You are on page 1of 4

Merleau-Ponty and me: some

REFLECTIONS
phenomenological reflections
upon my recent bone marrow
transplant
Ron Morstyn

Objective: During my illness and transplant I experienced an overwhelming


existential crisis involving a complex intertwining of meaning and body which
was often ignored, rejected, or misunderstood by others and at times by myself,
which led to painful feelings of alienation. My treatment and my own
conceptualizations seemed founded on assumptions of a separation of body
and mind that were not true to what I was experiencing. I searched for a more
accurate understanding, which I eventually found in the writings of the French
existential philosopher Merleau-Ponty.
Conclusions: Merleau-Ponty’s extensive elaboration of the deep ambiguity of
our existence as body-subjects provides an alternative model to those of the
mind/body dichotomy currently in vogue in medicine and psychiatry. I found
his writings a useful framework within which to comprehend my experiences. I
wanted to write about these experiences and how they relate to Merleau-Ponty’s
insights because I found that those individuals who were able to relate to me at
this level of existential ambiguity were invaluable to my recovery.
Key words: consciousness, existentialism, illness, Merleau-Ponty,
phenomenology.

I
n November 2006 I underwent a bone marrow transplant for myelofi-
brosis, a potentially terminal illness. Since then I have been trying to
find a way to describe the changes in awareness and perception that
occurred during my diagnosis and treatment. As a practising psychiatrist, I
tried to conceptualize these experiences within the frameworks that I knew
within medicine and psychiatry but surprisingly discovered that a good
deal of additional insight was available in the literature of ‘20th Century
Continental Philosophy’ and in particular the works of the French
philosopher Merleau-Ponty (19081961).

Australasian Psychiatry . Vol 17, No 3 . June 2009


During my hospitalization I felt viewed from either a physically diseased
body (‘objectivist’) view or a detached subject (‘intellectualist’) view. It
reminded me of having my car repaired, with the mechanic-doctors
looking at the car and largely ignoring me while idealist-doctors, psychol-
ogists and social workers tried to be sympathetic to my ownership of a
defective car while ignoring the car itself. Neither of these approaches
seemed to remotely address what I was experiencing.
Merleau-Ponty’s work provided me with a new way of thinking about my
experience. In his best known book, Phenomenology of Perception,1
Ron Morstyn Merleau-Ponty argues that views of existence, which separate subject
Consultant Psychiatrist and Psychotherapist, Sydney, NSW,
Australia. from object, represent second-order abstractions that do not reflect ‘lived
Correspondence: Dr Ron Morstyn, Suite 10111012, 155 King experience’. Building on the work of Edmund Husserl, using a methodol-
Street, Sydney, NSW 2000, Australia. ogy of ‘phenomenological reduction’, which requires a conscious effort to
Email: ronmorstyn@bigpond.com
loosen or suspend our attachments to commonsense, including scientific

doi: 10.1080/10398560902866617
# 2009 The Royal Australian and New Zealand College of Psychiatrists 237
assumptions about existence, he shows how we can Dies in which the narrator, a dying man lying in bed,
reach the awareness that ‘‘the world is not what I realizes he has dropped his walking stick: ‘‘Now that I
think, but what I live through’’.1 He demonstrates have lost my stick I realize what it is I have lost and all
that ‘intentionality’ or meaning is contained within it meant to me. And thence ascend, painfully, to an
our bodily existence prior to any act of self-reflection understanding of the Stick, shorn of all its accidents,
or abstraction. During my illness, meaning and body such as I had never dreamt of. What a broadening of
were inextricably intertwined in a painful existential the mind.’’ At these times perception becomes as
crisis. Merleau-Ponty describes a ‘‘violent act’’.1

SUBJECTIVE EMBODIMENT SELF-ALIENATION AS A RESULT OF PAIN

According to Merleau-Ponty’s philosophy of ambiguity, Regardless of the setting in which he suffers (home,
it is the body which through its dynamic relations to a hospital, or torture room), and regardless of the cause of
lived situation constitutes the first meanings an intellect his suffering (disease, burns, torture, or the malfunction-
may grasp, as if by proxy, in any later attempt to codify ing of the pain network itself), the person in great pain
the experience in symbols.2 experiences his own body as the agent of his agony.5

Merleau-Ponty wrote that we are ‘‘condemned to I had an internal haemorrhage that caused intense
meaning’’1 and that the ‘‘phenomenological reduc- pain for several weeks for which I was offered various
tion’’ consists of ‘‘rediscovering my actual presence to narcotic and non-narcotic medications. Initially I took
myself’’.1 Rabil writes ‘‘the meaning of the eidetic an ‘objectivist’ view of my pain and decided it was
[phenomenological] reduction for Merleau-Ponty is merely a matter of taking sufficient quantities of the
precisely that it leads us back to this world which is right medication from a patient-controlled narcotic
already there and in which we are involved’’.3 pump. However, the pain became exacerbated rather
than subdued. The narcotic-induced consciousness
In my case, the suspension of belief in the natural,
was full of confusion, nightmares and memories. An
commonsense world that Merleau-Ponty describes as
‘intellectualist’ approach to force myself to think my
the pre-requisite for a ‘‘phenomenological reduction’’
way out of pain by putting a different cognitive spin
came about because of a number of factors.
on it was equally futile. Some other transplant patients
I was isolated in a single room for several weeks; I spoke to were similarly disappointed. I realized that
inseparably tethered to an IV pole which would set the more I struggled to consign the pain to ‘mind’ or
off a loud alarm at seemingly random intervals; there ‘body’, the more I was alienating myself from myself
was the constant threat of death and deterioration; I and the more disturbed I felt.
experienced physical pain and nausea, extreme fati-
gue; alteration of sensations such as being unable to
taste food for several months; the complete upset of AMBIGUITY OF EXISTENCE AT 3AM
normal waking and sleep cycles; the complex side-
effects of a variety of medications; physical changes in
The basic contention is that, even consciousness, as
my body (e.g. a football-sized spleen) and the neces- awareness of the world and of men in the world, is not a
sary disappearance of what Merleau-Ponty would refer disengaged consciousness, but one immersed into the
to as ‘sedimented’ (i.e. routine) habits and behaviours. very situation it perceives, experiences, judges, or reflects
upon . . . According to Merleau-Ponty, not only does not
I could no longer consider the world in the common- man ever judge a situation from a disinterested point of
sense way as being separate from my existence in it. I view, but his very viewing of the situation also modifies
could no longer disappear as a ‘subject’ in the way that it . . . That ambiguity prevails is not the outcome of
. June 2009

confused thinking on his part; the truth is that existence


I usually had in daily living where my perceptions were is itself ambiguous; beginning from the Cogito down to
equated with external reality and my body was gen- the last and most material level of being, that which is
erally invisible to me. The meaning of everything was experienced is not clear.6
disturbed by new forms of spatial and temporal
Vol 17, No 3

experience. The banal ceiling structure immediately


The ambiguity of existence, the multitude of meanings
above my bed took on a new significance as the first
that it can adopt, became most evident at around 3am.
thing I saw after awaking from disturbing hallucina-
It is a time when I found myself alone, and awake with
tory dreams. The normal divisions of time dissolved
Australasian Psychiatry .

the noticeable absence of the usual daytime routines of


and I was ‘‘relearning to look at the world’’.1
investigations, treatments, meals and visits. The ward
Mundane concerns took on global importance such as was dark and quiet. There was the occasional noise or
struggling to the toilet, getting dressed, watching TV disturbance, perhaps an emergency, perhaps a death,
or looking out of the window at some helicopters but otherwise silence. For comfort I would turn to my
taking off from an airfield. Samuel Beckett4 portrays small bedside radio and listen to classical music or read
this profundity of the mundane in his book Malone Bertrand Russell’s History of Western Philosophy, which I

238
found strangely comforting at such times. There was There were some doctors and other carers who were
plenty of time, for reflection and there was a great prepared to engage more deeply. The doctor who had
sense of solitude, at times overwhelmingly painful and first suggested I have a transplant helped me with my
at other times familiar and comforting. struggles with ambiguity for several years. One doctor
took the time to help me realize the difference between
personal time and clock time, which was invaluable.
ALIENATION AND CONNECTION IN THE
Another doctor was able to connect with me through
INTERSUBJECTIVE REALM his own philosophical interests and personal under-
standing.
Co-existence must in all cases be experienced on both However, not unexpectedly, it was my wife of 30 years
sides . . . if the interworld is not an inconceivable in-itself
who intuitively was able to accept and understand the
and must exist for both of us, then again communication
breaks down, and each of us operates in his own private crisis I was going through the most. For a few hours
world like two players playing on two chessboards a each day we would watch old movies from our child-
hundred miles apart.1 hood on a laptop, and we would almost seamlessly
discuss the most profound and superficial topics. This
I had many relationships in hospital and I certainly did evoked a simpler childhood time where, as Merleau-
not expect or want all of them to be deep and Ponty writes, ‘‘The child lives in a world which he
meaningful. During times of crisis, those individuals unhesitatingly believes accessible to all around him’’.1
willing to engage with me were helpful, and those that He reminds us ‘‘that the unsophisticated thinking of
were not ended up reinforcing my sense of alienation. our earliest years remains as an indispensable acquisi-
tion underlying that of maturity, if there is to be for
For example, I discovered, thanks to my brother, that I
had not been told about a promising new drug to the adult one single intersubjective world’’.1 These
diminish side-effects from my chemotherapy. I shared times with my wife of temporary intersubjec-
believed the drug had not been offered largely for tive unity provided enormous relief and were vital to
economic reasons but there was an unwillingness to my emotional survival. However, I am also painfully
engage in a mutually honest discussion of the ambi- aware that many people do not have access to this kind
guities of current medical practice and the doctor of support.
refused to consider himself anything other than an
impartial observer, which left me feeling alienated.
Ultimately, though, I was able to make private REFERENCES
arrangements to receive the drug, for which I was
1. Merleau-Ponty M. Phenomenology of Perception. New York: Routledge, 2002.
very grateful.
2. Kaelin EF. An Existential Aesthetic: The Theories of Sartre and Merleau-Ponty. Madison,
Cognitive-behavioural ‘intellectualist’ approaches WI: The University of Wisconsin Press, 1962.
assumed I was a detached subject who could think
3. Rabil A Jr. Merleau-Ponty: Existentialist of the Social World. New York: Columbia
and feel whatsoever I chose. A nurse recommended University Press, 1967.
that I ‘think positive’ or otherwise my cancer would
4. Beckett S. Malone Dies. New York: Grove Press, 1956.
get worse. Merleau-Ponty argues that meaning is
something that exists within our physical embodiment 5. Scarry E. The Body in Pain: The Making and Unmaking of the World. Oxford: Oxford
prior to any self-reflection and therefore cannot be University Press, 1985.
imposed at will. The nurse’s admonition was not 6. Barral MR. Merleau-Ponty: The Role of the Body-Subject in Interpersonal Relations.
helpful and made me angry. McGrath et al. have Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press, 1965.
recognized ‘‘that urging patients to ‘think positive’ 7. McGrath C, Jordens CFC, Montgomery K, Kerridge IH. ‘Right’ way to ‘do’ illness?
may be neither welcome nor helpful’’.7 Thinking critically about positive thinking. Internal Medicine Journal 2006; 36: 665668.

Australasian Psychiatry . Vol 17, No 3 . June 2009

239

You might also like