You are on page 1of 6

A Primer on Knowledge?

Rationalism vs Empiricism

WRITTEN BY
Erik Kenrick
POSTED IN
Epistemology, Philosophy
TAGGED
Aristotle, Belief, Empiricism, Epistemology, Justification, Knowledge, Philosophy, Plato, Rat
ionalism, Ronald Nash, Truth

Humans are knowing creatures. Our mental capabilities are vital to our existence and full of
amazing possibilities. Our ability to expand our knowledge spurs science, culture, and
religion forward. But how do we know what we know? Maybe we should back up a little.
What is knowledge? How do we grow what we know? Can we justify what we know to
others? Knowledge—what seems to be a basic feature of everyday life—is a complex
subject.

What Is Epistemology?
All these inquiries fall under the philosophical branch of study called epistemology. The
word epistemology is an English word derived from two Greek words:
• Episteme (knowledge or understanding)
• Logos (the study of)
In short, epistemology is the study of knowledge.[1] Philosophers know it as the “study of
the theory of knowledge.” We’ll look at a brief historical overview of the philosophical
category of epistemology. Our special focus will be the differences between rationalism
and empiricism.
What is Knowledge?
Knowledge is “justified true belief.” It’s been the accepted definition for centuries and it’s
the one I’ll be using.[2] Defining one’s terms is easy to neglect, but it’s integral to the
philosophical process. More ink has been spilled over definitions than you’d imagine. So
let’s take care of this important matter. Knowledge is “justified true belief.” This definition
has three parts:
• Belief – You must believe something in order for to have knowledge. You
cannot know something is you don’t believe it.
• Truth – The thing you believe must correspond to reality. You cannot know
something that is false.
• Justification – You need a reason for your belief. This is why guessing the
number of M&Ms in a carnival game (it’s 527 by the way) by chance is
called “luck.” You cannot “luck” into knowledge.

You need all three to have knowledge. If you only have two out of three you get one of the
following:
• Belief + Truth = Something you believe, that’s also true, but for which you
lack any justification. Some might call this blind faith.
• Belief + Justification = Something you believe but are wrong about.
• Truth + Justification = Something you should believe but don’t.
3 Kinds of Knowledge
Philosophers have categorized knowledge into three different and unique groups:[3]
Acquaintance Knowledge (Who)
The knowledge of a person through being in some sort of relationship to them. Sometime
called intimate knowledge.
Competence Knowledge (How)
The knowledge of a skill or ability. For example, knowing how to play an instrument or a
sport. It’s a knowledge gained through repetition and the development of muscle memory.
Propositional Knowledge (What)
The knowledge of facts or propositions gained through study or observation.
Putting It All Together
What’s it like to have one kind of knowledge but not another about a topic? Imagine I knew
every fact (proposition) about you mother: height, favorite movie, age, etc. My knowledge
would still be qualitatively different from yours. You know her (acquaintance knowledge).
I just know about her. The same goes for competence knowledge. You can tell me all the
facts about how to play the trumpet, but I won’t be able to play it well without practice and
repetition.
The Acquisition and Justification of Propositional Knowledge
The only kind of knowledge debated by philosophers is propositional knowledge. The two
major schools of thought that have been duking it out for centuries are:
• Rationalism (Represented by Plato)
• Empiricism (Represented by Aristotle)
The other minor schools of thought are just variations of these two. I consider myself a
rationalist and utterly detest empiricism. Nonetheless I’ll try to give you an accurate
account of both.
Plato and the Rationalist School
Plato believed that humans participated in two spheres of existence:
• The world of the forms (pure being)
• The world of particular things (becoming)
The world of the forms is an unchanging immaterial world of pure being. The world of
particular things is the material, constantly changing world we’re all familiar with. Plato
got these ideas from two philosophers before him, Heraclitus and Parmenides.[4]
For Heraclitus, ultimate reality is in a state of flux; it’s always changing or becoming. He
said that you can never step in the same river twice. If you remove your foot from the river
and then put it back, all the molecules have moved and it is, in a sense, a different river.[5]
Parmenides, on the other hand, believed that all of reality is pure being. He realized that
there are such things as universal, unchanging principles. For example, one plus one equals
two.
Plato saw the elements of truth in both perspectives. Instead of picking one over the other,
he synthesized them into his doctrine of the two worlds. Plato agreed with Parmenides that
there are unchanging principles. Plato calls these unchanging principles the “forms.” Plato
relegated the forms to another world because he agreed with Heraclitus that the world we
experience is always changing. Thus Plato divides the universe into two categories:
• Forms (essences)
• Particulars (individual examples of forms)
Plato taught that every particular thing represents an essence. For example, if you draw a
square your drawing would be a particular square and not the essential or perfect square.
Your particular square is representing the idea (form) of the perfect square.
Plato applied this dualism to mankind saying that the human being is composed of body
and soul. The body is participating in the world of becoming by getting older and changing
in appearance. The soul is participating in the world of the forms through immortality and
reason. Plato did this because he noticed that humans are capable of interacting with the
forms through reason. He attributed this ability to the reality of innate ideas.[6]
Innate Ideas
Innate ideas are a form of knowledge that the mind contains prior to experience and birth.
For Plato, innate knowledge is knowledge of the forms. Plato explained the existence of
innate ideas with that of the preexistence of the soul. The only way that one could have
knowledge of the forms at birth is if the person’s soul existed in the world of the forms
prior to birth.[7] For Plato knowledge in this life is not a process of acquisition but of
remembrance.
The World of Particulars Is Structured on the World of the Forms
Plato contends that the world of particular things is structured off off the world of the
forms. This means that the mind is capable of understanding things about the external
world (the world outside one’s own mind) because it’s conscious of the structure that the
world it’s founded upon. This is essentially what it means to be rationalist; it is to believe
that the world and the mind share the same structure. This is what makes knowledge
possible. For the rationalist, reason is both a reliable and primary guide for grounding
knowledge.
Aristotle and the Empiricist School
Aristotle was Plato’s student. He knew all about Plato’s doctrine of the two worlds, but
rejected it. Although he believed in universals (forms), he denied the preexistence of the
soul as being necessary to explain how we know about them. Aristotle said we become
conscious of universals the other way around. Rather than starting with innate ideas we
start with particulars and work our way up. This is because Aristotle believed that
universals or the forms are not innate knowledge.[8]
Aristotle said we’re all born as blank slates. We acquire knowledge through our experience
of particulars. We then universalize these experiences and apply them to new
experiences.[9]
Consider the idea of similarity. Things that are similar share certain characteristics.
Remember the game “Which of these does not belong?” You won by picking item doesn’t
share the characteristic the others do. Care to play? Which of the following does not
belong:
• Bat
• Penguin
• Crow
• Sparrow
If you answered “Bat” congratulations! Bats are mammals the rest are birds. Bird-ness is
what all the members of the list above share (their similarity) except for the bat. We learn
what bird-ness is by experiencing particular birds. This is what it means to be an empiricist;
we gain knowledge through experience. For an empiricist, experience is the grounding
principle of knowledge.
And the Winner Is…
In conclusion, as tempting as empiricism may appear, it has significant problems. How can
the idea of similarity even get off the ground if we didn’t have some notion of it to begin
with? This goes for the idea of equality, dissimilarity, and sameness as well. If it’s true that
we’re born with no innate knowledge how could we come to any conclusions at all? We
couldn’t. Empiricism destroys knowledge. We’d be a bundle of perceived particulars we
couldn’t do anything with. We’d be like the beasts driven by instinct. Or we might be like a
tree having life but no discernible consciousness. If empiricism destroys our foundation for
knowledge then it is demonstrably inferior to rationalism.
Rationalism Works
Furthermore, rationalism works. We can apply universal principles to the external world
(the world outside our own minds) successfully. Engineers do this every day. They draw
their reason on paper. When followed, reason produces stable buildings. This implies that
reality has a structure complementary to the human mind. But how could this be? Was
Plato right? Is there a world of forms that serves as the foundation for the world of
particular things?
Rationalism, Plato’s Forms, and God’s Aseity
Since we just finished beating up empiricism you may be tempted to say “yes.”. Not so fast.
There’s one more qualification we need to make. In the Christian worldview God is the
only entity which has the characteristic of aseity. Aseity is complete independence.[10] The
forms are not completely independent, but rather find their origin in the mind of God which
St. Augustine pointed out.[11]
Because we’re created in God’s image we have these principles implanted in our
consciousness. This makes the whole knowing enterprise possible. It also explains why
rationalism works. The external world is intelligible because a supremely intelligent God
created it.
Christian rationalism is superior to empiricism because:
• It has the most explanatory power.
• It does not share the weaknesses of empiricism.
• It’s faithful to the Bible.
• It works in the real world.
So there you have it, an overview of the differences between rationalism and empiricism.
1. Lawhead, William F. The Philosophical Journey: An Interactive Approach.

Mountain View, CA: Mayfield Pub., 2000. 52. Print.


2. Lawhead, William F. The Philosophical Journey: An Interactive Approach.

Mountain View, CA: Mayfield Pub., 2000. 53. Print.


3. Lawhead, William F. The Philosophical Journey: An Interactive Approach.

Mountain View, CA: Mayfield Pub., 2000. 52. Print.


4. Nash, Ronald H. “History of Philosophy and Christian Thought: Early Greek
Philosophers.” Apple (audio blog), November 9,
2010. https://itunes.apple.com/us/podcast/early-greek-

philosophers/id403537295?i=88863458&mt=2.
5. Nash, Ronald H. “History of Philosophy and Christian Thought: Early Greek
Philosophers.” Apple (audio blog), November 9,
2010. https://itunes.apple.com/us/podcast/early-greek-

philosophers/id403537295?i=88863458&mt=2.
6. Nash, Ronald H. “History of Philosophy and Christian Thought: The Essence
of Plato’s Philosophy.” Apple (audio
blog) https://itunes.apple.com/us/podcast/essence-platos-

philosophy/id403537295?i=88863473&mt=2
7. Botton, Alain De, Benjamin Jowett, and M. J. Knight. The Essential Plato.

New York: Quality Paperback Book Club, 1999. 616-17.


8. Nash, Ronald H. “History of Philosophy and Christian Thought: Aristotle and
Dualism.” Apple (audio
blog) https://itunes.apple.com/us/podcast/aristotle-and-

dualism/id403537295?i=88863462&mt=2
9. Lawhead, William F. The Philosophical Journey: An Interactive Approach.

Mountain View, CA: Mayfield Pub., 2000. 91. Print.


10. Robert Audi ed., The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy. 2nd ed.

Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999. 240.


11. Nash, Ronald H. “History of Philosophy and Christian Thought: Augustine”
Apple (audio blog) https://itunes.apple.com/us/podcast/augustine-

01/id403537295?i=88863441&mt=2
https://www.credocourses.com/blog/2015/a-primer-on-knowledge-rationalism-vs-
empiricism/

You might also like