You are on page 1of 18

Sigma Xi, The Scientific Research Society

CAUSALITY, CHANCE, AND LAW


Author(s): MARIO BUNGE
Source: American Scientist, Vol. 49, No. 4 (DECEMBER 1961), pp. 432-448
Published by: Sigma Xi, The Scientific Research Society
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/27827906 .
Accessed: 18/06/2014 21:29

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Sigma Xi, The Scientific Research Society is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access
to American Scientist.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 72.221.114.155 on Wed, 18 Jun 2014 21:29:48 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
CAUSALITY, CHANCE, AND LAW
By MARIO BUNGE

halfofour
CAUSAL principlefellintodisreputeduringthe first
THE century as an effect of two independently acting causes :the criticisms
of empiricist philosophers, and the growing use in science and technology
of statistical ideas and methods. Progress in knowledge was, at one
point, viewed as taking place in three stages. In the first stage, spirits
were replaced by causes (or, if preferred, animism by Aristotelianism).
In the second stage, causes were replaced by forces (Aristotelianism re
placed by mechanism). And in the third stage, forces were replaced by
laws (mechanism replaced by a broader, noncommittal, world outlook).
But this picture of progress has proved to be an oversimplification.
Superstitious persons have often conceived of spirits as causes and
even as capable of exerting forces on material bodies :witness the belief
in psychokinesis. And we realize that forces are a kind of cause and are
subject to law, so that the concepts of cause, force, and law, are far from
being mutually exclusive. We also grant that laws may be causal or non
causal and, in particular, that chance is not the absence of law but the
outcome of lawful process and is, in turn, subject to laws (statistical
regularities) of a higher order.
We have renounced spirits, but not causes and forces on condition
that they be law-abiding. We retain the concepts of cause and force in
their proper contexts, namely, philosophy and dynamics respectively.
But we do not regard cause and force as panaceas for the explanation of
becoming we: account for change in terms of laws which may or may not
involve the concepts of cause and force. Contemporary science has not
expelled causes and forces in the name of law : it has subjected the former
to the latter and has assigned both strict causation and force narrower
but still important domains.
The realization of the statistical nature of all macroscopic laws, and of
the objective nature of chance, has not led us to believe in uncaused
events: it has only shown that not all relations are causal bonds. We
grant that the sequences of fire outbreaks and suicides in a city are ran
dom, but this does not prevent the insurance companies from inquiring
into the causes of every single fire and suicide. And an analysis of such
causes, if deep enough, will involve certain laws of nature or society,
some with a causal ingredient, others predominantly statistical.
Causation, chance, and law are intertwined in any scientific analysis
ofmatters of fact. The following should bear out this statement.

The Causal Relation

Causation has traditionally been understood as the constant and


one-one relation among events whereby causes produce effects. Accord
432

This content downloaded from 72.221.114.155 on Wed, 18 Jun 2014 21:29:48 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
CAUSALITY, CHANCE, AND LAW 433
ingly the causal principle may be stated thus m :If C happens, then (and
only then)E is always produced by it. This formula states neither a con
stant conjunction nor a constant succession of events :the gist of causation
is uniform production rather than mere coincidence or following in order.
Let us illustrate this interpretation with some examples.
Some psychophysiologists believe that thought processes are accom
panied by synchronous physiological processes but not produced by the
latter, either because they hold the hypothesis of parallelism (as is the
case of Charles Sherrington), or because they think psychological phe
nomena are physiological phenomena seen from within, i.e., regarded
subjectively (e.g., Alejandro Lipschutz). We say that infancy is followed
by youth, not that the former produces the latter. Conjunction and
succession may be external to each other and even accidental, which is
not the case of production.
On the other hand, we do not say that demoralization happens to be
merely conjoined with, or to follow upon, unemployment: we believe
there is a specific psychosocial mechanism whereby moral derangement
is produced by inactivity and social estrangement, just as we believe
heavy rains produce erosion and tranquilizers produce relaxation. That
not every production of an effect is causal, that is, that not every effect
is related to its causes in the simple way stated by the causal principle,
is another matter.
What produces and what is produced are always events, that is, changes
in the state of real entities, whether natural or cultural. Hence a neces
sary, though not sufficient, condition for a law to be causal is that it re
lates differences of some sort and, more precisely, differences in the prop
erties that specify the states of a concrete system.
The temperature and available energy of a physical system are func
tionally related, and so are the price and mean lifetime ofmerchandises,
but such relations are not causal. Properties cannot produce other prop
erties: it is only a change AP in the cluster of properties P that may
produce a change AQ in a system of properties Q. Even so, the two changes
may not be causally related: they may be concomitant or successive,
without the one producing the other. Hence, not every constant relation
among properties, not even every constant relation among variations of
properties, is a causal law.
= const. It
Consider, for instance, Boyle's law pV certainly is a con
stant relation between two key properties of an ideal model of a certain
class of entities (gases). But it is not a causal relation, although we can
rephrase it in terms of variations of properties, i.e., in terms of events.
In fact, upon differentiation and division by pV we obtain

_ ^Y. _. dp =
(Compression Pressurization) (1)

This content downloaded from 72.221.114.155 on Wed, 18 Jun 2014 21:29:48 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
434 AMERICAN SCIENTIST

Recalling the obvious rules of meaning of the symbols involved, this


equation may be read as follows: the relative decrease in volume equals
the relative increase in pressure that accompanies the compression. Notice
the symmetry of this statement : it suggests no arrow indicating a one
sided relation between a cause and an effect, it does not allow us to tell
which is which. The two events, compression and pressurization, are
concomitant. Even better: compression and pressurization are two traits
of one and the same event?a change of state of the gaseous system.
However?and this is overlooked by functionalism [2]?a causal state
ment can be obtained from the above if the environment of the physical
system is taken into account. By so doing we may be able to point to an
externally impressed force as the cause of the compression and the simul
taneous increase in internal pressure. And we are bound to take thismore
comprehensive view ifwe wish to understand the origin of change in
addition to recording and summarizing it.
Also, we may look into this same event with the help of a deeper the
ory, the kinetic theory ofmatter, which will tell us what the "external"
or phenomenological theory will not?namely, that a compression will
produce an increase in internal pressure because less space will be available
for the motion of the molecules, the impacts of which on the walls of the
container are macroscopically manifested as pressure.
The description of an event or process as causal or as noncausal will
depend on the context inwhich the description ismade and, in particular,
on the laws involved in the latter. And the laws occurring in it will in
turn depend on the level of analysis and on the knowledge at hand. Noth
ing is inherently causal or noncausal. The question "Is x causal?" should
always be completed in some such way as "Is x causal relative to the
bundle of laws Lf"

The Causal Range of a Law


The description of an event or process by means of a set of laws and
a set of informations concerning actual circumstances can be said to be
causal if certain conditions are jointly satisfied. It may be argued [3]
that the following conditions are jointly necessary and sufficient:
(i) the system concerned and its environment are fairly distinct from
one another ; in other words, an inside and an outside can be clearly rec
ognized;
(ii) the main changes under consideration are produced by external
factors : the internal determinants, which give rise to the so-called spon
taneous behavior and are always present, are negligible in the respect
that is being investigated and to the approximation that has been agreed
upon;
(iii) the process in question, involving both the system and its en
vironment, can be regarded as practically isolated, i.e., its actual connec

This content downloaded from 72.221.114.155 on Wed, 18 Jun 2014 21:29:48 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
CAUSALITY, CHANCE, AND LAW 435
tions with the rest of the world are practically ignorable ; in particular,
it is possible to neglect the random perturbations that are constantly
impinging upon any real system;
(iv) every interaction can be approximated by one-sided agent-patient
relations: i.e., the reactions of the system upon its environment can be
neglected;
(v) the input and the output can be related in a one-one way to each
other, with neglect of both multiple causation and statistical relations
between sets of causes and sets of effects.
If the above conditions are not fulfilledwe may still have a perfectly
determinate description, but not a causal one. Now, the above conditions
are difficult if not impossible to meet in actual fact. Therefore strictly
causal laws are never exactly operating. There is always, as a matter of
fact, some amount of spontaneity, mutual action, and randomness. In
other words, there are no purely causal laws. There are, rather, causal
ranges of scientific laws, or domains in which certain laws of nature or
society are predominantly causal, at least at some level of analysis. Let
me introduce the idea of causal range with the help of an illustration.
Suppose we are interested in behavior. Let our fundamental variables
be the strength Se of the external stimuli, the strength St of the internal
stimuli, the overt or external response Re, and the covert or inner response
=
Ri. The total response R Re + Ri will be a (still unknown) function F
of the remaining variables:
Re + Ri = F(Se, Si) (2)

Now, below the so-called absolute threshold?i.e., below a certain


value of the stimulus?there is no response; since there is input but no
output, there is no causal relation in this interval. Let this be called a
noncausal range of the law schema (2).
A further noncausal feature of (2) is the occurrence in it of the inner
input St. In the first place, it is not external to the system (organism),
as it should if it were to be called a cause in accordance to clause (ii)
above. Secondly, the internal stimuli and the total response R are nothing
but different aspects of one and the same functioning of the organism.
If we wish to obtain the causal range of the law schema (2) we have to
neglect the internal stimuli or hold them constant, so as to be sure that
only external factors will produce behavior effects. In this approxima
tion Equation (2) becomes
Re + Ri = G(Se) (3)

If we further neglect the covert responses, which for the time being are
anyhow inscrutable in the case of nonhuman subjects, we obtain the
famous law
=
Re k'S.*, (4)

where p = 0.3 for sound.

This content downloaded from 72.221.114.155 on Wed, 18 Jun 2014 21:29:48 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
436 AMERICAN SCIENTIST

We may call Equations (3) and (4) causal approximations of Equa


tion (2). We may also say that the causal range of the law schema (2)
is the region forwhich the internal stimuli St are negligible as compared
with the external stimuli (i.e., St <^ Se).
Similar results may be obtained in other fields: in science we always
deal with concrete systems presumably having an internal structure
and interacting with a part of their environment, and the study of such
systems and their changes (events and strings of events) can be made on
various levels of analysis
and, consequently, with various degrees of
approximation. Sometimes, the approximations are such that simple
causal interpretations of the laws are possible. But every causal interpre
tation is, ifadequate at all, only approximately valid. As soon as a deeper
analysis is performed, further, noncausal, categories of determination?

such as interaction, statistical determination, teleological determination,


dialectical determination, and so on?will occur. Let us sketch a program
for such a deeper analysis in the case of behavior.
The general psychophysical relation (2) is phenomenological, or non
representational, in the sense that it involves no "mechanism" connect
ing the various variables. Although Equation (2) has a causal range, it
is phenomenological because it treats the organism as a "black box"
upon which stimuli impinge and out of which responses emerge (see Fig
ure 1). On the other hand, a deeper, representational theory of behavior
will take the risk of proposing definite "mechanisms" linking (a) the
external stimuli to the responses, and (b) the physiological and the psy
chological levels (see Figure 2).
Conceivably, such deeper, representational theories of behavior would
depart from causality even more than the phenomenological theory:
they would account not only for the randomly impinging external dis
turbances and the internal stimuli of various sorts, but they would
postulate inter-level relations, which are noncausal.
One such inter-level or border-zone law, linking properties belonging
to different levels of organization of one and the same organism, would

This content downloaded from 72.221.114.155 on Wed, 18 Jun 2014 21:29:48 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
CAUSALITY, CHANCE, AND LAW 437
be the relation between the internal stimuli St (such as hunger and other
drives) and the underlying physiological variables 0 (such as sugar level
in blood). Representational or neodeterministic theories of behavior
would provide, then, equations of the form

Re + Ri = H[S? Si(<f>),<f>](5)

It should be clear that the relation St = St (0) between the set of


physiological variables </>and the psychological variables St is not a
causal relation, no matter how precise it is and no matter how accurately
it would enable one to predict behavior with the help of physiological
information. There is no question here of an unsymmetrical relation of
production between an external "agent" and an internal "patient," but
only a relation between two levels of one and the same organism.
The internal stimulus St is a whole compounded of microchanges de
scribed by the physiological variables we have lumped in t<f>. Such a non
causal relation is not a mere "reduction," since nothing is explained
=
away by the relation S{ Si (</>).Neither St is eliminated in favor of
nor
<t>, <j>is reduced to St: the two variables describe peculiar traits of an
organism at different levels, and the fact that its behavior might par
tially, or even totally, be explained by reference to lower-level processes
does not annihilate behavior as such. Logical reduction (explanation)
need not involve ontological reduction (levelling), just as the disclosure
of a deeper level need not involve the disclosure of causes.
In short, 'causal' is a qualifier that can best be applied to laws of a
certain kind when certain rather stringent conditions are approximately
met. As a consequence, in the absence of a knowledge of pertinent laws
and circumstances it does not make much sense to ask whether a given
event or process is causal.
Let us now turn to the examination of the persistent confusions be
tween causation, the temporal precedence of the cause over the effect,
and the continuity of causal lines.

Causality, Antecedence, and Contiguity


Local field physics has accustomed us to such an extent to the union of
causation, antecedence, and nearby action, that we often fail to recognize
that these principles are logically independent no matter how closely they
may hang together inmost of contemporary physics. Yet such a logical
independence must be granted in order to understand the mere exis
tence of causal thought before and outside field physics, and also in
order to leave the door open to the possible relaxation of the condition of
contiguity or nearby action.
The confusion between antecedence and causation is so common that
there is even an old special phrase to brand this fallacy, namely, Post hoc,
ergo propter hoc (after that, hence because of that). It is not physically

This content downloaded from 72.221.114.155 on Wed, 18 Jun 2014 21:29:48 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
438 AMERICAN SCIENTIST

possible for the effect to precede its cause, since the cause is supposed to
give rise to, or produce, the effect. But itwould be logically possible for
the cause and the effect to be simultaneous in a given frame of reference,
particularly if they occurred at the same place. Even if the cause and
the effect took place at different regions in space, one could imagine that
a physical agent might traverse
hi X a distance in no time?as has
O
been held by most theories of
action at a distance. And such
an instantaneous action at a dis
tance would be perfectly com
patible with causality?Hume
notwithstanding.
All that the principle of an
tecedence states is that the cause
cannot happen after the effect.
W2
This excludes, among other con
ceivable phenomena, the so
called precognition, since what
does not yet exist cannot be a
source of information (or even
Fig. 3 of noise!) for what exists. A
possible general formulation of
the principle of antecedence is this :B at time t is uniquely determined by
A at all times t' prior than and up to t. In obvious symbols, A(t'^ t)D
B(t).
Unlike the principle of causation, the principle of antecedence can
be given a precise mathematical ?
formulation. Let Ki(t' t) be the con
tribution of the antecedent A(t') at a
time t', contribution that will ob
? t.
viously depend upon the lapse t' Then the contribution of A to the
consequent B during the time interval dt' will be Ki(t' ? t) -A(tf) dt' ,
and the total effectB at time twill be obtained by collecting all the con
tributions of A at previous times, i.e., by summing them:

B(t) =
-
Ki(t t') >A(t') -dt' (Antecedence) (6)
f*_t
In most cases the past history of the system concerned will be short
or it will be entirely incorporated in the immediately prior state of the
system; but in a few cases the system will have a memory of some sort,
i.e., there will occur aftereffects. If A operates only at time t,we shall
? = k-b
represent its contribution by an impulsive "function": Kx it' t)
- =
{V t), whence B(t) k-A(t).
In any case, the antecedent A and the consequent B are not necessarily
connected in a causal way according to Equation (6). In fact, the prin
ciple of antecedence does not speak about the antecedent A producing

This content downloaded from 72.221.114.155 on Wed, 18 Jun 2014 21:29:48 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
CAUSALITY, CHANCE, AND LAW 439
the consequent B, but about B being both dependent upon and following
A, or being at most simultaneous with A. 'A' and lB' will usually desig
nate properties or states (clusters of properties) rather than events. Fur
thermore, no reference to an external action of A upon a system ismade
in (6). In short, antecedence is compatible with causality but logically
independent of it.
As to the principle of nearby action, or contiguity, it states that what
ever happens at some place is the effect of what happens in its neighbor
hood. The latter is not limited to immediate vicinity: conditions in dis
tant regions (reported in the so-called boundary conditions) are usually
as important as conditions in the immediate neighborhood. The principle
of contiguity would be falsified if something could jump over space with
out traveling through it. If there are trajectories, they must be contin
uous, but the principle does not require that the velocities along such
trajectories be finite. In other words, the principle of nearby action does
not exclude the possibility of instantaneous propagation. The existence
of limiting velocities must be postulated independently from both the
principle of contiguity and the principle of antecedence.
A possible general formulation of the principle of nearby action is this :
B at theplace x is uniquely determined byA at theplaces x' surrounding x.
In symbols, A(x' 9^ x) DB(x). To be more specific, letK2(x' ? x) be the
weight of the factor A at the point x'; this contribution will depend on the
? x
distance x' between x' and x. The contribution ofA over the volume
element dxf will be K2 (x' ? x) A(x') dx'} and the total effect of A at
x will be obtained by scanning the whole space and collecting all the
local contributions, i.e.,

(Nearby action) (7)

Notice the analogy between the mathematical formulations of the


principles of contiguity (7) and antecedence (6). But note also the dif
ference :while we collect contributions from left and right, we stop col
lecting contributions at time t,and this simply because there is nothing to
be collected from a still unborn time. Time is the pace, not the source, of
becoming.
The two principles may be regarded as particular cases of a third prin
ciple, which might be called the principle of spacetime contiguity.
The form of this principle is, obviously, A(xr 9^x, V'< t)D B(x,t). A
possible general formulation of this hypothesis in mathematical terms
is
CO
dt' ?I dx' K(t' ? t,x' ? x) -A(x',t') (Spacetime contiguity)
rt
(8)
= ?
Putting K S(x' -x) K\ (f t)we obtain the principle of antecedence

This content downloaded from 72.221.114.155 on Wed, 18 Jun 2014 21:29:48 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
440 AMERICAN SCIENTIST

(6), which can then be interpreted?in this wider context?as spacetime


contiguity when the antecedent and the consequent are located in the
same place. And putting K = ?(t' ? t) K2(x' ? x) we obtain the prin
ciple of nearby action in its special form (7). There still is no causality,
although many a physicist would like to call Equation (8) a "causality
condition."
In contemporary field physics the so-called strict local causality "con
dition" (that is, hypothesis) is usually respected. This assumption may
be read as follows :Parts of a field that cannot be connected by a field
disturbance (a light wave in the case of the electromagnetic field) can
not interact. A corollary of this objective physical law statement is the
following nomopragmatic statement [4i: The measurement of a field
quantity at any given point in spacetime will not affect themeasurement
of the same (let alone of a different) field quantity in a place that cannot
be reached from the former by a field signal.
"Strict local causality" is a misnomer for this principle, which is noth
ing but a specification of the principle of spacetime contiguity. In fact,
the field variables, the principal ties, are supposed to undergo spontaneous
random fluctuations, and randomness?particularly if uncaused?is not
precisely compatible with causality at one and the same level. Inciden
tally, themere occurrence of postulates such as the "causality condition"
shows once more that the quantum theory is not indeterministic, no
matter how noncausal itmay be. In fact, the theory does not hold that
anything may happen but, on the contrary, it prohibits such logically
conceivable events as the interaction of field regions separated by a space
like interval (i.e., not connectible by a field ripple such as a light wave).
In short, antecedence and contiguity, while compatible with causality,
are not involved by it. For one thing, the principles of antecedence and
contiguity refer to properties (denoted by variables) rather than to
events. Secondly, these variables may be probability amplitudes or ran
dom variables?i.e., variables with built-in chance, so to say; on the
other hand, the changes of properties involved in the causal principle
are not supposed to be subject to random fluctuations. Thirdly, there
exists no general mathematical formulation of the causal principle,
whereas both antecedence contiguity can be given fairly general
and
mathematical expressions (Equations (6), (7), and (8)).
While it is important to realize the differences between causation and
spacetime contiguity, it is no less important to recognize that antece
dence and contiguity, combined with specific assumptions (laws) con
cerning particle motion and field structure, do provide specific mecha
nisms of physical determination. Such mechanisms may have a causal
ingredient (as occurs with the assumption that the acceleration ofmasses
and charges produce waves) even though they may make room for a
noncausal process, such as the propagation of a wave in a void, which is

This content downloaded from 72.221.114.155 on Wed, 18 Jun 2014 21:29:48 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
CAUSALITY, CHANCE, AND LAW 441
a self-sustained process.

Moreover, chance itself is often traceable to the operation of mecha


nisms. To this we now turn.

Causality and Chance


Causation and chance are often regarded as polar concepts, and not
without some reason as long as it is not forgotten that bulky masses of
chance events may average out to nearly "causal lines" and that, vice
versa, the interplay of numerous independent and individually determi
nate entities always results in chaotic situations.
For example, the motion of a single particle in a smoke stream is like
the almost-random walk of a drunkard, yet the stream as a whole has
a well-defined pattern, even when it degenerates into small voitex mo
tions. Conversely, every single marriage is supposed to be the outcome
of a planned course of action, yet the sequence ofmarriages in a commu
nity is a random sequence in time. Random behavior at the microscopic
or individual level may result in ordered behavior at a macroscopic or
collective level, and orderly individual behavior may fit a random
collective pattern. Moreover, chance has its peculiar laws. Thus, smoke
particles will move away from a given point to an average distance pro
portional to the square root of the time elapsed, and the average ages
of brides will be a fairly constant characteristic of every community.
There is nothing arbitrary in chance. Consider, for instance, a sim
plified roulette game inwhich only "reds" and "blacks" occur. Poincar?
[5]proved that, no matter what the initial positions and velocities of the
marble may be in the successive trials, the long-run frequency of "reds"
and "blacks" will be the same, namely, J^- In other words, any initial
distribution will ensue, in the long run, in a fixed, perfectly determinate,
final distribution. This phenomenon, described by means of what is
known as themethod of arbitrary functions, is not arbitrary itself?a nice
example of the absence of one-one correspondence between facts and
constructs. Far from being arbitrary, the mechanism of the phenomenon
is stable in the sense that, no matter how we vary the circumstances
(in this case the initial conditions), the outcome is always the same in the
long run. In this respect, chance phenomena do not differ from more
strongly determinate phenomena : in either case we have invariable laws
holding for variable individuals in variable circumstances.
Disorder, far from being absolute, is relative to a set of laws. Killing,
a disorderly behavior in civilized society, is orderly behavior in war.
The assertion "The a's are random, accidental, or contingent," ismis
leading. On the other hand, an assertion such as "The a's are accidental
relative to the bundle of laws L" is not only meaningful but also testable
as soon as a large set of similar a's can be examined and the bundle of
laws is specified. Even though the a's in question may be accidental with

This content downloaded from 72.221.114.155 on Wed, 18 Jun 2014 21:29:48 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
442 AMERICAN SCIENTIST

respect to the laws L, they may not be accidental relative to a different


bundle, Z/, of laws. That is, both -La and L'a may be true. (For
example, every single accidental error of measurement fits the bell
shaped distribution curve.) In short, chance is not absolute but is rela
tive to law.
Quite often, the predication of chance is the result of a limited view.
For instance, the differences in the initial positions and velocities of the
marble in the roulette game are, in turn, the outcome of individually
orderly (but not controlled) processes : they do not spring out of nothing,
they do not violate what may be called the genetic principle. It is only
by deciding, for practical reasons, to ignore their previous histories that
we are lured into talking of chaotic initial conditions. Again, storms and
other meteorological phenomena are random if regarded, so to speak,
from the outside; but modern, dynamic meteorology is disclosing the
mechanism of storms and is in principle capable of predicting every single
storm. The random nature of the whole sequence of storms will not
thereby disappear: itwill be merely explained; and the explanation will
be performed in terms of laws of averages (fluidmechanics and thermo
dynamics). The explanation of chance does not eliminate it.
Any perfectly definite mechanism involving a large number of nearly
independent (i.e., weakly interacting) similar entities, whether they be
electrons or persons, will produce a stable limiting frequency distribution
of some sort or other. For example, an initially heterogeneous dis
tribution of dust particles in the air will, in the long run and annoyingly
enough, become quite uniformly distributed on the floor and furniture.
Chance is not chaos or lawlessness: far from being arbitrary every
chance distribution is characterized by certain constant frequencies,
averages, and mean fluctuations?whence pure chance is so difficult to
imitate. Thus we will hesitate to say that the nth decimal figures of the
logarithms of integers are randomly distributed, unless we can ascertain
that every digit occurs in that place with nearly the same frequency
Mo?as in fact it does.
Any detailed description of random processes will involve the con
cepts of law, circumstance (e.g., initial conditions), and probability.
The occurrence of the term 'probability' will not, of course, be designed
tomask our ignorance. On the contrary, we can make use of probability
theory only if we know or assume something concerning the system
under study: for instance, laws ofmotion, symmetry properties, or fre
quencies. The probability distributions occurring in factual science are not
a product of human frailty but an achievement of research. Moreover,
such distributions are supposed to mirror objective traits of the world.
Chance and causation are probably as objective traits of the world as
any conceptual model can be. Perfect randomness is probably as much
of an abstraction as perfect causation is, and yet neither is in our minds

This content downloaded from 72.221.114.155 on Wed, 18 Jun 2014 21:29:48 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
CAUSALITY, CHANCE, AND LAW 443
alone. We infer that the world has a causal ingredient because we estab
lish some laws that have a causal approximation, just as we infer that
the world ismade up of chance as well because we find some statistical
laws to work.

Inferring Causation from Correlation


From complete randomness to strict causation there is a continuum
of degrees of correlation. This correlation ismeasurable, and is helpful
in the search for systematic relations, such as causal bonds. Suppose we
wish to find out whether the factors or variables x and y (or, rather,
their variations) are systematically related to one another. (By "system
atic relation" I mean what is usually, and wrongly, called causal rela
tion?i.e., "systematic relation" covers functional relation, interaction,
and causation.) Suppose, further, that we are prevented from either
observing x and y or varying them at will, e.g., because they represent
social traits such as division of labor and technical skill.
Obviously two cases are possible : either x is systematically related to
y, inwhich case we write xSy, or x is not systematically related to y, a situ
ation we symbolize xSy. In the first case the absolute value of the coeffi
cient of correlation rxywill be near 1, in the second case itwill be approxi
mately 0. In short, we have the two conditionals
If xSy, then rxy= 1.

If xSy, then rxy^ 0.

We now gather data and compute rxv. If the empirically found value of
rxy near 1,we
is infer that xSy, and if it is nearly zero we infer that xSy.
But, of course, either inference is at best plausible, because all we know
is the converse of the first conditional, namely, that if there is a syste
matic relation between x and y, it is likely to show up in high correla
tion. The converse is not true :a high correlation will suggest but will not
establish a systematic relation.
Contrary to usage, we have been speaking of a systematic rather than
of a causal relation between x and y. The reason is this :a high value of the
coefficient of correlation rxv is compatible with at least the following
different hypotheses concerning the nature of the relation tying x to y:
(a) x and y are functionally related to one another, such as p and V in
Boyle's law; (6) x and y are interacting factors, and indeed mutually
favorable ones, such as rainfall and vegetation; (c) x causes y; (d) y
causes x; (e) x and y are both produced by a third factor z. The frequent
conjunction of x and yy or the concomitance of their variations, as indi
cated by a high value of rxy,does not establish their causal relation. And
scientists?unlike Humean philosophers?are vitally interested in the
difference between a frequent conjunction and a uniform production.
To make a decision among the various hypotheses consistent with

This content downloaded from 72.221.114.155 on Wed, 18 Jun 2014 21:29:48 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
444 AMERICAN SCIENTIST

the finding rxy= 1, additional information, analyses, and criteria are


needed. Some of the criteria used in physics are: (a) y comes after x; (b) y
is near x; (c) y ismore stable than x; (d) y is associated with a greater
entropy than x; (e) y is associated with a smaller energy than x. However,
none of these criteria could by itselfmore than support the hypothesis
that x causes y. Only a detailed study, both empirical and theoretical,
of the relation between x and y?a study going far beyond the statistical
data at hand, and deeply into the mechanism involved?might even
tually establish that x and y are parts of a causal process.
In short, by itself the statistical method cannot establish the existence
of systematic relations, although it can suggest the existence of a mecha
nism which may be partly causal. This conclusion is reinforced by a
study of the statistical correlations among more than two variables.
If for two variables we had two possible causal hypotheses, "x y"
and "y x" for three variables we have no less than a dozen possible
causal hypotheses?not to count the noncausal ones. In fact, if there is
a systematic relation among the three variables x, y, and z, in addition
to the functional relations z = f(x,y) and the interaction x <->y <-> 2, we
have the following possible models:

Multiple Causation
Plurality of Diversity of
Linear Causation CausesEffects
Hi x -> y z *yx\
Hn Jtz H10<
H2 x z y y'*z
Hz y x z *x
y\
Hs ?x Hn y<*
Hi y z x *z
z/
Hh z-+x-+y *x z\
?
H9 *y Hu z\
H 6 z y x

All such cases, where some variables are indirectly related?as in


? ?
lx y z'?come under the heading of the so-called spurious corre
lation; the variable mediating between the extremes is often called the
intervening variable. In multiple causation with plurality of causes and
a single effect (hypotheses Hi to H$), the causes may be jointly or dis
jointly operative, and, in either case, their coefficient of correlation may
be nearly zero. In all other cases, interesting relations can be established
among the indirectly related variables and, by making further assump
tions of a nonstatistical character, inferences can be drawn about likely
systematic patterns of relations (some of which may be causal) [6].For
example, for both Hi and Hu we have
?
Txz Txy'Tyz (9)

If the data at hand confirm this relation, we still have to decide between
Hi and Hn. The ambiguity can be partially or totally removed by making
certain specific assumptions.

This content downloaded from 72.221.114.155 on Wed, 18 Jun 2014 21:29:48 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
CAUSALITY, CHANCE, AND LAW 445

Sociologists and anthropologists are, of course, interested in knowing


whether a given set of social variables, or traits, stand all on the same
footing or are somehow genetically related. Suppose we consider the
interrelations of the following variables: division of labor (w), postnup
tial residence (x), land tenure (y), and system of descent (2), all with
reference to the North American Indian tribes. Blalock [7]has put the
following competing hypotheses to the test of statistics:
Hi w ? x-x ?> yy z

H2 w-+X'W-+y-x-+y-y-+z

According to Equation(9), ifHi is true, we should find the following pre


dictions to be confirmed:
P\\ Twy Tvox'Txy

Pu rsz = rxy-ryz (10)

Pit rwa = rWX'rXJJ-rvz

On the other hand, on the basis of H2 and Equation (9) we would pre
dict the following statistical relations :
~
Pil fXZ TXy'Tyz
-
(11)
P%2 rWZ fwy'Tyz

Notice, in the first place, that Hi is simpler than H2 but has more com
plex consequences than H2. Note, in the second place, that predictions
Pi2 and P2i are identical but the remaining predictions are quite differ
ent, so that a clear cut decision among them (or against the two) is pos
sible on the basis of empirical data.
It so happened that data supported the second hypothesis, which had
been advanced prior to the test. But the same data also support alter
native hypotheses, such as those obtained by reversing some or even all
of the arrows in H2. However, the anthropologist will adduce further
laws, or data, to show that such reversals are unlikely or even impossible.
In conclusion, statistics, far from being the scaffold of causality, is a
tool that may suggest the existence of systematic relations and, in par
ticular, of relations of causation. The inference of causal laws from sta
tistical relations is not unambiguous, but the ambiguity can sometimes be
removed with the help of additional assumptions, of a nonstatistical
nature.

Causality, Lawfulness, and Determinism

The usual classification of scientific laws into causal and noncausal is


insufficient. A more fertile approach should be to group scientific laws
into those which contain determination categories (causation, inter
action, triggering, blocking, etc.) and those which do not [8i.
Among the law statements free from determination categories we find

This content downloaded from 72.221.114.155 on Wed, 18 Jun 2014 21:29:48 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
446 AMERICAN SCIENTIST

the laws of irrelevance, i.e., propositions which assert that a given factor
makes no difference to some other factor; all conservation laws fit in this
class, since they state that a certain change (the "flow" of time, trans
lations, rotations, etc.) does not alter the value of a given variable.
Other
conspicuous classes of the genus of law statements not containing deter
mination categories are the following : law statements of statistical corre
lation (e.g., between age and cancer incidence), of functional relation
(e.g., between the concentration and the conductivity of an electrolyte),
of composition or distribution (e.g., chemical formulas), structural (e.g.,
concerning equilibrium configurations), extremum law statements (e.g.,
minimum principles), transformation formulas (e.g., Lorentz transfor
mations), and kinematical law statements (such as life curves). Let us
not look for causation in this group, because causation is a category of
determination not to be confused with either order, determinateness or
even connectedness.

Among the law statements involving categories of determination the


following are found: causal laws (e.g., "External conditions select bio
logical variations"), interaction law statements (e.g., Ampere's laws of
themutual action of currents), dynamical law statements (e.g., Newton's
second law of motion), trigger-action law statements (e.g., laws about
chain reactions), blocking-action law statements (e.g., Pavlov's laws of
inhibition), global dynamical law statements (e.g., Le Chatelier's prin
ciple), dynamical statistical law statements (e.g., stochastic relations in
Brownian motion), dialectical law statements (e.g., about the conflict
between cell multiplication and the pressure of the environment), and
teleological law statements (e.g., about human means?end relations).
The variety of kinds of laws shows how misleading the equation
=
Causality Lawfulness is, despite the fact that it enjoys the authority of
both Aristotle and Hume.
=
Equally confusing is the equation Determinism Causality, once the
multiplicity of kinds of determiners?noncausal and causal? has been
recognized, i.e., once it has been realized that things can acquire and
retain properties in a variety of ways. For, after all, when we say that
x determines y we mean that x brings about, produces, or contributes to
the production of y, and the mechanism of such a production may be
anything from almost pure chance to teleology, according to the nature
of the case.
The further equality, Lawfulness = Determinism, is no less mistaken
despite its popularity. Consider the central hypothesis of the steady
state cosmological theory, according to which matter is self-created
ex-nihilo at a pace slow enough to escape direct detection. This is a hy
pothesis of nonconservation, which is perfectly respectable as far as the
principle of lawfulness is concerned?a principle that may be formulated
thus: "Nothing occurs in a lawless, arbitrary, way." But the hypothesis

This content downloaded from 72.221.114.155 on Wed, 18 Jun 2014 21:29:48 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
CAUSALITY, CHANCE, AND LAW 447
of creation out of the blue conflicts with the genetic principle, according
to which "Nothing arises out of nothing or goes into nothing," which
can be regarded as an ontological generalization of all the conservation
principles. The creation ofmatter is supposed to be not only uncaused?
which would be unobjectionable?but also indetermined, that is, deter
mined by nothing. Hence, the rate of creation could never be slowed
down or accelerated by man, because no mechanism is provided upon
which we might conceivably act: matter is said just to pop up magically
here and there without any antecedent condition. This hypothesis, then,
is indeterministic because, although it obeys the principle of lawfulness,
it violates the genetic principle.
Conversely, some theory might be advanced which postulated the
occurrence of entirely lawless events which, still, would somehow be pro
duced?even though erratically?by something else. If we were to accept
some of the various popular misconceptions of the quantum theory,
we would say that this theory violates the principle of lawfulness, simply
because?at least in the orthodox version of the theory?it does not
account for the details of the whereabouts of the individual microsys
tems, even though it does account for their collective behavior and for
the behavior of collections of observations on individual systems.
We see, then, that the genetic principle and the postulate of lawful
ness are logically independent from one another and that both are nec
essary and sufficient to build up a theory of general determinism making
room for a wide class of categories of determination and kinds of law [9].
According to this liberal version of determinism?which may be called
neodeterminism?noncausal laws do not commit us to indeterminism
but, rather to a renewal of classical determinism. Only law-breakers and
creationists (whether in magic, religion, or cosmology) would be inde
terminists in this general sense of 'determinism'.
Since scientific research is essentially the search for law and the trac
ing of the lawful transformation or genesis of things out of other things,
those who are interested in either law-breaking or creation ex nihilo
should turn to politics, magic, or religion. Science is now as determinis
tic as it ever was. Only, the philosophy of determinism must be modern
ized to keep the pace of science.

NOTES AND REFERENCES

1. M. Bunge, Causality: The Place of the Causal Principle in Modern Science


(Cambridge, Mass., Harvard University Press, 1959), 2.5.
2. For a recent account of the functionalist view of causation see, e.g., F. Waismann,
"The Decline and Fall of Causality," in A. C. Crombie et al., Turning Points in
Physics (Amsterdam, North-Holland, 1959), p. 87.
3. For a slightly different set of conditions and an argument in favor of their relevance,
see M. Bunge, op. cit., 13.2.1.
4. The term 'nomopragmatic statement' stands for a law statement cast in a way
convenient for validation or use, and is introduced by M. Bunge, Metascientific

This content downloaded from 72.221.114.155 on Wed, 18 Jun 2014 21:29:48 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
448 AMERICAN SCIENTIST
Queries (Springfield, 111., Charles C Thomas), ch. 4. Since in the quantum theory
of fields the field variables are operators, the so-called "causality condition" cannot
be expressed by a classical formula like (8); usual statements are commutation
relations among the field variables ^?(x) at different points in spacetime, such as,
e.g.,
- = -
i?i(x)\l/ilx') tk(xf)ti(x) i8ik'&(x x').

5. H. Poincar?, Calcul des probabilit?s, 2nd ed.


(Paris, Gauthier-Villars, 1912),
pp. 148 ff.
6. See H. A. Simon, "Spurious Correlation: A Causal Interpretation," Jour. Amer.
Statist. Ass., 49, 467 (1954); H. M. Blalock, "Correlational Analysis and Causal
Inferences," Amer. Anthropol., 62, 624 (1960).
7. Reference 6.
8. For a dozen classifications of law statements see M. Bunge, "Kinds and Criteria
of Scientific Law," Philosophy of Sei., 28, 260 (1961).
9. For an exposition of general determinism, see M. Bunge, reference 1.

This content downloaded from 72.221.114.155 on Wed, 18 Jun 2014 21:29:48 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

You might also like