You are on page 1of 20

See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.

net/publication/272808739

Emotion in Motion: Conceptualization of FEAR in English in terms of


movement and location

Article  in  Филолог – часопис за језик књижевност и културу · July 2014


DOI: 10.7251/fil1409063r

CITATIONS READS

0 585

1 author:

Jelena Rakic

9 PUBLICATIONS   1 CITATION   

SEE PROFILE

All content following this page was uploaded by Jelena Rakic on 27 October 2016.

The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file.


ʪʤʟʙʜʧʞʟʩʜʩ ʪ ʘʗ˄ʥˀ ʢʪʭʟ
ʫʟʢʥʢʥʯʡʟ ʫʗʡʪʢʩʜʩ

ʫʟʢʥʢʥʚ
ʮʗʨʥʦʟʨ ʞʗ ˀʜʞʟʡ, ʡ˄ʟʝʜʙʤʥʨʩ ʟ ʡʪʢʩʪʧʪ

V 2014 9
ORIGINALNI NAUÿNI RAD

Jelena Raki© UDK 811.111.09


Philological High School Belgrade DOI 10.7251/fil1409063r

EMOTION IN MOTION:
CONCEPTUALISATION OF FEAR IN
ENGLISH IN TERMS OF MOVEMENT
AND LOCATION
Abstract: This paper investigates the conceptualisation of fear in English in terms of
movement and location to show that conceptualisation of emotions relies in part on
metaphorically understood motion. One line of investigation focuses on fear as location,
which can be the destination of movement the Experiencer may or may not reach, the
starting point of movement, or an intermediate location in transition. Linguistically, fear
as location is realised by prepositional phrases, which often acquire causal meaning in
addition to the locative one. The other line of investigation consists in analysing fear as a
moving entity. It has been shown that fear can be conceptualised as an entity capable of
self-propelled motion, but also as an object whose motion is caused externally. Finally, it
is proposed that conceptualisation of fear as a location or a moving object fits in with
other possible metaphorical conceptualisations of fear in English, as they all assume the
underlying force-dynamic principle.
Key words: English, fear, motion, location, metaphor, conceptualisation.

1. Introduction which are shared between members of one


emotion family, are substantially diơerent

I
n this paper we aim to show that con-
ceptualisation of emotions in English from characteristics associated with other
relies in part on metaphorically under- emotion families. This principle is in ac-
stood motion. We propose to do this on cordance with the prototype theory, one of
the example of fear, which is deemed as a the tenets of cognitive linguistics. Nouns
basic emotion in numerous, if not all psy- examined in this paper are fear, fright, ter-
chological and anthropological studies1. ror, apprehension and panic.
Our argumentation is based on syntactic We suggest two directions of investi-
and semantic analysis of original examples gation: Þrst we examine emotions as loca-
containing nouns belonging to the seman- tions in relation to movement. Emotion is
ʫʟʢʥʢʥʚ V 2014 9

tic Þeld of fear, which is in line with Ek- thus conceptualised as a landmark for the
man’s (1992:172) statement that a basic Experiencer2, who is conceptualised as a
emotion is not one single aơective state, trajector3. Fear can be conceptualised as a
but a “family of related states”, in which 2
Experiencer is that participant in the situation
each member shares certain commonali- who “neither controls nor is visibly aơected by an
ties with the rest, and these characteristics, action. Prototypically an EXPERIENCER is an en-
tity that receives a sensory impression.” (Payne
1
On basic emotions see Scherer, 1987; Ortony and 2011:138)
3
Turner 1990; Ekman 1992; Averill 1994; Mesquita In brief, trajector is a more prominent participant
et al. 1997; Prinz 2004; Lim 2003; Thamm 2006. in a situation, which is located, evaluated or de- 63
Jelena Raki©

destination of movement, a starting point, caveat here: however detailed and system-
or an intermediate location in transition. atic the analysis is, the Þndings are de-
Syntactically this is realised with diơerent pendent on the structure of the corpus and
prepositional phrases, which, in addition are by no means exhaustive.
to spatial, develop a causative meaning as The source of every example in the text
well. is given in the parentheses following it.
The second line of investigation fo-
cuses on emotions conceptualised as tra-
jectors – i.e. we suggest that fear can be 2. Emotion and motion
conceptualised as a moving object – either The English term emotion, which re-
as an entity in the exterior world, or a sepa- ßects a model of reality based on modern
rate entity inside the Experiencer. In order insights in psychology, entered the global
to show this, we analyse verbs of motion scientiÞc vocabulary in the mid 19th centu-
that go with the nouns we have investigat- ry from folk English, in which it had previ-
ed, as well as the types of constructions in ously been used in a variety of senses con-
which they appear. nected with its Latin root MOVERE, mean-
Last but not least, we propose to show ing to move. The connection between feel-
that, on the example of fear, emotions un- ings and movement is present in contem-
derstood as locations or trajectors comple- porary general, non-scientiÞc English as
ment other metaphorical conceptualiza- well, as demonstrated by expressions such
tions, which can be found in Kövecses as move to tears, ßy into a rage, or fears
(2000). rose, to name just a few. Parallels between
The description presented here is motion and emotion are also evident in the
based on original examples, which are tak- historical overview of meaning of this
en from subparts of electronic dictionaries word given in the Oxford English Diction-
containing examples from corpora of both ary.
written and spoken English. In line with The Þrst meaning that OED lists for
the aforementioned goals, the data from EMOTION is “A moving out, migration,
the corpus were handled in two ways: in transference from one place to another”
order to show that fear can be conceptual- and dates the Þrst example to 1603:
ised as a location, we performed a corpus- (1) The divers emotions of that people
based analysis of the extracted examples, [the Turks]. (OED)
searching for the prepositional phrases
with prepositions with primarily locative The notion of motion in its physical
meaning. In order to show that fear can be sense is also retained in the second mean-
seen as a moving object in English, we car- ing that OED provides, “A moving, stirring,
ried out a corpus-driven analysis4, letting agitation, perturbation (in a physical
the resulting Þndings emerge from the raw sense)”. The earliest instance of this word
data. It is therefore appropriate to insert a meaning is dated at 1692:
ʫʟʢʥʢʥʚ V 2014 9

scribed. Another participant, with the secondary (2) When exercise has left any Emotion
focus in the situation, is called landmark. For a in his blood or pulse. (OED)
detailed account see Langacker, 1987: 231–243;
2003.
4
In short, the distinction between a corpus-based The Þrst example of the transferred
and corpus-driven approach is the following: in sense dates back to 1579, which OED de-
corpus-based studies, corpus data is used to Þnes as “A political or social agitation; a
validate a starting hypothesis, while the corpus-
tumult, popular disturbance”.
driven research allows the theoretical statements
and categories to emerge from the data. For a (3) There were great stirres and emo-
64 detailed account see Tognoni-Bonelli 2001. cions in Lombardye. (OED)
Emotion in Motion: Conceptualisation of Fear in English in Terms of Movement and Location

A Þgurative sense, deÞned as “Any role in matching physical experiences and


agitation or disturbance of mind, feeling, actual linguistic behaviour via diơerent
passion; any vehement or excited mental mental processes, the most prominent of
state”, appeared in 1660: which is metaphorisation. Kövecses (2006:
(4) The emotions of humanity…the 3) calls this “a diơerential experiential fo-
meltings of a worthy disposition. cus”, determined by cultural models in a
(OED) society and represented by particular syn-
tactic patterns and chunks of meaning in
It is not diƥcult to detect polysemic language of the society in question (see
relations between these senses, which all Deignan 2005: 159; Yu 2008: 404).
rely on motion, either in the physical real- Among the works that focus on the
ity surrounding an individual, bodily linguistic relations that exist between
movements, social tumults, or “feelings5” emotions, locations and motions, we
as distinguished from other mental phe-
would like to point out Pérez Rull (2000),
nomena.
who gives an overview of locative preposi-
The question that arises is why emo-
tional phrases with emotion-nouns and at-
tions are associated with motion. Part of
tempts to link them to our general bodily
the answer lies in physiology – physiologi-
experiences. In researching emotional
cal symptoms and expressive behaviour of-
causality, Dirven (1997), Radden (1998),
ten include actual body part movements,
and Radden & Dirven (2007), draw a paral-
such as facial expressions or an accelerated
lel between expressing spatial relations in
heart beat rate, or subjectively perceived
the “real” world and expressing causality in
ones, such as an increased muscle tension
or chest constriction, for example6. the domain of emotions.
The second part of the answer relates Kitis (2009a; 2009b) pursues a line of
to culture – emotion vocabulary, deÞned as investigation complementary to our own,
a “subpart of the lexicon of a language as a focusing on the verb fear and its predi-
whole referring to emotions, emotional cates, underscoring that the original prop-
states, feelings and related phenomena” ositional meaning of this verb can be
(Vainik 2004: 16), is never the result of di- traced to the spatial domain of bodily mo-
rect mapping between what is actually felt tion, while its emotional meaning evolved
and what is linguistically coded. Every lan- metonymically, only to develop pragmatic
guage uses some sort of a “cultural Þlter”, functions in the discourse later.
to borrow the term from Dobrovol’skij & Finally, Sandström (2006) examines
Piirainen (2005: 16), which lets through verbs of motion in conventionalised emo-
only those biological components that are tion metaphors and concludes that verbs
considered relevant for proper functioning of motion are essential for the construal of
in a particular society, regardless of the fact emotions, as the human mind normally re-
that physiological experiences are most lies on the concrete to express the abstract.
probably universal among all people. What She, however, does not limit herself to in-
ʫʟʢʥʢʥʚ V 2014 9

follows is that emotional content is coded vestigating just the examples in which
diơerently in diơerent languages. In other
emotion-nouns are explicitly coded, and
words, it is the culture that plays the key
her Þndings give an insight as to how mo-
5
For a more precise and detailed description of the tion can be understood. We have tried to
relationship between emotions and feelings see approach the matter from a diơerent angle,
Damasio 1999, Wierzbicka 1999, Goddard 2003.
6
For a list of emotions and symptoms and expres-
though, putting the emotion of fear into
sive behaviours associated with them see Guer- focus and associating diơerent verbs of
rero et al. 1998: 12. motion with it. 65
Jelena Raki©

3. Background: Conceptual mapping between the domains is not arbi-


Metaphor trary, though – it is grounded in our bodily
The cognitive linguistic view of meta- experience in the physical and cultural
phor opposes the traditional stance, by world that surrounds us. The conceptual
which metaphor resides in language, and domain of space is extremely signiÞcant in
starts with the hypothesis that both meta- cognitive linguistic research, since it is fre-
phorical language and thought arise from quently mapped onto more abstract do-
the fundamental embodied experience mains in two principal ways: an abstract
(see Kövecses 2010: xii). concept can be understood as a three-di-
Lakoơ & Johnson (2003: 3–4) assume mensional location, as in
that metaphor prevails in our everyday (5) He lived in fear of his wife and
lives; not only in language, but also in daughter and he made no noise at
thought and actions because our concep- all in the apartment. (CC)
tual system is metaphorical by nature. By
studying language we can Þnd evidence for or as an entity in space, as in
this claim, as language itself is structured (6) He said: Everyone’s got fears, eve-
by the same conceptual system present in ryone should have fears. (CC)
thinking and acting. Metaphor proves it-
self to be a suitable means for perceiving
Yu (2003: 30) states that spatialisation
reality, because it is “the missing link be-
is a general cognitive principle.
tween implicit background and explicit
According to the cognitive function
formulations, phenomenological experi-
they have, conceptual metaphors can be
ences and semantic utterances.” (Kaufmann
divided into three types: ontological,
2003: 137).
structural and orientational (see Lakoơ &
Cognitive linguistics also assumes
Johnson 1980; Kövecses 2010: 37–40).
that metaphor is the key mechanism with
Ontological metaphors assign a new
which we understand abstract concepts
ontological status to abstract concepts
and which enables us to think in abstract
from the target domains. Their function is
terms, because it provides a means to ma-
to identify and/or quantify immaterial ex-
nipulate mentally the concepts that are in-
periences in such a way to enable us cogni-
visible and intangible. It follows that meta-
tively to manipulate them more easily. One
phors exist in language solely because they
such metaphor is STATES ARE CONTAINERS,
exist in thought as well.
illustrated by
Generally speaking, metaphor is a way
(7) Fat, ugly and acned, she lived in
of conceiving one thing in terms of anoth-
awe of her sister. (OED)
er. More speciÞcally, conceptual meta-
phors are “structured, unidirectional map-
pings of elements from a more concrete Once an abstract concept obtains this
domain, called the source domain, onto a new status of a “thing”, it can become a tar-
ʫʟʢʥʢʥʚ V 2014 9

less tangible target domain” (Strugielska get domain for a structural metaphor,
and Alonso Alonso 2007: 3). The structures which enables understanding the more ab-
of the respective domains have to be mutu- stract domain in terms of a more concrete
ally consistent, according to the Invariance structure another domain has. Metaphor
Principle, which states that as much TIME IS MOTION exempliÞes it:
knowledge from the source domain should (8) Time ßies, he gets older, she blos-
be mapped onto the target as the coher- soms out – and not a sausage. Just
ence between the domains allows (see La- walks by and scorches you with a
66 koơ 2006: 233; Kövecses 2010: 131). The look of contempt. (OED)
Emotion in Motion: Conceptualisation of Fear in English in Terms of Movement and Location

Orientational metaphors aim to order and possess the same cognitive capacities.
the concepts from the target domain in our As Deignan (2005: 22) states, “Our biologi-
conceptual system in a coherent way. They cal structure projects itself into culture
are connected to our basic orientation in which in turn generates metaphoric guide-
space, referring to dimensions such as up– lines for the inhabitation of our world.” It is
down, front–back, inside–out and alike culture that provides the schemes that de-
(see Delschen & Fechner 2002: 10). What is termine what is associated with what. This
meant by coherence, can be shown by the begs the question as to why some meta-
following example: states that are con- phors seem to be universal, while others
sidered to be beneficial to a human being show strong cultural markedness. That is
are conceptualised as being up on this why contemporary theory of metaphor
imaginary axis, as corroborated by the suggests decomposition, which results in
following conceptual metaphors: HAPPY IS two types of conceptual metaphors – pri-
UP – SAD IS DOWN (9a); HEALTHY IS UP – mary and complex ones (see Grady 2007
SICK IS DOWN (9b); CONSCIOUS IS UP – [1999]).
UNCONSCIOUS IS DOWN (9c) etc.: Primary metaphors are said to be
(9) a. Johnson was in high spirits, he most directly motivated and are said to
talked with great animation have the least arbitrary structure because
and success. (OED) they stem directly from physical experi-
b. Three days later all of us, ence. Lakoơ & Johnson (1999: 54) exem-
including the cat, were struck plify this type with the metaphor MORE IS
down with Asian flu. (OED) UP, as in (10):
c. I was a very slow developer. By (10) With 93,000 savings accounts
the time I started to wake up opened over the year, balances
and think for myself, it was too went up from £18 million to £2.64
late. (OED) billion. (CC)

Although in their 2003 Afterword La- This metaphor is embodied because it


koơ & Johnson (2003: 264) revise this clas- relies on an experientially common every-
siÞcation saying day experience that the more things we
pile together, the higher the pile grows.
“The division of metaphors into three types – ori-
entational, ontological, and structural – was arti- Complex metaphors, however, come
Þcial. All metaphors are structural (in that they into being as a result of the combination of
map structures to structures); all are ontological the primary metaphor on the one hand,
(in that they create target domain entities); and and culturally conditioned knowledge on
many are orientational (in that they map orienta- the other. Thus, in English there is a meta-
tional image-schemas)”
phor RATIONAL IS UP – EMOTIONAL IS
DOWN, as in
we believe it is useful for perceiving
(11) The jury has risen above raw
ʫʟʢʥʢʥʚ V 2014 9

diơerent aspects of conceptualization that


metaphors help to coordinate, regardless emotion, passions and prejudices
of the fact that a single conceptual meta- and judged the case on the Evi-
phor can comprise all three of them, or the dence the law court gave them.
fact that it cannot be put into one category. (CC)
Nevertheless, this does not mean that
all languages present an identical picture This metaphor also incorporates ele-
of the world, even though all human be- ments of the cultural model of emotions in
ings share the same biological structure English, which is based on the dichotomy 67
Jelena Raki©

between reason and emotions and which to movement. The Experiencer is always a
holds reason superior. trajector in motion.
What follows is an account of the
commonest prepositions that head loca-
4. Emotions as locations
tive prepositional phrases with fear-nouns.
Speaking of general mappings in the Since movement in the domain of emo-
metaphorical understanding of the event tions cannot be understood but metaphor-
structure in English, Lakoơ (2006: 204 et ically, many of these phrases develop an
passim) claims that states can be concep- additional, causal meaning as well.
tualised as locations, i.e. bounded regions
in space. In combination with another 4.1.1 Fear is a destination
conceptual mapping, EXISTENCE IS PRES-
ENCE (Lakoơ 1987: 397), this mapping be- 4.1.1.1 TO
comes applicable to emotions, yielding the Pérez Rull (2001: 354) says that TO is a
conclusion that emotion is bounded space syntactic marker indicating the destina-
whose existence comes into focus when tion of a movement towards an emotional
the Experiencer is in that space. state. Fear can be conceptualised as a des-
Locations in English are generally tination at which the Experiencer can, but
coded with prepositional phrases. In con- need not arrive, as in
structions denoting emotional experiences (13) But that just leads to a crippling
this locative prepositional phrase inßu- paranoia, a truly debilitating fear
ences the meaning of the verb of motion which is the greatest threat of all.
used, which then acquires a more meta- (CC)
phorical meaning. In that sense, such
prepositional phrases are obligatory, which 4.1.1.2 INTO
becomes apparent when we compare utter- This preposition is used where the di-
ances (12a) and (12b): rection of motion towards an emotional
(12) a. She flew into a rage. state is expressed (Pérez Rull 2001: 355).
b. She flew. Emotion thus simultaneously becomes the
goal of motion and the container for the
Depending on the verbs of motion Experiencer.
used, emotions as locations can be concep- When fear is conceptualised as the
tualised as destinations, starting points, or destination the Experiencer reaches, most
middle locations in transition7. Particular frequently this destination is coded with
conceptualisation in combination with the the noun PANIC, which is logical, since it
verb of motion used determines the con- denotes a sudden, strong fear. Verbs of mo-
stitution of the prepositional phrase. tion used, show diơerent possibilities of
conceptualisation. In (14), the verb throw
4.1 Fear is a location denotes the event of caused motion (see
ʫʟʢʥʢʥʚ V 2014 9

Fillmore: FrameNet):
In this section we are going to explore
(14) Now, far be it from me to suggest
the syntactic and semantic possibilities of
a strategy for winning this kind
conceptualising fear as a location related
of man (I can assure you, you
7
Another possibility of conceptualising emotions don’t want him), but such a sim-
as locations is EMOTIONS ARE LOCATIONS WHERE ple push-pull dynamic is operat-
WE LIVE (Pérez Rull 2001: 358), but is left out of
scope of this paper as this conceptualisation
ing here that merely reversing it,
assumes a stative picture and syntactically it is and acting even more like a Visi-
68 realised with stative verbs. tor than he does, dissolves the
Emotion in Motion: Conceptualisation of Fear in English in Terms of Movement and Location

whole structure and throws him when the Red Army starts
into a total panic. (CC) rolling across the Ukraine,
and the President Þnally de-
Caused motion, together with the ele- cides he better do something.
ment of surprise, which further emphasis- (CCB)
es the Experiencer’s inability to control the b. The process of learning good
situation it is seen in (15) with the verb eating habits takes many
hurl: years, so don’t feel in any rush
(15) Elsewhere, the awful spectre of or get into a panic about a
an unfettered Neil Kinnock run- child who is fussy with food.
ning the country hurled the City (CC)
into major panic. (CCB)
Interestingly, though, the situation
The element of surprise is also present can also be conceptualised as if the Experi-
with the transitively used verb startle and encer moves consciously and willingly to-
the resultative phrase, as in (16): wards an emotional state, with the verb
(16) Though winded, the impact steer:
seemed to startle him into a state (19) Before John could invent
of panic. (LDOCE) words of comfort, she steered
abruptly into the true heart of
The Experiencer’s inability to control her panic. (CCB)
the situation comes into focus with verbs
fall and lapse, as in (17): Finally, the situation can be concep-
(17) a. Every widow, no matter what tualised as if the Experiencer brings herself
her assets, falls into a panic into an emotional state by her own doing,
over her Þnancial future, and in which case the construction is re-
you’re not going to sleep well sultative:
until you’ve done some Þnan- (20) Chronic blushers talk themselves
cial planning and know where into a panic. You have to try and
you stand. (CC) talk yourself through situations,
b. The cold, stark questioning recognise the negative, and deal
lapsed into undisguised panic with it. (CCB)
as she repeated the question a
second and a third time, 4.1.2 Fear is a starting point
fuelled by my silence. (CCB) 4.1.2.1 FROM
Since this preposition focuses on the
The incorporated direction of move- source of motion, i.e. the point that is situ-
ment is downward, which is in line with ated farthest from the goal, in more meta-
the conceptual metaphor RATIONAL IS UP phorical uses, this preposition expresses
ʫʟʢʥʢʥʚ V 2014 9

– EMOTIONAL IS DOWN. the indirect cause; that is, it cannot evoke a


Slightly more neutral regarding the cause-eơect relationship in which the ef-
Experiencer’s free will are conceptualisa- fect follows automatically from the cause
tions with verbs go and get, as in (18): (Dirven 1997: 61). Speaking of emotions as
(18) a. Let’s say the President does causes, Dirven (1997: 62–64) says that this
nothing about the Russians preposition evokes exit from a conÞned
until well after the shooting container, which takes place despite the
starts, but then the country conÞnement. In other words, the notion of
and the allies go into a panic free movement is incompatible with this 69
Jelena Raki©

preposition. Hence, conceptualisation of components present with other preposi-


emotions as causes with FROM phrases is tional phrases. Hence, it is possible to con-
diơerent from that with the preposition clude that the preposition FROM denotes
OUT OF, but shares some of the properties the most general causal link between an
with conceptualising emotions as causes emotional state and the subsequent reac-
with prepositions IN and WITH. Let us ex- tion (see Dirven 1997: 64).
amine the following example: Another possibility is specialisation
(21) SoÞa Petrovna’s knees were shak- towards the adverbial modiÞer of source,
ing – from fright, from the heat but not the source of movement:
and from the old woman’s bad- (22) Marlette cursed inwardly and
tempered shouting. (CCB) immediately lowered the pistol,
but he could see from the fear in
This form approaches in meaning the boy’s eyes that the damage
prepositional phrases in fright and with had already been done. (CC)
fright, which would also be possible in this
utterance, but stays more general than 4.1.2.2 OUT OF
these. In fact, causal prepositional phrases
This complex preposition normally
with IN, and nouns denoting emotional
evokes the picture of getting out, or emerg-
states imply that the emotion concerned is
ing from a three-dimensional container.
intense (see Radden 1998: 276). An emo-
Used with the emotion noun, it acquires a
tional state conceptualised as a container
causal meaning, which can be deÞned
constrains the movement, and, relying on
more precisely as a motive.
the conceptual metaphor INABILITY TO
In (23) the emotion noun is conceptu-
MOVE IS INABILITY TO ACT, the conceptu-
alised as a three-dimensional container,
alisation implies that when the Experienc-
which limits the movement of the Experi-
er is subject to strong emotions, he is in no
encer who is inside. The metaphorical
control over his actions. Interestingly
movement is aimed upwards, which is
enough, in the example (21) above, it would
again in line with the metaphor rational is
also be possible to use the prepositional
up – emotional is down. Also, another un-
phrase with IN, in the second phrase – So-
derlying metaphor is the inability to move
Þa Petrovna’s knees were shaking in the
is the inability to act:
heat, underscoring thus the similarity be-
tween conceptualising emotional states as (23) a. Parsons Þnally shook himself
external circumstances – they cannot be out of his panic, grasped the
controlled and they produce reactions that wing sweep handle, and
are independent of our will. shoved the wings forward
past the 54-degree lockout
Prepositional phrases with WITH
and all the way to 24 degrees.
have a somewhat diơerent focus, however.
(CCB)
Emotions conceptualised as causes and
ʫʟʢʥʢʥʚ V 2014 9

coded like this are understood as immedi- b. They must have thought the
ate triggers of a physiological reaction. Germans had landed. At the
Emotions are seen as concomitant with the last, the Lord delivered me out
psychological reaction they cause, and the of my panic. (CCB)
causation link is seen as more direct (see
Radden 1998: 283; Radden & Dirven 2007: The more spatial reading of utteranc-
329–330). Prepositional phrases with es in (23) becomes more apparent when
FROM, though, keep the causal link, but compared to the more motivational one, as
70 without any of the additional meaning in (24):
Emotion in Motion: Conceptualisation of Fear in English in Terms of Movement and Location

(24) Later he realised it was having unable to Þnd any other noun in this
the reverse effect: people started phrase except the noun FEAR, which is the
to join the IRA in greater numbers hyperonym in the lexical Þeld denoting
out of fear and anger. (CC) the domain of this emotion family. All oth-
er nouns investigated denote more intense
Conceptualised like this, the situation feelings, rendering them incompatible
implies that the Experiencer thinks about with the meaning of this phrase.
the state he is in Þrst, and then makes a
decision and acts in accordance with it. 4.1.2.3 FOR
Emotional states and reactions are thus The present-day preposition FOR
seen as controllable. Dirven (1997: 62) says preserves only a loose connection with the
that the complex preposition OUT OF is spatial meaning it once had, and which
metaphorised in the sense of free move- survives today in a very limited number of
ment out of the container. Free movement expressions, including before one’s eyes,
out of a container maps onto free motiva- for example. As the OED shows, this prep-
tion for actions. In addition to this, the osition indeed had a range of spatial mean-
three-dimensional conceptualisation of ings grouped around the imaginary front-
emotion allows its depth to map onto the back axis. This front-back schema moved
deeper sources, or reasons for actions, metaphorically to the domain of causality,
which are seen as more rational. mapping the fact that something that hap-
What follows from the comparison of pens before something else can be seen as
examples (23) and (24) is that the more its causal source. Here the metaphor that
spatial meaning of OUT OF does not im- underlies the mapping is TIME IS SPACE.
plicate freedom of movement. Rather, spa- More precisely, emotions are seen as rea-
tial readings incorporate opposition and sons, which Radden & Dirven (2007: 330)
hindrance, while only motivational read- deÞne as “real or conceived states of aơairs
ings, in which the Experiencer has control adduced as an explanation for a given situ-
over the situation, allow the free emer- ation”. Typically, only positive emotions
gence reading. and hypothetical situations can be concep-
This conceptualisation imposes yet tualised as reasons for actions. Radden
another signiÞcant constraint: since the (1998: 286) says that this is so because re-
Experiencer can rationalise only emotional ers becouse most of them will assert that
claim! (http://news.blogs.cnn.com/2012/02/
states that are of a relatively longer dura-
15/chasing-haley-barbour-ex-governor-
tion, and which do not provoke strong, in- d o d ge s - q u e s t i o n s - a b o u t- p a r d o n s /
stantaneous reactions, this preposition comment-page-8/)
does not head the phrases with emotion b. Experts say there are three main reasons
nouns that denote sudden emotional states why people commit murder. They kill out
of passion, they kill for profit and, scariest
or explosive emotional reactions. Search- of all, they kill for no apparent reason at all.
ing the OED, we were unable to Þnd a sin- (http://southshorenow.ca/old_site/
ʫʟʢʥʢʥʚ V 2014 9

gle example with phrases out of passion/ archives/2001/120501/news/19.html)


joy/surprise8. Accordingly, we have been
It is obvious from the examples above that the
8
This does not mean that these phrases are absent context supports the thesis that phrases with
from the English language altogether. As the OUT OF + emotion noun refer to the quest for
anonymous reviewer of this paper kindly pointed the reason behind the act in question. We believe
out, the phrases “crime out of passion” and “killed that the commonality of such phrases is related
out of passion” do occur in appropriate contexts: to the Anglo-American cultural interpretation of
(25) a. Well they you have it, if anyone commits an emotional person, who is often judged to have
a crime out of passion they deserve to be a diminished responsibility for his or her act (see
pardoned so just let out 95% of the murder- Lutz 1986: 292; Solomon 2007: 132-133). 71
Jelena Raki©

actions to positive emotions are less spe- but detectives believe many
ciÞc or conditioned, which makes them more have held back through
less of the necessary causes. Hypothetical fear of being identiÞed later.
situations gain this status due to their (CC)
counterfactuality: b. That night we retired to our
(26) The Department of Health said muddy billets. I did not sleep
last night that the inquiry could well, Father, but not through
not have released details of the apprehension, or rather I felt
28 any earlier for fear of compro- sunk in depression, I have to
mising the Þnal report. (CC) report, following the deaths
of so many good fellows - and
The phrase for fear of underwent the now of Raglan himself - to
process of petriÞcation, rendering a com- such little eơect. (CCB)
plex conjunction with the meaning “in or-
der to avoid or prevent” (OED).
5. Emotion as a trajector
As the gloss in the entry for fear in
OED suggests, fear does not have its full Emotion conceptualised as a trajector
sense in this phrase. When the emotional can move on its own, usually with verbs
content is in focus, FOR is substituted with that describe manners in which animate
the preposition THROUGH. beings move (see Levin 1993: 267), as in
(29) A familiar sense of irritation crept
4.1.3 Fear is an intermediate location up on him, he didn’t like being
in transition beholden. (CCB)
4.1.3.1 THROUGH
or alternatively, emotion nouns can
In prepositional phrases with THRO- be used as arguments of verbs that denote
UGH, fear can be conceptualised as a loca- externally caused motion, as in
tion in metaphorical transition towards a (30) The Spurs midÞeld is not one de-
goal, which can be some new, altered state. signed to strike fear into the
Also, transition through time can be con- hearts of opponents. (CCB)
ceptualised as transition through space,
which is in line with the metaphor TIME IS What is more, the corresponding
SPACE: landmark can be either in the outer world,
(27) Every widow before you has gone or in the Experiencer, who is conceptual-
through the anxiety, depression, ised as a container for the emotion. In the
fear, panic, and emotional paral- next section we will oơer an overview of
ysis that accompany the death of possibilities with fear nouns, as found in
a husband. (CC) our corpus. Syntactically, fear nouns are re-
alised as subjects of corresponding verbs,
The transition, however, is not a sim- which ascribes to fear agentive and hu-
ʫʟʢʥʢʥʚ V 2014 9

ple matter of moving, or time passing: man-like characteristics.


emotional states are considered as capable
of inßuencing the Experiencer, and there-
fore, these prepositional phrases are likely 5.1 Fear as an argument of verbs
to develop an additional, causal meaning. denoting self-propelled motion
The causal meaning is evident in the fol- Most frequently, fear is conceptual-
lowing examples: ised as an entity, which is capable of com-
(28) a. Dozens of women have Þled ing or going on its own, which emphasises
72 complaints against Wood, 46, its agentive properties:
Emotion in Motion: Conceptualisation of Fear in English in Terms of Movement and Location

(31) a. Naturally, a twinge of fear in the general direction of the


came with the haze. (CC) door handle, which darling
b. The ol’ freshman terror had Moira sometimes held fast
gone, and the girls started from the outside! (CCB)
lookin’ good. (CC)

ƒTraversing (Fillmore: FrameNet) – fear is 5.2 Fear nouns as an argument of


conceptualised as if it moves over an caused motion verbs
area. The location is also salient in the Fear is conceptualised as an entity
situation and is proÞled in the construc- that changes location under the inßuence
tion, and it is a body part: of some force from the outside that puts it
into motion. Typically, the movement verb
(32) He watched with a trembling implies a considerable force and the land-
of intensity as surprise, disbe- mark is a human being or some body part,
lief, confusion and terror which is conceptualised as a container.
chased each other across her What underlies this conceptualisation is
face. (CCB) the ontological metaphor EMOTIONS ARE

ƒLight emission (Levin 1993: 233) – in


THINGS, which allows mental manipula-
tion of fear as if it were a concrete object in
combination with the visible change in reality. The possibilities of linguistic reali-
Experiencer, fear is conceptualised as a sation are manifold:
beam of light: (35) a. The sight of his long hairy
hands, his hump covered in
(33) The panic ßashed at John dandruơ, and his yellow un-
again. (CCB) shaven face struck fear into
ƒAccompanied motion (see Levin 1993:
her. (CC)
b. Until then, Lewis had done lit-
270) – the situation is conceptualised as
tle to put fear in the heart of
if there were two persons present, and
Finkel. (CCB)
one person takes the other one from one
location to another. The nature of the c. And once more she stopped
relationship between the participants, in mid-stride as the fear she
one of which in our case is an emotion of was trying to control by words,
fear, can be diơerent: by anger, by indignation, was
edged aside by a darker, heavi-
(34) a. He kicked away his stool and er terror. (CC)
left the oƥce. Fear slid at his d. I want to remove the fear from
heels after him. (CCB) the disease. Increasingly we’re
b. But the relief was followed by talking about living with can-
apprehension that I was ex- cer rather than dying from it.
ʫʟʢʥʢʥʚ V 2014 9

pected to get rid of the mouse. (CCB)


(CCB) e. The thought sent a little chill
c. As the door slammed, the of panic through Sally’s stom-
overpowering darkness closed ach. (CCB)
in upon me, bringing terrors
with it, and I lay in sweaty pa- Syntactically, fear nouns are realised
ralysis until I could muster as patient arguments of verbs of caused
the courage to leap out of bed motion, and the construction is either
and dash across the dark room transitive or passive. 73
Jelena Raki©

6. How it all adds up him as if fear were contagious, as


Kövecses (2000: 23–24) provides a if terror were catching. (CCB)
summary of fear metaphors in English,
which includes the following9: FEAR IS INSANITY
(41) The men on the quivering, bat-
FEAR IS A FLUID IN A CONTAINER tered boat were mad with terror.
(36) a. He hadn’t said much in re- (LDOCE)
sponse to this announcement,
but surprising himself, inside THE SUBJECT OF FEAR IS A DIVIDED
he had felt a sudden surge of SELF
unfamiliar panic. (CCB) (42) A few weeks ago she had talked
b. Fitzpatrick poured out his about breaking it oơ with him,
fears about the Saints hand- mostly because her fear for him
ing over control to someone was diƥcult to live with. (CCB)
with no knowledge of their
history, of the town, of any of FEAR IS AN OPPONENT IN A STRUGGLE
the things which have con-
(43) NEW HOPE for arachnophobes
sumed his own life for 27
everywhere: London Zoo is run-
years. (CC)
ning three-hour hypnosis pro-
grammes to help people over-
FEAR IS A HIDDEN ENEMY come their fear of spiders. (CCB)
(37) Not just the beauty of a wide ex-
panse of estuary under a huge FEAR IS A BURDEN
dome of sky made its impres-
(44) For someone with Lowry’s Wes-
sion, but also the lurking fear of
leyan upbringing and its attend-
the speed with which the tide
ant sense of sin and guilt, com-
came in over those ßats. (CCB)
bined with the knowledge gained
at the Museum of the most path-
FEAR IS A TORMENTOR ological cases of advanced syphi-
(38) It was written by Sir Andrew lis, the whole business of casual
Lloyd Webber, but he is nagged sex in the dangerous purlieus of
by the fear that he may have sub- the Liverpool dock area must
consciously copied it from some- have been fraught with excite-
where. (CCB) ment and terror. (CCB)

FEAR IS A SUPERNATURAL BEING FEAR IS A NATURAL FORCE


(39) Fear of victory haunts many (45) Calm gauger of the swelling tide
sportspeople, but on Saturday, of mortal agony and fear. (OED)
ʫʟʢʥʢʥʚ V 2014 9

Christie was immune. (CCB)


FEAR IS A SOCIAL SUPERIOR
FEAR IS AN ILLNESS (46) How did it happen that the fear,
(40) He shepherded her out of the or the hope, or the mere fact of
room and she shied away from October 1917 dominated world
9
We were able to verify all the metaphors that
history for so long and so pro-
Kövecses posits in the data used in the present foundly that not even the coldest
74 analysis. of Cold War ideologists expected
Emotion in Motion: Conceptualisation of Fear in English in Terms of Movement and Location

the virtually unresisted disinte- force that connects these metaphors with
gration of 1989? (CCB) the one in which the target domain is a
natural force, which can instigate an ac-
tion, but not consciously or willingly (see
The Þrst of these, FEAR IS A FLUID IN A
Payne 2011: 137). Fear conceptualised as
CONTAINER, is not the central metaphor
burden is also connected to force, as it
for conceptualising fear in English, accord-
presses the Experiencer.
ing to Kövecses (2000: 23). This very gen-
Another view of force is present in the
eral emotion metaphor is based on the hu-
metaphors FEAR IS AN ILLNESS and FEAR IS
moral theory, which dates back to Hippoc-
INSANITY. Illness can be understood as a
rates, and which claims that all vital proc-
biological force that stands in opposition
esses in the human body are governed by
to the life force in the struggle for survival.
four bodily ßuids, the disbalance of which
When localised in the Experiencer’s mind,
could lead to emotional outbursts (see-
this force can be so strong that metaphori-
Stearns 1994: 62–63). This theory served as
cally Experiencer’s consciousness splits,
a basis for a later hydraulic emotion meta-
rendering the insanity metaphor.
phor, according to which emotions are ca-
Force is easily connected to motion,
pable of Þlling, overßowing or being chan-
rendering force-dynamic principle, which
neled (Solomon 1995). This means that
Lakoơ (2006: 213) formulates like this:
emotions as ßuids located in the container,
which is typically a human being, are capa- – A stationary object will move only when force
ble of movement under pressure. What is applied to it; without force, it will not move.
follows is that movement is an important – The application of force requires contact;
aspect of this metaphor, and what is more, thus, the applier of the force must be in spatial
the movement itself can be seemingly self- contiguity with the thing it moves.
– The application of force temporarily precedes
propelled, or under the inßuence of forces
motion, since inertia must be overcome before
that are beyond the Experiencer’s control, motion can take place.
so that it seems to be self-propelled, as in
(36a). Conversely, fear can be conceptual- What may not be that obvious is how
ised as the object of caused motion, where force dynamics relates to emotions under-
the Experiencer is conceptualised as if he is stood as locations. At Þrst glance, fear as a
in control of the situation, as in (36b). location does not show any agentive char-
This notion of force is present in other acteristics, but as we have seen earlier, the
metaphorical conceptualisations as well. conceptual image that emerges from the
Among the remaining metaphors, it is no- location metaphors is one of pressure and
table that in a considerable number of movement. The image of fear as a contain-
them, the target domain is a human being. er combines with that of force in prevent-
This means that a whole range of human, ing free movement of the Experiencer. Op-
agentive characteristics are ascribed to positely, prepositional phrases with OUT
fear, including the ability to move on its OF conceptualise fear as if it enables or
ʫʟʢʥʢʥʚ V 2014 9

own. What is more, fear conceptualised as even instigates metaphorically understood


a human being is either a superior in the movement. The combination of the loca-
social hierarchy or an opponent in the tive imagery and the causation, which ex-
struggle. In both cases it exerts a force on ists in prepositional phrases with FOR and
the Experiencer, who cannot easily put up THROUGH, adds the element of force to
resistance to it – social norms constrain the typically stative notion of location.
the opposition to the superior, and physi- The conclusion that can be drawn
cal struggling can be tiring, and its out- from this is that the umbrella metaphor for
come unpredictable. It is this exertion of conceptualizing fear in English is FEAR IS 75
Jelena Raki©

FORCE. More generally, this metaphor is an We have shown on the example of


instantiation of the conceptual metaphor fear-nouns that emotion can be conceptu-
EMOTION IS FORCE. According to Talmy alised as any of the points along the path
(2000: 409), when interacting with respect mentioned. This is linguistically coded us-
to force, entities undergo the exertion of ing diơerent prepositional phrases. And
force, resistance to it, the overcoming of since in the case of fear movement is meta-
such a resistance, the blockage of the ex- phorical, prepositional phrases acquire a
pression of force and the like. This model causal in addition to a spatial meaning, the
is to a high degree similar to a folk theory borderline between which is not always
of emotion in Western culture, which clear.
Kövecses (2010: 110) gives as Even when fear is conceptualised as
location, there are some elements that link
cause of
ĺ emotion ĺ
(controlling
ĺ response
it to other possible metaphorical concep-
emotion emotion) tualisations – Þrst of all the notions of
pressure and movement, which can both
According to Talmy (2000), force dy- be related to force dynamics, which we be-
namics plays a signiÞcant role in several lieve to be the underlying principle of emo-
language levels, including both grammar tion conceptualisation in general.
and lexis10. If this view is accepted, then the When conceptualised as a trajector,
model of emotions in English Þts more fear can be conceptualised as capable of
general patterns in line with the structure self-propelled motion, and this conceptu-
of both language and culture in which it alisation attributes to fear agentive charac-
exists. teristics. This is also in line with the force
dynamics, as agents typically exert force
and direct it towards some other entity or
7. Conclusion
simply move relative to the position of an-
Fear, as a concept that belongs to the other object in the situation.
abstract domain of emotions, is a suitable We have also found, however, that fear
object of research for metaphoric concep- can be conceptualised as an object that is
tualisation. This conceptualisation relies causally aơected by another participant in
on both physiological and cultural realia the situation, i.e. fear-nouns appear as ob-
that exist in a certain society. That emotion ject arguments of caused motion verbs. Al-
is connected to motion in Western culture though this runs contrary to the previously
to which English belongs is evident not mentioned conceptualisation of fear as pre-
only from the etymology of the word, but dominantly agentive, this conceptualisa-
also in numerous expressions and underly- tion conforms to another conceptual meta-
ing metaphors that exist in contemporary phor in English, ABSTRACT CONCEPTS ARE
language. As motion in general presup- THINGS. This does not deprive fear of its
poses the existence of a path schema, agentive characteristics – rather, multiple
ʫʟʢʥʢʥʚ V 2014 9

which consists of a starting point, a goal metaphorical mappings with the same tar-
and a series of intermediate points, as well get domain exist because the metaphor is
as an entity that moves along this path, it is always contextualised: diơerent aspects of
of little wonder that emotions can be con- an abstract concept become mapped de-
ceptualised as participants in this schema, pending on which one is considered ade-
and consequently coded linguistically in quate in a certain situation in reality. The
diơerent ways. multitude of mappings available only proves
10
For a more detailed account see Talmy 2000: 466– that abstract concepts can only be concep-
76 467. tualised via metaphorical processes.
Emotion in Motion: Conceptualisation of Fear in English in Terms of Movement and Location

References Vyvyan Evans, Benjamin K. Bergen &


1. Averill, James R. (1994), “In the eyes of JörgZinken (eds.), The Cognitive lin-
the beholder”, in Paul Ekman & Rich- guistics reader, 316–334. London &
ard J. Davidson (Eds.), The nature of Oakville: Equinox Publishing Ltd.
emotion: Fundamental questions, 7–14. 11. Guerrero, Laura K., Peter A. Andersen
Oxford: Oxford University Press. & Melanie R. Trost (1998), “Communi-
2. Damasio, Antonio (1999), The feeling cation and emotion: Basic concepts
of what happens: Body and emotion in and approaches”, in Peter A. Anderson
the making of consciousness. Harcourt: & Laura K. Guerrero (eds.), Handbook
Houghton Miƫin. of communication and emotion: Re-
3. Deignan, Alice (2005), Metaphor and search, theory, applications, and con-
corpus linguistics. Amsterdam & Phila- texts, 5–27. London: Academic Press.
delphia: John Benjamins Publishing 12. Kaufmann, Laurence (2003), “In search
Company. of a cultural ‘common denominator’:
4. Delschen, Corinna & Sabine Fechner Metaphors, historical change and folk
(2002), “Motivation and theoretical metaphysics”, Social Science Informa-
background”, in Marcus Callies & Rüdi- tion SAGE Publications: 107–146.
ger Zimmerman, (eds.), Cross-cultural 13. Kitis, Eliza (2009a), “Emotions as dis-
metaphors: Investigating domain map- cursive constructs: The case of the
pings across cultures, 9–14. Marburg: psych-verb ‘fear’”, in: Barbara Lewand-
Philipps Universität. owska-Tomaszczyk & Katarzyna Dzi-
5. Dirven, René (1997), “Emotions as wirek (eds.), Studies in Cognitive Cor-
cause and the cause of emotions”, in pus Linguistics, 147–172. Frankfurt am
Susanne Niemeier & René Dirven Main: Peter Lang.
(eds.), The language of emotions, 55–
14. Kitis, Eliza (2009b), “From motion to
84. Amsterdam & Philadelphia: John
emotion to interpersonal function. The
Benjamins.
case of ‘fear’ predicates”, in: Hanna Pis-
6. Dobrovol’skij, Dmitrij & Elizabeth Pi-
hwa (ed.), Language and social cogni-
irainen (2005), “Cognitive theory of
tion: Expression of the social mind,
metaphor and idiom analysis”, Jeziko-
433–454. Berlin & New York: Mouton
slovlje 6 (1): 7–35.
de Gruyter.
7. Ekman, Paul (1992), “An argument for
basic emotions”, Cognition and Emo- 15. Kövecses, Zoltán (2000), Metaphor and
tion 6 (3/4): 169–200. emotion: Language, culture, and body
8. Fillmore, Charles. FrameNet, Internet, in human feeling. Cambridge: Cam-
available at: https://framenet.icsi.ber- bridge University Press.
keley.edu/fndrupal (retrieved 3 May, 16. Kövecses, Zoltán (2006), “Embodi-
2013). ment, experiential focus, and dia-
9. Goddard, Cliơ (2003), Thinking across chronic change in metaphor”, in R. W.
ʫʟʢʥʢʥʚ V 2014 9

languages and cultures: Six dimensions McConchie, Olga Timofeeva, Heli Tis-
of variation. Cognitive Linguistics sari & Tanja Säily (eds.) Selected Pro-
14(2/3): 109–140. Available at: http:// ceedings of the 2005 Symposium on
www.une.edu.au/bcss/linguistics/ New Approaches in English Historical
nsm/pdfs/Goddard.Think.2003.pdf Lexis (HEL-LEX), 1–7. Somerville, MA:
(Retrieved 4 July, 2009). Cascadilla Proceedings Project.
10. Grady, Joseph (2007 [1999]), “A typolo- 17. Kövecses, Zoltán (2010), Metaphor: A
gy of motivation for conceptual meta- practical introduction, 2nd edn. Oxford:
phor: Correlation vs. resemblance”, in: Oxford University Press. 77
Jelena Raki©

18. Lakoơ, George (1987), Women, Þre, and 29. Ortony, Andrew &Terence J Turner
dangerous things: What categories re- (1990), “What’s basic about basic emo-
veal about the mind. Chicago: Univer- tions?” Psychological Review 97 (3):
sity of Chicago Press. 315–331.
19. Lakoơ, George (2006), “The contempo- 30. Payne, Thomas E. (2011), Understand-
rary theory of metaphor”, in Dirk Geer- ing English grammar. Cambridge:
aerts (ed.), Cognitive linguistics: Basic Cambridge University Press.
readings, 185–238. Berlin & New York: 31. Pérez Rull, Juan Carmello (2001), “The
Mouton de Gruyter. conceptualization of emotions as loca-
20. Lakoơ, George & Mark Johnson (1980), tions in English”, RESLA 14: 353–363.
Metaphors we live by, 1st edn. Chicago: 32. Prinz, Jesse (2004), “Which emotions
Chicago University Press. are basic?” in Dylan Evans & Pierre
21. Lakoơ, George & Mark Johnson (1999), Cruse (eds.), Emotion, evolution, and
Philosophy in the ßesh: The embodied rationality, 69–87. Oxford: Oxford
mind and its challenge to western University Press.
thought. New York: Basic Books. 33. Radden, G. (1998), “The conceptualisa-
22. Lakoơ, George & Mark Johnson (2003), tion of emotional causality by means of
Metaphors we live by, 2nd edn. Chicago: prepositional phrases”, In Athanasia-
Chicago University Press. dou, A., Tabakowska, E. (Eds.), Speak-
23. Langacker, Ronald W. (1987), Founda- ing of emotions: Conceptualisation and
tions of cognitive grammar, vol. 1: Theo- expression. Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin
retical prerequisites. Stanford: Stanford & New York, pp. 273–294.
University Press. 34. Radden, Günter & René Dirven(2007),
24. Langacker, Ronald W. (2003), “Con- Cognitive English grammar. Amster-
structional integration, grammaticiza- dam & Philadelphia: John Benjamins
tion, and serial verb constructions”, Publishing Company.
Language and Linguistics 4 (2): 251– 35. Sandström, Karin (2006), When mo-
278. tion becomes emotion: A study of emo-
25. Levin, Beth (1993), English verb classes tion metaphors derived from motion
and alternations: A preliminary study. verbs. Luleå: Luleå University of Tech-
Chicago: Chicago University Press. nology. Available at: https://pure.ltu.
26. Lim, Ji-Ryong (2003), “Aspects of the se/ws/files/30986184/LTU-DUPP-
metaphorical conceptualisation of ba- 06022-SE.pdf (Retrieved 22 July, 2009).
sic emotions in Korean”, Studies in 36. Scherer, Klaus R. (1987),“Toward a dy-
Modern Grammar 32: 141–167. namic theory of emotion: The compo-
27. Lutz, Catherine (1986), “Emotion, nent process of aơective states”, Geneva
thought, and estrangement: Emotion Studies in Emotion and Communica-
as a cultural category”, Cultural An- tion 1(1): 1–98.
ʫʟʢʥʢʥʚ V 2014 9

thropology 1(3): 287–309. 37. Solomon, Robert C. (1995), “Some


28. Mesquita, Batja, Nico H. Frijda & Klaus notes on emotion, ‘east’ and ‘west’”.
R. Scherer (1997), “Culture and emo- Philosophy East & West 45(2): 171–201.
tion”, in John W. Berry, Pierre R. Dasen Available at http://buddhism.lib.ntu.
& T. S. Saraswathi (eds.), Handbook of edu.tw/FULLTEXT/JR-PHIL/slolmon.
cross-cultural psychology, vol. 2: basic htm (Retrieved 16 November, 2012).
processes and human development, 2nd 38. Solomon, Robert C. (2007), Not pas-
edn., 255–297. Needham Heights: Al- sion’s slave: Emotions and choice. Ox-
78 lyn & Bacon. ford: Oxford University Press.
Emotion in Motion: Conceptualisation of Fear in English in Terms of Movement and Location

39. Stearns, Peter N. (1994), American cool: 44. Wierzbicka, Anna (1999), Emotions
constructing a twentieth-century emo- across languages and cultures: Diversi-
tional style. New York & London: New ty and universals. Cambridge: Cam-
York University Press. bridge University Press.
40. Strugielska, Ariadna & Maria Rosa 45. Yu, Ning (2003), “Synesthetic meta-
Alonso Alonso (2007), “Idiomatic ex- phor: A cognitive perspective”, Journal
pressions in multicultural integration: of Literary Semantics32 (1): 19–34.
A cross-linguistic perspective”, Multi- 46. Yu, Ning (2008), “The relationship be-
culturalism conßict & belonging: A di- tween metaphor, body and culture”, In
versity & recognition project, 1st global Roslyn M. Frank, René Dirven, Tom
conference. Oxford: MansÞeld College. Ziemke & Enrique Bernárdez (eds.),
Available at: http://inter-disciplinary. Body, language, and mind: Vol. 2: Socio-
net/ati/diversity/multiculturalism/ cultural situatedness, 387–407. Berlin
mcb1/strugielska paper.pdf (Retrieved & New York: Mouton de Gruyter.
17 July, 2009).
41. Talmy, Leonard (2000), Toward a cog-
Dictionaries
nitive semantics, vol. 1: Concept struc-
turing systems. Cambridge, MA: The CC
MIT Press. Collins COBUILD Advanced Learner’s
42. Thamm, Robert A. (2006), “The classi- English Dictionary, Lingea Lexicon,
Þcation of emotions”, in Jan E. Stets & Version 4.11. (2002), Harper Collins
Jonathan H. Turner, (eds.), Handbook Publishers Ltd & Lingeas .r.o.
of the sociology of emotions, 11–37. New CCB
York: Springer. Cobuild on Compact Disc Version 1.2.
43. Vainik, Ene (2004), Lexical knowledge (1995), Harper Collins Publishers Ltd &
of emotions: The structure, variability ATTICA Cybernetics Ltd.
and semantics of the Estonian emotion LDOCE
vocabulary. Tartu: Faculty of Philoso- Longman Dictionary of Contemporary
phy, University of Tartu dissertation. English, 4th edn. (CD-ROM), (2003),
Available at: http://dspace.utlib.ee/ Edinburgh Gate: Pearson Education
dspace/bitstream/handle/10062/756/ Limited.
Vainik.pdf?sequence=5 (Retrieved 22 OED
July, 2009). Oxford English Dictionary Second Edi-
tion on CD-ROM, (v. 4.0), (2009), Ox-
ford: Oxford University Press.

ʜʣʥʭʟˀʜ ʪ ʦʥʡʧʜʩʪ: ʡʥʤʭʜʦʩʪʗʢʟʞʗʭʟˀʗ


ʨʩʧʗʬʗ ʪ ʜʤʚʢʜʨʡʥʣ ˀʜʞʟʡʪ ʦʥʣʥ˅ʪ ʦʥˀʣʥʙʗ
ʡʧʜʩʗ˄ʗ ʟ ʢʥʡʗʭʟˀʜ
ʫʟʢʥʢʥʚ V 2014 9

ʧː˒˓˗ː

ʪ ˙ˍ˙˗ ˛ˋˏ˞ ˓˜˚˓˝˞˴ː ˜ː ˕˙˘ˡː˚˝˞ˋ˖˓˒ˋˡ˓˴ˋ ˜˝˛ˋˠˋ ˞ ː˘ˎ˖ː-


˜˕˙˗ ˴ː˒˓˕˞ ˚˙˗˙˹˞ ˚˙˴˗˙ˍˋ ˕˛ː˝ˋ˸ˋ ˓ ˖˙˕ˋˡ˓˴ː, ˕ˋ˕˙ ˌ˓ ˜ː
˚˙˕ˋ˒ˋ˖˙ ˏˋ ˜ː ˕˙˘ˡː˚˝˞ˋ˖˓˒ˋˡ˓˴ˋ ː˗˙ˡ˓˴ˋ ˏː˖˙˗ ˒ˋ˜˘˓ˍˋ ˘ˋ
˗ː˝ˋ˟˙˛˓ˢ˕˓ ˜ˠˍˋ˹ː˘˙˗ ˕˛ː˝ˋ˸˞. ˀːˏˋ˘ ˚˛ˋˍˋˡ ˓˜˝˛ˋˑ˓-
ˍˋ˸ˋ ˕˙˘ˡː˘˝˛˓ˣː ˜ː ˘ˋ ˜˝˛ˋˠ ˕ˋ˙ ˖˙˕ˋˡ˓˴˞ ˕˙˴ˋ ˗˙ˑː ˌ˓˝˓
˙ˏ˛ːˏ˓ˣ˝ː ˕˛ː˝ˋ˸ˋ ˏ˙ ˕˙˴ːˎ ˙˘ˋ˴ ˕˙˴˓ ˏ˙ˑ˓ˍ˷ˋˍˋ ˜˝˛ˋˠ ˗˙ˑː 79
ˋ˖˓ ˘ː ˗˙˛ˋ ˜˝˓˹˓, ˒ˋ˝˓˗ ˕ˋ˙ ˚˙˖ˋ˒˓ˣ˝ː, ˓˖˓ ˕ˋ˙ ˖˙˕ˋˡ˓˴ˋ
˕˛˙˒ ˕˙˴˞ ˜ː ˚˛˙˖ˋ˒˓. ʨ˝˛ˋˠ ˕ˋ˙ ˖˙˕ˋˡ˓˴ˋ ˞ ˴ː˒˓˕˞ ˛ːˋ˖˓˒˞˴ː
˜ː ˚˛ːˏ˖˙ˣ˕˓˗ ˟˛ˋ˒ˋ˗ˋ ˕˙˴ː ˢː˜˝˙, ˚˙˛ːˏ ˖˙˕ˋ˝˓ˍ˘˙ˎ,
ˏ˙ˌ˓˴ˋ˴˞ ˓ ˞˒˛˙ˢ˘˙ ˒˘ˋˢː˸ː. ʛ˛˞ˎ˓ ˚˛ˋˍˋˡ ˓˜˝˛ˋˑ˓ˍˋ˸ˋ
ˌˋˍ˓ ˜ː ˋ˘ˋ˖˓˒˙˗ ˜˝˛ˋˠˋ ˕ˋ˙ ː˘˝˓˝ː˝ˋ ˞ ˚˙˕˛ː˝˞. ʦ˙˕ˋ˒ˋ˖˓
˜˗˙ ˏˋ ˜ː ˜˝˛ˋˠ ˗˙ˑː ˕˙˘ˡː˚˝˞ˋ˖˓˒˙ˍˋ˝˓ ˕ˋ˙ ˜˚˙˜˙ˌˋ˘ ˒ˋ ˜ˋ-
˗˙˜˝ˋ˖˘˙ ˕˛ː˝ˋ˸ː, ˋ˖˓ ˝ˋ˕˙˭ː ˓ ˕ˋ˙ ˙ˌ˴ː˕ˋ˝ ˚˙ˏ˜˝ˋ˕˘˞˝˙ˎ
˕˛ː˝ˋ˸ˋ. ʤˋ ˕˛ˋ˴˞, ˜˕˛ː˹ː˗˙ ˚ˋˑ˸˞ ˘ˋ ˝˙ ˏˋ ˴ː ˕˙˘ˡː˚˝˞-
ˋ˖˓˒ˋˡ˓˴ˋ ˜˝˛ˋˠˋ ˕ˋ˙ ˖˙˕ˋˡ˓˴ː ˓˖˓ ː˘˝˓˝ː˝ˋ ˞ ˚˙˕˛ː˝˞ ˕˙˗-
˚ˋ˝˓ˌ˓˖˘ˋ ˜ˋ ˙˜˝ˋ˖˓˗ ˗˙ˎ˞˹˓˗ ˕˙˘ˡː˚˝˞ˋ˖˓˒ˋˡ˓˴ˋ˗ˋ ˜˝˛ˋ-
ˠˋ ˞ ː˘ˎ˖ː˜˕˙˗ ˴ː˒˓˕˞, ˚˙ˣ˝˙ ˓˗ ˴ː ˒ˋ˴ːˏ˘˓ˢ˕˓ ˓˘ˠː˛ː˘˝˘˓
˚˛˓˘ˡ˓˚ ˏ˓˘ˋ˗˓˕ː ˜˓˖ː.

ellen.jelena@gmail.com
ʫʟʢʥʢʥʚ V 2014 9

80

View publication stats

You might also like