You are on page 1of 6

Perspectives

Research Ethics Recommendations


for Whole-Genome Research:
Consensus Statement
Timothy Caulfield*, Amy L. McGuire, Mildred Cho, Janet A. Buchanan, Michael M. Burgess, Ursula Danilczyk, Christina M. Diaz,
Kelly Fryer-Edwards, Shane K. Green, Marc A. Hodosh, Eric T. Juengst, Jane Kaye, Laurence Kedes, Bartha Maria Knoppers,
Trudo Lemmens, Eric M. Meslin, Juli Murphy, Robert L. Nussbaum, Margaret Otlowski, Daryl Pullman, Peter N. Ray,
Jeremy Sugarman, Michael Timmons

A
dvances in technology have covered in this paper are current issues field (Box 2). Indeed, the door must
made it possible to sequence worthy of immediate attention. remain open for further reflection on
a whole human genome [1,2]. The paper starts with initial these and other social concerns.
National and international funding considerations, including general
initiatives have stimulated whole- recommendations about governance Initial Considerations, Governance,
genome research activities [3,4], and and the characterization of the and Oversight
media coverage of both the science research activities related to the whole Whole-genome research can be utilized
[5,6] and the emerging commercial genome. It is important to note that in a wide variety of contexts, including
offerings [7,8] related to genome while there was consensus on all as a mode to advance sequencing
research has heightened public recommendations, there was a good technology, to develop a research
awareness and interest in personal deal of debate about the degree to resource platform, and to do disease-
genomics. As technology continues which they satisfy existing ethical and specific investigations. Regardless of
to advance, whole-genome research legal norms [13]. All participants the purpose of the activity, whole-
activities seem likely to intensify believed that we need both empirical genome research may implicate issues
and expand, necessitating carefully research and continued conceptual and ethics norms associated with
considered consensus guidelines for analysis (Box 1). These are early days population health (particularly when
ethical research practice. in the field of whole-genome research. used in conjunction with biobanks and
To date, there has been only Research ethics guidance is needed cohort studies), the provision of health
minimal consideration of the research immediately, but we should continue care, and research. Recognizing that
ethics issues associated with this work to explore the ethical, legal, and social the characterization and resolution of
[9–12]. We therefore convened an implications of this rapidly evolving ethical challenges will vary depending
interdisciplinary consensus workshop
to develop ethically rigorous and
practical guidance for investigators Citation: Caulfield T, McGuire AL, Cho M, Buchanan and Michael Timmons are at the X Prize Foundation,
and research ethics boards. What JA, Burgess MM, et al. (2008) Research ethics Santa Monica, California, United States of America.
follows are recommendations on the recommendations for whole-genome research: Eric T. Juengst is at the Department of Bioethics, Case
Consensus statement. PLoS Biol 6(3): e73. Western Reserve University, Cleveland, Ohio, United
four topics that were the focus of the doi:10.1371/journal.pbio.0060073 States of America. Jane Kaye is at the Ethox Centre,
workshop. These topics—consent, Oxford University, Oxford, United Kingdom. Laurence
Copyright: © 2008 Caulfield et al. This is an Kedes is at the Institute for Genetic Medicine, Keck
withdrawal from research, return open-access article distributed under the terms School of Medicine of the University of Southern
of research results, and public data of the Creative Commons Attribution License, California, Los Angeles, California, United States of
release—were selected because they which permits unrestricted use, distribution, America. Bartha Maria Knoppers is at the Faculty
and reproduction in any medium, provided the of Law, University of Montreal, Montreal, Quebec,
were viewed as being among the most original author and source are credited. Canada. Trudo Lemmens is at the Faculty of Law,
pressing research ethics issues and University of Toronto, Toronto, Ontario, Canada.
as representing areas where whole- Timothy Caulfield is at the Health Law Institute, Eric M. Meslin is at the Center for Bioethics, Indiana
University of Alberta, Edmonton, Alberta, Canada. University, Indianapolis, Indiana, United States of
genome analysis creates unique Amy L. McGuire and Christina M. Diaz are at the America. Juli Murphy is at the Genetics and Public
challenges. They are not, of course, Center for Medical Ethics and Health Policy, Baylor Policy Center, Washington, D. C., United States
College of Medicine, Houston, Texas, United States of America. Robert L. Nussbaum is at the Division
the only policy issues that need to of America. Mildred Cho is at the Stanford Center of Medical Genetics, University of California San
be considered; commercialization, for Biomedical Ethics, Stanford University, Stanford, Francisco, San Francisco, California, United States of
patenting, benefit sharing, and the California, United States of America. Janet A. America. Margaret Otlowski is at the Faculty of Law,
Buchanan is at the Centre for Applied Genomics, The University of Tasmania, Hobart, Tasmania, Australia.
possibility of genetic discrimination Hospital for Sick Children, Toronto, Ontario, Canada. Daryl Pullman is at the Memorial University of
are among other topics that warrant Michael M. Burgess is at the Centre for Applied Newfoundland, St. John’s, Newfoundland, Canada.
reflection. Regardless, the four topics Ethics, University of British Columbia, Vancouver, Peter N. Ray is at the Department of Medical Genetics
British Columbia, Canada. Ursula Danilczyk is at the and Microbiology, University of Toronto, Toronto,
Institute of Genetics, Canadian Institutes of Health Ontario, Canada. Jeremy Sugarman is at the Johns
Research, Toronto, Ontario, Canada. Kelly Fryer- Hopkins Berman Institute of Bioethics, Baltimore,
Perspectives provide experts with a forum to Edwards is at the University of Washington School Maryland, United States of America.
comment on topical or controversial issues of broad of Medicine, Seattle, Washington, United States of
interest. America. Shane K. Green is at the Ontario Genomics * To whom correspondence should be addressed.
Institute, Toronto, Ontario, Canada. Marc A. Hodosh E-mail: tcaulfld@law.ualberta.ca

PLoS Biology | www.plosbiology.org 0430 March 2008 | Volume 6 | Issue 3 | e73


Box 1. Ethical Questions for the Future on existing ethics resources (e.g., local
committees and experts). Attention has
The following is a list of research to withdraw to endure as long as
to be paid to concerns that research
ethics questions that warrant future possible. As such, this issue should
ethics review structures may not always
investigation and analysis. It is not an be investigated with consideration of
be sufficiently independent and
exhaustive list of the research ethics existing and evolving legal and ethical
that improvements to the system are
questions associated with whole-genome norms, emerging information
needed to promote their accountability
research. technology tools that may facilitate
[20]. Regardless, as will be discussed,
1. Duty to Recontact: Given the withdrawal, and governance structures
appropriate governance schemes
numerous disciplines and health care that can be implemented.
seem essential to the ethical conduct
providers potentially involved in 3. Risk/Benefit Analysis: There is a of whole-genome investigations—in
whole-genome research, further need for a comprehensive risk/benefit part because the unique challenges
analysis of the legal and ethical analysis of public data sharing. Studies associated with the research make it
obligations of each (particularly in that explore the impact on research impractical to satisfy the norms, tools,
the context of return of results) seems of restricted access versus open access and processes usually utilized to respect
warranted. Who has what obligations? would be useful, and should include a autonomy (e.g., specific informed
Who, if anyone, has the duty to return consideration of costs and actual risk consent). Also, the ethical issues often
results? Is there a “chain of obligation” of harm. move beyond autonomy challenges
that runs through the various 4. Governance Structures: There is a alone [21].
members of a research team? need to systematically evaluate
2. Right to Withdraw: Because of the existing and emerging governance Consent
potential for the rapid dissemination structures. This should include a Whole-genome research involves the
of research results, the right consideration of the ways in which collection of a biological sample, the
to withdraw can quickly become new information technologies can be sequencing of the genome, various
impractical. This raises the issue of utilized to facilitate, inter alia: levels of data analysis, and, possibly,
the degree to which there is an ethical continued communication with the use of the sample and/or data for a
requirement to structure the research participants; the continued right wide variety of future research projects
and dissemination of results in a to withdraw; and, when appropriate, that are likely unknown at the time
manner that will allow the right community engagement. that the sample is taken. In addition,
the data may be released into scientific
databases that are publicly accessible
on which domain is used as the lens example, this research will produce in order to facilitate research (to be
of analysis, we explicitly chose to an amount of genetic information discussed below). These activities create
consider the following issues from the about an individual well beyond what is tremendous consent challenges.
perspective of research ethics. This lens currently done in most genetic research First, the implications and
was chosen because most of the current protocols. Also, given the recent rapid potential social risks associated
work seems to be research activities advances and intense interest in whole- with the sequencing of an entire
and, for the purpose of governance and genome research, it seems worthwhile genome remain unknown. While
regulation, should be characterized as to consider how existing research ethics most of the data will have limited
such. In addition, given the preliminary norms apply. immediate clinical significance, the
nature of the technology, it was felt that This area of research invites a massive volume of the data triggers
it was prudent to frame whole-genome move beyond reliance on the usual challenges to protecting privacy and
sequencing as a biomedical research informed consent strategies [18], to the respecting autonomy. In addition,
enterprise, and more specifically as utilization of robust governance and as will be discussed below, whole-
research involving human subjects. oversight mechanisms [19]. Ideally, genome research creates complex
As with other emerging areas of the governance scheme should have a ethics challenges associated with the
research (e.g., biobanking initiatives) mandate to ensure research integrity repercussions of data release and
[14,15], whole-genome sequencing and the protection of the interests return of results, all of which must
tests traditional clinical trials ethics of all stakeholders, including the be covered in the initial informed
paradigms, particularly in the areas public, participants, family members, consent process. The involvement of
discussed below. For example, the communities, and the research commercial entities and the potential
vast amount of data produced, the community at large. Governance commercialization of research results
uncertain future research uses of the structures should reflect the nature and complicate the process even more.
data, the implications of the data for scope of the particular whole-genome Given the uncertainty and complexity
family members, and the technological research protocol (Figure 1). A project of the activity, ensuring fully informed
ability (and expectations) to publicly involving a single research participant consent will be difficult.
release the data are realities that would have a more modest governance Second, the fact that there will
challenge existing research ethics framework than an initiative engaging likely be many unspecified future
norms. While these issues have a large number of individuals or a uses for the data raises the question
emerged in other contexts [16,17], particular population or community. of whether reconsent is required.
they seem particularly acute in the Also, in designing governance Given that numerous investigators may
context of whole-genome research. For structures, investigators should draw be using the data over an extended

PLoS Biology | www.plosbiology.org 0431 March 2008 | Volume 6 | Issue 3 | e73


period, reconsenting all individuals
who participate in whole-genome
research for all uses of the data seems
impractical—a challenge that has been
encountered in other areas of research,
such as biobanking [13,22].
Finally, when individuals provide
consent for whole-genome scanning of
their own biological material, this also
has implications for family members
and community members with whom
they share some genetic information.
Traditional individually based informed
consent procedures do not deal well
with this aspect of genetic research.
Informed consent is a foundational
principle in research ethics [23,24].
It is meant to respect individual
autonomy. While it is recognized
that consent remains essential, in the
context of whole-genome research it
is not likely that it can be fully satisfied
nor do all the work. As such, the doi:10.1371/journal.pbio.0060073.g001

consent process must be supplemented Figure 1. Example Governance Structure


with a governance structure that can The following governance structure is similar to other policies [22]. It is only an example and should
respond to the particular ethics issues be modified to meet the needs and scope of each research initiative. The mandate and scope of
associated with whole-genome research. the entity’s responsibilities, obligations, and powers should be clear and should be reconciled with
roles and requirements of existing ethics review committees. The membership of the entity, their
Recommendation 1. Prior to criteria and process for making decisions, and the review and appeal system should be publicly
participation in a whole-genome available in order to ensure transparency and accountability.
project, participants should be asked
to provide consent for future use that whole-genome research results in the written information, must, so far as
includes as much detail as possible, production of data that, when used for possible, be respected and be part
including information about the research, are likely to be disseminated of the whole-genome research ethics
sampling and sequencing process, rapidly and widely (depending on the process. In addition, the fact that this
associated commercialization activities, relevant data release policy), there right may be severely limited once
possible risks, and the nature of will inevitably be profound practical data are disseminated must be clearly
likely future research initiatives. The limitations to the right to withdraw. communicated as part of the initial
consent process should also include Indeed, once whole-genome research informed consent process.
information about data security and the data are released, it will be very Recommendation 3. The design of
governance structure and, in particular, difficult, if not impossible, to retrieve personal genome projects and ethics
the mechanism for considering future or destroy the data in response to a review should explicitly consider how
research protocols (Figure 1). When withdrawal request. the ability to withdraw from subsequent
deemed appropriate by the governance So, while research participants use is enhanced or diminished by how
scheme, reconsent for specific research retain the right to withdraw their data and samples are collected, stored,
projects may be required (e.g., when consent whenever possible (e.g., they and disseminated. The appropriate
the proposal deviates significantly from could request the destruction of the balance will need to be considered for
what was stated in the initial consent). relevant tissue sample or the severance each project on a case-by-case basis.
of ongoing linkages to personal
Withdrawal from Research information), it will often be impossible Return of Results
The right of research participants to to destroy data that have already been Even if the purpose of some whole-
withdraw consent at any time, for any released. As part of the ethics review genome research is not to provide
reason and without repercussions process, there should be a careful results about individual participants,
is a central component of existing consideration of how far along the the work may generate such results,
research ethics statements [23–25]. In research process withdrawal can (and ranging on a continuum from clinically
general, this right extends to research should) be possible. This should also significant information to information
on identifiable health information be done in order to inform the consent relevant to ancestry and genealogy
and tissue samples [26]. In the context process and to ascertain the proper to information that is merely of
of whole-genome research, this right balance between research goals and the recreational interest.
endures and must be respected. right to withdraw. On this continuum, there may
Indeed, any minimization of the Recommendation 2. The right be situations in which the research
right to withdraw could pose a threat to withdraw consent, including the generates genetic information that
to public trust. However, because destruction of tissue samples and the researcher has a moral (but not

PLoS Biology | www.plosbiology.org 0432 March 2008 | Volume 6 | Issue 3 | e73


Box 2. Personal Genome Research: What Are the Possible Risks? necessarily legal) obligation to offer to
individual participants [27,28]. Such
By Timothy Caulfield, Mildred Cho, and Amy McGuire research may also generate results
The ability to sequence an individual’s police show up at your door with a that could be detrimental or that a
entire genome will allow for the search warrant. They are looking for research participant has specifically
production of an unprecedented amount the suspect from a crime scene 2,000 asked not to be returned. Due to
of detailed genetic information, helping miles away in Des Moines, Iowa. It turns the unknown clinical value of much
researchers to explore the relationship out that some DNA that was left at the of the genomic data, the amount
of genes and environment in the crime scene matched a sample from a of information that a researcher
development of a wide variety of human publicly accessible scientific database might have a duty to disclose will
diseases. that contained DNA from one of your likely be small at the current time.
But imagine being a research brothers. However, it is expected to grow
participant in this exciting new field. Imagine that at the time you first with increased knowledge about the
Researchers would be seeking to donated your sample for genetic clinical significance of the genome.
produce a record of all your genetic research, it was explained as part of the In addition, some associations will
information. As a result, all known consent process that no information be found by other research teams,
genetic predispositions will be available about your genetics would be returned warranting review and tough decisions
and, depending on the data sharing to you. Years later, you develop a about whether to invest time in
policy, accessible to a wide range of heritable form of cancer and learn that confirming results for one’s own study
researchers and, possibly, the public at the research team must have known population and informing subjects
large—this, at a time when we are still you were genetically predisposed to the about those secondary findings [29].
seeking to understand the social, clinical, disease. To complicate matters further, The duty to offer results is, in part,
and personal implications of genetic you have a large number of siblings, related to the relationship between
information. none of whom want to know about their researchers and participants. It may
These uncertainties can create unique genetic predispositions. This information also be based on expectations founded
ethical challenges. What do you tell is now available to all. on institutional or cultural assumptions.
potential participants during the consent Imagine you just opened your own Because results may be generated by
process about risks when we still don’t electronics recycling business and are researchers who did not collect the
have a clear sense of their nature? Also, trying to find private health insurance. samples and who may not know the
it is difficult to know, at the time of Your friend recommends that you identity of the research participants,
recruitment, exactly how the genetic contact a specific company. As part of the there are interesting questions about
information will be used, and by whom. enrollment process, the company finds who may have a duty to offer results.
While most of the risks remain out that you participated in a genetic Do researchers who provide samples or
speculative, and we imagine that much study and that your genetic information data to other researchers for secondary
of this research will be conducted by has been released into a publicly analyses retain responsibility to support
highly respected researchers at leading accessible database. By accessing the return of appropriate results?
academic centers, one can imagine a database, the company finds out that Recommendation 4. Personal
number of controversial scenarios. Some you are at increased risk of early-onset genome research projects should have
of these may seem far-fetched, and we Alzheimer disease and are highly an established process, approved by
do not intend to be alarmist, but it is susceptible to cancer from the chemicals a research ethics review entity, for
important to recognize that just one encountered in your recycling process. evaluating whether findings (incidental
breach similar to those described below, They also find that you are at greatly or otherwise) meet criteria for offering
or even the threat of such a breach, could increased risk of colon cancer, which to individual participants (Figure 1).
hurt public trust and significantly hamper alerts you to now take early screening This process should be highlighted
the ability to conduct genetic research. and preventive measures. in the initial consent and should
Imagine you are watching the news This is, no doubt, an exciting time for acknowledge the participants’ right not
and learn about a study linking race to IQ, genetic research. And it cannot move to know certain results.
which you find offensive. You later learn forward without research participants. Recommendation 5. The process
that they used your DNA for this study. As such, it is important to note that the of identifying and disclosing research
You donated your DNA five years ago risks associated with this kind of research results should involve professionals
for use in a genetic association study of may be limited and controversial events with the appropriate expertise required
cancer and heart disease. At the time, you rare. But history has told us that they to provide the participant with
were told that other researchers might do occur and can have a devastating sufficient interpretive information.
want to use your DNA for other types impact on public trust and the research In general, the results offered should
of research. You want to withdraw your environment. It is therefore critical that be scientifically valid, confirmed, and
consent, but it is too late. Your genetic as this research moves forward, there should have significant implications
information has been analyzed by many are guidelines in place, such as those for the subject’s health and well-being.
researchers and is now integrated in outlined by this paper, to promote ethical Plans to return other forms of data—
databanks throughout the world. research conduct and to help avoid, as such as significant non-health-related
Imagine that you are sitting home, much as possible, scenarios like those data—should be built into the study
minding your own business, and the described above. design and governance structure.

PLoS Biology | www.plosbiology.org 0433 March 2008 | Volume 6 | Issue 3 | e73


Public Data Release research participation would promote Competing interests. Marc A. Hodosh and
reciprocity for participation in research Michael Timmons are employed by the X
International policies call for the rapid Prize Foundation. Eric Meslin is consultant
public release of all sequence data with no direct benefit to the individual.
It may be more appropriate to to Eli Lilly and Company.
[30–32]. The benefit of public data
release genome data into databases References
access is that it provides significant 1. Levy S, Sutton G, Ng PC, Feuk L, Halpern AL,
scientific utility by enabling immediate with restricted access. Restricted et al. (2007) The diploid genome sequence of
international research use of the access databases typically require some an individual human. PLoS Biol 5(10): e254.
authentication so that only bona fide doi:10.1371/journal.pbio.0050254
data. However, policies that advocate 2. Baylor College of Medicine Genome
unrestricted data sharing have been researchers can access the information. Sequencing Center (2008) James Watson’s
challenged because of the privacy Most restricted access databases provide personal genome sequence. Available: http://
some phenotypic information linked jimwatsonsequence.cshl.edu/cgi-perl/gbrowse/
risks associated with public access jwsequence/. Accessed 14 February 2008.
to genomic information [33,34]. to the genotypic data, increasing the 3. Department of Health and Human Services,
Whole-genome research increases scientific utility of the data. Restricted National Human Genome Research Institute
(2007) Near-term technology development for
these privacy concerns, particularly access provides enhanced privacy genome sequencing (R01). Available: http://
the uncertainties surrounding the protection, but the level of restriction grants.nih.gov/grants/guide/rfa-files/RFA-
and stringency of oversight vary HG-06-015.html. Accessed 14 February 2008.
implications of the data. As a result, a 4. X Prize Foundation (2008) Archon X Prize for
cautious approach seems warranted. significantly depending on the database genomics. Available: http://genomics.xprize.
Investigators and research ethics boards (e.g., the degree to which the database org/. Accessed 14 February 2008.
contains sensitive or identifying 5. Dizikes P (2007 September 24) Gene
need to carefully consider whether information opens new frontier in privacy
public data release is warranted. information). Regardless, appropriate debate. Boston Globe. Available: http://www.
As noted above, once data are security, oversight, and access policies boston.com/news/globe/health_science/
articles/2007/09/24/gene_information_
released into a publicly accessible are essential for the protection of opens_new_frontier_in_privacy_debate/.
database, it becomes impossible to human subjects. Accessed 14 February 2008.
Recommendation 6. Data release 6. Abraham C (2007 September 3) This human’s
withdraw the data from the public life, decoded. The Globe and Mail. Available:
domain. The finality of public data policies must be designed to http://www.theglobeandmail.com/servlet/
sharing needs to be clearly articulated appropriately balance the benefits story/RTGAM.20070903.wgenemap0903/
and requirements of access against BNStory/Science/home. Accessed 14 February
in the informed consent process. 2008.
A balanced approach should be the privacy interests of research 7. Winslow R (2007 November 6) Is there a heart
adopted when explaining the risks participants. The rationale for the attack in your future? Wall Street Journal.
Available: http://webreprints.djreprints.
and benefits of data sharing. In the proposed data release policy needs com/1823310460614.html. Accessed 14
consent and review process, neither the to be clearly explained, justified as February 2008.
necessary for the goals of research, 8. Hayden EC (2007) Personalized genomes go
benefits of research nor the potential mainstream. Nature 460: 11. doi:10.1038/
privacy risks should be minimized or and deemed acceptable by the relevant 450011a
exaggerated. In this regard, several ethics review entity. 9. Lowrance WW (2006) Privacy, confidentiality,
Recommendation 7. The and identifiability in genomic research.
potential privacy issues should be Discussion document for workshop
discussed: the data security mechanisms implications of data release must be convened by the National Human Genome
put in place; the primary concern of adequately disclosed to the potential Research Institute, Bethesda, October 3−4,
2006. Available: http://www.genome.gov/
identifiability; the practical limits on participants in the consent process. Pages/About/OD/ReportsPublications/
an individual’s right to control access This disclosure should include a IdentifiabilityWorkshopWhitePaper.pdf.
discussion of the likely finality of the Accessed 14 February 2008.
to their personal information; and 10. McGuire AL, Cho MK, Caulfield T (2007)
the secondary concern about genetic release process and the implications The future of personal genomics. Science 317:
profiling and an individual’s right to that this may have on privacy and the 1687. doi:10.1126/science.1147475
future right to withdraw. 11. Ravitsky V, Wilfond B (2006) Disclosing
control their “ascribed social identity” individual genetic results to research
[35]. Given the complexity of these Recommendation 8. As part of the participants. Am J Bioeth 6: 8-17.
privacy challenges, it is essential that consent and ethics review process, the 12. McGuire AL, Caulfield T, Cho M (2008)
Research ethics and the challenge of whole-
the relevant ethics review entity have issues associated with family members genome sequencing. Nat Rev Genet 9: 152-156.
appropriate ethics expertise. and relevant groups and populations doi:10.1038/nrg2302
should be considered (this may, 13. Caulfield T (2007) Biobanks and blanket
More research and policy analysis on consent: The proper place of the public
the issues associated with data release is for example, involve encouraging/ perception and public good rationales. King’s
clearly needed, including an analysis of requiring discussions with family Law J 18: 209-226.
members).  14. Cambon-Thomsen A (2004) The social and
the actual harms and benefits resulting ethical issues of post-genomic biobanks. Nat
from publicly accessible data; the Rev Genet 5: 866-873.
implications for family members and
Acknowledgments 15. Knoppers BM, Chadwick R (2005) Human
genetic research: Emerging trends in ethics.
relevant communities; the appropriate We would like to thank the Institute of Nat Rev Genet 6: 75-79
balance between public access and Genetics (Canadian Institutes of Health 16. Arnason V (2004) Coding and consent: Moral
Research), the Archon X Prize, and the challenges of the database project in Iceland.
individual privacy interests; and Bioethics 18 (1): 27-49. doi:10.1111/j.1467-
Ontario Genomics Institute for funding and
considerations regarding compensation 8519.2004.00377.x
administrative support, and Alethea Adair 17. Elger B, Caplan A (2006) Consent and
for research-related injury resulting and Genome Alberta for additional editing anonymization in research involving biobanks.
from participation in personal genome and research assistance. We would also EMBO Rep 7: 661-666. doi:10.1038/
research. While the likelihood of injury sj.embor.7400740
like to thank Adam L. Felsenfeld, National 18. Kahn JP, Mastroianni AM, Sugarman J, editors
is small, compensating individuals Human Genome Research Institute, National (1998) Beyond consent: Seeking justice in
for harm or loss associated with Institutes of Health, for his helpful insight. research. New York: Oxford University Press.

PLoS Biology | www.plosbiology.org 0434 March 2008 | Volume 6 | Issue 3 | e73


19. Gibbons SMC, Kaye J, Smart A, Heeney C, 25. Department of Health and Human Services, Seattle, Washington. Am J Epidemiol 155:
Parker M (2007) Governing genetic databases: National Institutes of Health, Office for 585-592.
Challenges facing research regulation and Protection from Research Risks (1991) 30. The Wellcome Trust (2003) Sharing data
practice. J Law Soc 34: 163-189. Title 45, Code of Federal Regulations. Part from large-scale biological research projects:
20. Lemmens T, Waring D, editors (2006) Law 46—Protection of human subjects (45 CFR A system of tripartite responsibility. Available:
and ethics in biomedical research: Regulation, 46). Available: http://www.hhs.gov/ohrp/ http://www.wellcome.ac.uk/assets/wtd003207.
conflict of interest, and liability. Toronto: humansubjects/guidance/45cfr46.htm. pdf. Accessed 14 February 2008.
University of Toronto Press. Accessed 14 February 2008. 31. Genome Canada (2005) Data release and
21. Burgess MM (2001) Beyond consent: Ethical 26. Canadian Institutes of Health Research, resource sharing policy. Available: http://www.
and social issues in genetic testing. Nat Rev Natural Sciences and Engineering Research genomecanada.ca/xcorporate/policies/
Genet 2: 9-14. Council of Canada, Social Sciences and DataReleasePolicy.pdf. Accessed 14 February
22. UK Biobank (2007) UK Biobank ethics and Humanities Research Council of Canada 2008.
governance framework version 3.0. Available: (1998) Tri-Council policy statement: Ethical 32. National Human Genome Research Institute
http://www.ukbiobank.ac.uk/ethics/ conduct for research involving humans. (2003) Reaffirmation and extension of
documents/20071011_EGF_Version_3_1_ Ottawa: Public Works and Government Services NHGRI rapid data release policies: Large-scale
0October_2007withTOR.pdf. Accessed 14 Canada. sequencing and other community resource
February 2008. 27. Johnston C, Kaye J (2004) Does the UK projects. Available: http://www.genome.
23. US Government Printing Office (1949) Biobank have a legal obligation to feedback gov/10506537. Accessed 14 February 2008.
Nuremberg code. Available: http://ohsr. individual findings to participants? 33. McGuire AL, Gibbs RA (2007) No longer de-
od.nih.gov/guidelines/nuremberg.html. Med Law Rev 12: 239-267. doi:10.1093/ identified. Science 312: 370-371. doi:10.1126/
Accessed 14 February 2008. medlaw/12.3.239 science.1125339
24. World Medical Association (2000) Declaration 28. Otlowski MFA (2007) Disclosure of genetic 34. Lowrance WW, Collins FS (2007) Identifiability
of Helsinki: Ethical principles for medical information to at-risk relatives. Med J Aust 187: in genomic research. Science 317: 600-602.
research involving human subjects. Edinburgh 398-399. doi:10.1126/science.1147699
(Scotland): 52nd WMA General Assembly. 29. Austin MA (2002) Ethical issues in human 35. Juengst ET (2004) Face facts: Why human
Available: http://www.wma.net/e/policy/ genome epidemiology: a case study based genetics will always provoke bioethics. J Law
b3.htm. Accessed 14 February 2008. on the Japanese American Family Study in Med Ethics 32: 267-275.

PLoS Biology | www.plosbiology.org 0435 March 2008 | Volume 6 | Issue 3 | e73

You might also like