You are on page 1of 11

ARTICLE IN PRESS

Social Science & Medicine 58 (2004) 975–985

Ancient euthanasia: ‘good death’ and the doctor in the


graeco-Roman world
Anton J.L. Van Hooff
Department of Ancient History, Nijmegen University, Erasmusplein 1, room 10.05, NL-6525HT Nijmegen, The Netherlands

Abstract

This article maps the concept of ‘good death’ (euthanasia) in the ancient world and explores the marginal role of the
doctor at a ‘good dying’. His assistance was not needed when the Homeric warrior died as a hero and was expected to
accept death with resignation. Later the city-state regarded as heroes the men fallen for the cause of the community,
honouring these model citizens as those who died well. In the more individualistic age of Hellenism and the Roman
Empire, a death in luxury or without suffering could be styled euthanasia. The doctor had neither a place in those acts of
dying nor in cases of natural death. He shunned death as a failure of his art. Sometimes a doctor was called in to assist
in voluntary death, a role that was not forbidden by the Hippocratic oath. An appeal to this oath by opponents of
euthanasia in the modern sense of the word therefore is mistaken.
r 2003 Published by Elsevier Ltd.

Keywords: Good death; Euthanasia; Voluntary death; Hippocratic oath; Medically assisted suicide; Graeco-Roman times

The ancient word euthanasia that he wishes to die on the spot. Thus, Menander has
the tyrant Dionysius say
From 1 April 2002, a new law regulates euthanasia in
One thing for my own self I desire—and this seems to
the Netherlands. After calling in a second opinion, a
me the only death (monos thanatos) that is a one ‘well
doctor is permitted to end the life of a patient whose
died’ (euthanatos)—to lie on my back with its many
suffering he/she regards as intolerable as well as
rolls of fat, scarce uttering a word, gasping for
incurable, provided the patient has explicitly expressed
breath, while I eat and say: ‘I am rotting away in
the wish to die. The new law constitutes a major victory
pleasure.’1
for the Dutch Association for Voluntary Euthanasia
(Nederlandse Vereniging voor Vrijwillige Euthanasie) An astrologer from the second century CE, Vettius
that for decades has pleaded for adequate legal rulings. Valens, describes a (physically) good death: those who
It is to be noticed that in the modern concept of are born under a certain constellation ‘die well
euthanasia the presence of a doctor is taken for granted. (euthanatousin) falling asleep from food, satiety, wine,
In the ancient idea of euthanasia, good dying, there was intercourse or apoplexy’.2 It is this kind of sudden,
no place for the doctor. gentle death that the emperor Augustus wished for
The noun euthanasia, the adjective euthanatos, the himself, according to his biographer Suetonius: ‘For
adverb euthanatos# and the verb (ap)euthanat(iz)ein made always when he heard that somebody had died fast and
their appearance in the fourth and third century BCE. It without pain he bade for himself and his family a similar
seems that they were first used by Greek comedy writers, euthanasia, for this is the word he used.’ Interestingly,
such as Menander, Posidippus and Cratinus, in scenes in the Roman emperor used the Greek term that obviously
which a glutton enjoys the good things of life so much by his time had acquired a specific meaning.

1
Menander frg. 23 Edmonds (1961).
2
E-mail address: a.v.hooff@let.kun.nl (A.J.L. Van Hooff). Anthologiarum libri ix 126.

0277-9536/$ - see front matter r 2003 Published by Elsevier Ltd.


doi:10.1016/j.socscimed.2003.10.036
ARTICLE IN PRESS
976 A.J.L. Van Hooff / Social Science & Medicine 58 (2004) 975–985

The idea of good dying was not limited to a painless themselves, and died like brave men and Spartans.’8
exit. The word euthanasia and its derivatives were also Such an end befitted this king ‘who was, in one word,
used to indicate a happy end that crowned a good life. In formed by nature both to lead and to rule’, but even a
his instructions on how to praise somebody in a speech, despicable person like Lykiskos who had caused much
the orator Aelius Theon sums up the various personal misery for his fellow-Aetolians, died so nobly (160/59
conditions that deserve acclamation: education, friend- BCE) that he was an example how Fortune grants to the
ship, respect, political position, richness, being blessed worst men the fine death, euthanasia, which is the
with children (euteknia) and last but not least euthana- guerdon due to the good and brave.9
sia.3 ‘Who does not know that a good old age (eug#eria) The heroic connotation of euthanasia is still used with
and euthanasia are the highest of human goods?’ so the respect to Jewish and Christian martyrs. In Book 2 of
Jewish writer Philo of Alexandria says—only to mark Maccabees, the aged Eleazar declares that by his death
the difference with God whose ‘old-age-less’ and he will leave a noble example to the young of how to die
immortal (athanatos) nature has nothing to do with well (apeuthanatizein) in accordance with the revered
these human goods.4 The Christian Clemens (c. 150– and holy laws of the Jews.10 This Bible passage is quoted
211/212 CE) echoes this idea of a God who is in no way by Origenes (184/5–254/5) in his Exhortation to Martyr-
to be compared with humans. The early Christian dom.11 He expects Christians when they have to give
theologian revels in the paradoxes of faith. God has proof of their faith to die nobly (euthanatizein) as
given us humans innumerable blessings in which He Eleazar did.
Himself does not participate: ‘He by birth unborn, as to Although the Greek euthanasia as a euphemism for
food in want of naught, in growth remaining the same, gentle death was not unknown to the Romans as we
as to good old age and euthanasia immortal and have seen with regard to Augustus, a prominent Roman
undecaying.’5 like Cicero who was more versed in Greek literature
In this argument, Clemens still holds to a rather used it in the more common sense of a noble death. In
concrete meaning of euthanasia. However, to ancient the chaotic situation after the murder of Caesar on
philosophers dying a good death was more than having March 15th 44 BCE, he had left Rome on the advice of
a painless or happy end. It meant dying in moral Atticus. Now this same close friend urged him only a
perfection. One fragment of the Stoic Chrysippus (281– few months later to come back. Cicero is surprised
208 BCE) says ‘euthanatein is ending life by whatever about this change of mind and shows some irritation
death in perfection.’6 This idea is developed by the Stoic about Atticus’ arguments: ‘What did astonish me
emperor Marcus Aurelius (121–180), who recently beyond measure was that you should use the words:
became familiar to a world audience through the film ‘A fine thing for you, who talk of a noble death
Gladiator, in which he appeared as the wise emperor. (euthanasia), a fine thing, !ı’faith. Go desert your
This reputation is based on the philosophical diary he country.’12
composed during his reign, Exhortations to Myself. In Our linguistic exploration has shown that euthanasia
this unique piece of writing, he admonishes himself to be and its derivatives conveyed the idea of a comfortable,
nice to common people. Of course, the wise man shall happy and noble end. Medically assisted gentle death,
not be dragged away unwillingly from such people when which is the primary connotation of modern euthanasia,
the end is near, but rather ‘as the soul shall easily slip was not covered by the Greek terms. Presumably,
from the body of a person that dies well (euthanatoun- euthanasia became a popular euphemism in modern
tos), the departure from such persons has to be of such times because of its technical undertones. For the Greek
easy nature in order to die well (euthanat#esontes).’7 root of the word makes it look like the verbal constructs
Finally and most importantly, euthanatein could mean of which medical terminology is full. At the end of this
dying nobly. Thus the historian Polybius (c. 200–c. 120 paper, we shall see that ancient doctors did sometimes
BCE) describes the death of Cleomenes, a former king of assisted in self-killing, however not to ensure a gentle,
Sparta who, being imprisoned by king Ptolemy Philo- but rather a noble death. So already the exploration of
pator of Egypt, in the winter of 220/219 made a dash for the word suggests that the ancient paradigm of
freedom, ‘not that he really believed that he could euthanasia was quite different from the modern concept.
recover it [y] but rather because he was resolved to die The difference can only be fully understood against the
nobly (euthan#esai).’ When the attempt was thwarted he background of the ancients’ view of life and death. It
and his companions ‘turned their weapons upon may seem daring to cover many centuries in sketching

3 8
Progymnasmata 110. Histories 5, 38–39.
4 9
On the sacrifices of Abel and Cain 100. Histories 32,4,3.
5 10
Stromata 5,68,2–3. Macc.2:6,28.
6 11
Moral Fragments 601. Chapter 22.
7 12
Ta eis heauton 10,36. Letters to Atticus 16,7,3.
ARTICLE IN PRESS
A.J.L. Van Hooff / Social Science & Medicine 58 (2004) 975–985 977

this attitude in a few pages. However, there is a great A desperate ‘Why am I to die so young?’ would be a
deal of continuity where these ‘essential’ questions are perverse denial of heroic existence. The main concern of
concerned. A traditional society like the Graeco-Roman the dying hero is to meet his fate with dignity.
world did not easily change its views. Sometimes he will bemoan his father who is going to
Therefore, in this paper, the stress is on the concept of be left behind without any filial support. Another
a good death in the context of classical culture. Given concern may be to get a proper burial that will guarantee
the audience of this magazine, we shall pay special his memory. In this respect, Achilles risks showing
attention to the role of the doctor during our historical disrespect for the rules of heroic values. His wrath and
tour d’horizon. grief make him drag behind his chariot the corpse of
Hector whose remains he has promised to leave to the
dogs and birds. Finally Hector’s father Priam succeeds
Heroic resignation in softening Achilles’ rage, appealing to the common
fate of fathers and their heroic sons. Thus the epic of
It is not just the chronological order that makes us wrath, which the Iliad is, ends in a serene spirit: the hero
begin with Homer. Classical civilisation did not only constitutes the perfect man, but in the last resort he is
start with the Iliad and Odyssey, but these epics also mortal too. Only the gods, who for the rest are
continued to act as a point of reference, for they anthropomorphic both in (imaginary) appearance and
represented basic ancient values. Among these, shame in their passions are the immortal ones, athanatoi, or the
was a major concern for Greeks and Romans. The ‘always being’, aien eontes, as the Homeric epithets have
Homeric hero is only concerned with his own glory. This it.14 It was only in a sophisticated era that some
egotist attitude is the theme of Homer’s Iliad as he philosophers came to revel in the paradox that at least
announces in the first lines of the epic: in one respect humans are superior to the gods: only
man has the power to put an end to his life.15
The wrath sing, goddess, of Peleus’ son, Achilles, that
However, in the early stage of Greek civilisation that
destructive wrath which brought countless woes
Homer’s epic represents, the hero accepts death as an
upon the Achaeans, and sent forth to Hades many
unavoidable evil from which even the supreme god
valiant souls of heroes, and made them themselves
cannot save his mortal child. Only for a moment does
spoil for dogs and every bird; thus the plan of Zeus
Zeus hesitate, considering interference when he realises
came to fulfilment, from the time when first they
that Sarpedon, the son he had with Europa, is about to
parted in strife, Atreus’ son, king of men, and
die. Then his wife Hera warns him not to put the normal
brilliant Achilles.
order in disarray. Instead, she advises her divine
Achilles is unable to swallow his degradation by husband to make sure that Sarpedon’s corpse will be
Atreus’ son, Agamemnon, who has taken away his brought to his homeland of Lycia.16 In this way, his
concubine Briseis. The common well-being of the brothers and other relatives will be able to pay their
Greeks is no concern at all for the hero. With grim respect to the dead and to keep his memory, seeing the
satisfaction, Achilles watches the Greek failures against tumulus under which his ashes rest. To mark the tomb a
the Trojans during the time in which he abstains from standing stone suffices as a token, for in Homeric times
battle. Only when his closest friend Patroclus has been no inscription or representation is made. As long as
killed by the Trojan Hector does grief overcome people passing by remember, the dead Sarpedon will live
Achilles’ resentment. Then he returns to the battlefield on in memory.
to perform miracles of heroism. He does so being quite In order to remove Sarpedon’s body from the
aware that his death is near. The fatal end will be battlefield, Zeus sends the gods Death, Thanatos, and
brought about by an arrow that hits his only vulnerable his twin brother Sleep, Hypnos.17 These are, according
spot, his heel. This story is not told in the Iliad, but the to Hesiod, the sons of the goddess Night, Nyx.18
reader—or rather the listener—is supposed to know Elsewhere in Hesiod’s genealogy of the gods, they are
about Achilles’ tragic end. Only with this foreknowledge denoted as the ‘terrible gods’, deinoi theoi.19 A Greek
is he able to appreciate the perfect heroism of Achilles, vase by Euphronios in the New York Metropolitan
who goes into battle being aware that he is doomed to Museum shows how Sarpedon’s corpse is lifted by
die soon. Achilles accepts death as a fact of heroic life.
Similar resignation13 is demonstrated by the numer- 14
Iliad 1. 290, 494; 21. 518; 24. 99; Odyssey 5. 7; 8. 306; 12.
ous heroes who actually fall in battle during the episode 371, 377.
of the Trojan War that the Iliad deals with. No hero will 15
Pliny Historia Naturalis 2, 27.
utter any protest when the moment of his end is at hand. 16
Iliad 16, 433–457.
17
Iliad 16, 666–675.
13 18
The qualification ‘r!esignation’ was coined by Ph. Ari"es Theogonia 212.
19
(Ari"es, 1978), L0 homme devant la mort, Paris, 1977. Theogonia 759.
ARTICLE IN PRESS
978 A.J.L. Van Hooff / Social Science & Medicine 58 (2004) 975–985

Death and Sleep, who here as well as on other Greek The continuing appeal of these Homeric values is
pottery are depicted as winged gods.20 demonstrated more than five centuries later by the
In Homeric epic, it is only a violent end on the historian Polybius when he speaks about the determina-
battlefield that is described. Of course, in the scenes of tion of Cleomenes III to euthanatein (see above on the
heroic death, there is no place for a medical man historical context): ‘I suppose that there dwelt in his
to assist the dying in their last moments, let alone mind and inspired him those words of the hero which
to confirm death. Such a technical expert would are wont to commend themselves to men of dauntless
detract from the respect the poet wants to instil in spirit:
his listener. That is not to say that doctors are
unknown in the Homeric world. However, such a but now again is my doom come upon me.
# (Odyssey 17,384) is only
‘healer of evil’, i#et#er kakon Nay, but not without a struggle let me die, neither
called in when somebody is wounded, as Menelaus is in ingloriously,
Iliad 4,108. Then his brother Agamemnon sends for but in the working of some great deed for the
Machaon who is highly regarded for his medical hearing of men that are yet to be.’24
expertise. This i#et#er matches many men, Homer says,
but Machaon’s skill is not that of the professional
specialist.21 He leads his troops just like the other Greek Good death in the city-state
princes. He just happens to distinguish himself by some
specialist knowledge. The Graeco-Roman world never turned its back
The world of the Odyssey, which in many ways on the old heroic ideal. It modified this ideal to
represents a later stage of Greek civilisation, is already make it fit into the value system of the new community
familiar with professional doctors. Together with the state, the polis. The polis stressed the collective element
seer, the ship builder and the singer—Homer’s own of death by citizens who sacrificed their life for
profession!—they are counted as ‘people’s workers’, the common cause, for the virtues the polis wanted
d#emiourgoi, i.e. experts whose skills are of great were co-operative rather than competitive as they
importance to the community.22 These professionals had been in Homeric society (Adkins, 1972). The
travel around to offer their services. Obviously, one noblest end was to die together with compatriots,
could not reckon with their presence when somebody holding the line until the last moment. In this way, the
was dying. Besides, in a world with a high mortality, one polis domesticated or rather channelled the agonistic
did not need a doctor to confirm death. Thus, their spirit, which in olden times had proved to be a
absence at the deathbed in Homeric epic is not only to destructive power. The ancient city-state glorified the
be explained by the codes of the genre, which depicts men who had given their lives for the commonwealth.
mainly violent death. There was simply no place for a They were venerated as the heroes of the polis. Their
doctor when somebody was about to die. In the case of collective tomb, sometimes a cenotaph, became the
the hero, who had to exemplify good death, a doctor’s focus of a cult in which the whole community took part.
presence would damage the effect. For a hero dies his At Marathon in Attica, visitors still can see the tumulus
own good death. covering the bodies of the 192 Athenians who died there
That is not to say that death was welcome. Just a in the battle in which the Persian invaders were defeated
shadow, called psyche or eidolon (figure) of the dead in 490 BCE.
remained to go to Hades’ place. This underworld was The shift towards the social significance of death is
anything but a paradise, as Odysseus finds out when he exemplified in Herodotus’ story about the meeting
descends into it. Among other prominent ghosts he between the Athenian statesman Solon and king
meets Achilles, whom he praises exuberantly: ‘Say not a Croesus of Lydia, whose richness is still proverbial.
word,’ the great hero answers, ‘in death’s favour; I Solon was on a tour having reformed his polis
would rather be a paid servant in a poor man’s house into a community in which both rich and poor had a
and be above the ground than king of kings among the place. To prevent the personal respect he had
dead.’23 So being dead is no fun at all. The way the hero won among the Athenians becoming an obstacle
as a model meets his fate is essential for his fame. A to the free functioning of the new constitution, Solon
good death crowns a good life. went into a kind of voluntary exile. Having been
received with great distinction by the wealthy Lydian
20 king, he is shown around. When the king thinks that
Metropolitan Nr.1972.11.10. Three lecuthi showing the
winged pair made by the so-called Thanatos painter are his guest is sufficiently impressed, he asks him who
London D. 58, Munich 2777 and Berlin F3160. in his view is the happiest of men. Solon answers
21
Iliad 11,514–515. without hesitation: ‘Tellos of Athens.’ Surprised the
22
Odyssey 17,383–385.
23 24
Odyssey 11, 488–491. Iliad 22,303–305.
ARTICLE IN PRESS
A.J.L. Van Hooff / Social Science & Medicine 58 (2004) 975–985 979

king asks for an explanation, which is duly given by the Doctors and death
man who was regarded as one of the seven sages of
Greece: The fifth century BCE saw not only the climax of
democracy, ‘people’s power’ as a political system but
First, because his country was flourishing in his also the cultural climax of Athens. On the Acropolis, the
days, and he himself had sons beautiful and Parthenon was erected as the focus of the city’s cult. At
good, and he lived to see children born to each of two great annual festivals, tragedies and comedies were
them, and these children grew up; and further performed that have become part of world literature.
because, after a life spent in what our people look These plays by Aeschylus, Sophocles, Euripides and
upon as comfort, his end was surpassingly glorious. Aristophanes addressed the sentiments of the audience
In a battle between the Athenians and their and thus give an insight into contemporary public
neighbours near Eleusis, he came to the assistance opinion. In Sophocles’ Antigone, the praise of man’s
of his countrymen, routed the enemy, and died upon achievements is sung:
the field most gallantly. The Athenians gave him a
public funeral on the spot where he fell, and paid him Wonders are many, and none is more wonderful than
the highest honours.25 man. His power spans the sea, even when it surges
white before the gales of the south-wind, and makes a
The answer begins and ends with the common- path under swells that threaten to engulf him.27
wealth, for in the new code of the city-state it
Thus, the greatness of man shows itself in shipping, in
is not enough to have enjoyed a blessed private life.
agriculture, in the domestication of animals, in hunting
Of course Tellos was most lucky to have seen his
and fishing. Man has wrought miracles in intellectual
family flourish into the second generation. This
and social fields as well as in house building:
circumstance ensured that his tomb would be
visited by his male offspring who would pay respect Speech and thought fast as the wind and the moods
to him. However, what most contributed to his that give order to a city he has taught himself, and
happiness according to Solon was that he, living in a how to flee the arrows of the inhospitable frost under
flourishing state, contributed to its well-being by clear skies and the arrows of the storming rain. He
sacrificing his life. has resource for everything. Lacking resource in
The Athenians later regarded Solon as the founding nothing, he strides towards what must come. From
father of Athenian democracy, mistakenly from an Death alone he shall procure no escape, but from
historical point of view, for in 594 BCE Solon reformed baffling diseases he has devised flights.28
the constitution only from an aristocracy into a
timocracy (a kind of meritocracy), a system in which In this list of achievements that are proof of man’s
tim#e prevailed. The Greek word time# denotes ‘value’ formidability, deinot#es, medicine has a prominent place.
both in an abstract and in a concrete sense, for those Here, we see the impact of the school of Hippocrates of
who had the financial means to afford heavy armour Kos (460–c. 370 BCE), whose rationality is expounded
had a higher value and thus were accorded a higher in the first lines of the On the Sacred Disease: ‘As to the
status in the polis. so-called sacred disease it is like this: it seems to me no
When Herodotus (c. 484–424 BCE) composed or more sacred than other diseases, but it has a natural
remodelled the Tellos story, he saw Athens in its climax cause.’ The explanation that follows is complete non-
as a democracy. To sacrifice one’s life for the benefit of sense in modern eyes—an overflow of phlegm in the
this perfect polis made good all individual defects, as brains—but at least it is rational nonsense. For here a
Pericles argues in his famous funeral speech on the fallen serious attempt was made to establish a physical cause.
of the first season of the Peloponnesian War. ‘For there Looking for causes, aitiai, is the common concern of
is justice in the claim that steadfastness in his country’s historians and medical men in Greece’s Golden Age.
battles should be as a cloak to cover a man’s other Herodotus the historian says in the opening lines of his
imperfections; since the good action has blotted out the Histories that the aim of his studies is to find the cause,
bad, and his merit as a citizen has more than outweighed aitia, of the Persian Wars. Similarly, the Hippocratic
his demerits as an individual.’26 doctor does not content himself with the observation
So in the heydays of the polis, good death that diseases vanish spontaneously: ‘Indeed, under close
was understood as a socially meaningful end, in examination spontaneity disappears; for everything that
which the co-operative values of the city-state were occurs will be found to do so through something, and
demonstrated. this ‘through something’ shows that spontaneity is a

25 27
Herodotos Histories 1,30. Sophocles Antigone 332–337.
26 28
Thucydides Histories 2,42,3. Sophocles Antigone 354–362.
ARTICLE IN PRESS
980 A.J.L. Van Hooff / Social Science & Medicine 58 (2004) 975–985

mere name and has no reality. Medicine, however, good death. Maybe that is the reason why the
because it acts ‘through something’ and because its vocabulary of ‘euthanasia’ originated in this period. In
results may be forecasted, has reality.’29 Such is the the Menander fragment quoted above, Dionysios, the
glorious language of the scientist who believes that only glutton, ends by saying: ‘I am rotting away in pleasure.’
on a rational basis can medicine develop: ‘Medicine [y] The Greek word for ‘pleasure’ in this comedy
has discovered both a principle and a method, through #
fragment is hedon# e, which was to become a central
which the discoveries made during a long period are concept of Epicureanism. Modern language uses ‘Epi-
many and excellent, while full discovery will be made, if curean’ and ‘hedonistic’ in a vulgarised sense for
the inquirer be competent, conduct his researches with ‘pleasure seeking’. In fact, Epicureanism was a noble
knowledge of discoveries already made, and make them philosophy that tried to meet the new conditions of
his starting-point.’30 Hellenism. Since Alexander the Great had opened up the
In Hippocratic medicine, death is there when the whole of the Middle East to the Greeks, the city-state
balance between fire and water, the two basic elements was no longer the horizon of man’s existence. The whole
of all animal life, is lost.31 Only rarely, however, do (civilised) world, kosmos, merged into one polis, the
medical authors discuss the nature of death. Hippocratic kosmopolis, in which the individual could easily feel
doctors are primarily concerned with prognostics. himself lost. The two major philosophical schools of
Characteristically, an electronic search of all Hippo- Hellenism, Stoicism and Epicureanism, both tried to
cratic writings on the phrase ‘death is’ (thanatos esti) redefine man’s place in the world. The Stoics advocated
only produced places with ‘death is near wheny‘ Above a ‘cosmopolitical’ attitude, arguing that an individual
all, ancient doctors were interested in the question had to regard himself as a citizen of the whole world. A
whether an ailment was fatal or curable, so that they wise man just played the role that had been accorded to
could decide if they should take care of a case or not. him and subjected himself willingly to the great order of
For instance, diseases of the brains, liver, diaphragm, things. The Stoic sage accepted illness and death as
backbone, stomach, arteries and heart were regarded as natural vicissitudes of life, which he had to meet with
deadly.32 Doctors paid much attention to the indications firmness and moral perfection. We met this attitude
of death, in Greek the s#emeia thanatodea, in Latin the above in the dictums of Chrysippus, who was the second
signa letalia or indicia mortis. They discerned a specific head of the Stoic school of philosophy, as well as in
face that announced death, the so-called Hippocratic Marcus Aurelius. In modern usage ‘stoic’ denotes an
face, the facies hippocratica. This countenance is not like attitude of the stiff upper lip, whereas in the world of the
its usual self. ‘The latter will be as follows. Nose sharp, Hellenistic Greeks and the Romans it was a highly
eyes hollow, temples sunken, ears cold and contracted elaborated philosophy that defined the individual’s place
with their lobes turned outwards, the skin about the face in a divinely ruled world. In many ways Stoicism
hard and tense and parched, the colour of the face as a prepared the ground for Christianity.
whole being yellow or black.’33 The ancient doctor was Epicureanism on the other hand was loathed by the
an observer rather than a therapist. In the medical texts Christians. They rightly sensed that it was the ultimate
no mention is made of the doctor’s task to relieve the elaboration of pagan values. For Epicurus (341–270
suffering of those who are fatally ill. Palliative care to BCE), there was no existence beyond the grave. So death
ensure a gentle death was not a major concern of ancient was nothing to man. ‘When we live death is not, when
medicine. death is there, we are no more.’34 In phrases such as this
Epicurus and his followers argued for the doctrine that
the sense of life was life itself, i.e. a life of good quality,
for that is what h#edon#e stands for. In Herculaneum, the
Pleasant dying
charred papyrus rolls of a monograph On Death (Peri
thanatou) have come to light. In this work, Philodemos
In the fourth century BCE, the city-state no longer
(first century BCE) elaborates the Epicurean doctrine of
constituted the complete world of an individual. This
a good end. In his view it is nonsense to assume that
development was due to the emergence of great powers
death is always painful because the soul is separated
like Macedonia that reduced the significance of the polis.
from the body. As the soul consists of material particles
Now private life was more valued as well as a private
of the body death is just one of the changes, metabolai,
29 that a person undergoes. Moreover, there are instances
On the Art 6.
30 in which death comes without any suffering, e.g. during
On Ancient Medicine 2.
31
Peri diait#es 1, 3, 2; death as the effect of decreasing warmth intercourse, in drunkenness or in a coma. It does not
and moisture in Galen De temperamentis (Kuhn . 1.523, line 3 make sense to postpone enjoying life. This Epicurean
and 1.582, line 4 and 17). view was popularised in Horace’s famous dictum ‘carpe
32
On Diseases 1,3,5.
33 34
Prognostics 2. Epicurus, Letter to Menoeceus 125.
ARTICLE IN PRESS
A.J.L. Van Hooff / Social Science & Medicine 58 (2004) 975–985 981

diem’ (grasp the moment). To long for death was one, Theodosius II (401–450) had a fatal accident: he
unnatural. Why bother about one’s reputation after fell from his horse and broke his neck.38
death, the disfiguration of the decaying body, the The emperor, in particular the good emperor con-
absence of children or dying in a foreign country? Only stituted an example, a paradigm. He was well aware that
if one frees oneself from these common, but irrational he had to play the show to the end as Augustus did:
anxieties can one live and die without perturbation,
ataraxia. On the last day of his life he asked every now and
The Epicurean view of death is a development of a then whether there was any disturbance without on
generally shared pagan view, as is shown by epitaphs. In his account; then calling for a mirror, he had his hair
some of these the dead exhort the passer-by to enjoy life, combed and his falling jaws set straight. After that,
seeing what fate has in store for every mortal. calling in his friends and asking whether it seemed to
them that he had played the comedy of life fitly, he
* Nothing I was, nothing I am. You who are alive, eat, added the tag: ‘Since well I’ve played my part, all clap
drink, play, come (namely to the sad underworld that your hands and from the stage dismiss me with
is inescapable) Geist and Pfohl (1976) 35 applause.’ Then he sent them all off, and while he was
* Do not fear the river of the underworld. For it is asking some newcomers from the city about the
always stupid, by fearing death, to forfeit the joys of daughter of Drusus, who was ill, he suddenly passed
life.36 away as he was kissing Livia, uttering these last
words: ‘Live mindful of our wedlock, Livia, and
farewell,’ thus blessed with an easy death and such a
Titus Flavius Martialis who died at the age of 80 had
one as he had always longed for. For almost always
this text inscribed on his tomb:
on hearing that anyone had died swiftly and
painlessly, he prayed that he and his might have a
* What I ate and drank, I have; what I left behind, I
like euthanasia, for that was the term he was wont to
lost.37
use. He gave but one single sign of wandering before
he breathed his last, calling out in sudden terror that
It would be far fetched to see Epicurean philosophers forty young men were carrying him off. And even this
behind these epitaphs. Actually, these texts testify to the was rather a premonition than a delusion, since it was
popularity of the ‘Epicurean’ attitude. Their message, that very number of soldiers of the pretorian guard
sometimes backed by pictures of macabre skeletons, are that carried him forth to lie in state. (Suetonius, 1920,
the opposites of the Christian ‘memento mori’, remem- chap. 99).
ber you have to die. They do not admonish people to see
their temporary existence in the perspective of eternal In this description, some elements that mark the end
life. On the contrary, they say ‘memento vivere’, of a good emperors are stressed. Augustus preserves his
remember to live. bodily decorum. He is not left alone in his final
moments, but friends and family surround him. He
does not loose the grasp of his mind, apart from a minor
slip. Augustus’ end is without much suffering, the
Good emperors die well
euthanasia he had longed for.
Similar circumstances are highlighted in the story
For the Roman component of the ancient world, we
about the end of another good emperor, Antoninus Pius
use the emperors as a test group. No ancient biography
(86/7–161).
of an emperor will skip the way he died as death is the
final proof of his (un)worthiness. Out of 80 emperors He died in the seventieth year of his age, but his loss
whose death cause is more or less certain, only 29 died a was felt as though he had been just a youth. They say
natural death, 38 were murdered or executed, seven fell his death was somewhat as follows: after he had
on the battle field, out of whom five in civil war and two eaten too freely some Alpine cheese at dinner he
(Decius and Julian the Apostate) against foreign
enemies. Five emperors committed suicide. Finally 38
This count is based on a recent Dutch monograph: Fik
Meijer, Keizers sterven niet in bed. (Emperors do no die in bed),
35
Found in Cordoba, Corpus Inscriptionum Latinarum Amsterdam 2001, in which the author summarises the lives of
II2262. A collection of ‘Epicurean’ epitaphs in Geist and Pfohl 86 emperors from Caesar to Romulus Augustulus 44 BCE–476
(1976). CE, highlighting the end of these ‘legitimate’ rules. If one was to
36
.
Rome first century CE, F. Bucheler, Carmina Latina include all the pretenders, the number increases considerably A
Epigraphica, Leipzig 1895–1926, nr.1567. young German scholar, Tobias Arand, from Munster . who has
37
Hermann Dessau, Inscriptiones Latinae Selectae, Berlin processed all these cases too in his dissertation Das Schm-
1892–1916. nr. 8155a = Carmina Latina Epigraphica (previous a. hliche Ende (The Shameful End), Frankfurt a/M 2002 deals
note) nr. 244. with 171 persons.
ARTICLE IN PRESS
982 A.J.L. Van Hooff / Social Science & Medicine 58 (2004) 975–985

vomitted during the night, and was taken with a and with dignity and in a way to persuade another,
fever next day. On the second day, as he saw without tragic show.39
that his condition was becoming worse, in the
presence of his prefects he committed the state The Homeric heroic resignation in the face of death
and his daughter to Marcus Antoninus, and gave had developed into the philosophical ideal of equani-
order that the golden statue of Fortune, which was mity.40
wont to stand in the bed-chamber of the emperor, be
given to him. Then he gave the watchword to the
officer of the day as ‘Equanimity,’ and so, turning as Roman death
if to sleep, gave up the ghost at Lorium. To his
daughter he left his private fortune, and in his will he ‘Why should I play the Roman fool?’ Shakespeare has
remembered all his household with suitable legacies Macbeth say, playing upon the concept of ‘Roman
(David, 1967a). death’, i.e. suicide.41
This phrase reflects the popular idea that self-killing
Until the last moment this model emperor remained was permitted and even glorified in the ancient world,
true to himself. Before closing his eyes he had taken care especially among the Romans. In general, this view is
of his private affaris as well as those of the state. He correct, although there was always an undercurrent of
accepted death with the watchword he gave: ‘equani- doubt and even rejection of suicide, especially among the
mity’. Pythagoreans and Neo-Platonists who held to a dualistic
Other emperors of good fame died with similar view of man’s nature. In their philosophy the soul as the
dignity: Vespasian, Nerva and most of all the philoso- divine element was not to be released from the prison of
phical emperor Marcus Aurelius: the body by violence, but only by wisdom. It is not
surprising that this view prepared the ground for the
[y] being eager to die, he refrained from eating and Christian concept of self-killing as the mortal sin of self-
drinking, and so aggravated the disease. On the sixth murder, which was formulated by St. Augustine: ‘Who
day he summoned his friends, and with derision for kills himself is a homicide David (1967b).’42
all human affairs and scorn for death, said to them: Epicureanism in particular, with its stress on the
‘Why do you weep for me, instead of thinking about quality of life, recognised man’s fundamental right to
the pestilence and about death which is the common dispose of his own life. ‘Let us go out of life
lot of us all?’ And when they were about to retire he unconcerned, when it does not please us, as out of a
groaned and said: ‘If you now grant me leave to go, I theatre’, so the Epicurean says. In About Death,
bid you farewell and pass on before’. And when he Philodemos qualifies the Epicurean attitude: it is
was asked to whom he commended his son he preferable not to seek death before the best of life has
replied: ‘To you if he prove worthy, and to the been enjoyed (and one never is sure whether the best is
immortal gods’. The army, when they learned of his not still ahead). Epicurus himself had explicitly stated in
sickness, lamented loudly, for they loved him On Life that a wise man even when he has lost his
singularly. In the seventh day he was weary and eyesight, will not ‘withdraw himself from life’, as the
admitted only his son, and even him he at once sent Epicurean euphemism calls the final act of volition. So
away in fear that he would catch the disease. And the philosophy of pleasure warns against frivolous
when his son had gone, he covered his head as motivation for ‘leading oneself out’ (another euphe-
though he wished to sleep and during the night he mism). Therefore, Cicero is unfair when he summarises
breathed his last (David, 1976b). the Epicurean attitude as: ‘One should drink or die.’
(Aut bibat aut abeat).43 Personally, Cicero felt more
Apart from the familiar scenario, it is stressed that the attracted by Stoicism. This doctrine told every (wise)
emperor showed a contempt of death such as befitted a man to do his duty and stay in the place given to him by
philosopher. In his Exhortations to Myself (see above), fate. In principle, therefore, suicide was not permitted.
he had often dealt with the topic of a dignified death Only if one was sure that self-killing was in line with fate
stressing that one had to accept it as a natural
39
phenomenon. 11,3, transl. George Long, The Meditations, 1891.
40
Of course one can wonder in what degree the pictures of a
good emperor’s death was distorted. Arand p. 229 (see note 39)
What a soul that is which is ready, if at any
argues that anyway they contain more veracity than the ghastly
moment it must be separated from the body, descriptions of the end of bad rulers. Even if the pictures have
and ready either to be extinguished or dispersed or been idealised, they reflect the ancient model of good death.
continue to exist; but so that this readiness comes 41
Macbeth V, iii,1.
from a man’s own judgement, not from mere 42
De Civitate Dei out.
43
obstinacy, as with the Christians, but considerately Tusculan Disputations 5, 118.
ARTICLE IN PRESS
A.J.L. Van Hooff / Social Science & Medicine 58 (2004) 975–985 983

(or divine providence) could one leave life. So the to give assistance to suicide, it would be a mark of
doctrine was ‘no, unless’ as opposed to Epicurean ‘yes, distinction, implying that other doctors had fewer
provided that’. scruples, but we do not even know to what extent it
By an irony of history, however, the cases of Stoics was ever sworn. The evidence is very meagre indeed
who committed suicide have become emblematic of (Nutton, 1996).45
‘Roman death’. First it was Cato Minor, who preferred Even if the Hippocratic Oath had some meaning as a
death to appealing to Caesar’s clemency. Cato, the last professional ethical code, it should not be understood as
defender of the republican constitution, was besieged in dealing with assisted suicide, but with surreptitious
the North-African city of Utica in 46 BCE. There was murder by a doctor. The argument is mainly linguistic,
no escape. Having read Plato’s Phaidon—on # the so it is rather difficult to present it in English. However,
immortality of the soul—he plunged a sword into his we can approach this by giving a literal translation of
breast. In the time of the early emperors, in the first the key passage that—significantly—follows after some
century CE, Cato became something of a Stoic saint, sentences in which the doctor promises to refrain from
especially after the praise Seneca (c. 4 BCE–65 CE) gave ‘injustice’ (adikia): ‘And I will not give a drug that is
him. In his writings Seneca shows himself fascinated by deadly to anyone if asked [for it], (von Staden, 1996). In
the topic of suicide, a fact that attained a poignant the Greek text, the ‘anybody’ to whom the deadly
significance when he was forced to kill himself by his medicine is not given is in the dative, whereas ‘requested’
former student Nero who had become emperor. By his is nominative, going with the subject, the ‘I’ who swears.
time something of a suicide ritual had developed in the If the person who requests and to whom the fatal drug is
circles of the Roman aristocracy. Seneca’s death show not given were to be one and the same person, the
was the climax of this staging of voluntary death. The ancient Greek would be something like ‘to anybody
historian Tacitus devotes several chapters of his Annales requesting’, both words in the same case, i.e. dative,
to Seneca’s last act.44 especially as the words follow each other. Now the
First, Seneca’s veins and those of his young wife different cases, dative and nominative, are indicative
Paulina were cut by one stroke. Since Seneca’s aged that the two words are not be to be linked. The person
body, emaciated moreover by frugal living, did not who requests is not necessarily the person to whom the
produce much blood, the arteries in his legs and at the poison is (not) given. The Hippocratic doctor only
back of his knees were also opened. Even these measures swears that under no circumstance shall he lend himself
did not help. Next Seneca swallowed hemlock, a sacred to murder by poisoning on the request of a third person
method of death since Socrates the Athenians had been since, being in close contact with a patient, he was in a
executed by means of this poison. However, Seneca’s position to kill secretly.46 We should remember that the
body did not respond in the way expected. Finally, he fear of being poisoned was common in antiquity. Many
entered a warm bath, the idea being to make the blood a sudden death that was probably due to food poisoning
thinner. He sprinkled some water on the slaves who was ascribed to a criminal act. However, a patient who
surrounded him, saying that the liquid was a drink hired a Hippocratic physician could be sure that he did
offering to Jupiter the Liberator. So slaves were present not run the risk of being murdered by a criminal doctor.
as well as friends, who took notes of Seneca’s lengthy The argument that the oath formula was understood in
last words. Also a medical doctor was there, Statius antiquity to mean this is supported by the hexametric,
Annaeus. It was he who produced the poison on more elaborate version of the Oath: ‘Nor should
Seneca’s request. somebody by presents make me to commit a painful
trespass and to administer to a man harmful drugs that
will bring about a fatal evil.’ (Heiberg, 1927). In using
Medical assistance in a good death the words ‘fatal evil’ I render as neutrally as possible the
Greek thumophthoron kakot#eta, which rather means ‘a
Did this doctor breach his oath by furnishing Seneca
with the means to die? It is a widespread belief that
45
Hippocrates’ Oath forbade doctors to assist in suicide. Pious hopes from Scribonius Largus, a sentence in Gregory
Some in the medical field are still convinced of this, and of Nazianzus, Arabic reconstructions of Classical Antiquity,
think that their professional oath is based on the and the Constitutions of Melfi do not inspire great faith in the
traditional formula or at least implies the ancient pledge universality of the Oath, when contrasted with the numerous
occasions when one can state that the Oath was not sworn.
only to preserve life. 46
Even if one would argue that the passage refers to any
Firstly, we do not know whether Statius Annaeus assistance in bringing about death requested by the patient or a
belonged to the Hippocratici, who after all were only third person, the stress certainly is not on assisted suicide. The
one medical school. If their oath indeed did forbid them refusal to commit adikia also points to murder, for self-killing
was not regarded as a criminal act by ancient law, as was
44
15, 60–64. proven by Wacke (1980).
ARTICLE IN PRESS
984 A.J.L. Van Hooff / Social Science & Medicine 58 (2004) 975–985

deadly crime’. Also the word ‘trespass’ (paraibasi#en) In our medicalised world, the doctor is increasingly
points at a criminal context rather than one of placed in the moral position that priests used to have.
professional ethics. Most of all the pledge not to accept The ancient paradigm invites us to redefine the doctor’s
‘presents’ shows that murder by proxy is meant. Why role. Why should he be the arbiter of life and death,
should the patient wishing to die, or for that matter his instead of limiting his role to that of an instrument of
relatives, offer presents to the physician to induce him to euthanasia like his ancient colleague?
administer deadly drugs?
In modern times, Ludwich Edelstein, who was deeply
shocked by the perverse ‘euthanasia’ practices of Nazi
Acknowledgements
doctors, found in the Oath the magna carta of medical
pro-life ethics, a pledge valid for all times and all
Thanks are due to my colleague John Thorley of
doctors.47 His translation expressed his moral inter-
Lancaster University who corrected the English and
pretation: ‘I will neither give a deadly drug to anybody if
induced me by his comments to revise some of my
asked for it.’ (Edelstein, 1967). The Dutch historian of
arguments.
medicine Lindeboom was even more outspoken in his
translation: ‘I shall administer to nobody not even on his
request any deadly drug.’48 (the italics of ‘his’ are mine).
There is ample positive proof that ancient doctors References
were ready to assist in suicide, Seneca’s case being the
most famous of a euthanasia in the ancient sense, i.e. a Adkins, A.W. H. (1972). Moral values and political behaviour in
noble death. If physicians had no scruples in providing ancient Greece: From Homer to the end of the fifth century.
professional help to a healthy person who wanted to London: Chatto and Windus.
!
Ari"es, Ph. (1978). L’homme devant la mort. Paris: Editions du
leave life, why should they refuse to secure for their
Seuil.
patient a gentle death, a euthanasia in modern usage?
David, M. (transl.) (1967a). Life of Antoninus Pius 12. In The
The fact that ancient sources are silent on that topic is to scriptores historiae augustae I (p. 131). Cambridge, MA/
be explained by the fact that the ancient physician had a London: Heinemann.
position that radically differed from that of his modern David, M (transl.) (1967b). Life of Marcus Antoninus
colleague. philosopher 28. In The scriptores historiae augustae I (p.
203). Cambridge, MA/London.
Edelstein, L. (1967). The Hippocratic oath, In O. Temkin, &
C.L. Temkin (Eds.), Ancient medicine. Selected papers of
Relevance of the ancient euthanasia paradigm Ludwig Edelstein (pp. 3–67). Baltimore, reprint Baltimore/
London 1987.
In November 2001, a few months before the new Edmonds, J. M. (1961). The fragments of attic comedy, Vol. III
Dutch law on euthanasia came into force, the Dutch B. Leiden: Brill.
Association for Voluntary Euthanasia organised an .
Geist, H., Pfohl, G. (1976). Romische Grabinschriften (p. 167–172).
invitational conference on the association’s future task Munich: Heimeran.
now that it had achieved one of its major aims. I felt Heiberg, I.L. (Ed.) (1927). Corpus Medicorum Graecorum I.1.
much flattered to be invited among doctors, lawyers, (p. 5–6). Leipzig/Berlin. (in Greek)
Nutton, V. (1996). Hippocratic morality and modern medicine.
psychiatrists, pharmacologists and other experts. In my
In H. Flashar, & J. Jouanna (Eds.), M!edecine et morale dans
contribution, I stressed the element of volition in the l’antiquit!e (p. 46). Vandoeuvres-Gen"eve: Fondation Hardt.
ancient model of self-killing as an alternative to the von Staden, H (transl.) (1996). Personal and professional
modern approach. In the mors voluntaria, a medical conduct in the Hippocratic oath. Journal of Medicine and
doctor only acted as the instrument of the will of a Allied Sciences 51, 404–437, 407.
suicide, who was an agent rather than a patient. It was Suetonius (1920). Life of Augustus. Rolfe, J.C. (transl.) Cam-
not up to the doctor to decide whether life had lost its bridge, MA: Heinemann, 1920.
sense. He was only asked to present his expert view when .
Wacke, A. (1980). Der Selbstmord im romischen Rechts und
somebody considered ending his life because of serious inder Rechtsenwicklung. Zeitschrift der Savigny-Stiftung fur .
ailments, as Titius Aristo did, who opted for life ‘for the Rechtsgeschichte, 97, 26–77.
sake of his wife, daughters and friends’49

47
Ancient Medicine, Baltimore 1967, p. 9–20. Further reading
48
In the Dutch original: ‘Ik zal aan niemand, ook niet op zijn
verzoek, enig dodelijk geneesmiddel toedienen.’ G. A. Linde- Bremmer, J. (1983). The early greek concept of the soul.
boom, Hippocrates, Antwerpen/Amstersam 1949, 34. Linde- Princeton: Princeton University Press.
boom has denoted the Oath as the magna carta of medicine. Grmek, M. D. (1987). Les indicia mortis dans la m!edecine
49
Pliny Epistles 1,22,7–12. gr!eco-romaine. In F. Hinard (Ed.), La mort, les morts et la
ARTICLE IN PRESS
A.J.L. Van Hooff / Social Science & Medicine 58 (2004) 975–985 985

!
au-dela" dans le monde romain (pp. 129–144). Caen: Editions Jackson, R. (1995). Doctors and diseases in the Roman Empire.
Gallimard. London: British Museum Publications.
van Hooff, A. J. L. (1990). From autothanasia to suicide. Self- .
Pfannmuller, G. (1953). Tod, Jenseits und Unsterblichkeit in der
killing in classical antiquity. London/New York: Routledge. Religion, Literatur und Philosophie der Griechen und Romer, .
van Hooff, A. J. L. (1998/99). De antieke dokter en de dood Munich, Basel: Reinhardt.
(ancient doctor and death). Geschiedenis der Geneeskunde .
Rutten, T. (1997). Medizinethische Themen in den deontolo-
(History of Medicine), 5.5, 313–321. gischen Schriften des Corpus Hippocraticum. In M!ed!ecine
van Hooff, A. J. L. (2001). Thanatos und Asklepios. Wie antike et morale dans l’antiquit!e. Entretiens sur l’antiquit!e classique
.
Arzte zum Tod standen. In T. Schlich, & C. Wiesemann 43 (pp. 65–120, especially pp. 68–98). Vandoeuvres-Gen"eve:
(Eds.), Hirntod. Zur Kulturgeschichte der Todesfeststellung Fondation Hardt.
(pp. 85–101). suhrkamp taschenbucher . wissenschaft Sourvinou-Inwood, C. (1995). ‘Reading’ Greek death to the end
1525, Suhrkamp, Frankfurt am Main 2001, ISBN 3-518- of the classical period, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
29125-4. Toynbee, J. M. C. (1971). Death and burial in the Roman world.
Horstmanshoff, M. (1999). Ancient medicine between hope and London: Thames and Hudson.
fear: Medicament, magic and poison in the Roman Empire. Vermeule, E. (1979). Aspects of death in early Greek art and
European Review, 7.1, 7–51. poetry. Los Angeles: University of California Press.

You might also like