You are on page 1of 8

EDUCATIONAL PSYCHOLOGIST, 44(3), 202–208, 2009

Copyright 
C Taylor & Francis Group, LLC
ISSN: 0046-1520 print / 1532-6985 online
DOI: 10.1080/00461520903029030

Learning, Theories of Learning, and Units


of Analysis in Research
Roger Säljö
Department of Education
University of Gothenburg, Sweden

Over the past decades research on learning has become more diverse and complex. The concern
expressed by Alexander, Schallert, and Reynolds (2009/this issue) is that this diversity of
theoretical perspectives has resulted in a fragmentation that is destructive to the field. Although
it is important to engage in explicit discussions of how learning is construed in different
traditions, Alexander et al. do not give sufficient recognition to the significant epistemological
and theoretical differences between traditions; differences that make them incompatible in
important respects, for instance, with respect to their units of analysis. An acceptance of
incompatibilities in perspectives is not necessarily a problem. In fact, such a situation may, if
the debates are grounded in a mutual acceptance of the diverse manners in which knowing and
learning may be theorized, give us a richer frame of reference from which to analyze learning
in its various manifestations in complex societies.

Defining learning has always been difficult, it seems. All in- ing into the realm of explicit discourse” (Alexander et al.,
troductory textbooks and all authoritative texts on the state 2009/this issue, p. 177). This makes it possible to engage in
of research acknowledge this, often somewhat apologetically. stimulating reflections and debates of what unites perspec-
Most of them end up with definitions that contain expressions tives, and where the more or less irreconcilable differences
such as “change in a subject’s behavior or behavior poten- may lie. I think most readers also agree that “a fracturing
tial” (Bower & Hilgard, 1981, p. 11), as “any change in an of the community [of scholars] along theoretical fault lines”
individual that expresses itself in a relatively stable form of (p. 177) is improductive and that there is a need for the op-
behavior” (Borger & Seaborne, 1982, p. 13), or as a “process posite: a more vibrant debate between perspectives regarding
that results in a relatively enduring change in a person or basic assumptions, methods, and aims. A topographical view
persons” (Alexander, Schallert, & Reynolds, 2009/this issue, of the matter will contribute to this by considering how the
p. 186) as essential elements of what this elusive concept various perspectives deal with the what, where, who, and
points to. Generally authors are also concerned to separate when of learning. I also think that the particular emphasis
learning from other processes such as maturation, develop- the authors put on attending to the what of learning is im-
ment and accidental changes in a person’s capacities. The portant, as this promises to make learning research more
message one gets from reading attempts of defining the con- concrete with more attention paid to the integrity of the phe-
cept is that although it is not easy to define learning, and nomena studied. Learning of something—be it navigation
that every definition can be challenged (what does enduring (Hutchins, 1993), language (Nelson, 1996), blacksmithing
mean?), we can approximate what we are talking about in (Keller & Keller, 1996) or categorizing practices in the un-
sufficient detail for research to go on. employment office (Mäkitalo & Säljö, 2002)—should not
I am very sympathetic to the approach taken by the authors be seen merely as examples of a general category of learn-
of this article as they grapple with this set of dilemmas. The ing, but first and foremost as the learning of something, as
experience and overview they represent in the field of learn- real-world events involving transformations of people and
ing research are truly impressive, and I fully sympathize with activities.
the value of their ambition of bringing “the notion of learn- An immediate observation to be made is that the defini-
tion that the authors suggest is considerably more complex
Correspondence should be addressed to Roger Säljö, Department of Edu-
than the ones found in textbooks from the 1960s and 1970s,
cation, University of Gothenburg, Box 300, SE-40530 Gothenburg, Sweden. when the basic conflict to be taken into account concerned the
E-mail: roger.saljo@ped.gu.se struggle between behaviorism and cognitivism. In the present
LEARNING AND UNITS OF ANALYSIS 203

definition, the elements in focus include issues that concern WHAT’S IN A WORD? WHAT’S LEARNING?
how persons “perceive . . . and reciprocally respond to its [i.e.
the world’s] affordances physically, psychologically, and so- The first point I want to comment on is what I see as a ten-
cially” (Alexander et al., 2009/this issue, p. 186). These are sion in the text between the attempts to sort out how scholars
elements that perhaps would not have made it into a definition use the term/concept learning to characterize their research
some decades ago. In addition, the authors make a claim that and their object of inquiry, on one hand, and on the other
can be seen as going against what learning (and memory) hand the very difficult question of what learning is in some
research used to be about, when they argue that “the simple basic, essential, and down-to-earth sense. The first question
recall of that which was previously learned does not consti- is a problem that can be understood in terms of theoretical
tute learning per se” (p. 186). This might be interpreted as debates and epistemological conflicts between scholars of a
doing away with decades of research on learning and memory kind that is quite common in research. We expect scholars to
following in the footsteps of Ebbinghaus (1885), where the argue about what they are studying and what is the heart of
point of the experiments was precisely one of using exact re- the matter. Such activities bring our understanding forward,
production of non-sense syllables as the criterion of learning unless the gap becomes too wide, which is perhaps the experi-
and remembering. ence that the authors had as they embarked on their intellec-
As one reads the nine principles and the four dimensions tual journey. In Wittgensteinian (1953, §7) terms, scholars
that form the basis for the definition, it is obvious that this engage in different “language games” in which they argue
field of research has become much more diverse and com- about what is a relevant and productive conceptualization of
plex in what we have to take into account to do justice to learning, and what they find is that perspectives, methods,
our object of inquiry. Behaviors and cognitive processes no and assumptions about what should be relevant premises and
longer suffice as basic constructs for providing a coherent core assumptions vary.
and interesting conceptualization of learning; there are many The second point, however, which concerns what learning
other issues that have to be considered such as time, situ- is, makes me a bit uneasy, and, in spite of the integrative and
atedness, and reciprocity between individuals and cultural multidimensional ambitions, there is a tension in the text that
practices. Also, in the literature it is no longer just indi- concerns precisely this issue. Thus, there are, at places, clear
viduals who learn and remember but also collectives such signs of essentialist ideas, where the assumption seems to
as organizations, societies and systems of people and arte- be that because there is a term learning, and because we do
facts (Bouza, 2004; Hutchins, 1995; Wertsch, 2002). The research about it, there has to be something in common; there
challenges of the more anthropological, interactional, social, simply has to be a way of organizing perspectives in such a
and sociocultural perspectives are now so obvious that the manner that we realize that we are all part of the same river
classical psychological interpretation of learning is under system, to use the metaphor with which the authors begin
pressure. Learning has become very visible in what peo- their article. Some of the signs of this line of argumentation
ple refer to as the knowledge society, and there are many can be found in expressions such as the authors’ ambitions
disciplines and research traditions on the go to offer their to “understand the true nature of human learning” (Alexan-
insights. der et al., 2009/this issue, p. 176), their claim that a “critical
Of the many signficant points raised in the article, I choose look at the very nature of learning is beneficial” (p. 177),
to comment on a few. Because I am a strong believer in the and their interest in “understanding the essence of human
fruitfulness of understanding the differences and similarities learning” (p. 189). The uses of terms such as “true nature,”
between different approaches, I comment on those issues that “the essence,” and the like might be read as indicating that
I find in need of further elaboration or where I disagree. My we would some day, were we to conduct our inquiries metic-
main argument is that although it is important to engage in ulously enough, be able to make ontological claims about
reflexive work, where the assumptions of various perspec- learning that would settle the matter: We are all swimming
tives are scrutinized and challenged, the particular platform in the same river, we are just positioned a bit differently and
that the authors formulate, in spite of their claims, largely we cannot see each other owing to the flooding, the rocks, or
gives priority to a realist agenda and is too consensus orien- the bending of the river as it interacts with its environment.
tated when it comes to describing differences and similarities I was also somewhat worried by the analogy that the authors
between perspectives. Even if one pays attention to the what, make when they say that when defining something, it is “es-
where, who and when, and adheres to the principle of “inter- sential not just to establish what a thing is, but also to note
active complexification” (Alexander et al., 2009/this issue, what it is not” (p. 186). This things-ontology hovers in the
p. 181), there will remain important incompatibilities be- background of the text, when the authors seem to be long-
tween theoretical perspectives that should not be disregarded ing for some definition that pins down what learning really
or covered up. The richness in our knowledge about learning is.
(and development, perception, etc.) lies in the consideration On the other hand, there are the opposite tendencies in the
of the ontological and epistemological differences between text, for instance, when the authors claim that their intention
traditions. is not to “treat learning as a unitary process or outcome”
204 SÄLJÖ

(Alexander et al., 2009/this issue, p. 181) but rather to open seems to give priority to a biological interpretation of human
up for inquiry into its complexity in human activities (and the beings and learning as foundational. This creeps in here and
three empirical examples testify to this). The latter position there. For instance, it is evident in the figure, which symbol-
would also imply that one considers the term learning itself ically places biology as the pillar on which everything rests.
as quite metaphorical and in constant need of stipulative The authors also explicitly argue that “we want to acknowl-
definitions. Thus, one would always require that a scholar edge that all learning has as its foundation a biological and
makes explicit which theoretical lenses that she is using when neurological basis” (Alexander et al., 2009/this issue, p. 182),
studying and making claims about learning. In addition, such that our humaness is due to “the particular neurobiological
a perspective gives recognition to the fact that learning is architecture humans have developed” (p. 179), and, when
embedded in different “language games” and that there is describing “the who” of the four dimensions, they empha-
no single such game in which the final, most basic, or even size that it is essential to keep as a basic premise in research
common meaning can be found or agreed upon. on learning constant awareness on “how humans are wired”
In other words, what I am not entirely clear about in the (p. 184). And there are other arguments along the same line.
position taken by the authors is how they view the role of At one level, one cannot deny such claims, because it is true
theorizing in learning research. In some parts of the text it that biology plays an important role. But I fail to see why
seems as if they see the theoretical problems as having to precisely this, rather than some of the other fundamentals, is
do with the observation that theories diverge and that there considered equally prominent. And what is the implication of
really should be more of consensus and cohesion; it appears this claim? Is it that we must all ground our understandings
almost as a moral imperative for researchers to get their act and our theorizing in this fact? Should the learning of how to
together. In other parts of the text, especially when discussing write a scientific article somehow be carried out under this
the what of learning, they seem to accept that the areas and intellectual umbrella?
issues studied are far apart, and perhaps they should be al- Thus, the authors at some points seem to want to establish
lowed to be so. In my interpretation, the point of a theory does what are essentials and basics that have to be attended in any
not lie in its correspondence with the world (which would be attempt to do research. They almost seem to be operating with
the realist perspective) but rather in its explanatory power a wish to establish pretheoretical categories that every scholar
in relation to a set of issues. If a scholar should find that has to take into account. Another interpretation of what the
researching learning in the context of selling cookies in a authors are arguing is that there are many foundations that
girl scout community (Rogoff, 1990) or of apprenticeship in can serve as theoretical pillars. It is equally foundational that
the Swiss watch industry (Perret & Perret-Clermont, 2004) people have a capacity for communicating and developing
may be hard to align with learning research on the neuro- cultural forms of knowledge that we find nowhere else. Peo-
chemistry of the brain or conditioned behaviors, he or she ple are sign-making and meaning-making beings. People can
is, in my opinion, obliged to choose a theoretical perspec- build societies, create cosmologies, develop intellectual and
tive that takes better into account the relevant circumstances, physical technologies, and (re)produce knowledge through a
practices and identity transformations. Especially this is the social organization of learning that is completely unique in its
case if the interest is in the what of learning, and if we want complexity and power. Human societies can cumulate knowl-
to dialogue with those who have their primary concerns in edge over generations, and people can teach each other parts
the reproduction of skills and knowledge in this field. So the of those skills; they even invented classrooms thousands of
theoretical diversity may have as one of its backgrounds the years ago. We can engage in purposeful interaction specifi-
fact that learning is studied in so many contexts and that cally aimed at reproducing knowledge, and we organize soci-
there are many stakeholders with different needs and prior- eties so that we do not lose significant elements of our social
ities. And an important lesson to be learned for research is memory. All of these achievements are grounded in our abil-
that “truth must be otherwise conceived than as a correspon- ity to learn. Furthermore, this capacity for learning does not
dence with a ready-made world” (Goodman, 1978, p. 94); it lead in one direction; rather, it produces different kinds of
is a matter of responding to legitimate concerns of different societies with different types of knowledge and skills. Thus,
stakeholders. the biological basis is there, but it does not, as the authors
point out in other places, suffice as an explanatory basis,
nor can it be seen as a primary point of reference for every
issue we wish to explore. There are many things that are
REDUCTIONISM: COMPATIBILITIES AND foundational about human beings, including our capacities
INCOMPATIBILITIES IN PERSPECTIVES for communicating, sign making, and collective knowledge
building. In addition, a remarkable fact about our biology is
Research is a reductionist enterprise. We simply cannot rep- that it is so flexible that we can accommodate to the most di-
resent and codify the world in all its complexities in our verse circumstances of life as is evident if we look at human
accounts. What I find less appealing in the article is the ten- habitats historically or even today. Literacy is an interesting
dency to adhere to a reductionist agenda which somehow case in point—an intellecutual and material technology that
LEARNING AND UNITS OF ANALYSIS 205

is significant and important, but which accompanies only a In a similar vein, the authors establish as a fundament that
minority of the languages and societies we know through individual differences must be taken into account and again
history. their claim seems to be that such factors have to be consid-
To be more concrete, an example of this tendency to re- ered as fundamental. “Just as some of us are taller and faster
sort to establishing some kind of biological primacy for dis- than others, some of us have greater visual acuity, or memory
cussing human capacities is evident in the following quote, capacity,” there will be “significant differences among indi-
which serves as an illustration of the “neurobiological archi- viduals with regard to any cognitive or noncognitive factor”
tecture” of humans: “Consequently, the colors we see, the (Alexander et al., 2009/this issue, p. 179). The conclusion
tones we hear, the smells we can detect, and the nature of of this argument is that these “physiological [italics added]
our reasoning are all constrained by our evolved biology” differences set upper or lower boundaries within which learn-
(Alexander et al., 2009/this issue, p. 179). In my opinion, ing may be constrained in the human system” (pp. 179–180).
one can take issue with all of these claims if one is inter- Again, there is no point in denying that there are individual
ested in learning, cognition, development, or any other hu- differences in cognitive factors, even if many in this case
man practice that involves meaning making. For instance, and would be somewhat cautious in grounding these exclusively
to be anectodal, I vividly remember the first time I learned to in physiology in this manner. It is obvious that there are occa-
recognize the distinction between white and off-white. This sions and institutional practices where such differences play
distinction emerged for me as a living category when I went an explanatory role, but one can also see how sometimes indi-
in to a shop to buy a sweater as a present. While pointing to vidual differences do not play such a central role or how they
a sweater and calling it white, the shop assistant indirectly, may work out differently across activities. The authors give
and quite politely, corrected me by saying that this was the an example of how people experienced in one area (baseball)
color of current fashion, which was off-white. For him, the but low in general ability may outperform those with high
distinction between these colors was very important. Indeed, general ability in memory tasks within that particular activ-
the entire success of the promotional activities of the com- ity. Also, in many activities, such as when learning outside
pany that year built on the novelty of the color off-white. the school system, the activities may be organized in such a
Thus, humans can discriminate a vast number of colors, but manner that the role of individual differences are not decisive.
some are categorized and become significant in human prac- For instance, I would assume that in cookie selling among
tices. The other feature of this little event is that I learned to Girl Scouts, which is an example from Rogoff (1990) that
recognize that distinction, and I can now tell the difference the authors use, individual differences play a different role
between white and off-white. than when it comes to learning mathematics or performance
In a more serious key, perception is in some distant man- when running 100 m. Thus, we can imagine settings where
ner constrained by evolutionary processes and by our hard- individual differences are critical, but we can also imagine
wiring, but in human practices distinctions and categoriza- settings where the learning situation can be organized in such
tions emerge that cannot be traced back to that origin. In a manner that these differences do not appear as fundamental.
the study of perceptual and cognitive activities, this view of I am also somewhat sceptical against the general argu-
meaning-making practices has been developed in a series of ment that specific physiological factors set limits to peo-
fascinating studies by Goodwin (1994, 1997). What Good- ple’s learning, even though one should not deny that there
win has shown is how seeing is shaped by cultural practices. are things that not all of us can do. But, as we study the
Thus, archeologists learn to look at objects in particular man- history of education, we learn that we have been surprised
ners in order to ascertain, for instance, whether something on many occasions. During the 20th century and in some
is artificial (thus human-made and of interest to the arche- cases well up until after the Second World War, textbooks for
ologist) or natural (i.e., something that is just there). In a Swedish psychologists contained classifications of people
similar vein, Goodwin illustrated how a novice on board a with communicative handicaps, for instance, into categories
research vessel is learning how to stop a chemical process such as idiots, half-idiots and quarter-idiots, imbeciles, and
when the measurement instrument, a piece of fiber, turns jet- so on. These were all categories the scientific status of which
black. Thus, what the novice has to acquire is a categorical was grounded in psychiatric tests and evaluations (Hjörne &
distinction between black and jet-black (much as I acciden- Säljö, 2008). As a next step, it was said that people thus clas-
tally learned about white on my little shopping trip). This sified could not profit from education, nor could they achieve
distinction is grounded in a professional practice, because specific cognitive skills. Many of them were simply locked
a measurement technique has been developed that relies on up in psychiatric institutions, and in this sense the categories
precisely this distinction: Jet-black is different from black. were highly consequential. At present, the situation is very
In other words, the seeing is accountable to the specific pro- different, and some of these groups can achieve many life
fessional practices of a community and their situated activity skills, even learn to read at a basic level, and they are able
system; seeing is informed by a highly specialized knowl- to live relatively independent lives. This result, to a large ex-
edge system, and to see in this manner, one has to learn what tent, is produced by the fact that it was realized by insightful
there is to see. people that one cannot argue deterministically on the basis
206 SÄLJÖ

of physiology; rather, one has to adapt the pedagogy and the ethnomethodologists would put it. This more phenomenolog-
training to the specific needs of different groups. ical dimension of learning, in my opinion, is very important,
A productive interdisciplinary and multidimensional ap- and for instance, the epistemic beliefs that people hold about
proach to learning, thus, should be based on the explicit learning in educational settings should be allowed to play
recognition that there are many intellectual platforms that a part of a multidimensional approach, because learning is
can be legitimately defended as foundational. The social, lived. And an interesting question is how such insights can
the organizational, and the communicative ones are no less be made compatible with the more traditional perspectives
so than the biological. Individual differences are sometimes which look at learning from the researcher’s perspective.
important, but on other occasions less so. Learning, seeing, Learning thus clearly qualifies as a family concept in
reasoning, and remembering can be legitimately explored Wittgenstein’s terminology, and it is used in meaningful ways
from different perspectives that are not reducible to each in many contexts, practices, and their respective language
other. So, in the spirit of the article, rather than in the words games. For research on learning, a strategically important
of the quotes in the earlier paragraph, we should all stretch move seems to be to give recognition to this fact, and to care-
out from where are to make an honest intellectual attempt to fully examine learning in the context of human practices,
reach in other directions under the assumption that what is and to attend to the what, where, who and when of learn-
foundational is a matter of what perspectives we adopt and ing will be important. In this manner we might understand
what questions about learning we are addressing. Meaning how practices evolve and what happens to people in terms
making is as foundational as are biological constraints. of their capacities, intellectual repertoires and identities as
part of such processes. Then we may expand by inquiring
into what counts as learning in different practices (including
LEARNING THEORIES AND THE UNIT education), and how sensitive our theoretical perspectives are
OF ANALYSIS when it comes to showing us what is happening and why. But
even if we set out with the four w’s, we will still not find our
In my terminology, many of the dimensions that the authors perspectives compatible.
discuss concern the relationship between theories and the My problem is not that we have many perspectives and
units of analysis they imply and require. What I mean by units of analysis, although I must confess that I, almost on a
unit of analysis is thus the choice of a conceptualization of daily basis, see that this makes life much more difficult for
a phenomenon that corresponds to a theoretical perspective doctoral students in comparison to when I was in that position
or framework. And every phenomenon lends itself to many in the 1970s. Where I was trained, we had Grand Theorists
conceptualizations. For instance, if one studies the traffic flow such as Piaget, Skinner, some of the Gestalt psychologists,
in urban areas, one attends to vehicles as parts of that system; and the rising stars of cognitivism, but this was manageable
how many they are, how much space they occupy, how fast in comparison to the present-day situation with a rich, and
they travel during peak traffic hours, and so on. There is no rather confusing, array of more or less clearly articulated
need for that particular inquiry to analyze the functionality perspectives on offer. A more serious problem is the lack of
of the electronic ignition system or the details of the tires. dialogue, which the authors point to, but also, and perhaps
The interesting unit is the vehicle as a functional element of equally important, the claims to knowledge that lie in the
a traffic system. theoretical perspectives. Perhaps the most disturbing example
The concept of learning has many potential units of anal- of this in the 125 years of empirical research on learning is
ysis, all the way from the molecular level of neurochem- behaviorism, where the metaphorical nature of the concept
istry, via other fields of neuroscience over to various areas of of learning played such as problematic role: One studied rats
psychology, education, organization studies, and many other and pigeons and made claims about people. Thus, the claims
social sciences. These levels of inquiry, and their respec- to knowledge were not warranted on the basis of research
tive units of analysis, stand in very complex relationships that had very little to do with most of the many varied forms
to each, and to bridge between them is often a complex af- of learning that humans engage in.
fair. And, by the way, there is one approach to understanding The solution to the problems that the authors point to, in
learning that is almost absent in the author’s account, ex- my opinion, lies not in overemphasizing the complementar-
cept for a brief mention, and that is the experiential and ity of perspectives. It is equally important to recognize that
phenomenological one. Learning is quite a common term in ontologies and epistemologies differ between traditions, and
everyday language, and people use it frequently to commu- such differences imply that traditions become incompatible.
nicate their experiences. A university student might be heard Thus, some faults should be allowed to exist; how wide they
saying that “the course was good and I learned a lot,” and are, we have to explore. In the history of psychology, there are
this then is a report that in interesting manners communi- many examples of such incompatibilities between traditions
cates an experience. Perhaps this is something that I miss and with respect to how concepts are used and understood.
in the nine principles advocated. Learning plays a very im- For instance, with respect to such a foundational, and in
portant role in human discourse as a “members’ concept,” as some respect simple, idea as the notion of a stimulus, Dewey
LEARNING AND UNITS OF ANALYSIS 207

(1896), well more than 100 years ago in his famous article some practice, the driver does not need to pay conscious
about the concept of the reflex arc, pointed to the problems attention to all these separate activities that go into driving
of how it was construed: a car; actions have been turned into automatized behaviors
as they do in many settings when we familiarize ourselves
If one is reading a book, if one is hunting, if one is watch- with an activity. Another example of a similar development
ing in a dark place on a lonely night, if one is performing would be a person who learns to use an instrument, let us say
a chemical experiment, in each case, the noise has a very an abacus. While learning, the actions necessary are slow,
different psychical value; it is a different experience. In any are stepwise, and require much attention. Eventually, they
case, what proceeds the “stimulus” is a whole act, a sensori- become automatized, and skilled users reach an incredible
motor coördination. What is more to the point, the “stimu-
speed and reliability in their calculations when they collabo-
lus” emerges out of this coördination; it is born from it as its
matrix. (p. 361)
rate with this particular tool. In fact, some become so skilled
that they can calculate quite effectively with an imagined—
mental—abacus (Hatano, 1982; Hatano, Miyake, & Binks,
Thus, what Dewey so elegantly argued is that even in the
1977; Stigler, 1984).
manner we construe something as allegedly simple as a stim-
A major interest of a sociocultural perspective is thus the
ulus, sharp theoretical and conceptual differences emerge.
study of how human skills—be they bodily, cognitive, per-
The unit of analysis in the classical psychological concep-
ceptual or a mix of these dimensions—are appropriated by
tion is an external causal relationship a stimulus has to a
individuals. The ability to perform various activities is seen
response or a reaction, whereas in Dewey’s case what is de-
as resulting from an increasing ability to structure the world
scribed as a stimulus has totally different “psychic values”
by means of language. What the child can do with support and
depending on the act that precedes it. In consequence, Dewey
under control of a more competent peer, he or she can even-
argues for a circular understanding the relationship between
tually do independently and without such external support.
stimulus and response: The “response determines the stimu-
Thus, language learning is not the acquisition of vocabulary,
lus just as truly as sensory stimulus determines movement”
syntax, and other features, it also represents a growing capac-
(p. 363). Thus, the idea of stimuli, when conceived within a
ity to structure one’s own behaviors and intellectual practices
perspective that has a different conception of human action,
in purposeful manners in situated practices.
relies on a very different assumption than when it is seen as
A similar note on incompatibilities could be made for
a mechanical cause of behavior.
the case of cognitive processes. Cognitivist and sociocul-
In a similar vein, on the basis of their examples the au-
tural theories share an interest in thinking, but they conceive
thors seem to argue for a complementarity of perspectives
of cognitive processes and their genesis very differently. In
where representatives of different traditions frame the events
the traditional cognitivist perspective, cognitive processes
in different manners. Thus they argue that
were understood as an issue of how information is pro-
the whats that garner much attention from behavior theorists
cessed. Processing was conceived within a computational
would fit well within the acquired habits and conditionings model, as Bruner (1990) so passionately argued in his book
level of our depiction, whereas the interests of sociocultural Acts of Meaning. Acts of meaning or meaning-making prac-
theorists may more often nest themselves at the level of sci- tices, on the other hand, require a different unit of analy-
entific concepts and practices. (Alexander et al., 2009/this sis where the dynamics of the semiotics of human uses of
issue, p. 182) signs are attended to, and here the notion of mediated ac-
tion plays a fundamental role as a unit of analysis (Vygot-
This is another example where I fear both sides of this par- sky, 1981; Wertsch, 2007). In other words, what emerges in
ticular fault may feel a bit uneasy. For instance, locating the such practices is not determined by the input in terms of
prime interests of a sociocultural perspective in scientific information that is processed in a cognitive system; semi-
concepts and practices (as in the case of learning to write otic mediation implies that “a sign functions as a means
scientifically) constrains the claims to knowledge of that tra- of social or intrapersonal discourse” (Wells, 2007, p. 245)
dition in a manner that is not justified. It might be that much and that it is a resource for meaning making in thinking
of what is published attends to such issues, but the tradition and in interaction with others. This notion of a process
includes a strong interest in behaviors and embodied action. is clearly different from the conception within a cognitive
For instance, Leontiev’s famous example of how one learns tradition.
to drive a car exemplifies this. What is for a beginner a set of
discrete conscious actions requiring much attention (steering
the car, keeping your eyes on the road so you know where you
are, looking out for other cars, shifting gears, increasing and SO, “WHAT IS LEARNING ANYWAY?”
decreasing the pressure on the accelerator, etc.) eventually
are automatized and transformed into “operations” (or be- The discussion which the authors have started is important
haviors, but not behaviors in the sense of behaviorism). After and should always be present. It testifies to the fact that we
208 SÄLJÖ

have to take into account the complexity of learning and Ebbinghaus, H. (1885). Über das Gedächtnis: Untersuchungen zur experi-
inquire into how such processes are conceptualized in vari- mentellen Psychologie [On memory: Investigations in experimental psy-
chology]. Leipzig, Germany: Duncker & Humblot.
ous traditions and fields of research. In my opinion, learning
Goodman, N. (1978). Ways of worldmaking. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.
is meaningfully studied within many traditions and with dif- Goodwin, C. (1994). Professional vision. American Anthropologist, 96(3),
ferent units of analysis. These traditions stand in complex 606–633.
relationships to each other, and bridging between them is of- Goodwin, C. (1997). The blackness of black: Color categories as situated
ten hard work. Sometimes it is impossible. The “interactive practice. In L. B. Resnick, R. Säljö, C. Pontecorvo, & B. Burge (Eds.),
Discourse, tools, and reasoning. Essays on situated cognition (pp. 111–
complexification,” thus, is not a smooth process but implies
140). Berlin: Springer-Verlag.
that units of analysis will change as we move up and down Greeno, J. G., Collins, A., & Resnick, L. B. (1996). Cognition and learn-
in the figure provided by the authors. In line with the argu- ing. In D. C. Berliner & R. C. Calfee (Eds.), Handbook of educational
mentation presented by (Greeno, Collins, & Resnick, 1996), psychology (pp. 15–46). London: Prentice-Hall.
I would argue that the situated/pragmatist/sociocultural per- Hatano, G. (1982). Cognitive consequences of practice in culture specific
procedural skills. The Quarterly Newsletter of the Laboratory of Compar-
spectives are compatible (although not identical) in terms of
ative Human Cognition, 1(4), 15–18.
their units of analysis through their largely shared notions Hatano, G., Miyake, Y., & Binks, M. G. (1977). Performance of expert
of social action and through their focus on thinking as em- abacus operators. Cognition, 5, 47–55.
bedded in social and material practices. Cognitivism has a Hjörne, E., & Säljö, R. (2008). Att platsa i en skola för alla. Elevhälsa
different unit of analysis and explanatory framework. As it is och förhandling om normalitet i den svenska skolan [To fit into a school
for all. Pupil health and negotiating normality n the Swedish school].
probably easier to agree on, behaviorism tells a very different
Stockholm, Sweden: Norstedts Akademiska Förlag.
story. So, in the spirit of our business—learning research— Hutchins, E. (1993). Learning to navigate. In S. Chaiklin & J. Lave (Eds.),
we should learn about the traditions that are available; inquire Understanding practice. Perspectives on activity and context (pp. 35–63).
into their basic assumptions, ontologies, and epistemologies; Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.
and increase our sensitivity to what extent and in what sense Hutchins, E. (1995). How a cockpit remembers its speed. Cognitive Science,
19, 256–288.
they are compatible. And we should help each other realize
Keller, C., & Keller, J. D. (1996). Cognition and tool use: The blacksmith at
what the differences in assumptions and units of analysis are, work. New York: Cambridge University Press.
as they may be hard to see from inside any one of them. But Mäkitalo, Å., & Säljö, R. (2002). Invisible people. Institutional reasoning
there should also be competition between perspectives, be- and reflexivity in the production of services and “social facts” in public
cause there are so many contexts and practices where learning employment agencies. Mind, Culture, and Activity, 9, 160–178.
Nelson, K. (1996). Language in cognitive development. The emergence of
is a fruitful point of departure for analysing what individuals
the mediated mind. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
and collectives engage in. Rivalry and coexistence should Perret, J. F., & Perret-Clermont, A.-N. (2004). Apprendre un metier. Dans un
lead us forward. context de mutations technologiques [To learn a profession. In a context
of changing technologies]. Paris: l’Harmattan.
Rogoff, B. (1990). Apprenticeship in thinking: cognitive development in
social context. New York: Oxford University Press.
REFERENCES Stigler, J. W. (1984). “Mental abacus”: The effect of abacus training on
Chinese children’s mental calculation. Cognitive Psychology, 16, 145–
Alexander, P. A., Schallert, D. L., & Reynolds, R. E. (2009/this issue). What 176.
is learning anyway? A topographical perspective considered. Educational Vygotsky, L. S. (1981). The instrumental method in psychology. In J. V.
Psychologist, 44, 176–192. Wertsch (Ed.), The concept of activity in Soviet psychology (pp. 134–
Borger, R., & Seaborne, A. E. M. (1982). The psychology of learning. 143). Armonk, NY: M. E. Sharpe.
Harmondsworth, England: Penguin. Wells, G. (2007). Semiotic mediation, dialogue and the construction of
Bouza, A. F. J. (2004). Communication, knowledge, and memory in early knowledge. Human Development, 50, 244–274.
modern Spain. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press. Wertsch, J. V. (2002). Voices of collective remembering. Cambridge, MA:
Bower, G. H., & Hilgard, E. R. (1981). Theories of learning. London: Cambridge University Press.
Prentice-Hall. Wertsch, J. V. (2007). Mediation. In H. Daniels, M. Cole & J. V. Wertsch
Bruner, J. S. (1990). Acts of meaning. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to Vygotsky (pp. 178–192). New York:
Press. Cambridge University Press.
Dewey, J. (1896). The reflex arc concept in psychology. Psychological Re- Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations. Oxford, England:
view, 3, 357–370. Blackwell.

You might also like