You are on page 1of 14

CHAPTER 18
Cognitive Psychology

Cognitive psychology includes such topics as mem- Developments before 1950


ory, concept formation, attention, reasoning, prob-
lem solving, judgment, and language. Clearly cogni- Throughout most of psychology’s history human
tive psychology is very popular within contemporary attributes were studied philosophically. J. S. Mill
psychology. However, in psychology’s long history (1843/1988) set the stage for psychology as an exper-
some form of cognition has almost always been em- imental science and encouraged the development of
phasized. The few exceptions included the material- such a science. Fechner (1860/1966) took Mill’s lead
istic philosophies or psychologies of Democritus, and studied cognitive events (sensations) experimen-
Hobbes, Gassendi, La Mettrie, Watson, and Skinner, tally. Ebbinghaus (1885/1964), under the influence
which denied the existence of mental events. The of Fechner, studied learning and memory experimen-
schools of voluntarism and structuralism concen- tally. William James’s The Principles of Psychology
trated on the experimental study of cognition, and (1890) cited considerable research on cognition and
the school of functionalism studied both cognition suggested many additional research possibilities. Sir
and behavior. The supposed sterility of the research Frederick Charles Bartlett (1886–1969), in Remem-
on cognition performed by members of these schools bering: A Study in Experimental and Social Psychology
prompted Watson to create the school of behavior- (1932), demonstrated how memory is influenced
ism. Thus to say, as is common, that psychology is be- more by personal, cognitive themes or schema than
coming more cognitively oriented is inaccurate, be- by the mechanical laws of association. In other
cause with only a few exceptions it has always been words, he found that information is always encoded,
cognitively oriented. But there was a period from stored, and recalled in terms of an individual’s pre-
about 1930 to about 1950 when radical behaviorism conceptions and attitudes.
was highly influential, and when it was widely be- As early as 1926 Jean Piaget (1896–1980) began
lieved that cognitive events either did not exist or, if publishing research on intellectual development.
they did, were simply by-products (epiphenomena) During his long life Piaget published more than 50
of brain activity and could be ignored. As long as books and monographs on genetic epistemology or
these beliefs were dominant, the study of cognitive developmental intelligence. In general, Piaget dem-
processes was inhibited. onstrated that a child’s interactions with the en-
We mention here only a few of the people and vironment become more complex and adaptive as
events that helped loosen the grip of radical behav- its cognitive structure becomes more articulated
iorism, thus allowing cognitive psychology to gain its through maturation and experience. According to
current popularity. For more see, for example, Ma- Piaget, the cognitive structure comprises schemata
honey, 1991, pp. 69–75. that determine the quality of one’s interactions with

537

Wadsworth Publishing Co.


Hergenhahn: Introduction to the History of Psychology, 4/e CHAPTER 18 / BOOK PAGE 537
å Typecast, Inc. / Job #0981 / July 2000 SECOND PROOF
538 Chapter 18

the environment. For the young child, these sche- did much to reduce its influence. In his book The Or-
mata are sensory motor reflexes that allow only the ganization of Behavior (1949), Hebb not only sought
most rudimentary interactions with the environ- biological explanations of behavior but also urged
ment. With maturation and experience, however, the study of cognitive processes. As we shall see in
the schemata become more cognitive and allow in- chapter 19, Hebb continued to encourage the devel-
creasingly complex (intelligent) interactions with opment of both physiological and cognitive psychol-
the environment. For Piaget, it was always the ogy in the 1950s and 1960s. In 1949 Harry Harlow
schemata contained within the cognitive structure (1905–1981) published “The Formation of Learning
that determine what kinds of interactions with the Sets,” which provided evidence that monkeys em-
environment are possible. Piaget’s theory followed ploy mental strategies in their solving of discrimina-
the rationalistic rather than empiricistic tradition. tion problems. This finding was clearly in conflict
More particularly, because it stressed the importance with the behavioristic psychology of the time.
of schemata for determining a person’s reality, it fol- In 1948 Norbert Wiener (1894–1964) defined
lowed the Kantian tradition. Piaget wrote books cybernetics as the study of the structure and function
about the child’s conceptions of causality, reality, of information-processing systems. Of particular in-
time, morality, and space, all showing the influence terest to Wiener was how mechanical or biological
of Kant’s proposed categories of thought. It is inter- systems can achieve a goal or maintain a balance by
esting to note that Piaget was an even more prolific automatically utilizing feedback from their activi-
writer than Wundt. In chapter 9 we noted that ties. The automatic pilots on airplanes and ther-
Wundt published 53,735 pages in his lifetime, or mostats are examples of such systems. Soon it was re-
2.20 pages a day; Zusne and Blakely (1985) report alized that purposive human behavior could also be
that Piaget published 62,935 pages in his lifetime, or explained in such mechanistic terms, thus overcom-
2.46 pages a day. ing the argument that the study of purposive (goal-
As we have seen, Gestalt psychology and radical directed) behavior must necessarily be subjective. In
behaviorism were created about the same time (1912 1949 Claude E. Shannon, working for the Bell Tele-
and 1913, respectively), and the cognitively oriented phone Laboratories, and Warren Weaver, working
Gestalters were a constant thorn in the side of the for the Rockefeller Foundation, were seeking ways of
behaviorists. Also, during the 1930s and 1940s, improving the purity of messages between the time
methodological behaviorists such as Hull and Tol- they are sent and the time they are received. The
man were willing to postulate events that intervene work of Shannon and Weaver began what came to
between stimuli (S) and responses (R). For Hull, be called information theory. Information theory
these intervening variables are mainly physiological, notes the various transformations information un-
but for Tolman they are mainly cognitive. dergoes as it enters a communication system, as it
In 1942 Carl Rogers (1902–1987) published operates within the system, and as it leaves the sys-
Counseling and Psychotherapy: Newer Concepts in tem. As we will see later in this chapter, informa-
Practice that challenged both radical behaviorism tion-processing psychology, like information theory,
and psychoanalysis by emphasizing the importance attempts to understand those structures, processes,
of conscious experience in the therapeutic situation. and mechanisms that determine what happens to in-
In 1943 Abraham Maslow (1908–1970) first pro- formation from the time it is received to the time it
posed his theory of human motivation based on the is acted on.
hierarchy of needs. In spite of the efforts of individu-
als such as Rogers and the popularity of behaviorism
during the 1920s, 1930s, and 1940s, psychoanalysis
Developments during the 1950s
remained very influential, especially among clinical According to Bernard Baars (1986), “There is little
psychologists and psychiatrists. Donald Hebb (1904– doubt that George A. Miller . . . has been the single
1985) was an early critic of radical behaviorism and most effective leader in the emergence of cognitive

Wadsworth Publishing Co.


Hergenhahn: Introduction to the History of Psychology, 4/e CHAPTER 18 / BOOK PAGE 538
å Typecast, Inc. / Job #0981 / July 2000 SECOND PROOF
Cognitive Psychology 539

In 1951 Karl Lashley (1890–1958) argued that


the explanation of serial or chained behavior, offered
by the behaviorists, that stressed the importance of
external stimulation was insufficient. Rather, he said,
such organized behavior could emanate only from
within the organism. In an influential publication,
“Drives and the C.N.S. (Conceptual Nervous Sys-
tem)” (1955), Hebb continued to show his willing-
ness to “physiologize” about cognitive processes and
thus to engage in battle with the behaviorists. Leon
Festinger (1919–1989) noted that the ideas one en-
george a. miller

tertains may be compatible with or incompatible


with one another. Incompatibility exists, for exam-
ple, if one is engaged in an obviously boring task but
is encouraged to describe it as exciting, or if one
George A. Miller smokes cigarettes and yet believes that smoking
causes cancer. When ideas are incompatible, a state
of dissonance exists that motivates a person to
psychology” (p. 198). Miller remembers that, during change beliefs or behavior. In the cases above, for ex-
the 1950s, “‘cognition’ was a dirty word because cog- ample, a person could reduce cognitive dissonance
nitive psychologists were seen as fuzzy, hand-waving, by telling the truth about the task being boring or be-
imprecise people who really never did anything that come convinced that the task is actually exciting.
was testable” (p. 254). Miller argued that modern With the smoker, cognitive dissonance could be re-
cognitive psychology began during a symposium on duced by quitting the habit or by believing there re-
information theory sponsored by the Massachusetts ally is no proven relationship between smoking and
Institute of Technology on September 10–12, 1956. cancer. Festinger’s influential book A Theory of Cog-
During the symposium, Allen Newell and Herbert nitive Dissonance (1957) made no reference to behav-
Simon presented papers on computer logic, Noam ioristic ideas. In the early 1950s Jerome Bruner be-
Chomsky presented his views on language as an in- came interested in thinking and concept formation
herited, rule-governed system, and Miller described and in 1955 he assisted Sir Frederic Bartlett in ar-
his research demonstrating that people can discrimi- ranging, at Cambridge, one of the first conferences
nate only seven different aspects of something—for on cognitive psychology (Bruner, 1980). In 1956
example, hues of color or pitches of sound. Also, Bruner, along with Jacqueline Goodnow and George
people can only retain about seven meaningful units Austin, published A Study in Thinking, which em-
of experience (chunks) such as numbers, words, or phasized concept learning. Although concept learn-
short sentences. Miller summarized his research in ing had been studied earlier by Hull and Thorndike,
his influential article “The Magical Number Seven, their explanations of such learning were couched
Plus or Minus Two: Some Limits on Our Capacity for in terms of passive, associationistic principles. The
Processing Information” (1956). Participants in the explanation offered by Bruner and his colleagues
MIT symposium did much to bring the terminology stressed the active utilization of cognitive strategies
and concepts of information theory and cybernetics in such learning. In 1959 Tracy and Howard Kendler
into psychology. At about the same time, the English analyzed childrens’ discrimination learning in terms
psychologist Donald Broadbent (1957, 1958) was of concept utilization rather than in terms of behav-
doing the same thing. Crowther-Heyck (1999) dis- ioristic principles. Also in 1959 Chomsky published
cusses the importance of Miller’s work in the early his influential review of Skinner’s book Verbal Learn-
development of cognitive psychology. ing (1957). We will have more to say about Chom-

Wadsworth Publishing Co.


Hergenhahn: Introduction to the History of Psychology, 4/e CHAPTER 18 / BOOK PAGE 539
å Typecast, Inc. / Job #0981 / July 2000 SECOND PROOF
540 Chapter 18

sky’s review in chapter 19 when we discuss behav- ioristic phase and it produced precise, factual knowl-
ioral genetics. edge and scientific rigor that had not previously ex-
Also during the 1950s, humanistic theorists such isted in psychology. However, in their effort to be
as Maslow, Kelly, Rogers, and May continued devel- entirely objective the behaviorists had minimized or
oping their ideas, as did the Gestalt psychologists banished such topics as thought, imagery, volition,
and the psychoanalysts. and attention. Hebb urged that the second phase
of psychology’s revolution use the scientific rigor
promoted by the behaviorists to study the long-
Developments after the 1950s neglected cognitive processes. Concerning the sec-
In 1960 Miller and his colleagues Eugene Galanter ond phase of the revolution, Hebb (1960) said, “The
and Karl Pribram published Plans and the Structure of camel already has his nose inside the tent” (p. 741).
Behavior, in which it was argued that cybernetic con- He noted the works of Festinger, Broadbent, Kendler
cepts (such as information feedback) explain human and Kendler, Miller, Galanter, and Pribram as good
goal-directed behavior better than S–R concepts do, starts toward a rigorous cognitive psychology. He was
and at least as objectively. Also in 1960 Miller and especially impressed by the possibility of the com-
Jerome Bruner founded the Center for Cognitive puter acting as a model for studying cognitive pro-
Studies at Harvard. In addition to promoting re- cesses. He prophesized that such a model will be-
search on cognitive processes, the center did much come “a powerful contender for the center of the
to popularize the ideas of Piaget among U.S. psychol- stage” (1960, p. 741). Hebb’s preferred approach to
ogists. In 1962 Miller published an article entitled studying cognitive processes was to speculate about
“Some Psychological Studies of Grammar” (1962a), their biological foundations. We will have more to
which introduced Chomsky’s nativistic analysis of say about Hebb when we consider psychobiology in
language into psychology. In 1890 William James chapter 19.
had defined psychology as “the science of mental In 1962 and 1963 M. D. Egger and Neal Miller
life”; in 1962 Miller purposefully used James’s defini- demonstrated that, contrary to tradition, classical
tion as the title of his text Psychology: The Science of conditioning phenomena could not be explained in
Mental Life (1962b). terms of associative principles alone. Rather the in-
In 1963 as evidence of how far cognitive psychol- formation conveyed by the stimuli involved had to
ogy had progressed and in recognition of Miller’s role be taken into consideration. In 1967 Ulric Neisser,
in that progress, Miller was presented a Distin- who studied with George Miller, published his influ-
guished Scientific Contribution Award by the APA. ential book Cognitive Psychology, in which Neisser
Miller served as president of the APA in 1969, re- defined the term cognition as, “All the processes by
ceived the Gold Medal for Life Achievement in Psy- which . . . sensory input is transformed, reduced,
chological Science from the American Psychological elaborated, stored, recovered and used” (p. 4). Also
Foundation (APF) in 1990, and was Awarded a Na- in this book, Neisser attempted to integrate research
tional Medal of Science by President George Bush in on such topics as perception, concept formation,
1991. Miller is currently professor emeritus and se- meaning, language, and thinking, using a few con-
nior research psychologist at Princeton University. cepts adopted primarily from information theory.
In 1959 Donald Hebb served as president of the Once the grip of behaviorism—especially radical
APA, and his presidential address “The American behaviorism—had been loosened many earlier ef-
Revolution” was published in 1960. In this address, forts in experimental cognitive psychology were ap-
Hebb was referring not to America’s political revolu- preciated. About the influence of Ebbinghaus,
tion but to its psychological revolution. According Michael Wertheimer (1987) said, “His seminal ex-
to Hebb, only one phase of the American revolution periments can . . . be viewed as the start of what was
in psychology had taken place. This was the behav- to become the currently popular field of cognitive

Wadsworth Publishing Co.


Hergenhahn: Introduction to the History of Psychology, 4/e CHAPTER 18 / BOOK PAGE 540
å Typecast, Inc. / Job #0981 / July 2000 SECOND PROOF
Cognitive Psychology 541

psychology” (p. 78). Concerning the influence of but will act on that information only when one is
Gestalt psychology, Hearst (1979) said, “Present-day thirsty. For Tolman, this distinction between learn-
cognitive psychology—with its emphasis on organi- ing and performance was extremely important, and
zation, structure, relationships, the active role of the it is also important in Bandura’s theory. (Hergen-
subject, and the important part played by perception hahn & Olson, 2001, pp. 319–320)
in learning and memory—reflects the influence of its (See Bandura, 1986, for an excellent summary of his
Gestalt antecedents” (p. 32). In an interview with extensive research in Social Cognitive Theory.)
Baars, Neisser describes how Gestalt psychology in- The journal Cognitive Psychology was founded in
fluenced him: 1969, and within the next two decades 15 additional
I . . . became particularly interested in Gestalt psy- journals were established featuring research articles
chology. It had an idealistic quality that appealed to on such topics as attention, problem solving, mem-
me. To the Gestalt psychologists human nature was ory, perception, language, and concept formation.
something wonderful, worth exploring, worth Interest in experimental cognitive psychology had
knowing about. They were constantly doing battle become so extensive that many believe a revolution,
with the behaviorists, who seemed to see human or paradigm shift, had occurred in psychology (for
nature as a mere collection of conditioned re- example Baars, 1986; Gardner, 1985; Sperry, 1993).
sponses or blind associations. From the Gestalt Others, however, suggest that contemporary cogni-
viewpoint, the mind is something beautiful, well- tive psychology represents a return to a kind of psy-
structured, in harmony with the universe. (Baars, chology that existed before the domination of be-
1986, p. 274)
haviorism. If anything, then, there occurred a
And, regarding Piaget’s influence, Jerome Kagan counterrevolution rather than a revolution (see Her-
(1980) said, “With Freud, Piaget has been a seminal genhahn, 1994b). Even George Miller, who, as we
figure in the sciences of human development” have seen, was as responsible as anyone for the cur-
(p. 246). rent popularity of cognitive psychology, rejects the
One of the most popular cognitive theories in idea that a revolution took place:
contemporary psychology is Albert Bandura’s social
What seems to have happened is that many experi-
cognitive theory. In several ways, Bandura’s theory mental psychologists who were studying human
can be understood as a direct descendent of Tol- learning, perception, or thinking began to call
man’s theory. themselves cognitive psychologists without chang-
If one had to choose a theory of learning that is ing in any obvious way what they had always been
closest to Bandura’s, it would be Tolman’s theory. thinking and doing—as if they suddenly discovered
Although Tolman was a behaviorist, he used men- they had been speaking cognitive psychology all
talistic concepts to explain behavioral phenom- their lives. So our victory may have been more
ena . . . and Bandura does the same thing. Also, modest than the written record would have led you
Tolman believed learning to be a constant process to believe. ( Bruner, 1983, p. 126)
that does not require reinforcement, and Bandura Robins, Gosling, and Craik (1999) note that the
believes the same thing. Both Tolman’s theory and popularity of cognitive psychology has increased dra-
Bandura’s theory are cognitive in nature, and nei- matically over the last three decades. They agree
ther are reinforcement theories. A final point of
with Miller, however, that it is incorrect to refer to
agreement between Tolman and Bandura concerns
the concept of motivation. Although Tolman be- this increased popularity as a “cognitive revolution.”
lieved that learning was constant, he believed fur- In any case, from the many forms of cognitive
ther that the information gained through learning psychology that existed prior to the 1970s, informa-
was only acted on when there was reason for doing tion-processing psychology emerged as the dominant
so, such as when a need arose. For example, one form. Information-processing psychology is the kind
may know full well where a drinking fountain is of cognitive psychology that took the computer

Wadsworth Publishing Co.


Hergenhahn: Introduction to the History of Psychology, 4/e CHAPTER 18 / BOOK PAGE 541
å Typecast, Inc. / Job #0981 / July 2000 THIRD PROOF
542 Chapter 18

program as a metaphor for the workings of the mind. puter possesses those mental attributes just as hu-
Before discussing information-processing psychology, mans do? No, say the proponents of weak artificial
however, we will first review the field of artificial in- intelligence, who claim that, at best, a computer can
telligence that influenced its development. only simulate human mental attributes. Yes, say the
proponents of strong artificial intelligence, who
claim that the computer is not merely a tool used to
Artificial Intelligence study the mind (as the proponents of weak AI
Developments in cybernetics, information theory, claim). Rather, an appropriately programmed com-
and computer technology combined to form the field puter really is a mind capable of understanding and
of artificial intelligence. Fetzer (1991) defines arti- having mental states. According to strong AI, hu-
ficial intelligence (AI) as a “special branch of man minds are computer programs, and therefore
computer science that investigates the extent to there is no reason they cannot be duplicated by
which the mental powers of human beings can be other, nonbiological, computer programs. For the
captured by means of machines” (p. xvi). In 1950 proponents of strong AI, computers do not simulate
the brilliant mathematician Alan M. Turing (1912– human cognitive processes; they duplicate them.
1954) founded the field of artificial intelligence in
an article entitled “Computing Machinery and In- Searle’s argument against strong artificial intelli-
telligence,” in which he raised the question, Can gence. John Searle (1980, 1990) describes his now
machines think? Because the term think is so am- famous “Chinese Room” rebuttal to proponents of
biguous, Turing proposed an objective way of an- strong AI. Thinking, according to strong AI, is the
swering his own question. manipulation of symbols according to rules, and be-
cause computer programs manipulate symbols ac-
The Turing test. Turing proposed that we play the cording to rules, they think. According to strong AI,
“imitation game” to answer the question, Can ma- “the mind is to the brain as the program is to the
chines (like computers) think? He asked that we hardware” (Searle, 1990, p. 26). To refute this claim,
imagine an interrogator asking probing questions to Searle asks you to consider a language you do not un-
a human and to a computer, both hidden from the derstand—say, Chinese. Now suppose you are placed
interrogator’s view. The questions and answers are in a room containing baskets full of Chinese symbols,
typed on a keyboard and displayed on a screen. The along with a rule book written in English telling how
only information the interrogator is allowed is that to match certain Chinese symbols with other Chi-
which is furnished during the question-and-answer nese symbols. The rules instruct you how to match
session. The human is instructed to answer the ques- symbols entirely by their shapes and does not require
tions truthfully and to attempt to convince the in- any understanding of the meaning of the symbols.
terrogator that he or she really is the human. The “The rules might say such things as, ‘take a squiggle-
computer is programmed to respond as if it were hu- squiggle sign from basket number one and put it next
man. If after a series of such tests the interrogator is to a squoggle-squoggle sign from basket number
unable to consistently identify the human responder, two’” (Searle, 1990, p. 26). Imagine further that
the computer passes the Turing test and can be said there are people outside the room who understand
to think. Chinese and who slip batches of symbols into your
room, which you then manipulate according to your
Weak versus strong artificial intelligence. What rule book. You then slip the results back out of the
does it mean when a computer passes the Turing test room. Searle likens the rule book to the computer
for some human cognitive function? For example, if program. The people who wrote the rule book are
an interrogator cannot distinguish between a human the “programmers,” and you are the “computer.” The
and a computer with regard to thinking, reasoning, baskets full of symbols are the “database,” the small
and problem solving, does that mean that the com- batches of symbols slipped into the room are “ques-

Wadsworth Publishing Co.


Hergenhahn: Introduction to the History of Psychology, 4/e CHAPTER 18 / BOOK PAGE 542
å Typecast, Inc. / Job #0981 / July 2000 SECOND PROOF
Cognitive Psychology 543

nese, then neither does any other digital computer


solely on that basis. Digital computers merely ma-
nipulate formal symbols according to rules in the
program.
What goes for Chinese goes for other forms of
cognition as well. Just manipulating the symbols is
not by itself enough to guarantee cognition, per-
ception, understanding, thinking and so forth.
And since computers, qua computers, are symbol-
manipulating devices, merely running the com-
puter program is not enough to guarantee cogni-
tion. (p. 26)
Any problem that can be stated in terms of for-
mal symbols and solved according to specified rules
can be solved by a computer, such as balancing a
checking account or playing chess and checkers. The
manipulation of symbols according to specified rules
is called syntax. Semantics, on the other hand, in-
volves the assignment of meaning to symbols. Ac-
cording to Searle, computer programs have syntax
but not semantics. Human thoughts, perceptions,
and understandings have a mental content, and they
john searle

can refer to objects or events in the world; they have


a meaning or, to use Brentano’s term, they have in-
tentionality. A computer program (or you enclosed in
John Searle
the Chinese room) simply manipulates symbols
without any awareness of what they mean. Again, al-
though a computer may pass the Turing test, it is not
tions,” and the small batches of transformed symbols really thinking as humans think, and therefore
you slip out of the room are “answers.” strong AI is false. “You can’t get semantically loaded
Finally, imagine that your rule book is written in thought contents from formal computations alone”
such a way that the “answers” you generate are indis- (Searle, 1990, p. 28). Our brains are constructed so
tinguishable from those of a native Chinese speaker. that they cause mental events: “Brains are specific bi-
In other words, unknown to you, the symbols slipped ological organs, and their specific biochemical prop-
into your room may constitute the question, What is erties enable them to cause consciousness and other
the capital of France? and your answer, again un- sorts of mental phenomena” ( p. 29). Computer pro-
known to you, was Paris. After several such questions grams can provide useful simulations of the formal
and answers, you pass the Turing test for understand- aspects of brain processes, but simulation should not
ing Chinese although you are totally ignorant of Chi- be confused with duplication. “No one expects to get
nese. Furthermore, in your situation there is no way wet in a pool filled with Ping-Pong-ball models of
that you could ever come to understand Chinese be- water molecules. So why would anyone think a com-
cause you could not learn the meaning of any sym- puter model of thought processes would actually
bols. Like a computer, you manipulate symbols but think?” (p. 31).
attach no meaning to them. Searle (1990) concludes:
The point of the thought experiment is this: If I do Are humans machines? The argument about
not understand Chinese solely on the basis of run- whether machines (in this case, computers) can
ning a computer program for understanding Chi- think reintroduces into modern psychology a number

Wadsworth Publishing Co.


Hergenhahn: Introduction to the History of Psychology, 4/e CHAPTER 18 / BOOK PAGE 543
å Typecast, Inc. / Job #0981 / July 2000 SECOND PROOF
544 Chapter 18

of questions that have persisted throughout psychol- far-fetched for him. Similarly, the philosophers, like
ogy’s history. One such question is, What is the na- Kant, who divided the mind into various faculties
ture of human nature? As we have seen, one answer were dualists. However, these faculties were often
has been that humans are machines. Most of the En- viewed as transforming sensory information in auto-
glish and French Newtonians of the mind took New- matic, mechanistic, lawful ways, and therefore both
ton’s conception of the universe as a machine and ap- the physical and mental aspects of humans were ma-
plied it to humans. For anyone who believes that chinelike. In more recent times, the methodological
humans are nothing but complex machines—and behaviorists, like Tolman, who postulated cognitive
there have been many philosophers and psycholo- events that mediate between stimuli and responses
gists with such a belief—there would be no reason followed in the tradition of the faculty psychologists.
that a nonhuman machine could not be built that Thus being a dualist does not preclude one from
would duplicate every human function. This might re- viewing humans as machines and thus embracing
quire placing a computer into a sophisticated robot, some form of AI. As we will see, information-
but in principle there is no reason a nonhuman ma- processing psychology is a form of cognitive psychol-
chine could not duplicate every human function, be- ogy that followed in the traditions of faculty psy-
cause humans too are nothing but machines. For chology and methodological behaviorism and so
example, materialists have no trouble with the con- found much that was useful in AI.
tention that machines like robots could be built that Standing in firm opposition to using any form of
duplicate all human functions. Humans, say the ma- AI as a model for understanding the human mind
terialists, are nothing but physical systems. However, would be all rationalistic philosophers or psycholo-
for the materialists there is no “ghost in the machine” gists who postulated a free will (like Descartes). Also
(that is, a mind); thus there is no reason to wonder in opposition would be the romantic and existential
whether a nonhuman machine can think or not. philosophers and the modern humanistic psycholo-
Neither nonhuman machines nor humans can think. gists. Aside from postulating human free will, hu-
Thoughts, ideas, concepts, perceptions, and under- manistic psychologists claim that there are so many
standings cannot exist if they are thought to be non- important unique human attributes (such as creativ-
physical in nature; only physical things exist. To sug- ity and the innate tendency toward self-actualiza-
gest otherwise, say the materialists, is to embrace tion) that the very idea of machine simulation of hu-
dualism. Being materialists, radical behaviorists do man attributes is ridiculous and perhaps even
not deny that machines could be made that duplicate dangerous. It may be dangerous because if we view
human behavior. However, such a machine could not humans as machines, we may treat them as ma-
think any more than humans can think and, there- chines; and if we treat them as machines, they may
fore, talk of duplicating human thought processes is act like machines. According to the humanistic psy-
plain nonsense. For materialists, such as the radical chologists, this is what tends to happen when the
behaviorists, both weak and strong AI are useless methods and assumptions of the natural sciences are
concepts. applied to the study of humans. With such methods,
Psychologists and philosophers who accept dual- humans are treated like physical objects (machines)
ism may or may not find AI useful. Postulating a and are thus desacralized. Most humanistic psycholo-
cognitive component to human nature does not re- gists find the very idea of AI repulsive.
quire that such a component be unlawful. Most of
the British empiricists and French sensationalists
embraced mentalism, but the mental events they
Information-Processing Psychology
postulated were governed by the laws of association. There is no better example of how developments
Even being a rationalist does not preclude being a outside psychology can influence psychology than
determinist concerning mental events. For example, the emergence of information-processing psychol-
Spinoza believed thought to be lawful, and therefore ogy. Although individuals such as George Miller
a machine analogy of the mind would not have been (1956) and Donald Broadbent (1957, 1958) had al-

Wadsworth Publishing Co.


Hergenhahn: Introduction to the History of Psychology, 4/e CHAPTER 18 / BOOK PAGE 544
å Typecast, Inc. / Job #0981 / July 2000 SECOND PROOF
Cognitive Psychology 545

ready used the computer metaphor to study human Calling a behavior a response implies something
cognition, it is generally agreed that the 1958 article very different from calling it an output. It implies
by Allen Newell, J. C. Shaw, and Herbert Simon different beliefs about the behavior’s origin, its his-
marked the transition between artificial intelligence tory, and its explanation. Similarly, the terms stimu-
and information-processing psychology. In their arti- lus and input carry very different implications about
how people process them. (Lachman, Lachman, &
cle, the authors claimed that the computer programs
Butterfield, 1979, p. 99)
they developed solved problems the same way hu-
mans do. That is, they claimed that both the human Information-processing follows in the rationalis-
mind and computer programs are general problem- tic tradition, and, like most rationalist theories, in-
solving devices. This claim was highly influential, formation-processing theory has a strong nativistic
and an increasing number of psychologists began to component:
note the similarities between humans and computers:
We do not believe in postulating mysterious in-
Both receive input, process that input, have a mem- stincts to account for otherwise unexplainable be-
ory, and produce output. For information-processing havior, but we do feel that everything the human
psychologists, the term input replaces the term stimu- does is the result of inborn capacities, as well as
lus, the term output replaces the terms response and learning. We give innate capacities more signifi-
behavior, and terms such as storage, encoding, process- cance than behaviorists did. We think part of the
ing, capacity, retrieval, conditional decisions, and pro- job of explaining human cognition is to identify
grams describe the information-processing events how innate capacities and the results of experience
that occur between the input and the output. Most combine to produce cognitive performance. This
of these terms have been borrowed from computer leads us, especially in the area of language, to sup-
technology. The information-processing psychologist pose that some aspects of cognition have evolved
usually concentrates his or her research on normal, primarily or exclusively in humans. (p. 118)
rational thinking and behavior and views the human Note the similarity between the Gestalt position
as an active seeker and user of information. and the following statement of Lachman, Lachman,
As we have seen throughout this book, assump- and Butterfield: “The human mind has parts, and
tions made about human nature strongly influence they interrelate as a natural system” (p. 128). Also
how humans are studied. The assumption that the note the similarity between Kant’s philosophy and
mind or brain either is or acts like a computer dem- another statement made by Lachman, Lachman,
onstrates this point: and Butterfield: “Man’s cognitive system is con-
Computers take symbolic input, recode it, make de- stantly active; it adds to its environmental input and
cisions about the recorded input, make new expres- literally constructs its reality” (p. 128). In fact, con-
sions from it, store some or all of the input, and give siderable similarity exists between Kant’s rationalis-
back symbolic output. By analogy, that is most of tic philosophy and information-processing psychol-
what cognitive psychology is about. It is about how ogy. Many consider Kant to be the founding father
people take in information, how they recode and of information-processing psychology: “When cog-
remember it, how they make decisions, how they nitive scientists discuss their philosophical forebears
transform their internal knowledge states, and how one hears the name of Immanuel Kant more than
they transform these states into behavioral outputs.
any other” (Flanagan, 1991, p. 181). As we saw in
The analogy is important. It makes a difference
chapter 6, Kant postulated a number of categories of
whether a scientist thinks of humans as if they were
laboratory animals or as if they were computers. thought (faculties of the mind) that act on sensory
Analogies influence an experimenter’s choice of re- information, thereby giving it structure and mean-
search questions, and they guide his or her theory ing that it otherwise would not have. In other
construction. They color the scientist’s language, words, according to Kant, the faculties of the mind
and a scientist’s choice of terminology is significant. process information. It is Kant’s philosophy that cre-
The terms are pointers to a conceptual infrastruc- ates a kinship among Piaget’s theory of intellectual
ture that defines an approach to a subject matter.

Wadsworth Publishing Co.


Hergenhahn: Introduction to the History of Psychology, 4/e CHAPTER 18 / BOOK PAGE 545
å Typecast, Inc. / Job #0981 / July 2000 SECOND PROOF
546 Chapter 18

development, Gestalt psychology, and information- haviorists “solved” the problem by denying the exis-
processing psychology. tence of a mind. For them, so-called mental events
are nothing but physiological experiences to which
The return of faculty psychology. Largely because we assign cognitive labels. That is, the radical behav-
of its relationship with phrenology, faculty psychol- iorists “solved” the mind-body problem by assuming
ogy came into disfavor and was essentially discarded materialism or physical monism. Cognitive psychol-
along with phrenology. To some, discarding faculty ogy, however, assumes the existence of cognitive
psychology with phrenology was like throwing out events. These events are viewed sometimes as the
the baby with the bath water. We just saw that by-products of brain activity (epiphenomenalism),
information-processing psychology marks a return to sometimes as automatic, passive processors of sensory
faculty psychology. The recent discovery that the information (mechanism), and sometimes as impor-
brain is organized into many “modules” (groups of tant causes of behavior (interactionism). In each
cells), each associated with some specific function case, bodily events and cognitive events are assumed,
such as face recognition, also marks a return to fac- and therefore the relationship between the two must
ulty psychology. As Jerrold Fodor (1983) noted: be explained. A number of contemporary cognitive
Faculty psychology is getting to be respectable again psychologists believe they have avoided dualism by
after centuries of hanging around with phrenolo- noting the close relationship between certain brain
gists and other dubious types. By faculty psychology activities and certain cognitive events (for example,
I mean, roughly, the view that many fundamentally Sperry, 1993). The fact that it appears likely that
different types of psychological mechanisms must such a relationship will soon be discovered for all
be postulated in order to explain the facts of mental mental events is sometimes offered in support of ma-
life. Faculty psychology takes seriously the apparent terialism. D. N. Robinson (1986) explained why
heterogeneity of the mental and is impressed by such reasoning is fallacious:
such prima facie differences as between, say, sensa-
tion and perception, volition and cognition, learn- This is hardly a justification for materialistic mo-
ing and remembering, or language and thought. nism, since dualism does not require that there be
Since, according to faculty psychologists, the men- no brain! Indeed, dualism does not even necessarily
tal causation of behavior typically involves the require that mental events not be the effects of
simultaneous activity of a variety of distinct psy- neural causes. A modest dualism only asserts that
chological mechanisms, the best research strategy there are mental events. To show, then, that such
would seem to be divide and conquer: first study the events are somehow caused by material events, far
intrinsic characteristics of each of the presumed fac- from establishing the validity of a monist position,
ulties, then study the ways in which they interact. virtually guarantees the validity of a dualist posi-
Viewed from the faculty psychologist’s perspective, tion. (pp. 435–436)
overt, observable behavior is an interaction effect Replacing the term mind-body with the term mind-
par excellence. (p. 1)
brain does little to solve the problem of how some-
In his influential book How the Mind Works (1997), thing material (the brain) can cause something men-
Steven Pinker also embraces faculty psychology: “the tal (ideas, thinking).
mind, I claim, is not a single organ but a system of or- In the 1970s a number of information-processing
gans, which we can think of as psychological facul- psychologists attempting to understand cognition
ties or mental modules” (p. 27). combined their efforts with philosophers, anthropol-
ogists, linguists, neuroscientists, engineers, and com-
The return of the mind-body problem. The current puter scientists, thus creating cognitive science. Like
popularity of all varieties of cognitive psychology, in- information-processing psychologists, the cognitive
cluding information-processing psychology, brings scientists seek to understand the mental processes
the mind-body problem back into psychology—not that intervene between stimuli and responses, but
that it ever completely disappeared. The radical be- they take a broader base in studying those processes.

Wadsworth Publishing Co.


Hergenhahn: Introduction to the History of Psychology, 4/e CHAPTER 18 / BOOK PAGE 546
å Typecast, Inc. / Job #0981 / July 2000 SECOND PROOF
Cognitive Psychology 547

However, even with the development of cognitive moves away from computer models of human cogni-
science, or perhaps because of it, there was a growing tion and the narrow confines of laboratory experi-
realization that information-processing psychology mentation and toward a study of cognition as it oc-
and the AI from which it developed had become curs naturally in real-life situations. Neisser’s new
sterile. Even Ulric Neisser, whose 1967 book Cogni- approach to cognitive psychology was influential, but
tive Psychology did so much to promote information- the influence of AI in the study of cognitive pro-
processing psychology, eventually became disen- cesses was far from over. Enthusiasm for AI was
chanted with that kind of psychology. In 1976 rekindled by a dramatic new development that uses
Neisser published Cognition and Reality, in which he the brain as a model for cognitive functioning in-
argued that information-processing psychology be re- stead of the computer—new connectionism. We will
placed by ecological psychology. Ecological psychology discuss new connectionism in chapter 19.

Summary
Throughout most of psychology’s history, human In 1950 Alan Turing created the field of artificial
cognition was studied philosophically. J. S. Mill pro- intelligence (AI). AI attempts to simulate or dupli-
vided the framework within which human cogni- cate the intelligence exhibited by humans, using
tion could be studied scientifically. Fechner, Ebbing- nonhuman machines such as computers. Turing pro-
haus, James, Bartlett, and Piaget were among the posed the “imitation game” as a means of determin-
first psychologists to demonstrate that human cogni- ing whether a machine can think as a human does. If
tion could be studied experimentally. Also included the answers to questions given by a machine (like a
among the pioneers of experimental cognitive psy- computer) are indistinguishable from those given by
chology were the Gestalt psychologists, Rogers, a human, the machine can be said to think. Those
Hebb, Wiener, Shannon, and Weaver. During the adhering to strong AI believe that nonhuman ma-
1950s, interest in experimental cognitive psychol- chines can duplicate human intelligence, and those
ogy increased mainly because of the efforts of such adhering to weak AI believe that nonhuman ma-
individuals as George Miller, Broadbent, Lashley, chines can only simulate human intelligence. Searle
Festinger, Bruner, Tracy and Howard Kendler, argues that his thought experiment of the “Chinese
Chomsky, the humanistic psychologists, and the Room” showed that computers manipulate symbols
psychoanalysts. In 1960 Hebb urged that the rigor- without assigning meaning to them, and therefore
ous scientific methods utilized by the behaviorists to strong AI must be rejected. Whether or not AI is
study behavior be applied to the study of human seen as a useful model for studying humans depends
cognition. Also in 1960 Miller and Bruner founded on one’s view of human nature. According to materi-
the Center for Cognitive Studies at Harvard. In alists, such as the radical behaviorists, there is no rea-
1962 and 1963 Egger and Miller demonstrated that son machines cannot duplicate human behavior.
classical conditioning could not be understood in However, efforts to construct machines that simulate
terms of associative principles alone. Rather the in- or duplicate human thought processes must fail be-
formation conveyed by the stimuli involved had to cause such processes do not exist. But accepting a
be considered. In 1967 Neisser synthesized the di- dualist position does not necessarily preclude the
verse findings within experimental cognitive psy- usefulness of AI, because many dualists are also
chology, using a few basic principles primarily from mechanists. It is only those dualist positions that pos-
information theory. In 1969 Miller served as presi- tulate unique features of the human mind (such as
dent of the APA, illustrating how far experimental free will) that see AI as having little or no usefulness.
cognitive psychology based on information theory Information-processing cognitive psychology de-
had come. veloped from AI. As the computer does, humans re-

Wadsworth Publishing Co.


Hergenhahn: Introduction to the History of Psychology, 4/e CHAPTER 18 / BOOK PAGE 547
å Typecast, Inc. / Job #0981 / July 2000 SECOND PROOF
548 Chapter 18

ceive input; process that input by using various pro- be seen as marking a return to faculty psychology? a
grams, strategies, schemata, memories, and plans; return to the mind-body problem?
and then produce output. The major goal of the in-
formation-processing psychologist was to determine InfoTrac College Edition
the mechanisms humans employ in processing infor-
mation. Information-processing psychologists fol- Explore InfoTrac College Edition, your online
lowed in the rationalistic tradition, and their work library. Go to http://www.infotraccollege.com/
and assumptions showed similarities to Kantian phi- wadsworth/access.html.
losophy, Gestalt psychology, Piaget’s theory of intel- Search terms:
lectual development, and methodological behavior- Cognitive Psychology: Research
ism. Both faculty psychology and the mind-body Cognitive Dissonance
Artificial Intelligence
problem reemerged as cognitive psychology became
Searle, John
popular. In the late 1970s, information-processing Environmental psychology (ecological)
psychologists joined with researchers from other dis-
ciplines to form cognitive science.
Suggestions for Further Reading
Discussion Questions Baars, B. J. (1986). The cognitive revolution in psychology.
New York: Guilford Press.
1. Justify the contention that psychology has almost Beakley, B., & Ludlow, P. (Eds.). (1992). The philosophy
always been concerned with studying human cogni- of mind: Classical problems/contemporary issues.
tion. Throughout most of psychology’s history, how Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
was cognition studied? What philosopher provided Block, N., Flanagen, O., & Güzeldere, G. (Eds.)
the framework within which cognition could be (1997). The nature of consciousness. Cambridge,
studied experimentally? MA: MIT Press.
2. Give examples of early efforts (before 1950) to Boden, M. A. (Ed.) (1990). The philosophy of artificial
study human cognition experimentally. intelligence. New York: Oxford University Press.
3. Give examples of events that occurred in the 1950s Churchland, P. S., & Sejnowski, T. J. (1994). The com-
that contributed to the development of experimen- putational brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
tal cognitive psychology. Johnson, D. M., & Erneling, C. E. (Eds.) (1997). The
4. Describe the pivotal events that occurred in the future of the cognitive revolution. New York: Oxford
1960s that contributed to the current popularity of University Press.
experimental cognitive psychology. Pinker, S. (1997). How the mind works. New York:
5. Define each of the following: cognitive science, artifi- Norton.
cial intelligence (AI), strong AI, and weak AI. Rychlak, J. F. (1997). In defense of human conscious-
6. What is the Turing test, and for what was it used? ness. Washington, DC: American Psychological
7. Describe Searle’s thought experiment involving the Association.
“Chinese Room.” What, according to Searle, does Von Eckart, B. (1993). What is cognitive science? Cam-
this experiment prove? bridge, MA: MIT Press.
8. Which philosophies would tend to support the po-
sition of strong AI? weak AI? Which would deny
the usefulness of either type of AI? Glossary
9. What are the major tenets of information-process-
ing psychology? How is information-processing psy- Artificial intelligence (AI) A branch of computer sci-
chology related to AI? ence that investigates the extent to which ma-
10. Why can information-processing psychology be chines can simulate or duplicate the intelligent
seen as following in the tradition of Kantian philos- behavior of living organisms. (See also Strong artifi-
ophy? Why can information-processing psychology cial intelligence and Weak artificial intelligence.)

Wadsworth Publishing Co.


Hergenhahn: Introduction to the History of Psychology, 4/e CHAPTER 18 / BOOK PAGE 548
å Typecast, Inc. / Job #0981 / July 2000 SECOND PROOF
Cognitive Psychology 549

Cognitive science A multidiscipline approach to study- Turing test A test devised by Turing (1950) to deter-
ing cognition in humans, animals, and machines. mine whether a machine can think. Questions are
Information-processing psychology The approach to submitted to both a human and a machine. If the
studying cognition that follows in the tradition of machine’s answers are indistinguishable from those
faculty psychology and methodological (media- of the human, it is concluded that the machine
tional) behaviorism and typically employs the com- can think.
puter as a model for human information processing. Weak artificial intelligence The contention that ma-
Strong artificial intelligence The contention that ma- chines (such as computers) can simulate human
chines (such as computers) can duplicate human cognitive processes but not duplicate them.
cognitive processes.

Wadsworth Publishing Co.


Hergenhahn: Introduction to the History of Psychology, 4/e CHAPTER 18 / BOOK PAGE 549
å Typecast, Inc. / Job #0981 / July 2000 SECOND PROOF

You might also like