You are on page 1of 21

3° CHAPTER ONE

the existing order is partial. It shows the socially constructed charac-


ter of the legal norms and institutions; it partially illuminates the val-
ues that are realized in that order. But its reconstructive ambitions TWO
determine the point at which it takes up the descriptive enterprise.
T h e radical scholar pursues the norms ofjustice, the understand-
ing of gender, or the idea of democracy operative in the legal order
as the focus of her critique and reconstructive agenda. These are cer- Imagining the Rule of Law
tainly valuable subjects of study, yet the legal order creates a world
far more basic that slips from view—a world of subjects moving in
time and space, oriented toward claims of authority, and understand-
ing themselves as members of particular communities. Where can we find a place for a free study of law within a culture
We must accept the proposition that there is nothing natural about wholly permeated by law's rule? If law's rule claims both reason and
the legal order, that it is a constructed social world that could be will as its foundation, what place is left for a form of scholarship that
constructed differently. Nevertheless, we must put off the impulse to insists on a neutral stance toward law? Must such a discipline of law
re-create that world on our own blueprint. We must first bring the set itself against reason? Against the popular will? Does that place it
legal world to light^by raising to self-conscious examination the social with an irrational, dictatorial authority? To think that these are the
and psychological meanings of a world understood as the rule of law. only alternatives is to remain within the worldview of law, in which
Who are we and what does our world look like when we find our- the law has already claimed for itself all of the reason and consent
selves in this culture of law's rule? Both the mainstream and the radi- available, and in which the only question addressed to the scholar is
cal scholar are too much of this world to ask this question. We need "What reforms are you proposing?" If the forms of reason and will
a form of scholarship that gives up the project of reform, not because are multiple, then there is no need to fear that a scholarly distance
it is satisfied with things as they are, but because it wants better to from law's rule dooms us to irrational forms of arbitrary authority.
understand who and what we are.
The task ahead is both prescriptive and descriptive. Scholarship
The legal academic is the captive of law. If a discipline of law is to must be stripped of its normative commitment to the rule of law if it
emerge that actually studies law as an object for theoretical descrip- is to disentangle itself from the practice of law. In the next chapter,
tion and elaboration, the scholar must first free herself from the law. I set forth a series of methodological rules that would support and
Truth has a debt to freedom that has not yet been paid. guide such a study. In this chapter, I take up the descriptive task
of setting forth the possibility and the general subject matter of such
a legal discipline. In order to avoid too much abstraction, I offer
a sketch of the most basic areas of inquiry of the new discipline.
T h e details of this sketch, which are inevitably controversial, should
be distinguished from the larger project of studying the culture of
law's rule.

THE C R I T I C A L TURN
What I am after as a mode of inquiry is hardly a new invention. We
have an enduring image in the West of free inquiry within a culture
of legal practice. Plato portrays Socrates as a committed Athenian
citizen, living and dying under the laws of Athens. Yet Socrates is also
a philosopher, subjecting the values and practices of the Athenian

31
p-

32 CHAPTER TWO IMAGINING THE RULE OF LAW 33


legal order to free inquiry The problem Socrates represents for critical examination. It always begins abruptly, erupting without rea-
Plato—and has represented ever since—is how to understand the son in the everyday course of experience. It begins with a chance
relationship between the citizen and the philosopher, between living encounter. We cannot predict which encounter will take off in this
under the law and pursuing a free inquiry into the moral, political, direction. Most people, most of the time, are too busy. But the philo-
and epistemic dimensions of legal authority. sophical engagement remains a possibility in every encounter. It is
Already in Plato's works, we find three different answers to the built into the nature of speech that every discursive act can itself
problem of reconciling free inquiry and legal practice, meaning by become the object of a further discourse. Every encounter provides
"practice" a way of living within the polity. First, a pessimistic answer: a possible occasion for a self-transcending, critical deployment of
citizenship under law and philosophy are essentially incompatible. speech in which the object of examination is the ordinary speech
On this view, the city kills the philosopher despite his best efforts to of the speakers themselves. If the problem of legal scholarship has
comply with law while sharing with his fellow citizens the insights of been the collapse of the distinction between the inquiring subject and
philosophy. This is Socrates' fate; it is the fate Plato predicts, in his legal practice, then the Socratic encounter offers a possible antidote.
famous myth of the cave, for any philosopher who returns to his na- The Socratic discourse begins only with the erection of just such a
tive city.' Political authority, even democratic authority, cannot tol- distinction.
erate a free inquiry that_ declines to commit itself in advance to sup- The Socratic question with which a dialogue begins—for ex-
port not just the specific commands of law—as Socrates does—but ample, is a proposed act just?—is designed to create a shock that is
also to support the spirit of legal authority as a culture of belief in the experienced as speechlessness. The interlocutor cannot provide an
virtues of the city's political order. Socrates, we remember, is indicted account of his ordinary practice or belief. This shock establishes the
for failing to believe in the city's gods. Second, an optimistic answer: distance between inquiry and practice, subject and object. The in-
the city can be remade to embody the truth that is revealed in the quiry, then, moves in a direction tangential to the discursive practice
course of philosophical inquiry. If law can be re-formed, then it is that is subjected to questioning. Practice is suspended while the in-
possible to bring about a coincidence of philosophical insight and quiry occurs.
political authority. This would be rule by the philosopher-king of the Because the dialogue occurs within a space in which practice is tem-
Republic. Plato claims no more for this answer than that it is possible, porarily suspended, its aim is not reform. Socrates will talk through
even if extremely unlikely 2 If it is possible, then the philosopher's the night to the point of exhaustion-—his own or his interlocutors'.
political task can be understood as the attempt to bring it about, de- But in the morning, life in the city goes on. Suspending belief, we
spite the risk that he will meet Socrates' fate.3 realize a new form of practice that is the activity of philosophy itself.
The first two answers—-albeit contradictory—are Plato's; the third The practice rests upon the capacity of the individual to transcend
is Socrates'. On this view, philosophy is actively carried on within the every context, and so to examine the conditions of belief that make
state but not as a political activity. Socrates does not claim that the possible our ordinary activities and norms. 5 At the end of the inquiry,
insights he gains by way of philosophy entitle him to any form of rule. the interlocutors may suspect that their ordinary beliefs are without
Indeed, in the Apology he tells us just the opposite, saying that he has a solid foundation. Yet they do not emerge with a new set of moral
stayed away from offering any political advice. He suggests that a and political values to substitute for the beliefs with which they
philosophical program must abandon political ambition if it is to sur- started. If they were to try directly to translate philosophical insight
vive as a form of life. Thus, after the verdict against him, Socrates into political practice, they would have no grounds for believing that
announces that there was no inevitability in that outcome—a few the substitute values would be acceptable to anyone outside of the
votes the other way would have changed the decision.4 Philosophy discourse. Socrates is in Athens; Athens is not in him.
may be risky, but it is not always deadly. The Socratic dialogue is without end because it is without a polit-
If we strip philosophy of its Platonic ambitions, we can find in ical product. It is not the progressive realization of a single truth, but
Socrates a model of free inquiry within a life that remains embedded a critical mode of being in the world. It is not an effort to reconstruct
in law. Socratic dialogue is a temporary suspension of belief in order the political order on the basis of a philosophically perceived truth.
to subject the ordinary norms and activities of the political order to It operates within the political order not as a revolutionary truth
34 CHAPTER TWO IMAGINING THE RULE OF LAW 35
brought to the state from outside, but as an attitude toward ordinary that there was only a single, universal form of understanding, his con-
practice. temporary successors see claims to knowledge as the products of di-
The first step toward a new discipline of legal study is the brack- verse social practices. They perceive multiple social practices within
eting of any truth claims for or about law. This is the equivalent of a single culture, as well as across cultures. The goal of critical thought
the shock of Socrates' first question, which always reveals ignorance. is to examine the conceptual conditions of these multiple social prac-
Acknowledging ignorance, the interlocutor temporarily withdraws tices: how does each structure a world of meaning?
his commitment to existing norms and practices. This withdrawal This modern enterprise of critical thought is not limited to philoso-
permits the inquiry to proceed under its own direction. The self- phy. A modern, critical discipline of law needs to draw equally from
directed inquiry becomes a new model of freedom, relying on its own work in anthropology and cultural theory. Scholars such as Clifford
norms of reason and will. Reason is no longer a form of deduction Geertz and Michel Foucault emphasize that social practices are his-
from first principles, but rather an open-ended inquiry in which every torically specific and that each such practice must be approached
proposition becomes the subject of yet another question.6 Will is no through a process of thick description. These scholars turn away from
longer consent to authoritative institutions, but the commitment to claims of a truth independent of the knowing subject; they seek in-
sustain the suspension of belief. We understand this mode of inquiry stead to elaborate the structure of the imaginative possibilities within
when it is pursued by the cultural anthropologist. She suspends her which a world of social meanings appears. These social practices are
ordinary beliefs andaiormative commitments; she does not judge the somewhat like games, in that they have rules and expected customs
object of her inquiry— r she does not offer reforms—-but pursues each of behavior that are the product of a community's history. We can
proposition offered byiier informants with yet another question. The argue about what these rules and practice are, as well as what they
interpretive task of such an inquiry has no natural stopping point: require in any given set of circumstances. To take up these questions
meanings always exceed the revelatory capacity of the particular is to adopt a particular interpretation of their meaning. This requires
question. A Socratic inquiry into the rule of law would deploy the an "internal" point of view, but it does not require participation in
same form of free inquiry, directed now at our own cultural practice. the practice.
This conception of Socratic discourse connects our earliest, and From the outside, social practices look like sequences of events that
still most powerful, model of philosophy with the modern enterprise may be explained without reference to the meanings they bear for
of critical thought that begins with Immanuel Kant. For Kant, the the participating individuals. We might, for example, explain politi-
task of philosophy was to determine the limits of reason, by which he cal practices in terms of geography or economic laws of supply and
meant the boundaries within which knowledge, action, and hope can demand, without any reference to the participants' own beliefs. But
be legitimately pursued. To understand those limits required an ex- as with other games, we do not have to be players to try to under-
ploration of the conceptual conditions within which knowledge, ac- stand the rules. We can elaborate the rules of chess, pursuing them
tion, and hope are possible. He argued that the way in which we far beyond the formal definitions of the possibilities for each piece,
perceive our world, i.e., how its meanings appear to us, is determined without ever moving a piece on the board. We have the capacity to
by the categories of our own understanding. We can know only that stand within the social practice in order to understand it, but to with-
which falls within-—-or, more accurately, is a product of—this con- hold any commitment to the practice while we pursue the inquiry.
ceptual apparatus. The role of critical inquiry is not to add to our Because no single social practice claims us wholly and exclusively, it
knowledge or to reinvent the moral norms of our experience, but to is always possible to distance oneself from a particular practice and
set forth the a priori conditions of our own experience, both epistemic take it as an object of thought. Cultural inquiry is itself a social prac-
and moral. What are the conceptual conditions and imaginative tice that cultivates the practice of simultaneously standing within and
structures that we bring to experience and that make possible a world without, of articulating beliefs in order to subject them to critical
of meaningful events? examination. 8
Modern inquiry extends this goal of Kantian critique to diverse In this critical interpretive inquiry we do not measure beliefs
systems of symbolic forms or culture practices.7 Where Kant believed against a separate truth. Rather, we ask how truth is constituted

L
36 CHAPTER TWO IMAGINING THE RULE OF LAW 37
through beliefs. Philosophy and anthropology become overlapping conceptual and imaginative structure of that world. When we under-
inquiries. Kant's a priori becomes a contingent, historically deter- stand ourselves as citizens of a state committed to the rule of law, how
mined set of meanings. Foucault speaks of the "historical a priori—- do we imagine the self and the community? When we make legal
a contradiction for Kant, but a fair description of our lives in a less arguments, respond to legal demands, or criticize actions as unlawful,
certain, more diverse, time. how do we understand authority? These are the conceptual condi-
The rule of law is a social practice: it is a way of being in the world. tions that make possible the diverse disagreements that we have
To five under the rule of law is to maintain a set of beliefs about the within the practice of law's rule. They are not a set of answers to
self and community, time and space, authority and representation. It controverted legal questions, but the conditions of belief within which
is to understand the actions of others and the possible actions of the it becomes possible for those questions to arise. In short, we seek to
self as expressions of these beliefs. Without these beliefs, the rule of comprehend the forms of understanding that make possible the range
law appears as just another form of coercive governmental authority. of behaviors that we characterize as living under the rule of law.
This is the way law appears to the alien who happens to find himself A social practice is not merely a set of prescribed actions. More
temporarily within the jurisdiction. He must negotiate around a set importandy, it is the way of understanding self and others that makes
of rules, under a threat of coercion, without understanding the signifi- these actions meaningful. We cannot separate action and belief when
cance of the rules to those who see them as "ours." Law is something describing a social practice. Every action rests on some set of beliefs;
done to him, rather than something we do. Within the beliefs of the every belief makes possible a range of actions. Disputes may rage
citizen, however, law appears as the legitimate and even "natural" over the meaning of an action and over the action required by a
arrangement of our collective life. belief, but they remain disputes within the practice. These disputes
To couple the method of philosophical critique—i.e., exposing the may be the subject of inquiry for a cultural study of law, but the end
conceptual conditions of the practice—to that of thick, anthropo- of that inquiry is not the "correct" resolution of these arguments. The
logical description—-i.e., investigating instances of practice in their scholar, bracketing the questions of truth that animate the practice,
layered character of multiple, juxtaposed meanings—is both the end is simply not speaking to the issue of what the law should be. Neither
and the technique of a cultural study of law's rule. The philosophical should she expect to be heard by those who are listening for an an-
and anthropological aspects of the inquiry point in slightly different swer to this question.
directions. The former maintains the philosophical ambition of co- A study of law's rule as a cultural practice can proceed at various
herence, unity, and system. It seeks an interpretation that would pre- levels of generality. A plan of inquiry should, however, begin at the
sent the rule of law as a unified conceptual order. The latter is open most general, moving to the specific only as the general terrain of the
to the possibility, and indeed suspects, that the elements of such a conceptual order of legal practice and belief is filled in. We need to
"system" are not well-ordered, that they do not all point in a single investigate the shape of legal space and time generally before we in-
direction, and that, indeed, there are tensions-—if not contradic- quire into particular kinds of space and time—for example, the mu-
tions—within the beliefs that support the cultural practice of law's nicipal border or the operation of stare decisis.9 An inquiry into the
rule. In this aspect of the discipline, coherence has no priority over general conceptual features is not, however, an abstract inquiry. The
contradiction. The urge toward systemic unity can usefully push the inquiry must stay bound to particular examples of the social-practice
inquiry to investigate further the deep structure of law's conceptual because there is no general truth apart from the ongoing practice it-
universe. But that inquiry is always conditioned by the acknowledg- self, and there is no practice- apart from particular acts and events.
ment that all need not be well-ordered in the end. A cultural practice Generalizations may appear within the practice, but not as first prin-
is not a philosophical system. ciples from which legal meanings are deductively derived.' 0 The
Accordingly, the question that defines a cultural discipline of law inquiry may pose general questions such as "who is the subject of
is: What are the conceptual conditions that make possible that prac- legal obligations?" but its answer must examine the multiple concep-
tice that we understand as the rule of law? We approach that ques- tions of the subject that operate in legal practice.
tion by first offering a thick description of the event as it appears in To this general path of inquiry, one might object: if a cultural study
the world of law's rule and then by offering an interpretation of the investigates the conceptual conditions of living in a political world
38 CHAPTER TWO IMAGINING THE RULE OF LAW 39
that appears as the rule of law, is there not a reflexive movement by suspend both the moral and the political in pursuit of understanding.
which this study itself appears as a particular play of the imagination? The discipline of anthropology does not normatively evaluate a for-
Do we not have to ask about the conceptual conditions of this disci- eign culture, comparing its practices to our own practices and values.
pline? Are we not bound to the structures of the imagination even as Similarly, a cultural discipline of legal study does not seek to tell any-
we pursue this inquiry? If so, are we doing anything more than sub- one how to live a life under the rule of law or whether one should
stituting one contestable social construction for another? Free inquiry lead such a life at all. Such a suspension does not mean that individu-
looks no more free than the practice from which it attempts to dis- als do not face choices and have to make normative evaluations. At
tance itself. The choice between a cultural study of law and ordinary best, this form of inquiry can make clear a set of practices and the
legal theory is not between a free inquiry and an inquiry captured by beliefs they entail. Individuals must still apply moral and political
legal practice, but merely a choice between two forms of p r a c t i c e - norms. A free discipline is not an excuse for failing to exercise free
only one of which promises to do something constructive in the world choice in the way in which one's own normative beliefs require.
as we know it. This is a powerful argument and I suspect that many A cultural inquiry into law's rule cannot make any claims to an
legal scholars would use it to reaffirm their own practice of inquiry. unconditioned truth, either empirical or normative. Nor can it lay
This 'question arises not just from an epistemic perspective, but claim to a wholly unconditioned freedom of thought. The inquiry is
also from a normative one. Just as we cannot escape the conditions not a step in a progression toward truth. Rather, it is a product of the
of our own thought,-we 'cannot escape our own moral judgments. imagination that stands slightly apart from other products of the
How can we possibly avoid a normative evaluation of the results of imagination. Geertz and Foucault both describe their work as fic-
an interpretive inquiry*into -law's rule, when the object interpreted tion.11 A similar fiction must be brought to law. The ambition is to
involves our own deepest commitments? Perhaps we cannot. Never- achieve a re-presentation of the meanings at play in the social prac-
theless, we can push that evaluation off into the future a bit. The tice. The study takes the social construction of reality as a given, in
mistake is to believe that we live in a single coherent world in which order to explore the conceptual and historical conditions of these
morality, politics, and knowledge coincide. Plato believed that the constructions. To pursue this inquiry is like moving from three di-
good, the beautiful, and the true must coincide. Arguably, this belief mensional to four dimensional space: we get no closer to a world
was a condition for the philosophical activity in which he engaged. outside our imaginings. We do, however, reframe our experience.
Kant made a similar mistake of universalizing the historically contin- Understanding the constructed character of the rule of law allows
gent. Our political, moral, and epistemic lives are not single, but mul- us to see its contingent character and to understand that law's claim
tiple. They overlap, but they are not identical. upon us is not a product of law's truth but of our own imagination—
From a moral perspective, we will never justify our political lives. our imagining its meanings and our failure to imagine alternatives.
Politics begins with a distinction between citizen and alien, which We can understand that other societies have constructed the charac-
quickly becomes that of friend and enemy. This distinction is outside ter of the political community and the meaning of political events in
of our ordinary moral discourse, which begins from a premise of in- different ways and that even in our own society a constant batde is
dividual, universal equality. Even within the polity, the inequalities of fought over the terms of this construction. We can clarify the tensions
wealth, power, and resources are too great to survive a moral cri- among the possibilities that we confront and see how each makes a
tique. We are committed to both of these worlds—the moral and the world for itself that cannot be subsumed within the others. Even if we
political. We cannot make them one. If we try, morality becomes a try to move in one direction, rather than another, we cannot resolve
form of political apologetics or politics becomes a form of moral uto- the tensions. There is no original foundation from which we can
pianism. Neither have much to do with our actual experience of po- begin a project of free construction, unbounded by a past that estab-
litical and moral demands. We want our politicians to be moral, but lishes the conditions of our own understanding. What we instead dis-
not to the point of lacking political realism. We want our moral cover is that freedom is itself a contested term and that each form of
leaders to support our political enterprises, but not to the point of political perception makes a claim to the truth of freedom.
failing to identify those inequalities that we must still overcome. All of this testifies to critical inquiry as the practice of a kind of
Just as we can suspend the moral in pursuit of the political, we can freedom: not a political freedom to do anything, but the freedom to
4o CHAPTER TWO IMAGINING THE RULE OF LAW 41
construct a distance from the self. This is the freedom to observe and Different political communities imagine time and space in differ-
understand the self. Nevertheless, there is no alternative, when the ent ways. A multinational empire has a different conception of ter-
book is done, to stepping back into the very world that one has just ritory than a nation-state; a theocracy, a different sense of history.
exposed as historically contingent. Like every constructed world, the Before any particular legal artifact or practice appears, a field of
critical world exists only as long as we imagine it. It is one possibility possible experience has already been constituted by the understand-
within life, not a better one. It is as incommensurate with the rest of ings of history and territory that operate within the community. I2
our experience as love is incommensurate with law. The critical turn, Even within the modern nation-state, the rule of law does not exhaust
then, is a different practice of freedom brought to the study of law. the possibilities of historical and territorial meaning. The rule of law
But law too can claim to be a practice of freedom. If we lived our is one way of imagining the political; it is not the sole form in which
lives wholly within an academy of critical thought, then perhaps we we experience our political practices.
would find law's claim to freedom to be more compelling than that T h e state does not simply appear at a particular moment in
of critique. chronological time, as if it were an evolutionary mutation or a natu-
A cultural study of law is precisely not a part of the practice of law. ral event like the arrival of a meteorite. It appears only with a recon-
It should not, therefore, be asked to reform law. It has nothing to say ception of past and future. It locates itself within an historical project
in this respect. It is, however, a necessary supplement to our current that is both source and product of the state. Political communities
practice of legal s,tuclies. The critical turn is a turn away from the construct the past of which they conceive themselves to be the prod-
professional school .and back to the disciplines of philosophy, psy- uct.13 The same is true of the territory of the state. The state invests
chology, anthropology, and history. We can know more about our- and maintains meaning in a bounded space. It creates the boundary
selves. This is all that a cultural study of law can promise. What we that is then perceived as constitutive of its existence.14
do once we have that knowledge is a question for practice, not theory. A cultural discipline of law, accordingly, starts with a description
of the shape of time and space under the rule of law. When we take
up this study, we see the twofold character of the descriptive and criti-
T H E A E S T H E T I C OF LAW
cal inquiries required by this discipline. There is both a vertical and
A new discipline of law should begin where Kant began his original a horizontal dimension of study. The former traces the history of
effort at critical philosophy—with time and space. He labeled this concepts; the latter maps the present structure of belief. Following
branch of his study "aesthetic." We need a legal aesthetic, i.e., a study Foucault, I will call the former "genealogy." T h e latter I will call
of the time and space within which legal experience—both belief "architecture."
and practice—becomes possible. The rule of law is an organization The ambition of legal genealogy is to show how the nature of belief
of institutions, practices, persons, and objects within the ongoing in the rule of law emerges from longer traditions within Western cul-
historical and spatial project that is the state. The state occupies time ture and particularly within the experience of the state. Modern un-
and space not as an object in the natural world, but as an imagina- derstandings of the rule of law are a product of two fundamental
tive construction of temporal and spatial meanings. The state's time cultural transitions: from a religious to a secular understanding of
is history; its space is territory. These are the subjects of a legal political order, and from a monarchical to a popular understanding
aesthetic. of sovereignty. All of the conceptions that we use to understand the
What we mean by "politics" entails a commitment to both history general character of political order pass through this double transi-
and territory. Political life differs from moral life in both of these di- tion.15 This transition, however, is not a complete transformation; it
mensions. Morality can appear to be timeless and universal. Politics is a process of adaptation. The concepts continue to bear meanings
does not. A dream of a universal empire—world government—may derived from their past; they carry "remnants" of this past. Legal
also be a dream of a moral Utopia. It is only when actual political genealogy seeks to excavate these remnants. To do that, we need to
differences among communities disappear that we can imagine a co- trace the contingent, historical course by which these beliefs be-
incidence of the political and the moral. came ours.
42 CHAPTER TWO IMAGINING THE RULE OF LAW 43
Thus, law's time and space have their own history. For Americans of experience within the contemporary social practice of law's rule.
that history does not begin with our nation's founding or even with This is the task of legal architecture, which describes the way in
the colonial charters. It is not the history of the state, but the history which distinctively legal conceptions draw upon, and distinguish
of the belief that concerns us. The founding, as an act of constitu- themselves, from other beliefs and practices operating in the polity.
tional law-making, was itself already a product of a set of beliefs about My exploration in chapter 1 of the way in which contemporary legal
the character of the state. These beliefs included contemporary polit- theory maps onto the psychological distinction of reason and will is
ical theory; the Founders knew their Locke and Harrington. But the an example of such an architectural inquiry.
appropriation of those texts rested on more fundamental ideas about Each aspect of the discipline sets limits on the other. Architecture
political history and the territory of the state. Why, we should ask, is bound by genealogy—we cannot make something out of nothing.
would anyone conceive of the state as a project for new construction? Our endowments are conceptual as much as they are physical. Ge-
How did they conceive of the relationship between the founding act nealogy is bound by architecture; the historical resources must fit
and the future of law's rule? How must time appear to those who within a contemporary structure of belief. Genealogy and architec-
think that a new beginning is possible? ture together constitute the branches of inquiry of a new discipline
These patterns of thought, within which the Framers thought that of law.
a project of state creation could be informed by modern political sci-
ence, were a product, o£ a legal culture that extends back to the Old Law's Time
Testament narrative of.God giving the law to Moses. We still cannot We intuitively know that law carries forward the past as an authori-
speak of new beginnings without hearing religious resonances. We tative source of substantive norms. We see this constantly—in the
cannot think of such a beginning without borrowing from larger maintenance of a written constitution intended to be permanent, the
traditions of struggle and redemption. A secular conception of the role of stare decisis in judicial decision-making, and the temporally
state does not invent a new politics stripped of any taint of the reli- unbounded character of most legislation. Some administrative laws
gious tradition. Rather, it appropriates concepts that are already may include "sunset" provisions, but we do not expect to see judicial
present and gives them a secular cast. Remnants of their past con- decisions announcing that they will serve as valid precedents for only
tinue to inform the character of the political world the concepts make ten years nor a legislature enacting the demise of its work product.
possible. Genealogy is not separate from the project of thick descrip- Once made, law generally remains until a new act of law-making
tion. Indeed, if we fail to see the manner in which our conceptions displaces it. At any given moment, the law appears as the sum total
bear remnants of their past, we are likely to substitute an ideal con- of all that has been done and not yet undone. Indeed, undoing law is
ception of the secular legal order for the experience itself. usually disfavored, as if it entails the admission of a mistake. Consti-
Genealogy is only one half of a cultural approach to the rule of tutional amendments are notoriously difficult to pass, stare decisis
law. History provides the materials for the imagination, but these makes exceptional any overruling of a prior holding, and the legisla-
conceptions must still be arranged in relation to each other and to tive process always favors the status quo. It is as if the rule of law
other contemporary beliefs. We find ourselves in possession of mul- operates on the edge of a huge wedge creeping forward in time.
tiple beliefs that are potential resources for the imaginative construc- This historicity of law is its single most prominent feature. Legal
tion of political meaning. Nevertheless, we are not bound to endless decision-making differs from other kinds of policy formation in just
repetition. We try to make the best of them. We reason within and this way: it always begins from a set of sources that already have au-
upon these resources, finding new connections and supplementing thority within the community's past. Legal arguments do not begin
distinctively political conceptions with other contemporary beliefs. by asking about "the best outcome, all things considered." They be-
This manipulation and deployment of our conceptual inheritance is gin from a commitment to the past. This is true not just of arguments
subject to no test of logical coherence; we are not striving to perfect in court, but wherever law is the ground of authority. Lincoln did not
the logic of our political practices.16 The genealogical perspective ask whether he should free the slaves until he resolved whether he
must, therefore, be supplemented with a description of the shape already had the legal authority to do so. Only when he concluded
44 CHAPTER TWO IMAGINING THE RULE OF LAW
that he had that authority under the presidential war powers—i.e., practice is bound to it. We can imagine a policy science that is wholly
under existing law—was he willing to do that which, from a moral unbounded by the past, but it is not law's rule.20
point of view, he never doubted should be done. 17 We will not grasp the distinctive character of law's past if we focus
In its insistence on linking the present to the past, law differs from only on particular rules-—statutes, judicial decisions, or constitu-
other forms of authoritative command. Legal coercion never appears tional provisions—and the distinctive manipulations, both logical
to those under law's rule as simply the force of the stronger, the will and rhetorical, that legal argument deploys upon these resources. If
of the majority, or the practical conclusion of a moral argument. It approached in this way, law's rule looks like a rather complex game,
may appear this way to those outside of the political community, who distinguished only by the fact that its rules are enforced by violence,
nevertheless find themselves subject to the state's coercive powers. 18 if necessary. Such an approach misses what is most significant about
To be sure, those "outside" the community may be permanently lo- law. Law's rule carries forward a past that makes a meaningful claim
cated within the territory of the state. Consider, for example, how upon us. That claim is internal to our beliefs. It is also deadly serious,
Jim Crow laws appeared to black Americans. For those fully within extending to life itself. We must approach law's rule from the per-
the community of law's rule, however, the authority of law rests on a spective of the subject who finds herself already within the practice,
set of beliefs about the past. rather than from the perspective of the rules operating on a collection
Not until we place an, authoritative command within an historical of individuals. "*==1
narrative of the community of which we are a part do we begin to When we focus on the source of that claim of law's meaning, the 1
reach the distinctive character of legal rule.19 Of course, we can ar- first thing we notice about the authoritative past of law is that it ap-
gue— or even hope—that the public interest of the community un- pears to us as the experience of a unitary actor of which each citizen
der law will prove to be stronger than any factional interests, that the is a part. 21 We easily use a language of first-person plural that speaks
majority will support legal constraints on their own actions, and that of "our" past: the past is a common possession of each of us because
law's rules will have a defendable moral content. Each of these claims we all share in a collective identity in and through a political order
usually appears in what can be called its "privative" mode, that is, as that is the rule of law. Thus, if we ask why we are bound by past legal
a basis for criticizing particular laws. It will be said that a law is the acts, we are likely to answer that we are bound because they were
product of a powerful minority interests—e.g., corporate wealth; or our acts. The people ratified the Constitution; the people were rep-
that it is a product of an unconstrained majority acting in ignorance resented in Congress, which passed the laws. And we are the people.
of, or out of prejudice against, minority interests; or that it is the When we express our experience of law in this way, we are reifying
product of abstract beliefs—usually those of judges—in moral rules under the image of a communal, transtemporal subject a present ex-
that are only matters of subjective preference. Nevertheless, it is perience of the meaning of the past. We attribute causal and norma-
wrong to assume that meeting the criticism would in fact satisfy our tive significance to this appearance of the people as subject.
understanding of law's rule, just as a failure to meet the criticism does These are not statements of fact against which we can measure
not negate a claim to legal authority. It is not enough that the ma- particular claims of law. There is not first a transhistorical, communal
jority rules morally and with sympathy to minority groups. These subject who decides to maintain a common past. There is only the
may be the ends of a program of reform, but reform occurs within a experience of law's rule that shows itself "as if" it were the extended
world already perceived as one of law. temporal experience of a single subject. We come to this communal
In a short-hand fashion, we can say that the rule of law is for us subject through the law, not- vice versa. Scholarship goes wrong,
the manner in which the authoritative character of the past appears. therefore, when it looks for this subject or makes claims about what
Coercive authority cut free of the past appears to law as "illegiti- this subject has done, as if it were a particular actor in the world.22
mate," regardless of its popular support or moral insight. At the very This historical subject doesn't exist apart from the social practices-—
core of law's rule is the distinction between applying the law and mak- the rule of law—within which it appears. It cannot do anything apart
ing new law, or between interpreting and creating law. No matter from what it has already done, for it is only by its acts that we know
how much scholars question the distinction, the rule of law as a social it. Conversely, our knowledge is the limit of its actions. There are no
46 CHAPTER TWO IMAGINING THE RULE OF LAW 47
other acts that the people accomplished that have somehow been lost Moses descends with the law as a new gift from God that will se-
to us or that we may still discover. Finding new historical sources may cure the nation in what would otherwise be the chaotic time—and
tell us a good deal about particular historical actors, but it cannot tell space—of the Exodus. This law is simultaneously a product and a
us that we were "wrong" in our beliefs about the people or that "we" continuing representation of the divine origins of the community.
are actually something other than what we thought we were. This Keeping the law maintains the meaning—and thus the presence—
does not mean that nothing new will ever appear to have been done of the divine intervention. For this reason, the authority of the legal
by "the people." Law, however, is a matter of interpreting what the decision is always located outside of the decision maker. To claim for
people have always already done; it is not the doing itself. the self an authority to make law is blasphemous. We see remnants of
Law is not the product of a single, collective subject. Rather, that this idea in the passion with which critics accuse the Court of making,
subject is the product of a social practice of law's rule. Indeed, if we rather than maintaining, law; we see it again in the always reaffirmed
were to find ourselves in a situation in which the people actually ap- belief that a legal order subjects the legal decision makers to the same
peared to be acting in the present, we would be outside of law's rule. rules of law as everyone else. Apart from the sovereign source of law,
We often call that situation "revolution." everyone stands equally under the legal rules.
A genealogical approach must look for the historical confluence of Every legal decision ultimately traces its authority back to this ap-
these different ideas: the-unitary actor that appears in and through pearance of the sacred. The fact of a beginning makes history deter-
the legal order of the st&te, the authority of law as the maintenance minate, rather than an endless inquiry into a deeper and deeper past.
of the community's past, and the past as the source of an ultimate T h e meaning of the nation of Israel, to those who understand
meaning in the present! We do not have to look very far for the ori- themselves as a part of that community, is its continuing representa-
gins of this conception of law. The shape of time under the rule tion, in ordinary time, of the divine intervention. Law creates a single
of law has its origins in the Old Testament idea of the linear history identity in what would otherwise be a changing community, or com-
of the nation of Israel.23 That history has a beginning in God's reve- munities, through time. History now stands against mere time as a
lation to Abram; it also has an eschatological vision. History will end meaningful order with a unitary theme; it has a beginning and it will
with a second, divine revelation. The history of the nation is the time have an end. Because the end is imagined from the beginning, history
in between these two moments of revelation. Law is the unifying or- is unified and linear. The time of law carries forward a representation
der of the community that exists suspended between these epiphanic of the origins, but only a representation. Participation in law is not a
moments. Law carries forward the authority of the origin. Without return to origins. Law's time, unlike the sacred time of archaic man,
adherence to law, some other point of origin might come to define is not circular.24 The second coming is not a return to origins in order
the community. This is the biblical problem of worshiping false gods. to. repeat the whole process, but rather the end of a single, unique
The divine enters the community through an act of law giving. temporal progression. Law thus points backwards and forwards at
Through maintenance of law, the order of the community becomes once; it carries the beginning forward toward an end that it has al-
a continuing representation of the divine. Law marks the passage in ready imagined. That end is not just another event within the pro-
both directions, the point of transit between the sacred and the pro- fane history of the state, but a new intervention of the sacred into
fane. Thus, following the law links the present moment back to a ordinary time. If time continues after that point, it will be as a new
divine beginning. That linkage is the historical life of the commu- history.
nity. The linking of law to the origin makes every point of political In this religious tradition, law makes history possible, but historical
time a continuation of a narrative of ultimate—i.e., sacred—signifi- time is bounded on both sides by an experience of revelation that is
cance. This is not just time travel in the individual imagination. The beyond law and outside of history. There is no "accounting for" the
lived experience of a community carries this meaning through time beginning or the end. Law has no control over these moments be-
and space, while suffering personal sacrifices to insure that this his- yond law that define its temporal domain. They are causally and nor-
tory continues to its imagined end. This imaginative construction be- matively inexplicable. In this tradition, a prelegal state of nature, as
comes a fact as real and objective as our language, our families, and secular political philosophers have developed the idea, makes no ap-
our communities. For it, individuals live and die. pearance. Law succeeds revelation, not nature. A failure to maintain
CHAPTER TWO IMAGINING THE RULE OF LAW 49
law appears not as a return to nature, but as a loss of divine meaning through the memory— or more exactly, what appears as if it were a
and thus a state of sin. Our modern, secular idea of law maintains memory— of a prior act. As with a dream, we may inquire into the
this remnant, even as it takes up a parallel conception of law's origin past acts that are the objective source or cause of the appearance. Yet
out of a state of nature. identifying those particular events will not tell us the meaning of the
Genealogy explores our conception of law's time as a remnant of appearance, but at best only the occasions that brought it forth. We
this deep tradition. We maintain a secularized version of this concep- cannot get to the meaning of the dream or of the remembered ap-
tion of legal time which continues this relationship of the sacred to pearance of the people except by interpreting the appearance itself.
the profane. For us, every legal decision traces its authority back For Americans, law's origin is characterized by a radical otherness.
to the sovereign people who have usurped the power of God in the In contrast, for a common-law tradition, law appears to emerge from
modern political world. It is often said that law is our civic religion.23 a deep past that is fundamentally the same as the present. In the
We can be more precise in understanding how law takes up and re- classic common law, law emerges from more law: it is law all the way
deploys a religious conception of history. In a post-Enlightenment down. 27 This is a "monist" view of history in which the present is
world, revolution replaces revelation, just as the popular sovereign the same as the past and the future will be more of the same. This
replaces the divine sovereign. The new popular sovereign displays common-law conception of law results in a reciprocal conception of
itself and intervenes in^ history through an act of revolution. Law the sovereign. In the British tradition, law precedes any particular act
remains an order of "history bound at its beginning and its end by of the sovereign, which can always intervene to change law—the
extraordinary acts that are beyond law and yet produce law. doctrine of Parliamentary sovereignty. Law is the context against
Revolution has the1 dual meaning of ending and beginning. A which the sovereign acts. For Americans, on the other hand, the sov-
revolution terminates one political order and begins another. Both ereign action always occurred prior to law. Law is the consequence
objectives are accomplished through an extraordinary act of revela- of sovereign action. Parliamentary sovereignty here would look like a
tion by the popular sovereign. For us, revolution and constitution congressional abuse of power, even when supported by popular opin-
making are inseparable: what is it that the people do in and through ion and a contemporary majority.
revolution? They write a constitution. 26 We understand that act as Thus, the American conception of law's rule always locates the
the "origin" or "founding" of the state. It is conceptually, if not liter- origin of law in acts beyond law. At the most general level, this is
ally (as in French and Cambodian revolutions), year "zero" in the the relationship of law to revolution. We continue to privilege this
state's calendar. Without a successful constitutional product, revolu- distinction in the supreme authority we vest in the Constitution. At
tion is unsuccessful. Indeed, without a constitution, what looked like the level of ordinary affairs, we insist on the distinction between poli-
revolution was not really revolution at all. T h e states that joined the tics and law. The process of law-making is political; politics ends,
Confederacy did not have a revolution. Rather, they engaged in an however, once law begins. This distinction separates judges—i.e.,
illegal act of rebellion. We know this because their project of consti- those who apply the law—from political representatives—those who
tutional creation failed. make new law. Even about these "political" acts of law-making,
Thus, the rule of law continues to appear as the maintenance of however, we can ask whether they are lawful. When we do this, we
the extraordinary, revelatory act of the sovereign through ordinary shift perspective from the particular statutory or regulatory output
time. The history of the state is the maintenance of law, which means to the process itself. That process must be authorized by law. When
that through law we create an order of daily life that gains its unity we trace that law, we tell a story that eventually takes us back to the
through the memory of the truth revealed by the sovereign people. origin of all law in the sovereign act of the people: the revolutionary
Again, this does not mean that this truth exists independendy of construction of a constitution. Thus, a particular regulatory decision
memory as if it were something that we could objectively discover may be authorized by a prior judicial decision, which may have in-
and measure. That truth is simply not available to those outside of terpreted a regulation, which was authorized by a statute, which in
the political community. They may see rebellion or merely violence turn was authorized by the Constitution, the authority of which
in place of revolution; they may see illusion in place of law's represen- comes from the people. This story of origins must be attachable to
tation of the sovereign act. The experience of that truth is only every event within the polity. This is the core narrative of judicial
50 CHAPTER TWO IMAGINING THE RULE OF LAW 51
review, and why the Supreme Court has the ultimate authority to say that there is nothing left over for God to know. Predestination is secu-
what the law is. At stake is the identity of the community as an his- larized and put within the reach of man's mind now enlarged and
torically continuous expression of the sovereign people. projected in the supercomputer. Any surplus knowledge God might
How do we conceive of this "sacred" act of self-revelation by the possess would have to be of the miraculous—i.e., that which is with-
sovereign people, which is both beginning and end of law? It does not out reasonable explanation—but this possibility is excluded in ad-
appear to us as an inexplicable mysterium tremendum, although it surely vance by the scientific mind. If God's unique knowledge can only be
still carries remnants of mystery. Secularizing the mystery of the sa- of the miraculous, then we can do without divine knowledge.
cred, we lack words to describe the attachment of the community to The same eclipse of the sovereign may be happening politically. If
its own foundation. We turn to the language of the Enlightenment the mind of the popular sovereign is pure reason, then the traditional
and to secular political philosophers—we turn, in short, to the virtues temporal structure of law will inevitably be threatened by the rise of
of reason and will, because this is the only political language we know. an administrative state guided by a number of policy sciences. In-
Although thought of as an expression of the sovereign will, the found- deed, the legal realists made just this challenge to the structure of
ing act is equally imagined as a kind of pure reason focused on the legal belief. Law's knowledge, if not the same as that of the social
public good. Thomas Jefferson, although not at Philadelphia, cap- sciences, had to be a false claim to knowledge. The surplus to which
tures this spirit of ^will expressing itself in pure reason, when he law could lay claim was only the irrational, which has the same status
imagines enactment "of codes "adopted to our republican form of for the policy scientist as the miraculous has for the natural scientist.
g o v e r n m e n t . . . with a single eye to reason, and the good of those for Law's myth of the people acting on the basis of reason at the moment
whose governmenrit was framed." 28 This is will unsullied by private of origins is undermined by new forms of reason that are operation-
passions or factional interests. When the people truly act, they deploy alized by experts administering the mundane operations of the wel-
pure reason in the pursuit of justice. This is the ideal, even as we fare state. The modern science of governance may look more like the
recognize that any particular expression of popular sovereignty may policy decisions of the Federal Reserve than the republicanism of the
not be pure; it may be mingled with factional interests. The threat of Founders. The state as law's rule may be undermined, over the long
these factional interests makes a new appearance now as the state term, by its own claim to the virtue of reason.
of nature. T h e constitutional project appears simultaneously as the Revolutionary beginnings and endings are not the only temporal
overcoming of nature and of the injustice of a prior political order. structures that are important to law's rule. Turning from genealogy
That the people might act irrationally—or even rationally pursue to architecture, we turn from the extraordinary, sacred past to the
unjust ends—is an idea with which we are familiar; take for example, ordinary, profane present. The architectural inquiry starts by noting
the Constitution's protection of slavery. But to the degree that people a curious kind of temporal flatness in the relationship of legal texts
act unjustly, they are never quite the popular sovereign itself. Slavery and resources to each other. This flatness is just the opposite of the
was protected by the Constitution because factional interests de- sharp contrast between revolution and law that genealogy traces.
manded it as a political matter, not because the sovereign people All law exists in a condition of simultaneity. This is not, however,
willed it. At least, this is the way the legal imagination remembers the the simultaneity of a mathematical proof. Legal argument moves
event.29 Having purged the evil of slavery, we are now more confident through authoritative sources neither by tracing a process of chrono-
in imagining a convergence of reason and will in the revolutionary logical development nor by formal logic. Instead, it constructs analo-
act of the popular sovereign. gies. Through analogy the present moment can be linked to any
Placing reason in the mind of the popular sovereign has had a other moment. 30 We cannot know in advance what point in law's past
destabilizing effect on belief in the sovereign in the modern period. will suddenly become the resource for an analogical construction. We
Arguably, we see a similar effect with respect to God. Insofar as mod- can think of the time of legal texts as rather like the time of a work of
ern science seeks to understand the fundamental elements and laws fiction. The work is read sequentially, but it all exists from the begin-
of the universe, from which all else follows, it seeks to replicate the ning. We can open it up at any place. Law too may show itself to us
mind of God. Success within such an epistemic project would mean sequentially, but that time of learning or discovery is not law's time.
52 CHAPTER TWO IMAGINING THE RULE OF LAW 53
To identify a proposition as a statement of law is to recognize its this a normative claim about legitimate methods of interpretation un-
current authority. Statutes or judicial decisions are not more authori- der law—although it does suggest the conceptual framework within
tative the more recent they are. There are, of course, procedures for which various theories of interpretation contest against each other. It
overruling a decision or repealing a statute, but as long as the past is, rather, an observation of the place of the distinction between in-
act has not been negated, its place in the chronology of decision- terpretation and invention in the legal imagination. An interpretation
making does not matter. 31 Thus, within the rule of law the past does that fails to appear as a rediscovery will appear as an illegitimate
not always cause the present. It is common to find the sequence run- construction of new law. New law is not law at all; it is only a false
ning the other way: a present decision determines the meaning of a appearance of law. For that reason, the Court will expunge whatever
past one. For example, in Planned Parenthood v. Casey, the Court upheld it sees in this way, simultaneously identifying a past act—whether its
a right to an abortion in the period before fetal viability, but allowed own or that of a political institution of government—as novel and
the state to impose conditions upon this right. 32 It asserted that its I eliminating it from the timeless present of the real law. T h e best ex-
decision was required by the principle of stare decisis as applied to ample of this is the "myth of recovery" by which the post-Lochner
the holding of Roe v. Wade. In fact Roe does not account for Casey. Court expunged the novel acts of the Lochner Court and returned to
Rather, Casey determines the meaning of Roe by substantially narrow- the timeless law of John Marshall. 34 This same myth of recovery op-
ing what we might have thought the case held. erates in every overruling of a precedent: without a conceptual space
Judicial opinions -do not operate in the same temporal succession for novelty, every new act must be made to seem a recovery.35 This
within which we experience natural phenomena or even other polit- same temporal intuition is behind the judicial concern that a failure
ical phenomena. O n e political act disappears in the face of another. to make rulings retroactive violates the rule of law. Prospectivity can
For law, the past is still present—or it is not law. Thus, judicial opin- appear as convenient policy, yet seem lawless.36 To interpret the law
ions exist side-by-side in the volumes of judicial reporters, just as is to make explicit what has been there all along.
statutes are arranged in a code organized by topic rather than by This description of law's present best fits the internal temporality
chronological order of passage. 33 Every judicial opinion can serve as of the judicial opinion. It is not a description of the way in which
a precedent; each can become the point of origin for a new legal policy-making appears to legislatures or regulatory agencies. But if
holding. Progress in law cannot be marked in any simple way by the we look at those institutions from the perspective of law, we find the
addition of new volumes to the series of reporters or by additional same temporal characteristics that are evident in the judicial opinion.
volumes of the United States Code Annotated or the Code of Federal We can ask whether any particular legislative act is lawful, in which
Regulations. case we understand the legislature not from the perspective of policy-
This uniform presence of law is not limited to the volumes record- making but rather from that of realizing a possibility that has always
ing judicial, statutory, and regulatory output. It is deeply imbedded been there. We answer this question by arguing from existing legal
in all of our public law. We see it, for example, in the Court's easy use resources, and we advance that argument through analogical reason-
of an atemporal "we" to speak about past decisions. The same judi- ing. Policy judgments are, from a legal point of view, exercises of an
cial subject, acting across all time, decided the past cases and must already authorized discretion. If we have to ask whether any particu-
decide the present ones. This subject, who authoritatively announces lar regulatory act is lawful, the argument will move through a series
the law, exists in the same extended temporal present as the law itself. of legal resources that ultimately extends to the Constitution itself.
The subject and the object share a temporal symmetry: a timeless We understand the entire. universe of possible actions within the
subject views a timeless law. polity as already structured by law. There is no further domain to
To the degree that our public law appears as an interpretation of which law does not extend. It used to be said that law was silent in
the Constitution, it too fails to fit within an ordinary conception of time of war: Inter arma silent leges. But the explicit extension of legal
temporal progression. T h e point of legal interpretation is always to norms to combat, as well as to decisions whether to deploy forces, has
recover, i.e., to make present, something that appears already to ex- been one of the most prominent features of twentieth-century politi-
ist. Of course, this does not mean it actually exists, as if interpreta- cal developments. 37
tion were the discovery of an object hidden in another room. Nor is The temporal structure of scientific inquiry does not apply to the
IMAGINING THE RULE OF LAW 55
54 CHAPTER TWO
rule of law. The history of scientific inquiry is a narrative of progress the future. It is difficult even to make sense of a claim that our law is
in which the present constantly supersedes the past. The history of getting better. What would be the appropriate measure? No one
law's rule, on the other hand, is a collection of interpretive commen- would choose nineteenth-century medicine over that of the twentieth
taries. The judicial opinion takes the form of "commentary," a writ- century, but is it the case that no one would prefer the Marshall Court
ing that gains its authority from a prior writing. There is a tradition to that of Rehnquist? Indeed, the idea of a "golden age" from which
of legal scholarship that views the legislative act in the same way, we have declined seems a recurring aspect of the constellation of be-
describing every bill as a commentary by Congress on its consti- liefs attached to law's rule. Those most attached to law—the law
tutional responsibilities.36 One commentary cannot definitively dis- professors—are most likely to long for that golden age.41 Again, this
place another, because each locates its authority in the same source is a function of the conceptual shape of commentary in which the
outside of itself. None can claim to be final, because no commentary future is always bound to authoritative origins.
has the power to declare itself the last word. Commentary, more- This may seem a strange claim given the focus on "reform" that
over, does not necessarily "improve" with time. Indeed, the argu- I attributed to contemporary legal practice in chapter 1, since reform
ment can always be made that it gets worse: commentary may be suggests a belief in progress. There is a tension, but not a contradic-
more reliable the closer it is to the original text. We see such argu- tion, here. The tension is just that built into the structure of commen-
ments made, for example, about the privileged position of the First tary, between claims for erudition and claims for a return to origins.
Congress or the insights of The Federalist Papers. To this claim, others Not even "reform" is a stable temporal norm. Thus, for those law
will always respond that commentary does indeed improve over time. professors who long for the golden age of law, reform is identified
It grows more "sophisticated" by building on the insights of earlier with recovery. Reform and interpretation are one and the same pro-
cess under the rule of law. Reform in law is a process of realizing
commentaries.
meanings we take to be already present. The lawyer or judge who
This is the structure of debate within a field of commentary: a con-
works toward reform of law believes she is telling us what the law
stant dialectic between the claim for scholarly erudition and a coun-
already is. Of law's rule, we can say with the ancient philosopher
terclaim for return to the original text. This is as true of law as it is of
Heraclitus, "the way up and the way down are one and the same."
biblical hermeneutics. This is not a debate that can be resolved by
choosing one side or by achieving a final synthesis because both in-
Law's Space
terpretive positions appeal to an essential aspect of commentary.
Thus, under the rule of law we are not moving unambiguously This sketch of law's time only sets forth the major elements that a
toward a better future. The truth of law can appear at any point in cultural approach to law's rule would have to pursue in detail. A simi-
the history of the nation. All law remains available at every moment. lar study must be made of the character of space within the practice
Indeed, even law that has been overruled and seems dead can return of law's rule. Again, there must be a genealogy and an architecture.
to life. What had been taken for true can come to appear as error, The genealogy of space focuses on the concept of the border—yet
just as error can come to be seen as truth. 39 That which seems per- another concept redolent with remnants from the larger tradition of
manently past—for example, Dred Scott—is excluded by the limits of Western religious and political experience.
the present imagination, not by some unalterable character of the The rule of law is always rule over a defined territory. Morality
legal sources or some fact of legal progress. Bruce Ackerman has re- may be without borders, but law's rule begins only with the imagi-
cently shown the questionable "legal" validity of the passage of the nation of jurisdiction. We have moral, but not legal, obligations to
Thirteenth and Fourteenth Amendments. 40 Such arguments could be those beyond our borders. No matter how reasonable the law, reason
used to recover the "true" Constitution, of which Dred Scott was the alone does not authorize the extension of law's rule over the popula-
"correct" interpretation. We can confidently predict that this will not tion of a foreign territory.42 We cannot rule others under law simply
happen, but not because the law does not permit it. Rather, our con- because it would be "good" for them. We might be doing the morally
fidence rests on the place of slavery in the total constellation of con- correct thing in coercing others to comply with our legal standards,
temporary beliefs. but those who experience such coercion, as well as those who do the
The past of law's rule is not necessarily worse than the present or coercing, do not perceive it as the rule of law. Americans know this
56 CHAPTER TWO IMAGINING THE RULE OF LAW 57
intuitively as an aspect of their collective memory of the origins of Space appears first as a representation of meaning derived from out-
law's rule in the Revolution against British rule in colonial America. side of the self. Only later does territory become property, i.e., the
No country had, at that time, a stronger claim to the rule of law than possession of particular subjects. Social contract theorists imagine
Great Britain. Moreover, the law that Parliament attempted to ex- property before the state, as if man in the state of nature is a property
tend to the Colonies was arg- " 'y reasonable. A main point of con- holder. They imagine the state's territory as the aggregation of these
tention concerned the British effort to tax the Colonies in order to property interests, brought about by the consent of the owners. But
force them to pay part of the cost of their own defense.43 The problem territory appears as property only to those already within an imag-
was not the absence of law, or even the unreasonableness of the ap- ined political space.48 The myth of a propertied state of nature is a
plicable law, but the separation of territorial jurisdiction. British law justification of law's rule, not a genealogical account of law's origin.
was perceived as foreign law within the colonial jurisdiction. And rule From an external perspective, one claim to possession may be no
by foreign law is not the rule of law at all. better than another. Possession often has its origin in dispossession.
Just as the reason of law alone is not the ground of a jurisdictional Yet the community does not imagine its link to territory as founded
claim, neither is consent an adequate account of the reach of law's upon a great act of injustice. It accepts instead a narrative of the gift
space. The problem of law's geographical locus is not a technical that privileges one claim to territory over competing claims. To those
question of the breadth of electoral participation in the choice of rep- outside that narrative, law's rule may begin with an act of theft and
resentatives^—-althougfi -jurisdictional unease may be expressed in remain a form of external coercion. This spatial conception of law's
this form at the revolutionary moment. The imagination of political origins is reflected in the idea of "domestic dependent nations," al-
space, however, exists-prior to efforts to justify the geographical reach ready applied by the Marshall Court to Native Americans. 49 The
of law. Representation, even as the eighteenth-century arguments narrative of borders, accordingly, establishes insiders and outsiders.
demonstrated, is a plastic concept. 44 There are multiple forms of rep- It necessarily excludes in order to preserve the identity of those
resentation, not all of which involve voting or sending one's "own" within.
representative to a legislative body. Representation, for example, can The genealogy of legal space also explores the unstable relation-
include those who do not participate in the political process because ship between the idea of the state as one among m a n y — a commu-
they are too young, do not yet exist, or have already died. Similarly, nity of states—and the idea of empire. Again, this is an idea with
consent can take multiple forms, both explicit and implicit. Noncon- deep religious roots. The nation of Israel is simultaneously a unique
sensual forms of government are not necessarily "unrepresentative." community among many—marked by its covenant with God and
Arguments about representation and consent come up too late to the gift of a particular territory—and destined to be the source of a
capture the fundamental intuition that a government's rule appears single community on earth. When the messiah comes, it will be for
as an illegitimate extension of power from one bordered space to an- all men, not just for the Jews. Overcoming space is linked to over-
other. The modern process of decolonization could not have been coming time: the end of history also marks the end of spatial limits.
stopped by an extension of the system of representation. There can In both respects, divine presence overcomes representational dis-
be multiple systems of representation in a single space, but there is tance. Thus, the Jewish split with the early Christian community rests
only one state.45 not only on a disagreement over the character of the nation's time—
Law's space is always bordered space. The genealogy of this con- is the age of law over?—but also over the character of its space. Saint
cept takes us quickly back to an image of sacred space. The border is Paul, who believed the Second Coming was at hand, undermined
a kind of historical marker, representing the intersection of a geog- distinctions of space, spreading the Christian truth to gentile com-
raphy of place with a narrative of events.46 The border distinguishes munities. He is a person without place and thus a person of all places.
a particular territory that has become a representation of sacred The very idea of his proselytizing wanderings suggests a new concep-
meaning. Bordered space is a gift—first from the gods, but then from tion of space in which the border now appears as that which is to be
one's predecessors. 47 The narrative of the gift's origin establishes a overcome. Paul symbolizes this on the micro-level by insisting upon
locus of responsibility: the community is responsible for this land. eating with gentiles: he will enter their space—their households—
58 CHAPTER TWO IMAGINING THE RULE OF LAW 59
and be a part of their communities as he tries to overcome all distinc- the nineteenth-century struggle over the proper conception of the
tions.50 The Jewish community would remain within its own jurisdic- federal state—was it a confederation of separate states, each under
tion, separate and unique from others.51 their own rule of law, or the singular source of law's rule for the entire
Ideas of limits and of transcending the limits continue to operate nation? 54 The victory of the national state on the battlefield did not
simultaneously in our conception of the border. We live with this am- translate into a similar defeat of the state-centered view of the nature
biguity when we take law's rule as our own unique practice but be- of the legal order. Very soon after the Civil War, we find the Supreme
lieve it to be the only possible "correct" form of government. The Court recovering the old ambiguity, protecting states from the na-
rule of law needs the border to mark, and thus make possible, its own tional government because ours is an "indestructible Union, com-
community of self-government. But it cannot rest within any limits. posed of indestructible states." 55 The idea of confederation remains
We proselytize law's rule as a rule of multiple nations each under law's a continually attractive counterpoint to the tendency toward empire.
rule. Simultaneously, we envision a single world order under law. We American constitutional law has a kind of cyclical relationship to
do not know whether law's rule points to one community or to many, these two ideas, moving back and forth between a nationalist and a
to empire or to nations. In either case, we imagine the other—those state-centered view.56
outside our space—as fundamentally like ourselves. The rule of law We see this same spatial ambiguity reflected in the introductory
steps into the place of the sacred, and as such we cannot imagine a remarks to The Federalist Papers. The question, we are told by Publius,
competing meaning that Could stand up to it. Law is both uniquely involves "the fate of an empire in many respects the most interesting
ours and our message'to the world. Such ambiguities cannot be re- in the world." Here will be decided the issue of whether law can be
solved; they rest on the structure of thought that is constitutive of the the product of the people's deliberate, democratic design. This proj-
world of law.52 ect can only begin within a space that has secured its borders against
Law's apparent origin in reason and will cannot help to resolve competing claims. Nevertheless, the rule of law that the border makes
this spatial ambiguity. If the order of law is the expression of reason, possible inevitably overflows those borders: at stake is not just one
there would seem to be an inevitable momentum toward empire, i.e., nation, but the world. The border, accordingly, makes law possible
a single world under reason's law. If, on the other hand, law is the at the same time that law seems to transcend its own limits.
expression of will, then movement would be toward multiple states, We see here, in earliest form, the problem of the colony for the
each with its own rule of law. As with all such arguments, however, practice of law's rule. This problem would plague the West for the
the terms can be reversed. If reason is a matter of experience and next two hundred years. There were two patterns of thought about
experiments, multiple states may be more likely to achieve reason in the long-term relationship of colony to colonizer. One believed that
law.53 Or, reason may be specific to context: what is reasonable for a the end of the process would be incorporation of the colony into the
Third World state may not be reasonable for an industrialized wel- metropolis such that the territory expanded into one extended na-
fare state. If the will of the community precedes law, then the bounda- tion. With some exceptions, this was the American pattern. 57 Law
ries of the state may be established through a conception of the nation overcame existing borders in the direction of empire. The other pat-
that pushes well beyond traditional borders—e.g., Germans or Rus- tern understood colonization as a kind of trusteeship, which would
sians living abroad or Jews in Diaspora. If there is no appeal to a end when the colony was capable of independent statehood under its
prelegal nation, then consent may take a radically individual form: own rule of law. This was the British pattern, which envisioned mul-
adding one's will to that of the group makes one a citizen. If so, there tiple states under law's rule, joined loosely in the Commonwealth. 58
are no borders that cannot be overcome by the appeal to consent. The one thing that was not compatible with the rule of law was the
Indeed, for this reason, liberal political theory, which assumes indi- fact of the situation: subordination of the colonial territory to the
vidual consent as its first principle, has never been able to stabilize a colonizing power as a permanent, structural relationship. This re-
conception of borders. Liberal theory seems to move inexorably to- quired an ideology of racism, not law. There has, for this reason,
ward world government. always been an air of lawlessness about the law with regard to Native
American history is bound up with these particular spatial ambi- Americans. 59 When this view of permanent subordination was actu-
guities of empire versus federation. Law's space was at the heart of ally given formal recognition, the territory of the colony appeared as
6o CHAPTER TWO IMAGINING THE RULE OF LAW 6l
a possession, not as a national gift.60 This reduces the political con- happen to share a set of symbolic forms. The power of the king was
ception ofjurisdictional space to a private claim of ownership. It cor- thought to flow from Christ. The king remained a visible presence of
respondingly reduces the populace from citizens to objects. To, the Christ on earth. The separation of the political from the religious
colonized, there was little distinction between the metropolis's claims remained for the future.
of possession or of gift. The act of dispossession set the modern A genealogy of law's rule must investigate the transition from the
agenda of revolution as decolonization. mystery of instantiation in the kingly corpus to the representation
The genealogy of law's space examines not only the place of the of political geography on the map. 63 This transformation of political
border, but also the forms of representation of bordered space. Here, space was a product of many changes: the general displacement of
there has been a fundamental transformation from premodern to instantiation by representation in the Reformation, the rise of com-
modern Western thought. Briefly stated, the map has replaced the petitive nation-states in place of an ideal political/religious empire as
king's body. For us, the territory of the state is represented by a the political norm, the growth of civil society, and the rise of political
m a p — a deliberately constructed, artificial representation. A repre- theory that attempted to build the state out of a conception of indi-
sentation is a sign that can be replaced by another equally functional vidual rights. Here, I want to emphasize only one aspect of the tran-
representation. Thus, the marks on the map are wholly arbitrary. sition: its problematic link to the identification of the sovereign voice
The king's body represented nothing; it was the corpus of the state. with the voice of reason. Were the law to be wholly a product of
At the heart of the imagination of the pre-modern state was the reason, it could be mapped onto any geographical space. The space
mystery of instantiation: not the quantitative experience of spatial of the state would be wholly arbitrary, since its organization would
extension, but a qualitative experience of otherness.61 be disconnected from the particularities of any narrative concerning
By projecting political territory onto a representation of geogra- that space. An extreme version of this is the market, which as a sys-
phy, the map suggests the divisible and thus contingent character of tem of exchange knows no borders. The same could be said of a
the state. Borders are subject to divisions and redirection. The map- Rawlsian idea of the rule of law in a liberal state: behind the veil of
pable state can always be remade. T h e king's body, on the other ignorance one is nowhere, and so, potentially, everywhere. T h e king's
hand, was indivisible. The whole of the state was present in the king body, however, had no prior commitment to reason. Coke claimed
as a form of mystical instantiation. The geography of state was as reason for law and opposed both law and reason to the king's claim
much that of the king's court as the territory of the domain. 62 Prox- that he is the state as sovereign will and mystical corpus. 64
imity to the king was a more important spatial relationship than ter- This concept of the mystical body of the king was traditionally
ritorial possession. The state experienced in the king's body was not linked with faith healing, practiced by both King James and King
only an indivisible spatial whole, but also an indivisible temporal Louis XVI. 65 The mappable state has no power to heal the body,
whole. T h e body of the king, as the mystery of the state, never died. yet the executive retains the power to pardon—an idea wholly at
Here too political order drew upon religious antecedents. variance with the norms of legal rule and accountability. Similarly,
Christ's body is the corpus of the Church. Through the Church— we remain attached to ideas of sovereign immunity. This suggests
and particularly the sacrament of the Eucharist— one is "born again" that map and reason will not give us an adequate understanding
in Christ. This is a sacred geography in which the physical body of the space of the state even under the rule of law. Law's space has
transcends its own finitude. The Church is in space but without geo- not entirely shed its sacred origins. It has, however, shed ideas of
graphical borders that can be represented on a map; it is in time, but qualitative difference within the jurisdiction. The rule of law applies
not as a temporally divisible set of chronologically ordered events. equally within all of the state's space.66 Modern law's space has about
Christ is always; He has always been everywhere at once. Similarly, it the equality of popular sovereignty, rather than the inequality of
the king's body, as the mysterious corpus of the state, was constitutive the monarch.
of a sacred geography. It too was timeless and complete. As a part of Legal genealogy must therefore investigate the remnants of the
the state, the individual was a part of the king's body, just as he was mystical corpus of the state in the contemporary imagination. The
a part of Christ through the Church. King and Christ did not just king's body had a kind of infinite or incomparable value. This remains

!
il
62 CHAPTER TWO IMAGINING THE RULE OF LAW 63
true of the body of the state under law's rule. This is the lesson of problem of borders—and contraction—the problem of seeing the
mutual assured destruction as the ultimate modern strategy of mili- whole in the part. Genealogy must take up both aspects to show us
tary defense. Rather than lose political identity, the state announces the imaginative materials out of which law's space is built.
its willingness to destroy itself entirely. This is hardly the state as a The architectural study of legal space focuses on the conceptions
product of reason. 67 We have divided up the mysterious corpus of the of property and jurisdiction. Space does not appear to the legal
king's body and distributed it equally among all citizens. Yet, what imagination as either abstract location or natural terrain. Over the
each possesses is still a mystery of infinite value. Everyone is king, geographic world of location, law spreads a complete conceptual
because no one is. Each citizen can become a focal point through grid. Within the ongoing practice of law's rule, any particular space
which the whole of the state appears. T h e monument to the king is appears first of all as property. T h e rule of law begins its modern life
replaced by the tomb of the unknown soldier. with the idea of property. Before he or she is anything else, the citizen
Lincoln captures this inversion in his Gettysburg Address, when under law is a property holder. Reflecting on the centrality of the
he places the power to consecrate space in the common soldiers who concept of property to early-nineteenth-century American jurispru-
have died rather than in a political leader's words. Yet we will not dence, Perry Miller writes: "there can be no question that the legalists
capture the power of the image of Lincoln himself in our political of unification had, ever since the Revolution, done a thoroughjob of
imagination if we take his address as a complete description of the making the reign of law in the country one with the inviolability of
sources of sacred space in a democratic polity under law. If the Civil property." 70 Law makes possible a regime of property by securing the
War begins from a ^vision of the divisibility of the mappable state, property holder against the possessive or predatory interests of oth-
Lincoln's life and nfartyrdom come to symbolize, now in a secular ers, including those who wield the coercive power of the state. Be-
form, the unity of the state in the king's body. Lincoln symbolizes yond protecting possession against the immediate threats of theft and
every man as king—the poor farmboy who becomes president—as trespass, law creates a stable and predictable future, which in turn
well as the symbolic confluence of the king's body and the rule of law allows for property dispositions of indefinite duration. Legal property
in the martyr to the Constitution. interests can be without temporal limits just in the way that every
We find another remnant—although one that points in a different legal rule is without limit. This is exactly the difference between prop-
direction-—in law's insistence that all property is fungible, i.e., there erty and possession.
is a monetized value of every property interest. Money is the contem- There is no space to which legal claims of ownership cannot be
porary, universal solvent.615 No individual can so invest himself in any made: all of the state's territory is property. Indeed, modern govern-
particular property interest such that his claim must be distinguished ment under law's rule comes to be seen as another owner of property.
from, and privileged above, all others. Law flattens all such claims, It is often the first property owner—-the originator of particular
transforming them not through the solvent of the king's body but claims to property—and the last owner—the owner by default when
through the mystery of monetary value. The mystical corpus of the other property claims fail. In between, it appears as a property owner
modern state under law's rule may be money. Money functions as a like everyone else, owning discrete parcels of property that exist
kind of material expression of the power of analogy under law's rule. alongside others. If it chooses to increase its property ownership, it
Just as analogy can connect any proposition of law with any other, must pay for its acquisitions the same as anyone else. There is no
money connects any interest with every other interest. Monetary power of eminent domain apart from "just compensation." 7 '
valuation is simply the expression of analogical equivalents. Both Spatial relations under law appear, therefore, as relations among
should be contrasted to the infinite value of the king and the king's property holders. This is a relationship that makes no appearance
claim to make law through his word. To consider money as only a to those outside of the state's law. They see only the political terri-
reasonable means of exchange fails to capture the full value of money tory of the nation, not an aggregation of particular property inter-
in its relationship to the meaning of the state. The British resistance ests.72 Under law, however, the question of where is always a predicate
to the Eurodollar is not wholly answered in terms of markets and to the question of who: who owns it? Property claims need not be
efficiency.69 absolute; there may be multiple claims of ownership centered on the
Law's space, then, has the double character of extension—the same object or place. Other legal relationships to property are built
64 CHAPTER TWO IMAGINING THE RULE OF LAW 65
out of this conception of ownership—e.g., questions of responsibility and complete. For example, jurisdiction may be conceived of as a
and use. kind of first-order property claim: all territory belongs to the state
The metaphor of a grid suggests the mappable character of prop- before it belongs to particular parties. Jurisdiction then appears as a
erty. All property can be located in relationship to all other property. kind of nondelegable right of ownership with priority over all other
r
This is not, however, a relationship of one geographic space to an- ownership claims.73 We see a modern remnant of this traditional idea
other. Law's space is not discoverable in the world; it is rather a linking ownership and jurisdiction in the constitutional law of pri-
particular form of discourse among those who share a common set of vacy. Here, an idea of property in the body (it is exclusively my body)
beliefs relating space to persons. Property claims rest on an historical is linked to jurisdiction (I alone have authority to decide about its
narrative that traces ownership. Thus, to describe space under law disposition). We are each king, if not exacdy in our homes, then at
we trace title. Titles move simultaneously across a horizontal and ver- least in the limited principality of the body.
tical dimension. The deed describes one property in terms of its re- We can see another example of the interpenetration of property
lationship to surrounding properties. The transfer of title sets this syn- and jurisdiction in the conceptual world of the p r e - N e w Deal Court.
chronous narrative of place in relationship to a diachronic narrative That Court's defense of a property regime as a matter of substantive
of personal succession. due process is well known. Also well known is its defense of state ju-
As with law's time, these shared beliefs about property can sup- risdiction against federal regulatory efforts.74 These are linked not
port competing a n d contradictory claims. Just as there is always just as mutual supports of a free market order, 75 but conceptually as
more than one available precedent, there are often multiple stories well. The Court approached jurisdictional issues from a perspective
of ownership. Any particular narrative is always exhausted before it of property. It analogized the state and national governments to com-
reaches an uncontrovertible foundation. It simply recedes into the peting property owners. It thought of federal regulation as a form of
past where, eventually, explanations fail. Law's space is not a just dis- "trespass" upon state property interests. It worried about "invasion"
tribution from first principles. A property regime is an ongoing pro- of state interests by the federal government. It deployed common-law
ject in which the distribution has always already occurred. T h e cul- categories of spatial relationships to understand the constitutional
tural approach to law seeks to expose the structures of thought that relationship of state and federal government. It appealed, for ex-
make this project possible. It is not concerned with the justice or in- ample, to spatial metaphors of causation across distance—proximate
justice of property, nor with correct beliefs about particular property cause—in order to maintain an allocation of jurisdiction. 76 When we
claims. try to understand why the relationship ofjurisdiction to property ap-
A regime of property requires a regime of jurisdiction because peared in this way, the study of architecture points back to the study
property claims are always in potential conflict. Jurisdiction speci- of genealogy. To understand this Court, we need to study the histori-
fies who or what institution decides among those conflicting claims. cal linkage of state authority and the control of space. This is a study
Thus, for every space that appears within the rule of law, we can ask that will move us quickly from law to war. We need to remember that
who has the authority to regulate that space. Property and jurisdic- the Civil War was still a part of the living memory of these Justices
tion are linked perspectives describing the character of space as it and that for them invasion by the national government was more
appears to those within law's rule. We decide the question of juris- than a metaphor.
diction in the same way that we decide the question of property own- Again, the point of this inquiry is not somehow to get it right, i.e.,
ership: we trace back through time allocations of decision-making to decide on the correct regime of property and/or jurisdiction.
authority. As with property, we may face competing claims, because Rather, the ambition is to make explicit those structures of thought
more than one narrative is available describing that history. In that by which we organize space when we live our lives under the rule of
case, we reach no final resting point, no foundation, for our conclu- law. What we will discover is not a single truth of property or juris-
sion. We stop from exhaustion and the need to act, not from a logical diction. Law's space is not a thing in the world about which we can
completeness. be right or wrong. It is a set of meanings displayed and maintained
Jurisdiction and property regimes intersect at many points, not just in an historically specific discourse that is deployed to defend particu-
in the obvious sense that property and jurisdiction are coterminous lar claims to property and jurisdiction.
66 CHAPTER TWO IMAGINING THE RULE OF LAW 67
Law is not the only form that our political life takes. JTherule of
THE L E G A L E V E N T law is just one way of perceiving the meaning of political events. To
Time and space make the event possible as an object of legal percep- "see" the event as an instance of law's rule is to suppress alternative
tion. But describing only the temporal and spatial frame of the event, .perceptions of the same event. Those alternatives do not disappear.
fails to capture the struggle involved in the imaginative construction Rather, we respond to and construct multiple dimensions of meaning
of the legal event. A cultural study of law's rule must follow the within our common political life. This^ompetition among political
aesthetic of law with an inquiry into the event that occupies this tem- perceptions will not appear unless we focus attention on that which
poral and spatial structure. The study turns now to the jmagjnfltJYP law places outside of itself. We only suppress that which we have al-
process itself-—i.e., to die process ]vywhiqht,ll^ lfg ql e"£"t '" •"'""Ir ready perceived. Recognition, suppression, and co-optation are all at
structed as one among a number of possihleAvavs^ofjuj^er issue in the relationships among symbolic forms. Plotting the rela-
ourexperience. At^Te^em^yofTrnTmiafflnatlve process, we find the _ tionship among these strategies of law is the task of an architectural
'us'rVnl m r r J p W , - study. Instead of attempting to measure legal meanings against an
Kant believed that there was a single shape of time and space and independent or objective truth, we need to measure legal meanings
a single causal pattern to events. There was, he thought, one com- against alternative forms of organizing and understanding political
mon world within which.events occurred—that of Newtonian sci- experience. These alternatives are no more true than law's world:
ence. The cultural study of law begins with the recognition thatjjaejx,. each is an historically contingent product of the imagination.
are competing worlds of e^pexkjice. This is not a challenge to scien- This contest among forms of political perception jis.rarrje.rl ont, in
tific objectivity, but a recognition that meanings are not exhausted the political rhetoric of the community, as well as in the imagination
by scientific descriptions. Science does not tell us anything about ofearh g t j ^ n , Jn part, the contest is a matter of normative devalua-
the appearance of events under the rule of law. Experience is not tion of competing understandings. For example, law's rule is always
constituted by things, but by the meanings through which we under- paired with a negative nltpmarivp _Wf* ririrribfi. tihrtumln nf-lmrihy.
stand events, communities, and ourselves. There are multiple pos- ^saving "it is not the rule of m e n / ' Alternatives to law are thereby
sibilities not just across distant societies, but also within a single so- .dismissed as an ^legitimate—?nd nVnErrnnnly .tyrannical—-ju\$ _o£
ciety. The meanings of events, as well as the appropriate course of men. If this is the only alternative seen, then outside of law's rule,
future actions, are contested not just in their particular features— there can be nothing of any political value at all. The legal imagina-
e.g., arguments over whether an act is or is not legal—but also in the tion leaves a place for just one extraordinary situation outside of law:
large-scale frames of reference through which we construct their revolution. Revolution, however, is always a possibility projected into
meanings. Do we, for example, come to the event prepared to under- the distant past or distant future.
stand it aesthetically, politically, or religiously? The rule of law versus the rule of men is not the delimitation of
Because of this competitive diversity in the forms of understand- two distinct places or times. Rather, the contrast is itself constitutive
ing, every cultural form must be analyzed from a perspective of of meanings within a legal culture. Law is not the rule of men. The
power. Power here is not a function of violence, coercion, and ex- contrast is first of all a means of legjtimatin^ law by excluding alter-
clusion—although all are elements of a legal regime. Rather, power native forms of politics from making any positive appearance. But the
is the capacity to exclude or dominate competing ways of under- same contrast migrates from the justification of law's rule to argu-
standing the event. A cultural study of law surely should include com- ments over the content of law. The contrast works within doctrinal
parison of the imaginative construction of the legal event to "exotic" legal argument as a means of attacking the opposing side in a legal
possibilities-—e.g., the perception of events by archaic cultures or dispute. Alternative positions are not merely disagreements within
non-Western societies.77 Nevertheless, the more pressing need is to the overall practice of law's rule. Quickly the rhetoric escalates to
examine the competition between alternative constructions of polit- accusations that those with whom one disagrees would lead the state
ical events in our own society. The power of law's rule is not mea- into an illegitimate rule of men. Judges are constantly accusing each
sured by the actions of the courts but by the citizens' disposition to other of failing to apply the law and instead imposing their own
understand events, actions, and subjects as instances of law. rule—the rule of m e n — o n the polity.78 This fracture between the
68 CHAPTER TWO IMAGINING THE RULE OF LAW
rule of law and of men is not a stabkjaorrj^er^but an argumentative view, maintenance of the existing legal order, not the making of a
resourceavaTtaHe™toeacK side of a controversy. The line of separa- new constitution. Thus, revolution had to be harnessed and subordi-
tion cannot be permanent because, once the Court rules, the. law is nated to law. For Madison, the revolution was over; for Jefferson,
what it has said and the "legal" obligation is to follow the precedent. 79 revolution was a continuing obligation of each generation. Is our
Before the fact of the decision, the proposed outcome may be de- model of self-government revolutionary self-expression or mainte-
scribed as the "rule of men." Even at the moment of decision, the nance of law? This is not a debate with which we are done or can
dissenting voice accuses the Court of straying from law's rule. Yet, ever be done. 83
after the decision, to fail to follow that precedent itself becomes the Both law and revolution claim a truth that the other misses; yet
rule of men. each claims to be the underlying truth of the other. Without revolu-
What law dismisses and devalues as "the rule of men" can be seen tion, law does not begin, yet without law, the memory of revolution
in a completely different manner. It can appear, for example, as po- would disappear from our political life. We do not celebrate the Glo-
litical leadership exercised by distinguished individuals meeting the rious Revolution, even if historians can trace its effect on American
unique political demands of the moment in an innovative fashion. political life. Our revolution remains ours by virtue of the law that
Political argument need not be on law's terms, i.e., an argument purports to carry forward its truth. This revolution belongs to those
among conflicting claims of what the law is. There is a broader ar- who fall within the rule of law that places its origin in that moment
gument over the value-of law's rule in our political life. If we listen of political action by the popular sovereign.
only to the voice of law, we will not see this conflict. Thus, we regu- Accordingly, we cannot say of revolution that it is merely the rule
larly find political actors directing a rhetorical counter-devaluation at of men. Law must take up into itself the value of revolution in a way
law. Courts, we are told, are counter-majoritarian; our political cul- that respects revolution—both as fact and possibility—but simulta-
ture suffers from a dangerous disposition toward juridification that neously postpones any new revolution into an indefinite future. The
undermines the exercise of political responsibility by leadership and Constitution succeeds the Revolution not as night follows day, but as
citizens alike.80 Lawyers may be our leading political persons, but a work of art follows upon and completes a momentary inspiration.
they are also the object of an intense popular distrust. Thus, the rule of law claims to memorialize and maintain the revo-
In part, maintaining law's rule in this competition of political lutionary truth. If so, there is no need for a people under law to pur-
perceptions is a matter of co-opting that which law cannot wholly sue revolution, i.e., action outside of law. Or, so the legal mind would
devalue. For example, the rule of law presents itself as an order of have us believe. Again, this is not the only mind with which we un-
political meaning opposite to revolution. When revolution "breaks derstand political meanings. Even the Court has had to express its
out," law ends. Yet this opposition is not by any means a devaluation respect for revolution—as a theoretical possibility—on the rare oc-
or complete exclusion. Law and revolution are bound together as casions that it has found a need to address the issue.84
competing accounts of the deepest truth of the American political Affirming revolution as an ideal form, the Court can label every
community. Each tries to co-opt, not to dismiss, the other. We see an actual transgression of law criminal, regardless of its political intent.
early example of this competitive co-optation in the opposing views Ironically, the more explosive political action becomes, the more the
of Jefferson and Madison. Court is willing to allow its suppression. Consider, for example, the
Jefferson thought that no generation could rule another and, there- "clear and present danger" test as a limit on freedom of speech.85
fore, every generation had to carry out its own revolution. To lapse The Court must defend law against revolution at the same time that
into permanent law would be to fail in one's political and moral re- it recognizes law's debt to revolution. The latter is a strategy of co-
sponsibilities for self-government.,fl Law had to be harnessed and optation to accomplish the former.
subordinated to revolution; it had to be seen from the perspective of Law's rule devalues the rule of men and co-opts revolution. It has
self-government as revolutionary self-formation. Madison, otherwise a more complex relationship of suppression to what, borrowing from
his political ally, responded that law should appear as a secular reli- Hannah Arendt, I have called "political action." 86 Law understands
gion carried forward in a continuous and unbroken chain of genera- the meaning of an event as an instance of a rule that already exists.
tions that begins at the Revolution. 82 Self-government was, on his As a matter of law, that rule creates the possibility of the event. Legal
70 CHAPTER TWO IMAGINING THE RULE OF LAW 71
perception sees the event in the light of its possibility, locating what is achieving, or failing to achieve, fame through their unique contribu-
important about the event in the rule. Legal inquiry always asks tions to the future of the polity. Her perspective, however, was too
whether an event or proposal realizes a possibility that has already narrow. It led her to devalue law because it is not action. This de-
been established. Legal argument seeks to show that the event or pro- valuation is only a reverse image of law's devaluation of action. Our
posed course of action has been "authorized" by an existing rule or political world, however, is constituted by the contest between both
rules. This is formalized in criminal law as the prohibition on ex post forms of perception, i.e., between the perception of law and that of
facto legislation.87 Law is indifferent to the unique character of the action. There is no reason to make a choice, as if one perception were
acting subject or the unique circumstances of the act. For a legal de- right and the other wrong.
cision maker to be swayed by either appears unfair and prejudicial. The celebration of newness is a recurrent aspect of our political
This is true even if that outcome appears otherwise morally compel- life. Every political leader promises to be different and to be bring
ling. Under the rule of law, the morally good do not necessarily win forward new policies that are more just. We have had the New Deal,
their cases over the morally evil. Justice under law, we say, is blind. It the New Covenant, and the New Frontier. We constantly have ap-
need not see what actually happens, because law's meaning is already peals to a New America that lies before us. For those who approach
exhausted by what can happen. Only in law is blindness a good thing; politics from the perspective of action, we always live in, or are about
in a complete inversion of our ordinary experience, sight appears to to enter, the "new age." All of this is quite at variance with the legal
lead to arbitrary ancfcapricious behavior by the legal decision maker. perception of those same events. Judges are not appointed on the
Political action understands the event in just the opposite way. It basis of a promise to bring forth the new. When judges speak of a new
locates the meaning o£the event in the fact of its happening, not in jurisprudence, they inevitably defend their claims as "really" a return
its realization of a possibility already established by a rule. Its con- to the correct legal rules.89
cern is the unique subject and the particular historical circumstances. An event is legal when it appears as an instance of an already estab-
Action sees the event as the product of particular choices made by lished rule. As far as law is concerned, whether any particular event
particular subjects at unique moments. It is a matter of seizing op- happens or not is a matter of indifference. Legal perception is a series
portunities, not maintaining the past. Political action emphasizes the of hierarchically arranged possibilities. The particular event we are
subject's responsibility for the choice made: what matters is what we concerned with may fall within a rule established by a precedent; the
do, not what it is possible for us to do. Action is seen as a test of precedent may be the realization of a possibility established by a
character: it tells us—and others—-who we actually are. Possibilities regulation; the regulation, by a statute; and the statute, by the Con-
I'
I are always indefinite and indeterminate. They cannot determine stitution. In such a world, nothing new ever happens, because the
the actual course of events. For law, possibility precedes and limits measure of the event's meaning is limited to its realization of a pos-
I actuality. For action, it is the actual choice that constructs future sibility. The only genuinely new event was the revolutionary founding
possibilities. itself.
To perceive politics through the frame of action is to see the past I do not mean to suggest that placing an event under a legal rule
as dead, that is, without any normative force of its own. Indeed, often is a simple matter. The possibilities within law are never exclusive;
the perception is just the opposite—the past is viewed with suspi- they are often contradictory. Possibilities may not even exist until
cion.88 Justice appears to the political actor as an ideal measure they are constructed by the imagination responding to the event. We
that is equally applicable to the law we have and the law we might often do not know, for example, which past opinions will serve as
create. Of course, there can be strong disagreement about what jus- compelling precedents for a particular event until after the decision
tice requires, but a political actor believes it to be his or her respon- has been announced. We may think we know what an event means,
sibility to remake the present to realize a more just future. An open but find that we have been mistaken. A court may overrule a prece-
future owes no more to existing legal conventions than to any other dent upon which we had relied. The argument between the contend-
possibility. ing parties is over which precedents and rules best explain the legal
Arendt understood political action as the domain of great men meaning of the contested event. There is no list of legal rules or cases

You might also like