fictious unit for wave functions.
the fundamental level, must be variables in the sense that
9

final answer to the question in what respect physics dif- objects as reference standards is undeniable the funda-
fers from pure mathematics. ment of objectivity in physics. A final theory, if consid-
Therefore the first step towards a FiT would be to ered possible at all, has to incorporate the trivial and
provide an inventory of the primary principles that are fundamental role played by measurement standards.
trivially true in any world that allows for the formulation In the mentioned quote, Einstein describes what he
of physical laws and to remove all presumptions that can did when he formulated special relativity, but it is just
not be considered to be trivially fulfilled. Since substan- an example of what physicists always do, namely to in-
tial presumptions can not be preconditions for the formu- troduce references combined with certain invariance as-
lation of a FiT , they should be critically reviewed. Es- sumptions. As they seem blatantly trivial, these assump-
sentially this requires a description of the form of physics. tions are rarely spelled out explicitely; but to define rods
and clocks (e.g. some objects) as references, implies a
number of presumptions about the relevant properties of
A. The Form of Physics: What Physicists Do these objects, namely that they are invariant. First of all
they are assumed to be constant in time, but the meter
Mathematics is itself not a model of anything but a rod is also assumed to be invariant with respect to its ori-
logical framework, and also a FiT can not in it’s origin entation in space. Certainly we won’t suggest to doubt
be a model of anything. Hence it can not be directly these invariance principles, but we should be aware of
derived from the phenomena. If a FiT is possible, then the implications of this method. Because the presumed
the description of the physical aspects of reality is based invariance principle leads, if violated, to the introduction
on a set of formal principles and we will show that the of fields: If the spin of an electron has no preferred direc-
form of physics provides trivial principles that can be tion, then this is phenomenologically identical to the ab-
used as a starting point. sence of a magnetic field. And vice versa: The violation
Physics is a scientific discipline because it is based on of the isotropy of space is phenomenologically identical
a well-defined method to test theories. The method of with the presence of a magnetic field. Contrary to what
physics is “objective” - but not because it describes “real” one might expect, but the presumed isotropy of space
objects or some kind of “objective reality”. It is objec- does not require an experimental proof: Where we find
tive because it is based on the comparison of objects with space to be anisotropic, we (have to) presume a reason,
objects. Measurements are comparisons - physicists com- namely a (gauge) field. Newton’s axiom of inertia obeys
pare the size, weight, velocity, energy and other quantita- the same logic: According to this axiom a body moves
tive properties with the size, weight, velocity and energy with constant velocity on a straight line unless a force is
of reference objects: the prototype meter, the kilogram applied. Not only that, at the time of Newton, it was
and the velocity of light are - or have been - used as ref- technically impossible to provide experimental evidence
erence. The branch of physics that provides the required for the presumed straight motion, it is logically impossi-
references, is called metrology. The definition of units ble to prove Newton’s premise as it is itself the definition
and the production of reference artifacts might appear to of (the absence of) a force. Therefore it is introduced as
be an inevitable but merely formal act. However, it is ex- an axiom. The underlying principle of this method is the
actly of the kind of inevitability which is required for the principle of (sufficient) reason. Science has to provide
formulation of a FiT . The inevitable aspects of physics reasons for distinctions, for asymmetries, for differences.
are those which in summary are the form or method of And if such reasons are not at hand, then we (have to)
physics. Since physical theories are tested by measure- assume symmetry, homogeneity, equivalence. This is not
ments, the things that physisists do when they perform a principle of nature, it is a principle of thought.
measurements, is an essential part of the form of physics. It is one of the revolutionary but also one of the most
Einstein wrote about his theory of special relativity questionable aspects of relativity, that it does not simply
that “It is striking that the theory (except for the four- continue to presume the invariance of rods and clocks,
dimensional space) introduces two kinds of things, i.e. but describes precise conditions of invariance and co-
(1) measuring rods and clocks, (2) all other things, e.g., variance and the corresponding transformation proper-
the electromagnetic field, the material point, etc. This, ties. And in doing so, it apparently breaks with a rule of
in a certain sense, is inconsistent; strictly speaking, mea- thought: Rulers are, as we explained above, by definition
suring rods and clocks should emerge as solutions of the constant. However, this holds only, if the we assume that
basic equations [...], not, as it were, as theoretically self- space-time is a fundamental notion, an assumption that
sufficient entities.”11 . This confession should be surpriz- is, as we argued above, incompatible with the logic of a
ing and disconcerting to physicists and philosophers of FiT : it would deny the possibility to argue why space
science, as it suggests that there might be missing piece, should be three-dimensional. Whence there is no contra-
a systematic incompleteness in the logic of objectivity of diction between relativity and the rules of thought, if a
the natural sciences. However (to the knowledge of the FiT is possible. The FiT transforms the contradiction
author), the fundamental role that metrology plays with into an obligation: The FiT has to formulate a criterion
respect to the method of physics is rarely mentioned, dis- that allows to characterize dimensionalities and to show
cussed or even noticed, despite the fact that the use of how spatial notions emerge.
10

Prior to the invention of relativity, physicists simply turned out to be wrong? Our preconceptions about space
presumed that clocks and rods are the same for all ob- and time are taken from “reality” as it appears to the
servers under all conditions. The theory of special rela- senses and as it is processed by our mind. But is it not
tivity is the first theory that questioned this naive pre- science (and specifically physics) that provides evidence
sumption. Now, after the experimental confirmation of and confirmation for the existence of an objective real-
relativity, we believe to know that (perfect) rods are in- ity? Steven Weinberg dedicated a complete chapter of his
variant in proper time and under rotations, but not un- book to argue “against philosophy”1 . Nevertheless he ad-
der Lorentz boosts. As rods are rarely used to measure mits on the second page of this chapter: “Physicists do
a length when they move with relativistic speeds, this of course carry around with them a working philosophy.
effect is irrelevant in all practical situations. It is dif- For most of us, it is a rough-and-ready realism, a belief
ficult to imagine a situation in which the “length con- in the objective reality of the ingredients of our scientific
traction” could have been discovered by the direct use of theories.”
rods for length measurements and accordingly it is diffi- It is irritating that Weinberg argues against philos-
cult to confirm this “effect” by direct measurements. It ophy, as his book appears to be more about philoso-
is a consequence of a formalism that has been confirmed phy than about anything else. But as he explains, he
by a variety of other methods and predictions. Despite argues not against philosophy as such but against dog-
this, the theory of special relativity has achieved the sta- matism. He writes: “Although naive mechanism seems
tus of an almost unquestionable corner-stone of physics. safely dead, physics continues to be troubled by other
Namely in accelerator and particle physics, it has reached metaphysical presuppositions, particularly those having
the same status of daily applied engineering knowledge as to do with space and time.” and on the same page he
electrodynamics and is usually regarded as part of clas- writes: “Even now, almost a century after the advent of
sical physics. To the general public, relativity is usually special relativity, some physicists still think that there
presented as a theory of space-time and rarely regarded are things that can be said about space and time on the
as an extension of metrology. We think that this might basis of pure thought.” One might be tempted to remark
be a mistake: Seen by light, Einstein’s work is full of that the idea of a final theory, as Weinberg (pro-) poses
hints that relativity is intimately connected to problems it, may as well suit the purpose of arguing in favour of
of measurement standards and relative calibration (clock a theory derived from pure thought: The inevitability,
synchronization). logical necessity and coherence that he expects from a
Our considerations result in the insight that it is not final theory, are properties that can otherwise only be
the constancy of the length of a specific (inertial) ruler found in mathematics, that is: in a branch of science
that we have to presume, but we have to presume that that is based on pure thought. Again we arrive at an
regardless of the technical problems to provide a really irritating dichotomy. On the one hand, physics defines
constant ruler, it is in principle possible. This is part itself as an experimental science, but on the other hand
of the form of physics: Despite all practical problems, it is the final objective of (theoretical) physics to find a
we presume that there is no general physical law that final theory which must be similar to pure mathematics,
prevents us in principle from manufactoring a constant in various aspects. However, the keyword in the above
ruler or a perfect kilogram. As a final theory has to be quote is “metaphysical presupposition” and in this re-
free of logical circles, the final theory can not presume spect the author fully agrees with Weinberg. A theory
stability of the natural units and rulers and provide at should not (and a final theory may not) contain meta-
the same time an explanation for this stability. physical presuppositions. This is a key requirement that
A FiT can not be based on the assumption that a we specified for a final theory: It may not contain any
specific property of a specific object is constant in time, substantial distinctions without sufficient reason. Specif-
but it may be based on the more abstract assumption ically we deny the possibility that a FiT could be based
that there are constants. It has to incorporate the basic on metaphysical assumptions. Within the context of a
assumption of metrology, namely that nature provides FiT we have to refuse any assumption that is not based
objects with constant properties that can be used as ref- on reason, any distinction that is not inevitable. And in
erences. It is then logically impossible to prove this as- consequence this means that we refuse any substantial
sumption within the theory. Any attempt to do so pro- claim.
vides merely the proof of internal consistency: It would It appears that Weinberg is aware of the fact that the
just show that the theory allows to reproduce the as- “rough-and-ready realism”, understood as a habit or a
sumptions it is based upon. tendency to be philosophically attached to the appear-
ance of reality, insofar as it is similar to “naive mechan-
ims”, is disproven by experimental evidence.
B. Existence, Appearance and Philosophy In his allegory of the cave, the greek philosopher Plato
adressed the question, whether appearance generates a
But how at all can it happen that preconceptions based faithful image of the true form of reality: “Plato has
on empirical evidence fail, that matter is almost empty Socrates describe a gathering of people who have lived
space, that Newtons concept of absolute time and space chained to the wall of a cave all of their lives, facing
11

a blank wall. The people watch shadows projected on nature as a whole) is deterministic (i.e. if it could be pre-
the wall from things passing in front of a fire behind dicted by an algorithm), then we refer to a different kind
them, and they begin to give names to these shadows. of physical law, namely to a dynamical law, to so-called
The shadows are as close as the prisoners get to view- equations of motion (EQOM). EQOMs refer to a num-
ing reality.“9 . In Platos allegory the perception of real- ber of dynamical variables that can be expressed by the
ity does not show something unreal or an illusion, but components of a state vector ψ and have the archetypical
something that is a projection or a derivation from the form
true world 7 . Thus our preconceptions fail, because they
are based on notions derived from the appearance of the ψ̇ = f (ψ) , (11)
world, namely (as Weinberg emphazises) on wrong pre-
- where the dot indicates the time derivative - such that,
conceptions about space and time. Our preconceptions
if the state of a system is represented by ψ at a certain
fail because they are based on “empirical evidence”, but
point in time, all future states of the system can be com-
not on the kind of empirical evidence of a physics exper-
puted by integrating Eq. 11. We do not consider partial
iment, but on the kind of naive “empirical evidence” of
differential equations here, for two reasons: Firstly, we
common sense.
said that a FiT is allowed to be based on the notion of
Weinberg wrote: “It is just that a knowledge of phi-
time, but not on space - and secondly, we expect that the
losophy does not seem to be of use to physicists” 8 . Here
introduction of spatial notions can be delayed to a later
we clearly disagree with Weinberg. First of all, we be-
stage, as it is always possible to use a Fourier transfor-
lieve that some knowledge of philosophy is useful to any
mation to introduce spatial notions.
human being, but more than that, we doubt that the use-
In classical physics and namely in classical statistical
fulness of philosophy can be derived from the possession
mechanics, the state vector contains the coordinates and
of some kind of knowledge. Same as physics, philosophy
momenta (Hamiltonian mechanics) or the coordinates
is mainly a proficiency. Because a final theory may not
and velocities (in Lagrangian mechanics), respectively.
be based on metaphysical assumptions, the proficiency to
In the former case, the EQOMs are derived from a con-
recognize assumptions as metaphysical is required. Re-
servation law (usually the conservation of energy) and in
gardless on how we arrive at a FiT - only if the theory
the latter case from a variational principle (the so-called
can be (re-) constructed on the basis of pure thought, it
principle of least action). The EQOM depend on a single
can be said to have met his specifications. And philoso-
variable t which can be interpreted as time, the primary
phy (even more than mathematics) is the domain of pure
“quantity” that we accept as being undefinable. Time
thought.
is the (first) variable for which the question “why time”
Besides the major concepts of physics also the specific
makes no sense within a final physical theory: Already
(apparently relativistic) form of space and time including
the concept of physical variable and of measurement im-
Lorentz transformations and the dimensionality of space-
plies that we refer to change, variation and constancy,
time must be the result of a final theory. In order to
i.e. to those notions that are associated with time. And
obtain these notions as results from a final theory, the
we shall use the required distinction of variables and con-
theory has to be based on something else, e.g. not on
stants to discuss the possible forms of Eq. 11.
the presumption of a self-sufficient space-time model. It
has to include a part that describes the emergence (or
appearance) of spatial notions. V. A SURVEY OF (TRIVIAL) PRINCIPLES OF
PHYSICS

C. The Form of Dynamical Laws


Our considerations allow to give a first, possibly in-
complete, inventory of formal first principles. The most
The example of a physical law as described in Sec. III C important being the principle of sufficient reason. Sir
concerned some general relation between two physical Hamilton summarized this principle in the short formula:
quantities like (for instance) energy and momentum. “Infer nothing without a ground or reason.”8. The idea
Such relations allow to reduce the number of free vari- of a FiT itself is based on this principle as we explained
ables by uncovering a fixed relation between quantities in Sec. II.
(variables). If we discuss whether a specific process (or The principle of reason (PSR) is the first principle that
trivially has to be respected in a FiT . The believe that
things are comprehensible is a precondition for science in
general, of course. But the principle includes more than
7 Of course, Plato uses the allegory of the cave to claim that a that. From the specifications of Weinberg, t’Hooft and
philosopher is someone who broke the chains and is therefore able
Susskind it follows that if a FiT is supposed to be in-
to see the world as it really is. This claim possibly contains a fair
amount of “marketing” for the case of philosophy. Otherwise the evitable, evidently true, complete and final, then a FiT
famous (though slightly adulterated) quote “I know that I know may not contain any arbitary distinction or selection, no
nothing” would likely not be found in Platos work10 . concept should be introduced without a clear and ev-
8 Chapter 7, “against philosophy”. ident reason. The final theory does not have to pro-
12

vide causal explanations for individual phenomena, but Besides the distinction of variables from constants, we
it should provide sufficient reasons for the general form have to distinguish quantity from structure. It is trivially
of the phenomena. Hence a FiT can not (and does not true that physical models contain variables that repre-
have to) tell what time is, since we can not even formu- sent quantities. But structures have to be derived. A
late the idea of what physics is without presuming that quantity can be represented by a number and a unit. A
the concept of time is already known. structure is given by an algebra. The complex plane for
Secondly, as we explained before, the presumed con- instance is represented by an algebra: The unit imaginary
cepts of time and measurement inevitably lead to the i can not be represented by a number and therefore we
trivial confession that physical models contain variables (have to) introduce a symbol. Something similar holds
and constants. As we argued, for logical reasons, con- for the number π, namely the fact that we can not write
stants may not appear at the fundamental level, neither it down explicitely, suggests the use of a symbol. But
dimensional nor dimensionless. Despite this, the idea unlike π, which can by no means be completely written
of a measurement requires the appearance of true con- down, we can represent the unit imaginary by a structure
stants for reference. We might call this requirement “the that fully characterizes the algebra of the complex num-
principle of objectivity” (POO). It is the basis of the re- bers, namely that of 2 × 2-matrices21 . The introduction
lation between a physical theory and “objective reality”: of a new symbol like i is equivalent to the introduction of
Physical equations refer to relations between properties an algebraic structure. It is therefore reasonable to ask,
of objects and though this is rarely within the focus of if the unit imaginary is essential for quantum mechanics
attention, these objects have to be physically made, if or not - and if it is, then why? The use of complex num-
the equations are to be confirmed. The production of bers in quantum mechanics can be questioned and hence
artifacts with constant properties must after all be pos- it is a substantial choice. Since a FiT may not presume
sible in principle. If this is not the case, then we can what it is supposed to derive, it is not legitimate to sim-
not directly measure this property. Even worse, strictly ply presume a prominent role for complex numbers in a
speaking it could be questioned if such a property is ob- FiT ; the FiT has to provide a reason.
jectively there. This prelimenary survey does not claim to be com-
The dichotomy that we may not directly introduce con- plete. There are likely more trivial principles that belong
stants while measurements are nevertheless based on the to the form of physics which we did not even mention.
availability of such constants, can be solved: dimensional One of the principles that we did not discuss is implied
constants are logically connected to the laws of motion - in the possibility of a quantitative description: If there
they appear in the form of constants of motion (COMs). are observable quantitative properties of objects, then
Within a FiT constants of motion are the only possi- these properties must be additive: The length is of two
ble method to introduce dimensional constants. Either rods is twice the length of a single rod. And there are
we derive constants of motion from a law of motion, or certainly more principles of this kind. We summarized
vice versa, but in the former case we have to presume these principles in the formula “a world that allows for a
substantial laws, while in the latter case we just pre- physical description”, which is both, precise enough for
sume the trivial fact that constants must exist. The lat- the purpose of this paper and vague enough to include
ter presumption is sufficienty trivial to serve as a first those principles that we did not discuss explicitely.
principle, but we have a prize to pay: if the most fun- Let us finally emphasize that the describes principles
damental constants are constants of motion that come imply a strong selection: Whatever might be “out there”,
along with some law of motion of some set of fundamen- we can only measure those things that obey a law of mo-
tal variables ψ = (ψ1 , ψ2 , . . . , ψk ), then a reference for a tion which provides the necessary constants of motion as
measurement of the components of ψ is logically impos- reference standards. Everything else is noise. Scientists
sible. The fundamental level is a level of pure variables, should in general avoid to make claims about unmeasur-
while the “level” of constants of motion is at least second able things. However, as we argued, with respect to a
order in ψ. As we have shown in Ref.20,21 , the constants final theory, we can not avoid to make at least one claim
of motion are the even moments of ψ. Since COMs are about the wave-function, namely that its components are
required to obtain observables, then, within a FiT , the not directly measurable. This is not unreasonable, but a
fundamental level of reality can not be observed: The logical necessity.
final theory must distinguish between existence and ap-
pearance.
In Ref.20 we used an “ontology of time” as the basis VI. OBJECTIVITY AND CLASSICAL REALISM
for the same reasoning. But as we have shown in this
essay, the suggested principle of variation (POV) can be As explained in the previous sections, it appears that,
derived from the idea of a FiT , hence finally from the given a final theory would be possible or even the only
principle of sufficient reason. A genuine ontology is not logical consequence of the program of some specific ratio-
required, as we derived the law, that all variables on some nalism, then this seriously questions that objectivity and
fundamental level have to vary, from distinct formal con- realism are compatible with each other; if the final the-
siderations. ory would be found and could be regarded as objectively
13

and evidently (trivially) correct, then physical appear- objectively true, unless one questions that a kilogramm,
ance and existence must be distinguished and classical a meter rod or a clock can be used as measurement stan-
realism must be regarded as disproven. Or, if we choose dard. But classical realism reverses this logic and claims
to believe that classical realism must be correct, then a that only the “objective” aspects of the world “really” ex-
final theory is impossible and there must be something ist. We think that this type of restrictive realism is not
unreasonable, i.e. some kind of significant but unrea- only not required, but it builds a barrier between natural
sonable arbitariness in the world, something outside the and social sciences that is not helpful. Besides that, the
PSR, something that a FiT could not derive or explain. metaphysical assumptions of realism are not required to
Hence it appears that there is an intrinsic contradiction obtain objective knowledge of nature.
between realism and rationalism. The rationalist would Especially the closure claim of classical realism can be
expect that a FiT is possible - but then a “realistic” considered problematic, especially in the context of the
worldview is logically impossible. questions of free will and the nature of consciousness.
We defined the notion of objectivity of experimental
physics and we believe it is as clear as it is practically
and theoretically relevant, though it refers to the notion VII. SOME FORMAL CONSIDERATIONS
of object, i.e. to something that is given only through
experience. Realism, the complementary notion of ob-
While we measure the weight of an object, by compar-
jectivity, on the other hand, is more difficult to specify,
ing it to reference weights, we do not bother too much
also, because is appears in a number of variants. Often
about the number system used. This might be depre-
realism and objectivity are used in combination as objec-
cated by pure mathematicians, but for most experimental
tive reality, some sort of common sense agreement about
physicist (and likely for most engineers), there are only
what is meant by “the world”. Instead of making at-
two types of numbers required: integers and reals. The
tempts to give a theoretical definition of “realism”, let
question, whether it is logically necessary to use the reals
us instead refer to a number of statements, that a strong
instead of the rational numbers, can be pragmatically an-
realist would likely support:
swered insofar as there is no immediate reason to restrict
• The world is in a fundamental way as we perceive the number system to the rationals, despite the fact that
it, i.e. composed of objects located in space and we can never obtain a non-rational measurement result
time. Objects are made of matter. in measurements of limited precision. Though we can not
measure π with infinite precision, we are still be able to
• Every physical effect has an exclusively physical find ways to measure π to any required precision by the
cause: The physical world is closed. This includes: use a sufficiently large circles. Insofar the experimental
determination of π via measurement is in principle not
• The only possible way to influence the physical different from its computation: No one can compute (or
world is by physical action (i.e. through actions write down or store on a computer disc) the number π
of the body). with infinite precision; but it can be done with any re-
• All valid information about the world originates quired precision: there is no logical limit to the precision
from information that has been received physically, with which we can either compute or measure π.
i.e. with finite velocity v ≤ c via physical signals Sometimes it is argued that the reals are - besides the
through our senses. complex numbers and the quaternions - just the simplest
field over which one can define division rings and that
It is noteworthy, that while the principle of objectiv- this fact suggests that the most general mathematical
ity defines (and therefore limits) the scope of empiri- objects (i.e. the quaternions) should be used on the fun-
cal sciences, especially that of physics, realism defines damental level of a final physical theory. Despite the fact,
(and therefore limits) reality, most often to the notions of that quaternions might play a prominent role in some ar-
space, time, matter and causality, or by suggesting lim- eas of physics, we reject the general argument. Both the
its of possible information transfer. The former leaves complex numbers as well as the quaternions, can be rep-
the question open if the objectively real is a subset of resented by real valued structures, namely the complex
the real, while the latter reduces the world to the objec- numbers by real 2 × 2 and the quaternions by real 4 × 4
tive by definition. Strange enough that these notions are matrices. Therefore they are not more fundamental than
rarely distinguished by physicists. We do not intend to real matrices, but less, as they refer to specific matrix
discuss this is much detail, but we would like to empha- algebras. Instead of presuming a fundamental role for
size that the principle of objectivity defines a fundamen- a specific algebraic structure, a FiT should derive and
tal rule for quantitative empirical science that can not be explain this structure and prove its fundamentality. The
questioned on scientific grounds, while realism tries to es- intransparent mixture of quantity and structure however
tablish a specific ideology that is based to a large degree may lead to confusion about the meaning and role of
on unproveable metaphysical claims. One might summa- complex numbers in quantum mechanics and physics in
rize this as follows: it is logically impossible to question general. This is indicated by the discussion about the
that physical laws are - within their limits of validity - meaning of complex numbers in QM that is ongoing for
14

decades22–34 . suggests the pattern of Minkowski space-time. There are


We do not recognize the progress in mixing quantity 10 sympletic generators within this Lie-algebra that re-
and structure on the fundamental level. Rather, if com- quire an interpretation: a 3 + 1 dimensional vector and a
plex numbers are a preferable, this should be a result six-component bi-vector. The transformation properties
of the algebraic properties of the FiT . This fact is re- of these components suggest the interpretation in terms
flected by the architecture of number systems in com- of energy, momentum, electric- and magnetic field20,21
puters, computers which are able to perform simulations and the equations of motion of the autocorrelation matrix
of quantum systems, i.e. integers and reals. A com- allow for a derivation of the Lorentz force. However, the
puter is usually understood as purely based on binary primary and fundamental variables are not space-time co-
digits. Though this is trivially true for contemporary ordinates any more. Instead the fundamental variables
digital computers, the existence of analogue computers are the (abstract) components of ψ, which can best be
and the fact that the personal computer had originally described as points in an abstract phase space. These
two processing units, the central processing unit (CPU) ideas thus reverse the role between “real” space and
and the floating point unit (FPU), can be regarded as an phase space: The 3 + 1-dimensional “energy-momentum
argument against the fundamentality of the bit: Even, if space” is an effective space that emerges on the basis
the memory of modern computers is by design based on of a fundamental 4-dimensional phase space described
bits, it is undeniable that we can not use it in a general in proper time and the concept of space-time emerges
scientifically meaningful way without introducing a repre- through Fourier transformation. Effectively this Fourier
sentation of floating point numbers. This representation transformation is similar to the characteristic function of
is based on bits for purely practical reasons. Though any probability theory, but its argument is not the probabil-
given coding scheme of floating point numbers allows only ity density function (PDF) ρ, but the product of ψ and

for a limited precision, we are able to construct coding ρ. The 6-dimensional phase space of a “mass point”
schemes for any required precision. emerges from the equations of motion of the second mo-
ments and is symplectic only in a low-energy and low-field
approximation.
A. Structure Preservation Hence it seems possible to derive the concepts of mass
and spin (the two invarients of motion of a 4-spinor), of
Any finite physical system can be described by a (possi- energy-momentum 4-vector, of the electromagnetic field
bly infinite) set of varying real fundamental quantities as and the transformation properties of the Lorentz group
a function of time ψ(t). But all observable (measurable) (rotations and boosts) on the basis of trivial principles.
properties are of even (at least second) order in these fun- This is a first “proof of principle” that a FiT might in-
damental variables. The variables themselves can not be deed be possible - as a tautological theory.
directly measured due to the lack of constant references.
References for measurements are constants of motion and
they are at least of second order in ψ. Once we presume VIII. SUMMARY
some (arbitrary) constant of motion H(ψ), then further
constants of motion emerge in the description of this fun- In this paper we picked up the idea of a final theory of
damental “objects”20,21 , namely the traces of powers of physics. First we formulated the requirements of a final
the autocorrelation matrix (matrix of second moments), theory. These seem to be extreme in view of the severe
multiplied by the symplectic unit matrix. When the gen- difficulties of modern physics to unify gravity and quan-
eral constant of motion H(ψ) can be written as a (multi- tum mechanics. But regardless of the current status of
variate) Taylor series, then the leading order terms auto- theoretical physics, the idea of a final theory has its roots
matically generate structure preservation. The presumed in the principle of sufficient reason (PSR) and hence es-
constancy of H(ψ) generates a self-identity of “objects” sentially in rationalism. Specifically the idea that a final
via the identity of motional patterns. No other identity theory would be inevitable and that it would carry the
is required and possible. As we argued in Ref.20,21 , the evidence for its truth in itself seems to suggest that -
most general framework for structure preserving motion following Goldberg’s characterization of mathematics - a
is symplectic motion and it is a logical consequence of the final theory of physics must be a tautology. This implies
constancy of H 9 . Furthermore it has been shown that that all statements of the theory are predetermined in
the most simple, fundamental, and non-trivial algebra its premises such that it is possible to derive the content
that describes the general properties of symplectic mo- of physics logically from the premises, but also to elabo-
tion, is given by the real Dirac (Clifford-) algebra Cl(3, 1) rate to a higher degree of precision what a final theory is
which implies that the fundamental set of observables able to tell us about the world, and even more, what it is
not able to tell. The absence of metaphysical presuppo-
sitions is a logical necessity of the finality of a FiT - but
it does not imply the absence of “metaphysical” conclu-
9 It can be shown that unitary motion is a special case of sym- sions. The final theory as we scetched it, might tell a lot
plectic motion35 about reality, but likely not what some of us expected to
15

find. It will not tell us, why there is something instead of 14 Wikipedia; https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Physical constant,
nothing. It will not even tell us, what type of substance (5th July 2016).
15 P.A.M. Dirac “The Large Numbers Hypothesis” in: The Physi-
matter “really” is. The tautological FiT - and we claim
cist’s Conception of nature; Edt. Jagdish Mehra (1973), D. Reidel
that no other FiT is possible - is, well, tautological. Publishing Company Dordrecht-Holland / Boston-U.S.A..
Besides the PSR, which provides the rationale for a fi- 16 Hsu, L. and Hsu, J. P. ”The physical basis of natural units and

nal theory, and is therefore obligatory, we discussed some truly fundamental constants” (2012). Eur. Phys. J. Plus, 127: 11.
17 John P. Ralston “Quantum Theory without Planck’s Constant”,
premises for a FiT that may in summary be called the
arXiv:1203.5557, (2012).
form of physics. We presented a first primitive analysis of 18 Stanley Goldberg “Understanding Relativity”, Birkhäuser Basel
the conjectured possibility of a FiT . We identified three Boston Stuttgart (1984).
types of physical constants, namely dimensionless con- 19 C. Baumgarten “Use of real Dirac matrices in coupled linear

stants, dimensional conversion factors and natural units. optics”; Phys. Rev. ST Accel. Beams. 14, 114002 (2011).
20 C. Baumgarten; “Relativity and (Quantum-) Electrodynamics
We explained why the only possible dimensional physical
constant within a FiT is the natural unit and that it can from (Onto-) Logic of Time”; in Ruth E Kastner, Jasmina
Jeknic-Dugic and George Jaroszkiewicz (Edt.) “Quantum Struc-
only emerge from the theory as a constant of motion. We tural Studies”, World Scientific (2017), ISBN: 978-1-78634-140-2.
argued that this result logically implies that the funda- Preprint arXiv:1409.5338v5 (2014/2015).
mental level of a FiT is not directly measurable - not 21 C. Baumgarten; “Old Game, New Rules: Rethinking the Form

because the fundamental level is less “real”, but because of Physics”, Symmetry 2016, 8(5), 30; doi:10.3390/sym8050030.
22 F. Strocchi, “Complex Coordinates and Quantum Mechanics”,
there is an unavoidable lack of reference.
Rev. Mod. Phys. 38, No. 1 (1966), pp. 36-40.
23 D. Hestenes “Vectors, Spinors and Complex Numbers in Classical

and Quantum Physics”, Am. J. Phys. Vol. 39/9 (1971), 1013-


1027.
REFERENCES 24 W.E. Baylis, J. Huschlit and Jiansu Wei “Why i?” Am. J. Phys.

Vol. 60 (1992), 788-795.


1 Steven 25 Philip Goyal, Kevin H. Knuth and John Skilling “Origin of com-
Weinberg; “Dreams of a final theory”, Vintage Books
(1993), ISBN 9780099223917. plex quantum amplitudes and Feynman’s rules”, Phys. Rev. A
2 G. t’Hooft, L. Susskind, E. Witten, M. Fukugita, L. Randall, 81, 022109 (2010).
26 Julian B. Barbour, “Time and complex numbers in canonical
L. Smolin, J. Stachel, C. Rovelli, G. Ellis, S. Weinberg and R.
Penrose; Nature Vol. 433, 20th Jan. 2005, pp. 257-259. quantum gravity”, Phys. Rev. D 47, No. 12 (1993), pp. 5422-
3 A. Einstein in: The Living Age, Vol. 304 (3 Jan 1920), 41-43. 5429.
4 Wikipedia 27 J.L. Rosales “Remarks on the issue of time and complex numbers
on “Reality” (Jan. 2017):
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Reality. in canonical quantum gravity”, Phys. Rev. D 54 No. 6 (1996),
5 Max Tegmark: “The Mathematical Universe” (2007); pp. 4185-4188.
28 Matthew McKague, Michele Mosca and Nicolas Gisin “Simulat-
arXiv:0704.0646.
6 W. Smilga “Reverse Engineering Approach to Quantum Electro- ing Quantum Systems Using Real Hilbert Spaces”, Phys. Rev.
dynamics”; J. of Mod. Phys. Vol.4 (2013), 561-571. Lett. 102, 020505 (2009).
7 “Principle of Sufficient Reason”, Stanford Encyclopedia of Phi- 29 Felix Lev “Why is Quantum Physics Based on Complex Num-

losophy; https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/sufficient-reason/ bers?”; Finite Fields and Their Applications, Vol. 12, 336-355
8 Sir William Hamilton “Lectures On Logic Vol. 1”, Boston: Gould (2006), preprint: arXiv:hep-th/0309003.
30 Charis Anastopoulos “Quantum vs stochastic processes and the
(1859), https://archive.org/details/lecturesonmetaph00hamiuoft
9 Wikipedia on “Allegory of the Cave”, role of complex numbers”; Int.J.Theor.Phys.42:1229-1256,2003,
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Allegory of the Cave, dated preprint: arXiv:gr-qc/0208031.
31 J.A. Miszczak “States and channels in quantum mechanics with-
August 14th, 2016. Original: Plato Republic, 514a.
10 Wikipedia on “Sokrates”, https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Socrates, out complex numbers”, arXiv:1603.04787.
32 C.P. Kwong “The mystery of square root of minus one in quan-
original: Plato Apologeia, 21d: “Denn es mag wohl eben keiner
von uns beiden etwas Tüchtiges oder Sonderliches wissen; allein tum mechanics, and its demystification”, arXiv:0912.3996.
33 James M. Chappell, Azhar Iqbal, Derek Abbott “Geo-
dieser meint etwas zu wissen, obwohl er nicht weiss, ich aber,
wie ich eben nicht weiss, so meine ich es auch nicht.”. metric Algebra: A natural representation of three-space”,
11 A. Einstein, Autobiographical Notes, Trans. by Paul Arthur arXiv:1101.3619v4.
34 G. W. Gibbons “The emergent nature of time and the complex
Schilpp, Open Court Publ. 1979.
12 Antonis Modinos; “From Aristotle to Schrödinger”, Springer numbers in quantum cosmology”, arXiv:1111.0457v1.
35 J.P. Ralston: “PT and CPT quantum mechanics embedded in
(Cham, Heidelberg, New York, Dortrecht, London) 2014.
13 Dino Boccaletti, “Galileo and the Equations of Motion” Springer symplectic quantum mechanics”; J. Phys. A Math. Theor. Vol.
(Cham, Heidelberg, New York, Dortrecht, London) 2016. 40 (2007), pp. 9883-9904.

You might also like