You are on page 1of 11

JAMES M.

FIELDING

An Aesthetics of the Ordinary: Wittgenstein


and John Cage

abstract
Comparisons of Ludwig Wittgenstein and John Cage typically focus on the “later Wittgenstein” of the Philosophical In-
vestigations. However, in this article I focus on the deep intellectual sympathy between the “early Wittgenstein” of the
Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus—with its evocative and controversial invocation of silence at the end, the famous proposition
7: “Whereof we cannot speak, thereof we must be silent”—and Cage’s equally evocative and controversial work on the same
theme—his “silent piece,” 4 33 . This sympathy expresses itself not only in the common aim of the two works (a mystical
appreciation for the ordinary, everyday world that surrounds us) but also in a shared methodology for bringing about this
aim (tracing the limits of language from within in order to transcend those very limits). In this sense, I argue that Cage’s work
gives a concrete, performative reality to Wittgenstein’s early conception of language as well as the mystical revelation that
lies behind it.

i. therefore be broken. As Wittgenstein notes in the


Philosophical Investigations in a remark designed
It is no longer surprising to discover comparisons to liberate the philosopher (or the composer, for
to Ludwig Wittgenstein in the literature on John that matter) from the positivist idea that certain
Cage; however, where references to Wittgenstein concepts are absolutely the correct ones and that
are made in relation to the avant-garde composer, having a different approach would mean, as he
it is by and large to the “later Wittgenstein” of the says, “not realizing something that we realize”:
Philosophical Investigations that they are made— “Let him imagine certain very general facts of na-
the Wittgenstein of language games, forms of life, ture to be different from what we are used to,
and strange tribes, the Wittgenstein for whom the and the formation of concepts different from the
meaning of a word is its use in our language.1 usual ones will become intelligible to him.”2 Con-
These comparisons are illuminating, particu- sidering the great body of Cage’s work—and the
larly in relation to those works of Cage that em- many concepts “different from the usual” that he
ploy semi- or even highly indeterminate nota- helped to make intelligible to us through the em-
tional forms (such as Imaginary Landscape No. ployment of just such an approach—we can see
4, which is realized by tuning twelve radios ac- that such comparisons with the later Wittgenstein
cording to a predetermined randomizing proce- are clearly fruitful.
dure). By the light of this comparison, the aim However, I would like to take a different
of such an approach to composition would be to tack here and focus rather on the early Wittgen-
reveal a musical “form of life” that we had pre- stein of the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus—
viously considered to be a given, but which is in with its evocative and controversial invocation
fact flexible, a normative practice that privileges of silence at the end, the famous proposition 7:
certain sounds above others and whose rules may “Whereof we cannot speak, thereof we must be

The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 72:2 Spring 2014


C 2014 The American Society for Aesthetics
158 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

silent”—and John Cage’s equally evocative and cerned. But neither do written notes seem at first
controversial work on the same theme—his “silent sight to be a picture of a piece of music, nor our
piece,” 4 33 .3 What is revealed in the comparison phonetic notation (the alphabet) to be a picture
of these two works extends far beyond a shared of our speech” (T 4.011). But these are, Wittgen-
conception of how language or music function as stein wants to suggest, indeed pictures, “even in
normative practices. What is revealed here, per- the ordinary sense” (T 4.011), like a tableau vivant
haps surprisingly, given Wittgenstein’s otherwise to which the facts of the world can correspond,
quite traditional musical tastes, is a rather deep whether as a matter of fact they do or do not.
ethical and aesthetic sympathy. This sympathy ex- Wittgenstein’s point here is that, no matter
presses itself not only in the common aim of the whether a particular proposition turns out to be
two works—a heightened appreciation for the or- true or false, the state of affairs that it describes
dinary, everyday world that surrounds us—but remains the same in either case. “It is important,”
also a shared methodology for bringing that aim Wittgenstein writes, “that saying ‘p’ and ‘p’ can
about in the minds of their respective audiences. say the same thing. . . . The propositions ‘p’ and
For what sets 4 33 apart from Cage’s other works, ‘p’ have the opposite sense, but there corre-
much like what sets Wittgenstein’s Tractatus apart sponds to them one and the same reality” (T
from his later works, such as the Philosophical 4.0621). The propositions ‘p’ and ‘p’ correspond
Investigations, is not the proliferation of non- or to the same reality, Wittgenstein argues here, sim-
semi-determinate linguistic forms, but rather its ply because the objects within these propositions
austere, orthodox formalism.4 are combined in a like manner. Despite their ap-
The features of the Tractarian methodology are parent differences in form, for example, the tilde
most clearly spelled out in Wittgenstein’s remarks sign in the second proposition, they both give us
on logic, although the comparison with music is the same picture of reality. They describe the same
not difficult to make. Wittgenstein’s discussion of state of affairs, only in the first this arrangement
musical notation in the work is understandably is affirmed and in the second it is denied.
overshadowed by the more weighty remarks on It is because such apparent irregularities do not
the structure of propositional language; however, impede the understanding of a phrase that various
in those remarks where Wittgenstein does touch notational forms, as well as the translations be-
on music, he nonetheless clearly expresses how tween them, are possible. As Wittgenstein notes
for him propositional language and musical nota- in regard to musical notation: “And if we pene-
tion are but two species of the same genera: the trate into the essence of this pictorial character,
relationship between the logical structure of rep- we see that it is not impaired by apparent irregu-
resentation and the states of affairs of the world larities (such as the use of  and  in musical no-
that are represented. Both are held to the same in- tation). For even these irregularities depict what
ternal laws and limited by the same boundary con- they are intended to express; only they do it in a
ditions. In this sense, it matters little for Wittgen- different way” (T 4.013). He expresses this idea in
stein whether we consider representation from the the Tractatus as follows: “In a proposition there
point of view of propositional language or musical must be exactly as many distinguishable parts as
notation. What matters for him is that a proposi- in the situation it represents. // The two must pos-
tion, like a musical composition, is not a chaotic sess the same logical (mathematical) multiplicity.
mixture of sound. They are both, in an identical (Compare Hertz’s Mechanics on dynamic mod-
sense, articulate. As he notes: “A proposition is els.)” (T 4.04). Drawing on the comparison with
not a blend of words.—(Just as a theme in music Hertz here, we can see clearly how Wittgenstein’s
is not a blend of notes.)” (T 3.141). understanding of “logical multiplicity” is indeed
What it means to be articulate in this sense is just that—logical, and not, for example, what we
that a proposition (or score) gives us a clear pic- might traditionally, and mistakenly from the point
ture of what is represented therein. Wittgenstein of view of the Tractatus, consider to belong to do-
admits that this idea, commonly known as his ‘pic- main ontology. Hertz expresses his understanding
ture theory of language,’ may at first seem un- of “dynamical model” thus:
canny: “At first sight a proposition—one set out
on the printed page, for example—does not seem A material system is said to be a dynamical model of a
to be a picture of the reality with which it is con- second system when the connections of the first can be
Fielding An Aesthetics of the Ordinary 159

expressed by such coordinates as to satisfy the following the symbolism, much as ‘0’ is part of the symbol-
conditions: (1) That the number of co-ordinates of the ism in mathematics” (T 4.4611). They are rather
first system is equal to the number of the second. (2) senseless (sinnlos), like logical placeholders, which
That with a suitable arrangement of the co-ordinates mark the limits of logical space and do not form a
for both systems the same equations of condition exist. substantial point within it. They are not, in other
(3) That by this arrangement of the co-ordinates the words, meaningful.
expression for the magnitude of a displacement agrees In this sense, the tautologies and contradictions
in both systems.5 of logic form the extreme limits of a kind of rule—
which Wittgenstein calls a “method” or “law of
On Wittgenstein’s account, it is precisely this projection”—according to which it is possible for
logical isomorphism that allows something—such language to be compared to reality at all. In terms
as a proposition or score—to serve as a model of of musical notation, Wittgenstein expresses this
something else at all. In terms of the comparison idea like so:
with Hertz, the most important aspect of that rela-
tion is given by Hertz’s requirement that, for one There is a general rule by means of which the mu-
system to serve as a model for another, both sys- sician can obtain the symphony from the score, and
tems must have the same “degree of freedom.” In which makes it possible to derive the symphony from
other words, even if it is not possible to find an the groove on the gramophone record, and using the
equivalent of each and every component, it must first rule, to derive the score again. That is what con-
nonetheless be possible for all of the salient com- stitutes the inner similarity between these things which
ponents to be mapped one to one. We need not seem to be constructed in such entirely different ways.
consider here, as Wittgenstein himself did, any- And that rule is the law of projection which projects the
thing more exotic than the courtroom reproduc- symphony into the language of musical notation. It is
tion of a car accident with model cars: despite the the rule for translating this language into the language
irregularities between the model and the real thing of gramophone records. (T 4.0141)
represented (ontological questions of scale, mate-
rial, and so on), it is not difficult to see how for any This is possible, he says, because the “gramophone
number of purposes the model will serve as well record, the musical idea, the written notes, and the
as, if not better than, the original.6 But it can do sound-waves, all stand to one another in the same
so only insofar as all the salient components may internal relation of depicting that holds between
be mapped one to one. language and world. They are constructed accord-
Wittgenstein clearly recognized, however, that ing to a common logical pattern” (T 4.014).
in order for a picture to be determinate it re- It is well known, however, that Wittgenstein’s
quired a frame—a “logical scaffolding,” as he calls aim in this work was not purely descriptive, in the
it (T 3.42)—upon which it is mounted and held sense that he did not seek merely to describe the
fast, so to speak. In the Tractatus these are tau- logical isomorphism of language and the world
tologies and contradictions. Tautologies and con- for the sake of itself. He sought rather to em-
tradictions represent for him the two extreme ploy this theory of language in order to solve
poles of language, which thus provide the space (definitively, so he claims) the problems of phi-
wherein the form of the picture is articulated but losophy, a practice which in his estimation tor-
which do not themselves partake in what is repre- ments itself by posing questions that cannot, in
sented there: “Contradiction, one might say, van- principle, be answered. By tracing the limits of
ishes outside all propositions: tautologies vanish language from within, Wittgenstein thus aimed to
inside them” (T 5.143). Though they are valid demonstrate that “the deepest problems [of phi-
propositions, formed according to rules of forma- losophy] are in fact not problems at all” (T 4.003;
tion, these “limit case” propositions do not rep- cf. pp. 3–4). Having overstepped the limits of lan-
resent states of affairs within the world. They are guage, such propositions—“whether the good is
not about anything in particular, and thus they more or less identical than the beautiful” is the
are not sensical (sinnig, in Wittgenstein’s original example Wittgenstein proposes here at 4.003, in a
German). Nor, however, do they fail to touch the conscious parody of Platonic reasoning—descend
world completely, and thus neither are they non- into a kind of indeterminate nonsense that fails to
sensical (unsinig): “They are,” he writes, “part of refer to anything at all, and, therefore, can have no
160 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

solution. “The riddle does not exist,” he notes. “If in negative terms for Cage. It is not an absence of
a question can be framed at all, it is also possible sound, like an empty box within which sound may
to answer it” (T 6.5). be placed. A box is still something in the world
Beyond questions of the true, the good, and the that can be perceived with the senses. Silence, on
beautiful, which are familiar from the history of the other hand, cannot be heard in the ordinary
philosophy, questions about the existence of the sense of the word—as Cage makes clear: there is
world, the meaning of life, or ethical imperatives no such thing as silence; however, silence is there.9
are also examples of such nonsense by this ac- And it can be attended to:
count. According to the famous conclusion of the
work, this “nonsense”—because it does not par- What interests me far more than anything that happens
take of the world, because it does not belong to is the fact of how it would be if nothing were happening.
the sphere of facts but rather values—must be Now, I want things that happen to not erase the spirit that
passed over silence. The value of the world, in was already there without anything happening. Now, this
other words, must be allowed to show itself. It thing that I mean when I say not anything happening is
cannot itself be put into words. As Wittgenstein what I call silence, that is to say, a state of affairs free of
noted in regard to the Tractatus, in a letter sent to intention, because we always have sounds, for instance.
the Viennese publisher Ludwig von Ficker upon Therefore we don’t have any silence available in the
the completion of the manuscript: world. We’re in a world of sounds. We call it silence, when
we don’t feel a direct connection with the intentions that
The book’s point is an ethical one. I once meant to in- produce sounds. We say that it’s quiet, when, due to our
clude in the preface perhaps the key to the work for you. non-intention, there don’t seem to us to be many sounds.
What I meant to write, then, was this: My work consists When there seem to us to be many, we say that it’s noisy.
of two parts, the one presented here plus all that I have But there is no real essential difference between a noisy
not written. And it is precisely this second part that is silence and a quiet silence. The thing that runs through
the important point. My book draws the limits to the from the quietness to the noise is a state of non-intention,
sphere of the ethical from the inside as it were, and I am and it is this state that interests me.10
convinced that this is the ONLY rigorous way of drawing
those limits. In short, I believe that where many others In this sense, silence is not just another sound, like
today are just gassing, I have managed in my book to put one extreme end of the scale ranging from ‘quiet’
everything firmly into place by being silent about it.7 to ‘loud.’ It is rather a state or ‘spirit,’ a relation to
the world in which the listener attends to sounds
This reflection on the ethical part of the work—the without forming a musical intention. Cage thus
important one—concludes with the following sug- conceives of silence not in terms of volume but
gestion: “For the time being, I’d recommend that in terms of the open space of possibility in which
you read the foreword and the conclusion since sounds may arise and fall away on their own ac-
these express the point most directly.”8 The con- cord, without our intervention. The task of the
clusion, of course, is the most forceful expression composer who would seek not to erase this spirit
of Wittgenstein’s ethical and spiritual quietism: is then to construct a work that allows one’s atten-
“Whereof we cannot speak, thereof we must be tion to be turned toward all sounds, without excep-
silent.” Though his ethical stance remains unex- tion, so that the space of music may be revealed for
pressed in the pages of the book, it is not absent for what it is in itself rather than for what it contains:
all that. Rather, because it remains unexpressed, “The prized or sought-for something (that is noth-
it is capable of permeating the entire work as a ing) is obtained. And that something—generating
whole. nothing—that is obtained is that each something
Turning toward John Cage’s 4 33 , we can begin is really what it is.”11 Being confronted by sounds
to see how such an understanding of logic is also in a new way, we attend to qualities—in the world,
at work in his “silent piece.” Like Wittgenstein’s certainly, but also in ourselves—that had previ-
“logical space,” Cage’s score is conceived in terms ously gone unnoticed. In the ordinariness of the
of an open space of possibility that frames the world with which we are confronted anew, an ef-
music articulated within it, though it does not itself faced and forgotten realm of value resurges. As
substantially partake in it. In the dependence of Cage notes: “A performance of this piece would
sound upon silence, silence is not to be thought of be a measure—as accurate as a mirror—of one’s
Fielding An Aesthetics of the Ordinary 161

‘poverty of spirit,’ without which, incidentally, one we take eternity to mean not infinite temporal du-
loses the kingdom of heaven.”12 ration but timelessness, then eternal life belongs
The aim of Cage’s work is not therefore only to those who live in the present” (T 6.4311). This
aesthetic but also ethical. Its aim, like that of the sentiment is repeated shortly thereafter in a re-
Zen Buddhism that inspired it, is to bring about mark that ties this redemptive sense of eternal life
a renewed relation to being that is no longer dis- in the present moment together with an apprecia-
torted by fear or neurosis. Cage recognized that tion of the givenness of the world that surrounds
such a feat would only be possible if silence can us: “To view the world sub specie aeterni is to
be recognized for being pregnant with sound—as view it as a whole—a limited whole. // Feeling the
we know, silence can be filled with an abundance world as a limited whole—it is this that is mystical”
of sound, or even be quite noisy—so that “not (T 6.45).
one sound fears the silence that extinguishes it,” It is in the mystical experience that the world ex-
as he says.13 The religious overtones are apparent ists, not in a description of how, that one renounces
here.14 But it is not a conventional religiosity, for intention. Wittgenstein thus arrives at this conclu-
the possibility of redemption rests not in an eter- sion by moving from sensical language about very
nal salvation beyond the grave but in the present worldly facts to the “senseless” limits of sense—
moment, where one can free oneself from self- tautology and contradiction—only to find that at
interested moral and aesthetic judgments, achiev- the end of that road, redemption lies in an ac-
ing an appreciation of the world as it is rather than knowledgment of the meaninglessness of the task
as it ought to be. itself. The work, as Wittgenstein makes clear in the
Shared by mystics of all stripes, it is not sur- penultimate section of the Tractatus, is the “last
prising to find a common ethical aim in Cage’s rung of the ladder” to be cast aside in order to see
4 33 and Wittgenstein’s Tractatus. For Wittgen- the world aright:
stein too would note—immediately preceding his
admission that “ethics and aesthetics are one and My propositions serve as elucidations in the following
the same” (T 6.421)—that: way: anyone who understands me eventually recognizes
them as nonsensical, when he has used them—as steps—
the sense of the world must lie outside the world. In the to climb up beyond them. (He must, so to speak, throw
world everything is as it is, and everything happens as it away the ladder after he has climbed up it.) . . . He must
does happen: in it no value exists—and if it did exist, it transcend these propositions, and then he will see the
would have no value. world aright. (T 6.54)

If there is any value that does have value, it must lie In this sense, Cage too sought to create a piece of
outside the whole sphere of what happens and is the music that would trace the limits of music “from
case. For all that happens and is the case is accidental. within,” employing formal notions reminiscent of
(T 6.41) those of tautology (the empty score, which ad-
mits all sound and excludes none) and contradic-
What is surprising, however, is the manner in tion (its ‘performance,’ by a pianist who plays the
which the two seek to bring about this mys- piece by precisely not playing). And like tautolo-
tical experience of value. Recall that Wittgen- gies and contradictions in the Tractatus, though
stein sought to trace the limits of language from 4 33 is constructed according to the valid rules
within in order to demonstrate that the ques- of musical composition, it remains senseless from
tions of philosophers—concerning, for example, this formal perspective. Cage’s work thus gives
the meaning of life, the good and the bad exercise a concrete, performative reality to Wittgenstein’s
of the will, and so on—are an unnecessary source understanding of the limits of language: “A tautol-
of frustration. Redemption resides in giving one- ogy leaves open to reality the whole—the infinite
self over to the present moment. As Wittgenstein whole—of logical space: a contradiction fills the
remarked in the preparatory notebooks to the whole of logical space leaving no point of it for re-
Tractatus: “Only a man who lives not in time but in ality. Thus neither of them can determine reality
the present is happy. For life in the present there is in any way” (T 4.463). If Cage has claimed that
no death.”15 Not in time, but in the present? In the 4 33 is “meaningless,” it may be thought of as so
pages of the Tractatus, Wittgenstein explains: “If in this sense and not because meaning had been
162 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

figure 1. Sebastian Virdung’s O heylige onbeflecte (1511) in its original notation.

figure 2. Opening of Virdung’s O heylige onbeflecte, showing in modern notation the change between alto and tenor registers,
which by the standards of modern notation is irregular.

defined too narrowly in the conventional aesthetic case of music, this allows not only for a score to
of the time, as has been argued. It is rather because go proxy for the piece itself or the gramophone
meaning, by its nature, must be about something. recording to go proxy for the score and so on but
And 4 33 is not about anything whereof one can it also allows for the translation between nota-
speak. tional forms. In this sense, having the correct logi-
cal multiplicity allows for the translation from one
language to another.
ii. If we consider, for example, the historical de-
velopment of musical notation, we can see from
Two cases can be brought to bear on this account the translation of a renaissance score into modern
of meaning that may help to make its central fea- notation in Figures 1 and 2 that the logical mul-
tures more clear: one from the history of mu- tiplicity is in this sense indeed sufficient to effec-
sical notation and the other from within Cage’s tively transpose the one into the other—despite
own avant-garde context. Recall that for Wittgen- any apparent irregularities, such as the unusual
stein, what is essential in propositional language, ‘cross-bars’ that represent here the shift of the
in other words what allows a propositional model alto and tenor voices into the vocal register of
to go proxy for what is represented there, is that the other, which would have no place in the origi-
the right logical multiplicity be incorporated into nal because of the manner in which that notation
the representation. As Wittgenstein notes in the symbolizes. The point is that these irregularities
Fielding An Aesthetics of the Ordinary 163

figure 3. John Cage’s 4 33 , transcribed in the notation of Virdung.

do not, in fact, mar the meaning of the original score” is that it is not only musical notation within
phrase or its translation; each is as articulate as which Cage’s 4 33 can be translated.
the other, though it expresses what it is intended It would certainly be impossible to translate
to express in a different way. Virdung’s O heylige onbeflecte into the logical
As Wittgenstein notes, “A proposition can de- space of color or of geometry in any determinate
termine only one place in logical space: never- way. The necessary logical multiplicity would not
theless the whole of logical space must already be met. The “degrees of freedom” would not al-
be given by it” (T 3.42). Sebastian Virdung’s O low for the salient components to be mapped one
heylige onbeflecte is, in this sense, a singular logical to one. However, for 4 33 , which has no content
point regardless of the notational form employed. whatsoever, there is no necessary degree of logi-
It occupies a particular place in the whole space of cal multiplicity that must be met. For indeed, any
musical possibility. And any space of musical pos- space will suffice; any notational system can, in
sibility will therefore be able to accommodate it. principle, be empty. Finding its home at the limits
“A picture can represent any reality whose form of language—in which case, it matters not whether
it has,” Wittgenstein notes: “A spatial picture can the language is the “language of music” or some-
depict anything spatial, a coloured one anything thing else, for, as Wittgenstein makes clear, the
coloured, etc.” (T 2.171), and naturally, we might limits are identical in every case—Cage’s 4 33 is
add, a musical picture anything musical. revealed as a logical picture existing beyond the
What is interesting about this example is the relatively constrained multiplicity of a strictly mu-
manner in which Cage’s 4 33 at once admits such sical form. As Wittgenstein notes, the propositions
a formal notion of translation and goes beyond of logic are all equivalent, for “all the proposi-
it. We might consider here, for example, how the tions of logic say the same thing, to wit nothing”
score from Cage’s 4 33 (composed, for all in- (T 5.43).
tents and purposes, in modern notation) is equally Leaving aside the difficult ontological ques-
transferable to the renaissance notational stan- tions of an artwork’s identity, we see that per-
dards of Virdung (see Figure 3). haps Cage had good reason to note of Robert
This should not surprise us, for we have already Rauschenberg’s White Paintings that “the white
seen that the content of renaissance music can be paintings came first, my silent piece second.”16 If
articulated in modern musical notation without Cage felt obliged to acknowledge that Rauschen-
any significant loss. Given this, it is not surpris- berg’s White Paintings came first, it can thus be
ing that the same applies in the reverse direction. argued that this is not merely an acknowledg-
However, what is noteworthy about the “empty ment of the historically situated development of
164 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

avant-garde aesthetics. Rather, if it is necessary But like Wittgenstein, Cage ultimately recog-
for Cage to acknowledge Rauschenberg’s “silent nized that the empty score would not in itself suf-
piece” in reference to his own, it is perhaps also fice to ensure that the final rung of the ladder had
because they are, in this formal sense, the same been cast aside. It is for this reason that, in silenc-
work. In other words, both works say the same ing the performer, it is essential that the performer
thing: to wit, nothing.17 be a virtuoso pianist and likewise that the audience
In Rauschenberg’s White Paintings—which members be seasoned concert goers, knowledge-
Cage described as “airports of lights, shadows, able of the aesthetic context in which the work
and particles”—Cage recognized an emptiness is being produced. For the self-repudiating ges-
in which the unintentional play of shadow and ture is only appropriate to the silence it intends
light would become, would be, the work, just as to reveal if the practice being repudiated is one
the unintentional atmospheric sounds would be that has already been mastered.21 Like Wittgen-
4 33 .18 As Cage noted, fusing the significance of stein, Cage was obliged to lead the listener along a
Rauschenberg’s work with his own in a manifesto path that would begin by entertaining one’s expec-
that describes precisely the sought-after “aesthet- tations, precisely so that those very expectations
ics of the ordinary,” which would transcend the could later be revealed for what they are in and
traditionally hierarchical order of art and every- of themselves and thus loosen their grip.22 For en-
day life: “The way to test modern painting is tering into this new relationship with the world
this: If it is not destroyed by the action of shad- requires a genuine acknowledgment of the extent
ows it is a genuine oil painting. A cough or a to which the old relationships—with their well-
baby cry will not ruin a good piece of modern entrenched divisions between music and “mere
music.”19 sound,” for example, or between right and wrong,
Regardless of the ontological qualities that al- between our likes and our dislikes—permeate ev-
low what we would traditionally consider to be erything we see, hear, or say. Then and only then,
Cage’s 4 33 to be recorded on a gramophone if indeed such a state of nonintention can indeed
record and Rauschenberg’s White Paintings to be emerge, will the final rung of the ladder have been
reprinted in a magazine, they are in the logical cast aside. The work itself will no longer be impor-
sense outlined here identical (analogous, for ex- tant. As Cage would later joke—and we might
ample, to an audio recording of speech and its recall here that it was Wittgenstein who would
typewritten transcript). Each serves as a perfect famously remark that a perfectly good work of
model for the other, for they are constructed philosophy could be written consisting of nothing
according to a common logical pattern. As we but jokes—“No day goes by without my making
may translate Virdung’s work from renaissance to use of that piece in my life and my work. I listen
modern notation and recognize in it the same work to it everyday.”23
regardless of the surface irregularities, also be- The humor inherent in Cage’s remark may
tween these two works nothing essential is either tempt us to view his use of silence as ironic; how-
gained or lost in the translation. It is for this same ever, this temptation should be avoided. In his
reason, furthermore, that Cage was able to pro- work, as in Wittgenstein’s, it is not the silence that
duce a third version of 4 33 , which consisted only is ironic. It is rather his use of language that is
of three Roman numerals indicating the move- ironic. It is the self-repudiating gesture: the empty
ments of the piece and the word ‘TACET’ after score, the mute performer, the claim that every-
each one (this being the word used in orchestra- thing that has led up to this moment in the work
tion to indicate that a particular instrument should is so much nonsense. But that is only the first part
remain silent during the movement).20 Words spo- of the work, the part written down, recorded and
ken or written, paint, sound: a great gulf may be reprinted, stored in libraries, performed in concert
said to separate them ontologically. And the same halls. Dependent on the normative rules of forma-
might be said from the perspective of a traditional tion, the expectations of the audience or reader,
aesthetics, for certainly the faculties of the human the historical tradition that has been handed down
body that each are consequently able to engage to us, it is only this part that is ironic. If the work
differ greatly. However, from the logical point of itself is the final rung of the ladder, which must
view of Wittgenstein’s Tractatus, these are but su- be cast aside in order to see the world aright—
perficial irregularities. that is, to see the world as it is, simply there,
Fielding An Aesthetics of the Ordinary 165

ordinary and ultimately indifferent to our expec- which the notions at the heart of this critique con-
tations and evaluations—it is into the silence that tinued to evolve in the later work—which prob-
it is thrown. The difficulty is to realize that this lematize certain aspects of the characterization to
second part, the important one, is always there follow, specifically, concerning the role of proposi-
waiting to receive it. tions of natural science, but this need not concern
us here—this antiphilosophical task nonetheless
finds its clearest expression in the final pages of
iii. Wittgenstein’s earliest work:

In the Tractatus Wittgenstein famously claimed The correct method in philosophy would really be the
“to have found, on all essential points, the fi- following: to say nothing except what can be said, i.e.
nal solution to the problems [of philosophy].”24 propositions of natural science—i.e. something that has
Looking back, we know that this confidence would nothing to do with philosophy—and then, whenever
not be long-lived. Upon Wittgenstein’s return to someone else wanted to say something metaphysical,
philosophy in the 1930s, after a decade-long hia- to demonstrate to him that he had failed to give a mean-
tus following the publication of the Tractatus, his ing to certain signs in his propositions. Although it would
approach to philosophy had radically changed. not be satisfying to the other person—he would not have
He recognized “grave mistakes” in his earlier the feeling that we were teaching him philosophy—this
work.25 Where he had previously sought to trace method would be the only strictly correct one. (T 6.53)
the transcendental limits of language from within,
Wittgenstein later sought a higher vantage point, Undoubtedly the question of the continuity or dis-
what he described as a “synoptic view” or “per- continuity of Wittgenstein’s thought is a difficult
spicuous representation” (Übersichtliche Darstel- one, and perhaps no definitive answer will ever
lung). In the place of “the general form of the be found. However, from out of the comparison
proposition” outlined in the Tractatus, he later presented here, one possibility worth considering
sought (as did Cage) to experiment with a com- presents itself: as Cage makes abundantly clear, in
plex collage of phenomena on the basis of lived renouncing intention, one renounces the capac-
experience. ity to be critical of the world and of anything that
With this movement toward a plurality of lin- happens within it; we might wonder, then, whether
guistic forms, the notion of a singular and sta- Wittgenstein rejected the doctrines of the Tracta-
ble limit to language had to be abandoned for tus, which similarly professes to advocate such a
Wittgenstein, and so—it would appear—would state of nonintention, so that the critical faculties
the silence that had lain beyond that limit in of his Sprachkritik could be preserved.
his earlier work. Cage, however, who nonethe- Whether or not this is indeed the case is a mat-
less consistently employed a technique very rem- ter of dispute, and for good reason; however, from
iniscent of the “second Wittgenstein” throughout this we can nonetheless see that, despite their
his career, considered 4 33 to be among his best many great similarities, there is at least one fun-
works. To what might we attribute this different damental difference between the Wittgenstein of
attitude toward the silence that both thinkers had the Tractatus and the Cage of 4 33 . Wittgenstein
once invoked as the final step on the journey wanted to abolish the problems of philosophy by
back from theoretical abstraction to the ordinary showing that, at bottom, they are not problems
world? at all. Cage, on the other hand, would not have
In order to begin answering such a question we wanted to ‘abolish’ music in any sense of the word.
must not forget that Wittgenstein wished above He wanted rather to expand the possibilities of
all for his philosophy to be critical. “All philos- music, to open them up to the whole world of
ophy,” he writes in the Tractatus, “is a critique sounds—intentional as well as nonintentional. As
of language (Sprachkritik)” (T 4.0031). Despite Cage notes, his 4 33 would not be ruined by a
the great differences in form and content between baby’s cry. Likewise, neither would it be ruined by
the early Wittgenstein of the Tractatus and the a classical symphony performed in the next hall
later Wittgenstein of Philosophical Investigations, over. As the example of Virdung’s O heylige on-
if there is a single thread that runs throughout his beflecte makes clear, such traditional forms of mu-
work, it is very likely this. While the manner in sical composition are not capable of effacing the
166 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

ordinary world that Cage sought to deliver us unto which claims that only the form of the expression has
in 4 33 —if they are listened to in the right spirit. changed while the message of his philosophy remains es-
sentially the same. In what follows, I assume a modest “two
For the Wittgenstein of the Tractatus, there is no
Wittgensteins” view and hope that this will highlight the fe-
such spirit in which the nonsense he sought to cundity of the traditional reading. For more on the debate
quiet—which is to say, metaphysical speculation— surrounding this issue, see Alice Crary and Rupert Read,
may be embraced without effacing the ordinary, eds., The New Wittgenstein (London: Routledge, 2000).
nonmetaphysical world. For him, philosophical 5. Heinrich Hertz, The Principles of Mechanics Pre-
sented in a New Form, trans. D. E. Jones and J. T. Wal-
discourse can in no way become just another part ley (London, 1899; reprint, New York: Dover, 1956), §418,
of the world, something that “happens within it,” p. 175.
a state of affairs to be embraced along with all 6. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Notebooks 1914–1916, ed. G.
the others. If Wittgenstein later rejected the strict, H. von Wright and G. E. M. Anscombe, trans. G. E. M.
Anscombe (University of Chicago Press, 1979), p. 7.
formal framework of the Tractatus, where Cage
7. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Prototractatus: An Early Ver-
exalted 4 33 as his best work, perhaps it is then sion of Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, ed. B. F. McGuin-
for this reason. The silence in Cage’s 4 33 is called ness, T. Nyberg, and G. H. von Wright, trans. D. F. Pears
upon not in order to abolish music but in order to and B. F. McGuinness (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul,
transcend the hierarchical order of aesthetic judg- 1971), p. 16.
8. Wittgenstein, Prototractatus, p. 16.
ment that separates music and nonmusic, our likes 9. I owe this formulation to Kyle Gann’s superb mono-
from our dislikes, and—in the end—sense from graph No Such Thing as Silence, in which he notes the in-
nonsense. It is difficult to imagine that Wittgen- accurate characterization of 4 33 as Cage’s “silent piece”:
stein would have been willing to walk such a “4 33 is often mischaracterized as Cage’s ‘Silent Sonata,’
but the point is that it is not silent, that there is no such thing
path.
as silence; ‘Unintended Noise Sonata’ would come closer
to the truth” (No Such Thing as Silence: John Cage’s 4 33
JAMES M. FIELDING [Yale University Press, 2010], p. 163).
Université Paris I Sorbonne 10. John Cage, “Interview with R. Smalley and D.
Sylvester,” British Broadcasting Corporation, December
Paris, France
1966; partial transcription available as “John Cage (1966),”
internet: James.Fielding@malix.univparis1.fr in Interviews with American Artists, ed. David Sylvester
(Yale University Press, 2001), pp. 107–129, at p. 123.
11. John Cage, “Lecture on Something,” in Silence: Lec-
1. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, tures and Writings (Wesleyan University Press, 1961), pp.
ed. G. E. M. Anscombe and R. Rhees, trans. G. E. M. 128–145, at p. 141.
Anscombe (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1953). Most notably, it 12. John Cage, A Year from Monday: New Lectures and
is Marjorie Perloff who has engaged both Wittgenstein and Writings (Wesleyan University Press, 1967), p. 9. An ex-
John Cage, referencing Wittgenstein widely in the context cellent illustration of this ethical dimension of the silence
of Cage’s work and in the context of avant-garde aesthetics invoked by Cage can be found in Arthur Danto’s reply to
more generally. (Compare Marjorie Perloff, The Poetics of Lydia Goehr. (See Goehr, “For the Birds / Against the Birds:
Indeterminacy: From Rimbaud to Cage [Princeton Univer- Modernist Narratives of Danto and Adorno (and Cage),”
sity Press, 1981], and Wittgenstein’s Ladder: Poetic Language in Action, Art, History: Engagements with Arthur C. Danto,
and the Strangeness of the Ordinary [University of Chicago ed. Daniel Herwitz and Michael Kelly [Columbia Univer-
Press, 1996].) However, Perloff herself admits that she had sity Press, 2007], pp. 43–73, 79–81, and Danto, “Response,”
misunderstood proposition 7 of the Tractatus in her ear- in Action, Art, History, pp. 73–79.) Regarding the tension be-
lier work, The Poetics of Indeterminacy, and subsequently tween the optimism and pessimism that Danto and Adorno
makes no attempt to reexamine the question (Wittgenstein’s feel, respectively, in the face of avant-garde works such as
Ladder, p. xii). Cage’s 4 33 , Danto notes: “[Adorno’s] was a deep pes-
2. Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, p. 230. simism, with settled dispositions, and he was something of a
3. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logico- scold. Mine, by contrast, was a deep optimism. Wittgenstein
Philosophicus, trans. C. K. Ogden (London: Routledge & said that the worlds of the happy and the unhappy differ,
Kegan Paul, 1922), p. 155. All further references to the but Adorno’s world and mine differed actually, and I don’t
principal text of the Tractatus will be to Tractatus Logico- know that my optimism would have survived, living through
Philosophicus, trans. D. F. Pears and B. F. McGuinness what he did” (Danto, “Response,” p. 76).
(London and New York: Routledge, 1974), and indicated Danto is referring here to a remark in the Tractatus: “If
by T, followed by the proposition number. the good or bad exercise of the will does alter the world,
4. There is a growing body of literature on the pre- it can alter only the limits of the world, not the facts—not
cise contours of the similarities and differences between the what can be expressed by means of language. // In short
Tractatus and Philosophical Investigations, out of which has the effect must be that it becomes an altogether different
developed two conflicting readings: the more traditional one world. It must, so to speak, wax and wane as a whole. //
that assumes a “Wittgenstein I” and “Wittgenstein II” and The world of the happy man is a different one from that
the other a greater or lesser “mono-Wittgensteinianism,” of the unhappy man” (T 6.43). Danto’s remark suggests a
Fielding An Aesthetics of the Ordinary 167

misunderstanding of the formal aspects of the Tractatus— white that erases any accidental visual trace the work comes
in whose terms Danto and Adorno precisely do live in the to bare.
same world (of facts), so that if one hears beauty where the 18. Cage, “On Robert Rauschenberg,” p. 98.
other hears terror, this reflects rather a shift in the limits of 19. Cage, “45 for a Speaker,” p. 161.
their respective worlds in terms of value (and not the facts 20. Similarly, we might add, not even is duration—often
that make up its substance). considered, for good reason, to be the minimal ontological
13. Cage, “45 for a Speaker,” in Silence, pp. 146–192, substratum for a musical work—a salient part of the work;
at p. 173. for Cage admitted that he was unsure of the proper duration
14. In this respect, it is no coincidence that Cage’s and that perhaps he made a mistake in addition, and further
first reference to the work in “A Composer’s Confession,” entitled the second version of the work 0 00 (in a reference
four years before 4 33 was completed, was entitled “A to Christian Wolff’s “zero time”).
Silent Prayer” (“A Composer’s Confession,” in John Cage, 21. Daniel Herwitz expresses the significance of this
Writer: Previously Uncollected Pieces, ed. Richard Koste- performative gesture well when he notes: “First performed
lanetz [New York: Limelight Editions, 1993], pp. 27–44, at by David Tudor in Woodstock, New York in 1952, 4 33
p. 43). It is difficult not to recall here the well-known tale was inspired by an ‘artwork’ by Robert Rauschenberg, who
of Bertrand Russell’s, concerning one of the frequent ex- erased a fine drawing by Willem de Kooning (de Kooning
changes he had with the young Wittgenstein at the time he agreed to this erasure on condition that it be a first-class
was composing the Tractatus: “He used to come to see me ev- work of his that would be erased). Similarly, 4 33 ‘erases’
ery evening at midnight, and pace up and down the room like music (or, as the French would say, places it sous-rature): it
a wild beast for three hours in agitated silence. Once I said consists of four minutes and thirty-three seconds of silence.
to him: ‘Are you thinking about logic, or about your sins?’ . . . A gesture of silencing the performer (who does nothing
‘Both,’ he replied, and continued his pacing” (Bertrand but turn the pages of the score), it is important that the per-
Russell, Autobiography [London: Routledge, 1988], p. 330). former be a pianist, that he or she be very good at playing
15. Wittgenstein, Notebooks 1914–1916, p. 74. musical notes; for then, like a good de Kooning drawing, the
16. John Cage, “On Robert Rauschenberg, Artist and musician’s gesture is truly one of dropping a practice that
His Work,” in Silence, pp. 98–108, at p. 98. he or she has already mastered—of dropping it in the name
17. In this sense we need not see any tension, as Danto of entering into a new relation to music and sound. In this
appears to, between Cage’s approach to the indeterminacy breaking down of the very distinction between sound and
of a work and Rauschenberg’s: “It is widely known that music, what is at stake is the capacity to hear in a way that
4 33 was inspired by Robert Rauschenberg’s white paint- is open to the unexpected, the ordinary, the not so fancy”
ings, done when he was at Black Mountain College in 1951. (Daniel Herwitz, “John Cage,” in Encyclopedia of Aesthet-
Cage said that he saw them as ‘airports for shadows and ics, Vol. I, ed. Michael Kelly [Oxford University Press, 1998],
dust’—or ‘mirrors for air.’ The deep point was that they were pp. 325–327, at p. 326).
no more empty than his own 1952 composition was silent. 22. It is in this sense that if, as discussed above, Danto
The panels themselves collaborated, one might say, with the experiences a deep sense of optimism at the emancipation of
environment, so that the ambient lights and shadows be- art from philosophy in the works of the avant-garde, where
came a part of the art, instead of being aesthetically erased Adorno experiences only pessimism and doubt, this too be-
in order to allow a response to the pure, unsullied blank. longs to the logic of the work. As Wittgenstein would note
If a wayward pigeon dropped shat on the white, that would in the Tractatus: “The subject does not belong to the world:
be part of the work, at least in Cage’s view. (Rauschen- rather, it is a limit of the world” (T 5.632). It is only in our
berg, on the other hand, stipulated that the panels be re- reaction to the work that this realm of value reveals itself,
painted, to keep them fresh)” (Arthur C. Danto, “Upper and in works such as 4 33 or Rauschenberg’s White Paint-
West Side Buddhism,” in Buddha Mind in Contemporary ings this value is revealed purely in and of itself, for there is
Art, ed. Jacquelynn Baas and Mary Jane Jacob [University nothing in the work about which we might form a particular
of California Press, 2004], pp. 49–59, at p. 56). By the account intention; it is only presenting the everyday world that is
presented here, we can see that Rauschenberg had to make always already there. At the limit, confronted by the world
such a stipulation; however, this was not in order to keep in its totality, without exception, one only confronts oneself.
the work “ontologically pure” but logically pure, in order to 23. Quoted in William Duckworth, “Anything I Say
avoid, for example, the work becoming about something in Will Be Misunderstood: An Interview with John Cage,” in
the world—such as the onto-genetic history of layered pi- John Cage at Seventy-Five, ed. Richard Fleming and William
geon shit, and so on. As Cage notes about his own work, dis- Duckworth (Bucknell University Press, 1989), pp. 15–33, at
cussed above, it was necessary to construct a space in which p. 21.
“not one sound fears the silence that extinguishes it” (“45 24. Wittgenstein, Tractatus, p. 4.
for a Speaker,” p. 173). Nor, in Rauschenberg’s case, the 25. Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, p. x.

You might also like