You are on page 1of 12

Medicine Studies (2009) 1:367–378

DOI 10.1007/s12376-009-0031-7

ORIGINAL PAPER

A Dark History: Memories of Lobotomy in the New Era


of Psychosurgery
Jenell Johnson

Received: 14 April 2009 / Accepted: 12 November 2009 / Published online: 9 December 2009
 Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2009

Abstract Deep brain stimulation has recently been Lobotomy is remembered as one of the most
identified as the ‘‘new frontier’’ in the surgical spectacular failures in the history of medicine. During
treatment of major depressive disorder. Powerful the first half of the twentieth century, an untold
memories of the lobotomy era, however, pose a number of men, women, and children were subjected
rhetorical challenge to clinical researchers who wish to the procedure, which sought to alleviate the
to make a case for its therapeutic future. For DBS emotional symptoms of mental illnesses by partially
advocates, establishing the relationship between these separating the frontal lobes from the rest of the brain.
two treatments is not just a matter of telling a history; it Originally developed in 1935 by Portuguese neurol-
also requires crafting persuasive arguments for the ogist Egas Moniz under the name ‘‘leucotomy,’’
lineage of DBS that relate the new psychosurgery in lobotomy was in use as a mainstream psychiatric
some way to the old. Working from a rhetorical treatment in many countries until the early 1960s.
perspective, this article identifies and analyzes three Although Moniz was honored with the Nobel Prize in
strategies employed by DBS advocates to manage the 1949, it is American neurologist Walter Freeman who
memory of lobotomy, which it terms evolutionary, is most frequently associated with the procedure and
genealogical, and semantic. In conclusion, this article who, with his surgical partner James Watts, changed
suggests that a rhetorical perspective might be brought the operation’s name from ‘‘leucotomy’’ to ‘‘lobot-
to bear on the frequent calls for dialogue with regard to omy’’ when they introduced the operation to the
psychosurgery, which are meaningless without atten- United States in 1936. Freeman became something of
tion to the persuasive dynamics such dialogue entails. a medical superstar in mid-century America, promot-
ing the operation on trips across the country, fre-
Keywords Psychosurgery  Lobotomy  quently attracting (and often seeking) the attention of
History  Collective memory  the popular press, who lauded lobotomy as a miracle
Deep brain stimulation  Rhetoric cure. The ‘‘transorbital’’ version of lobotomy pro-
moted by Freeman used electroconvulsive shocks to
render the patient unconscious, and accessed the brain
by thrusting a leucotome, an icepick-like instrument,
through the patient’s eye socket. Freeman hoped
transorbital lobotomy would find a place in psychiatry
J. Johnson (&)
‘‘somewhere between shock therapy and major frontal
Louisiana State University, 260 Allen Hall, Baton Rouge,
LA 70803, USA lobotomy’’; the ‘‘simple,’’ ‘‘safe,’’ and ‘‘quick’’ pro-
e-mail: jjohn@lsu.edu cedure, Freeman maintained, was a perfect fit for state

123
368 J. Johnson

hospitals short on doctors, beds, and financial recommended for patients whose behavior is classi-
resources (1954, p. 261).1 Although patient outcomes fied as pathologically violent or aggressive. While
post-lobotomy varied widely—there were a number these forms of ablative psychosurgery are rare, deep
of patients who reported that lobotomy provided them brain stimulation (DBS), a procedure that uses
with significant benefit—it was clear that lobotomy implanted electrodes to directly stimulate targets in
took something from each of its patients, even if it was the brain, is heralded by many as the ‘‘new frontier’’
difficult to describe exactly what that ‘‘something’’ in the treatment of major depressive disorder
was.2 After lobotomy was shifted out of the psychi- (MDD).3 The first published reports of DBS for
atric armamentarium in the mid-1950s in the wake of MDD appeared in 2005 (Mayberg et al.), and
chlorpromazine’s rapid rise, it found new life as a citations rapidly have swelled to well over two
trope in fiction and films such as Suddenly, Last hundred. Although it is difficult to know the actual
Summer, One Flew Over the Cuckoo’s Nest, Planet of number of patients receiving this procedure, the
the Apes, and Frances, in which the once-miracle extant literature suggests that ‘‘the pace of DBS in
operation represented the ultimate authoritarian threat neuropsychiatric disorders is accelerating and the day
to individuality. In recent years, a number of horror in which DBS will be more widely available for
movies have resurrected the lobotomist as a blood- clinical use is not far off’’ (Goodman and Insel 2009,
thirsty monster who haunts abandoned asylums, p. 263).
armed in one film with a two-foot leucotome in each Lobotomy frequently appears in discourse sur-
hand (Asylum). In the public imagination, the terms rounding DBS in both biomedical literature and the
‘‘lobotomy’’ and ‘‘psychosurgery’’ evoke frightful popular press. According to a recent editorial in
images of sadistic doctors, zombie patients, mind Biological Psychiatry, ‘‘commentaries on the subject
control, and institutional brutality. For many in the of DBS in neuropsychiatry seem incomplete without
medical profession, the terms ‘‘lobotomy’’ and ‘‘psy- some discussion of the lessons to be learned from the
chosurgery’’ also bring to mind the era before excesses and abuses of its distant predecessor, frontal
institutional review boards, controlled clinical trials, lobotomy,’’ a discussion the editors believe should
and codified biomedical ethics. not be limited to the biomedical profession. As this
Although the specific practice of lobotomy has next ‘‘wave in psychiatric neurosurgery is ushered in
disappeared, the general practice of psychosurgery by DBS, the clinical and scientific community must
was never entirely abandoned as a ‘‘last resort’’ assure the public that the kind of mistakes made
therapy for mental illness. Bilateral cingulotomy, for before are not repeated’’ (Goodman and Insel 2009, p.
example, is an option for patients with obsessive- 263). If advocates for DBS, then, are to convince
compulsive disorder, and amygdalotomy may be their audiences that a new form of psychosurgery is
scientifically, technically, and ethically sound, it is
imperative that they answer the lobotomy ‘‘question’’
1
Freeman and Watts differed in their opinions on transorbital that hangs over psychosurgery in such a way that
lobotomy, a disagreement that ‘‘strained’’ their relationship leaves no doubt that the ‘‘new era’’ is not repeating its
(Pressman 1998, p. 337) and contributed to their professional ‘‘dark history.’’ For DBS advocates, establishing the
split. See also Freeman and Watts 1950, pp. 51–61, for a
relationship between these two treatments is not just a
discussion of their disagreement about transorbital lobotomy’s
stature as a ‘‘minor’’ or a ‘‘major’’ surgical operation. matter of telling a history; it involves crafting
2
One 1949 letter to The New England Journal of Medicine persuasive arguments for the lineage of DBS that
describes what was lost in these patients: address, in some way, the powerful memory of
Even in consideration of a certain general vagueness lobotomy. This article identifies and analyzes those
concerning just what constitutes a soul, some observers have
rhetorical strategies.
described post-lobotomy patients as persons who had lost this
ill defined but apparently indispensable part of their individ-
uality. Perhaps it would be more acceptable to say that many of
3
them had lost the vital spark of their personality, or the There is considerable disagreement about whether DBS
particular spiritual value compounded of the emotions and the ought to be classified as ‘‘psychosurgery,’’ a question that I
reasons, and consisting of the ability to know sorrow and believe should be answered in the affirmative. I address this
happiness, peace and anxiety, compassion and understanding issue later in the article, and give reasons for my position in the
that puts the final touches on the human being (p. 249). conclusion.

123
A Dark History 369

The term ‘‘rhetoric’’ is familiar to most people as Public perceptions of biomedicine, therefore, can
the derisive antonym of ‘‘reality,’’ a legacy with roots have a significant impact on medical research and
in Plato’s denunciation of the sophists. For rhetorical clinical practice. In addition, the line between bio-
theorists and critics, however, ‘‘rhetoric’’ is a neutral medicine and the ‘‘general’’ public is a permeable
term that describes the suasory elements of discourse boundary: doctors and research scientists are not
(Bryant 1973). To subject a discourse to rhetorical excluded from the ‘‘general’’ public. Medical profes-
analysis is to offer an ‘‘account’’ of that suasory sionals read the same newspapers, books, and mag-
element (Segal 2005, p. 5) in order to understand how azines, watch the same films, and live in the same
particular discourses ‘‘[control] and [structure] infor- communities as the general public, even as they have a
mation and the valuative mindsets that form the bases more specialized knowledge about certain medical
of others’ thoughts and actions’’ (Gronbeck 1998, p. matters (cf. Condit 1996). As we shall see shortly,
50). To approach a text with a rhetorical perspective biomedical and public arguments for DBS exhibit
focuses our attention on questions of persuasion and similar strategies of memory management, even as
power. Who is persuading whom of what and for they differ in terminology and emphasis for their
which reasons? What tropes, figurative language, respective audiences.
definitions, appeals, images, or arguments are Finally, a note about this article’s geographic
employed for which audiences? What is included, scope. The DBS arguments I analyze are almost
and what is left out? As a mode of inquiry that exclusively drawn from American medicine and
emphasizes the power of language to shape attitudes media. Although in a globalized and networked
and direct action, rhetoric offers medicine studies world, discourse knows no national boundary, the
unique insight into the role persuasive discourse plays collective memory I describe in this article should be
in biomedical development. In this article, for read as American collective memory. The legacy of
example, a rhetorical perspective allows us to move Walter Freeman and the recurrent trope of lobotomy
away from ontological questions about whether DBS in American popular culture, combined with psycho-
is ‘‘really’’ psychosurgery in order to focus on more surgery’s imbrication in US Cold War anxieties in the
important questions. What’s at stake in this distinc- early 1950s and early 1970s, has contributed to a
tion? Why is it persuasive? And, importantly, whose particularly strong memory of lobotomy in the United
interests does it serve? States. However, it is important to note that lobotomy
The arguments I analyze in this article are taken was an international procedure from its inception to
from medical and nonmedical discourse for a number its extinction, and it was practiced in hospitals from
of reasons. Mass media frequently present biomedical Japan to Brazil. Whether the memory I describe here
developments to a public audience hungry for infor- is distinctly American or not is an open question I
mation about the latest breakthroughs in science and hope a later comparative study might be able to
medicine, and DBS has frequently attracted the answer.
attention of the popular press. Yet the flow of In what follows, I first provide a brief introduction
information and influence is not unidirectional from to the concept of collective memory and then show
biomedicine to the public (Lewenstein 1995): public how it may be observed in rhetorical assumptions
interest may transform into public concern, which about an audience’s evaluation of past events. I then
may be transformed into political action and govern- analyze a number of arguments that advocate for the
mental regulation. It was public concern, for example, use of DBS for psychiatric disorders, which I group
that fomented federal investigation into the ‘‘second according to strategies they use to construct its
wave’’ of psychosurgery in early 1970s America.4 lineage in relationship to the lobotomy era. At a time
when there has been much hand-waving about the
value of dialogue in biomedicine, a rhetorical
4
The rise of psychosurgery in the early 1970s is one of the perspective provides insight into the metaphorical
reasons cited for the formation of the US National Commission dialogue between past and present, and also speaks to
for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and
ways in which this relationship is mobilized persua-
Behavioral Research. Psychosurgery was included ‘‘in
response to widespread public concern’’ (Quality…1973, sively in public and professional dialogues about the
26318; United States 1977). future of biomedicine.

123
370 J. Johnson

Collective Memory factor in the widespread distrust of public health


authorities in African-American communities (Tho-
The origin of the term ‘‘collective memory’’ is mas and Quinn 1991).
generally attributed to sociologist Maurice Halbw- Collective memory is more than just a vernacular
achs (1980), who attested that individual memory is account of the past; it is also a judgment on the past
constructed in relationship with a particular social enabled by a present set of values. Aristotle provides
environment. At present, there are perhaps as many one way to think about this valuative aspect of
definitions of ‘‘collective memory’’ as there are collective memory. Rhetoric, Aristotle suggests, can
scholars who use the term, and almost as many be classified into three ‘‘species’’ of discourse:
arguments that attempt to decisively articulate col- forensic, deliberative, and epideictic. Forensic rhet-
lective memory’s relationship to history (see Klein oric is devoted to the past, concerns the question of
2000 for an acerbic critique). Some scholars have what happened, and is exemplified by speeches in
suggested that collective memory has been subju- the courtroom. Deliberative rhetoric is devoted to the
gated by history (Foucault and Bouchard 1977; Nora future, concerns the question what should we do and
1989), while others have argued that history itself is a is exemplified by speeches in the political assembly.
kind of collective memory (Geary 1994; Ricouer Although it obviously concerns the past, and, as I
2006). Others maintain that collective memory and will explain shortly, also guides deliberation about
academic history may serve as complementary future action, collective memory might best be
accounts of the past (Assmann 2006). These distinc- thought of as a kind of epideictic rhetoric (Gronbeck
tions extend beyond the scope of this article, which is 1998), which is devoted to the present, addressed to
concerned not with how memories are formed, questions of what we value, and exemplified by the
preserved, or contested, but with how collective funeral oration. Epideictic, writes Judy Segal, ‘‘is a
memory is invoked in arguments as an implicit or culture’s most telling rhetoric, because, in general,
explicit assumption about an audience’s judgment of we praise people for embodying what we value and
the past. we blame them for embodying what we deplore’’
It hardly bears mention that the interpretation of (2005, p. 61). Heroes can be tarnished and villains
the past events has a powerful effect on the present. redeemed by later generations, a matter vividly
Disputes over how we remember historical events are illustrated in medicine by the controversial figure of
deeply political struggles. As Susan Reverby (2001) J. Marion Sims, the 19th century American surgeon
writes in her analysis of African–American memories often referred to as the ‘‘father’’ of modern gynecol-
of the Tuskegee syphilis study, collective memory ogy. Initially lauded for his pioneering work on
‘‘exists in the liminal area of historical fog and fact, fistula surgery and the development of the speculum,
available as a set of experiences to be used by those Sims became a site of argument when it was revealed
who wish to tell differing tales, make various political that much of his research was obtained by operating,
points, and remember in discordant ways’’ (p. 23). without anesthesia, on enslaved Black women. The
Bolstered by representations of Tuskegee in popular historical facts of Sims’ research are not disputed; for
media, collective memories of the study hold fast to critics, the point of contention centers on the
the idea that test subjects were deliberately infected question of whether present or past ethical standards
with syphilis, an account that conflicts with ‘‘official’’ should be used to evaluate his contribution to
histories of the study (which deny that deliberate medicine (Barker-Benfield 1999; Sartin 2004;
infection took place). When professionals in history O’Leary 2004). Should we praise or blame J. Marion
and medicine dismiss collective memories of Tuske- Sims? What eulogy should we write, and what form
gee as inaccurate, Reverby argues, and therefore should it take? The answers to these questions reveal
unworthy of serious consideration, they miss an more about what we value than they reveal about
opportunity to engage in potentially productive who Sims was or what he did. In this way, the past
dialogue about Black experiences of medicine. This ‘‘can guide the present, but the present also is
disengagement has a significant consequence: collec- reconfiguring the past; therefore, through evocation
tive memory of the Tuskegee study is often cited as a of collective memories, past and present live in

123
A Dark History 371

constant dialogue, even in a hermeneutic circle this way. The stronger a memory is, the less it needs
where neither can be comprehended without the to be articulated explicitly.5 In the arguments for
other’’ (Gronbeck 1998, p. 57). DBS I will analyze in the next section, the collective
The case of J. Marion Sims exhibits a struggle memory of lobotomy emerges in the argument as an
over the formation of collective memory. However, assumption that the audience knows something about
although collective memory is clearly contextual lobotomy and this something, to put it very simply, is
and subject to change, once established as memory, that lobotomy was bad.6
it forms a common ground with which groups
construct a visible identity for themselves and others
(Assmann 1995). If there is a collective biomedical Managing the Memory of Lobotomy
identity, it is shaped, like any other group, by shared
interpretations of its past. Biomedicine erects phys- The strategies employed by DBS advocates to relate
ical and linguistic monuments to commemorate the the new era of psychosurgery to the old take a
names of its heroes (Jonas Salk; Thomas Hodgkins; number of forms and they are not mutually exclusive.
Louis Pasteur); textbooks recount the therapeutic Arguments often employ multiple strategies in the
courage of Christiaan Barnard and the barrier- same paragraph, and sometimes in the same sentence.
breaking career of Elizabeth Blackwell. Heroes What characterizes each of these strategies is the way
and heroines of medicine are remembered not they answer the lobotomy question. I identify three
simply for their technical contributions to the such strategies in this section, which I have organized
profession, but also because they embody values according to the lineage they argue for DBS: the
that medical professionals would do well to emulate. evolutionary strategy, in which DBS is characterized
Collective memory therefore also serves a normative as an improved version of lobotomy, the genealogical
function (Assmann 1995): persons, actions, and strategy, in which the neurological, not psychiatric,
events are selectively recalled, praised or blamed lineage of DBS is emphasized, and the semantic
in order to inculcate values that ought to direct strategy, which argues that DBS is not a form of
future action. In this regard, memories of failure are psychosurgery in an attempt to rhetorically sever the
particularly resonant, and they are woven into a lineage with lobotomy altogether.
recursive narrative of medical development. Just as The evolutionary strategy reflects an idealized
a nation negatively constructs the virtue of patriot- vision of medical progress as the continuous refine-
ism by remembering its traitors, biomedicine devel- ment of biomedical knowledge, technique, technol-
ops ethics in sharp relief to its Mengeles, ogy and ethics in order to maximize human health
thalidomides and lobotomies. Rather than forget
these people and events in service of a mythic tale
of unblemished medical progress, by remembering
heroes and villains, successes and failures, medicine
develops a reflective attitude toward its past and
5
present in order to craft an ethical orientation In rhetoric, assumptions in argument are often discussed as a
form of enthymeme, a kind of truncated syllogism that
toward its future.
assumes, rather than expresses, one of its premises. To use
Although the collective memory I’ve described the famous example, a syllogism looks like this:
above takes an explicit form in textbooks, landmarks, All men are mortal.
and commemorative discourse, collective memory Socrates is a man.
Socrates is mortal.
can also be observed in arguments that implicitly An enthymeme, in contrast, might look like this: ‘‘Socrates is
assume an audience’s judgment about the past. For a man. Therefore, Socrates is a mortal,’’ which suppresses the
example, in the previous paragraph, I clearly assume common knowledge that ‘‘all men are mortal.’’
6
that as a reader interested in medicine, you are This assumed evaluation is characterized well in a comment
familiar with Josef Mengele’s experiments at Ausch- by psychiatrists Daniel Stewart and Kenneth Davis in The
American Journal of Psychiatry: ‘‘If someone today were to
witz-Birkenau, and I also assume you share the
suggest a frontal lobotomy as a means of relieving mental
judgment that he acted unethically, or at the very anguish, the responses might include sardonic laughter,
least, that you know his actions are remembered in revulsion, or even outrage’’ (2008, p. 457).

123
372 J. Johnson

and minimize human suffering. In arguments that to know. Collective memory provides a reference
employ an evolutionary strategy, the audience’s point for something the audience already believes.
memory of the lobotomy era is explicitly or implicitly There is no need to tell this story, nor to make an
referenced in order to show the extent to which extended evaluative argument about why psychosur-
contemporary psychosurgery has evolved from its geries’ past were erroneous or subject to ‘‘appropriate
notorious predecessor. One article, for example, public and governmental concern’’ (p. 2) because
states the evolutionary strategy in direct terms: the authors can count on the audience’s judgment—
‘‘psychosurgery has a complex and controversial their collective memory of lobotomy—to assist their
history dating back to antiquity, and continues to argument. To close the article, the authors state their
evolve in the present era of neurosurgery’’ (Mashour wish for properly regulated and controlled clinical
et al. 2004, p. 216). Other arguments express the studies ‘‘so as not to repeat the errors of the past’’
evolutionary strategy through comparison. For exam- (p. 8). In the last phrase, lobotomy is invoked as an
ple, the article ‘‘Biological Basis for the Surgical ‘‘error,’’ a lesson that must be learned. This sentiment
Treatment of Depression’’ (Abosch and Cosgrove is echoed by Mashour et al., who call DBS psycho-
2008), advocates for DBS using new models of surgery’s ‘‘new frontier,’’ and explain that ‘‘it is
depression as a systems-level disorder. The article critical that clinicians and ethicists alike maintain a
emphasizes the scientific grounding for today’s clear perspective on surgical intervention for psychi-
techniques by presenting a litany of improvements atric disorders so that the dark history of psychosur-
in contemporary psychosurgery: gery does not repeat itself’’ (p. 416).
In the evolutionary strategy, it is not only scientific
Although the field of psychosurgery has its
knowledge, technology and technique that have
roots in anecdotal experience as opposed to
improved since the days of the lobotomy, but also
hypothesis-driven experimentation assessed
the ethical environment in which DBS is researched
with validated outcome measures, a new era is
and therapeutically applied. As the arguments above
fortunately emerging. Advances in the field of
suggest, the ethical failures of lobotomy (an assump-
neuroimaging have allowed the use of human
tion problematized by Pressman 1998) may be
participants for testing hypotheses about the
remedied by today’s more stringent codes of bio-
mechanisms that underlie these disorders. In
medical conduct. An article from Psychiatric News
addition to higher expectations and greater
brings ethicists Joseph Fins and Benjamin Greenberg
scrutiny placed on investigations in this arena,
together to claim that the ‘‘appreciation of the
the advent of DBS technology has provided
importance of informed consent and other ethical
investigators with a tool that is nondestructive,
considerations—make the current environment vastly
modifiable, capable of being turned on or off,
different and more conducive to safe investigation’’
and more focal in its effects (p. 1).
(Moran 2004). Informed consent is immediately
The ‘‘new era’’ of psychosurgery finds its ‘‘roots’’ in familiar as one of the hallmarks of biomedical ethics,
the psychosurgeries of the past, and the authors and its need in DBS research is echoed by Goodman
suggest that contemporary psychosurgery is superior and Insel: ‘‘researchers need to ensure that a process
at every point of comparison: more rigorous testing is followed that protects human subjects’’ (2009, p.
based on controlled experimentation; better theories 265). Additional ethical issues pertinent to DBS,
of mental illness using the observational power of another article suggests, ‘‘include patient selection,
neuroimaging; greater regulations and oversight; less patients’ rights, adverse event reporting, and a
destruction; reversibility; refined precision. Contem- commitment to long-term care’’ (Hardesty and Sack-
porary psychosurgery is thus argued to be an heim 2007, p. 834).
improvement on its ‘‘root’’ in nearly every way. In recent years, it is been proposed that a new field
Note that the history of psychosurgery is not told in of ethics is required in order to address the unique
this article; it is referenced indirectly. The lobotomy ethical issues raised by developments in neuroscience
era is mobilized purely for its rhetorical force; no like DBS. Although still in the initial stages of
history is written for lobotomy because that history is theoretical development, neuroethics focuses on two
obvious. A history is told because the audience needs related sets of issues laid out by Roskies (2002). The

123
A Dark History 373

ethics of neuroscience addresses familiar bioethical tower, onto the floor, onto the tube and into print until
concerns with neuroscience research design, as well it penetrates every sentient being’s consciousness.’’
as the impact of that research on ‘‘existing social, The Economist published an article with similar
ethical, and legal structures.’’ The neuroscience of concerns that same year, arguing that developments
ethics addresses the impact that a neurological in neurotechnology raise ‘‘ethical and legal questions
substrate of morality has upon traditional notions of of the same nature and gravity as advances in
ethics (pp. 21–22). Although these two strands of genetics’’ (‘‘Open Your Mind’’).
inquiry are clearly related (which raises questions Not surprisingly, the popular press have reported on
about the logic of their division) they both find DBS with gusto, often taking an explicitly positive
exigency in psychosurgery, which raises traditional stance on the surgery, and the evolutionary strategy is
concerns about ethical research and treatment and mobilized in these arguments as well. In an interview
also provokes larger issues, such as what ethical with the Washington Post, ethicist Joseph Fins claims
behavior means if it can be modified by the flick of a that ‘‘today’s [psychosurgery] is far more discreet, less
knife or the flip of a switch. In an article in toxic and easier to study than its predecessor’’ (Stein
Neurosurgical Focus (2008), which investigates the 2004). An article in Slate comments that DBS is a ‘‘far
impact of neuroethics on contemporary psychosur- cry from the days when lobotomies robbed patients of
gery, Joshua Wind and Douglass Anderson reference the ability to feel emotions like love and compassion’’
the lobotomy era a number of times, most strikingly (Richards 2008). Time uses the history of lobotomy in
in the conclusion: much the same way: ‘‘the practice of psychosurgery
has long been dormant—tarnished by the notorious
In retrospect, it is interesting to ponder whether
brain-scrambling lobotomies of the 1940s and 1950s—
Egas Moniz would have traveled down the road
but it has recently reclaimed a bit of its luster, thanks to
of the leucotomy had he known the implications
a relatively new and much more benign technique
of his actions. If Moniz had known that he
called deep-brain stimulation’’ (Song 2006). When
was not simply searching for a treatment for
compared to psychosurgery of the past, the era of
psychosis, but rather traveling towards technol-
neurostimulation finds validation. ‘‘New’’ psychosur-
ogy that could shake the concept of human
gery is ‘‘much more benign.’’ Changes are ‘‘dramatic.’’
personhood, would he have continued? One can
The regulative environment is ‘‘vastly different’’ and
only speculate. But the questions left to be
‘‘safer’’ than that of the days of the lobotomy. These
answered, the therapies still to be developed,
stories invoke the collective memory of lobotomy as a
and the ethical lines yet to be drawn will be
comforting touchstone of medical progress.
some of the great challenges of medicine in the
One doesn’t often see newspaper articles that
near future (p. 4).
worry about the removal of a tumor or severing of the
In the neuroethics literature, the collective memory of corpus callosum in epilepsy patients on principle.
lobotomy justifies the existence of the new field, Safire, for example, bluntly states, ‘‘no ethical
which presents itself as an improved ethical environ- problem exists with a pacemaker to protect the
ment in which contemporary psychosurgery might heart.’’ Although there are clearly ethical issues
take shape. surrounding pacemakers, what we might take Safire
Neuroethics was brought to the American public’s to mean is that the ethical issues raised by surgery for
attention in 2002 by a New York Times editorial functional psychiatric disorders provoke (Safire
written by conservative columnist William Safire. In might say ‘‘merit’’) public attention in a way that
‘‘The But-What-If Factor,’’ Safire worries about the surgery for organic neurological disorders does not
dangers of ‘‘unbridled science’’ that accompany ‘‘the (and the battle over ‘‘organic’’ and ‘‘functional’’
benefits and dangers of treating and manipulating our disorders rarely plays out in the opinion section). ‘‘If
minds.’’ Because questions raised by neurotechnolo- [deep brain stimulation] was only restricted to
gies have such wide-ranging social implications, neurological disorders, it would not be a topic of
Safire writes, neuroethics should not be confined to ethical debate,’’ astutely observes one neuropyschia-
the pages of medical journals; this ‘‘soul-searching trist (Sachdev 2008, p. 68). If anything, neurosurgery
debate,’’ he writes, should ‘‘get out of the ivory is hailed in the popular imagination as the apex of

123
374 J. Johnson

medical achievement, and neurosurgeons are viewed where patients’ tremors and quakes are known
with the kind of awe reserved for that echelon of to arise. These same brain areas are targeted
super-human that includes fighter pilots and the with DBS, but instead of destroying tissue,
summiters of Everest. There is something about doctors implant slender electrodes that pump
surgical intervention into psychiatric disorders, how- steady pulses of electricity—think of it as a sort
ever, that pricks immediate ethical concern—an of pacemaker for the brain (Song).
admixture of the public’s trust in neurosurgery, its
The article’s description of DBS as a ‘‘sort of’’
perpetual wariness of psychiatry, and the persistent
pacemaker for the brain is one of the most frequent
memory of the lobotomy era. If we revere neurosur-
ways in which neurostimulation is rhetorically con-
geons as demigods, we revile the lobotomists as their
nected to nonpsychiatric conditions. This analogy has
monstrous counterparts—a perversion of everything
become so commonplace in discourse surrounding
we value about surgery on the brain.7 Another
neurostimulation technology, in fact, that it often
effective strategy to manage memories of the lobot-
loses its analogical quality: it is not like a pacemaker.
omy era, then, is to redraw DBS’s family tree in order
It is a pacemaker. The analogy is rhetorically
to highlight its respectable ancestors (neurosurgery
effective for a number of reasons. First, the pace-
for neurological disorders) and favorable relatives
maker is a device well known to a nonspecialist
(cardiac pacemakers) while downplaying its lineage
audience, and it is likely that many people know at
in the lobotomy era, a strategy I suggest might best be
least one person with a cardiac pacemaker personally.
termed genealogical.
Second, as William Safire has told us, the cardiac
Nearly every discussion of DBS in biomedical and
pacemaker is a prime example of a noncontroversial
popular literature references its initial development to
medical technology. In an interview with the Cleve-
control Parkinsonian tremor. In most biomedical
land Plain Dealer, Ali Rezai, head of the Cleveland
discourse about DBS, this genealogy is stated briefly
Clinic’s Center for Neurological Restoration, com-
at the start before moving into the current applica-
pares DBS’s medical moment to
tions for psychiatric disorders. Discussions of DBS in
the popular press spend much more time describing where heart pacemakers were in the 1950s.
its neurological lineage. In an interview with Time Back then, you would tell someone, ‘I’m having
(2006), neurologist Michael Okun explains, ‘‘we can a pacemaker put in,’ and people would go,
thank the patients with Parkinson’s disease for ‘What’s that?’ Now everyone knows what a
helping us develop these therapies because what we heart pacemaker is. I think that it will be a
learned from them we’re applying to other disor- similar situation for brain pacemakers in 10 or
ders.’’ In the genealogical strategy, the progenitors of 20 years (Hall 2001).
DBS patients are not lobotomy patients but Parkin-
Rezai is quoted in another article about DBS in
son’s patients, the difference between Ken Kesey’s
Discovery Magazine entitled ‘‘Brain Pacemakers
Cuckoo’s Nest and Oliver Sacks’ Awakenings. This
Tackle Depression,’’ a headline in which the anal-
article also provides a brief narrative common to
ogy-invoking quotation marks are dropped (Neergaard
many popular articles about DBS:
2008). An article about DBS in Wired magazine, of all
Deep-brain stimulation (DBS) was first devel- places, claims in its headline that the ‘‘Brain ‘Pace-
oped in France in 1987 and evolved out of the maker’ Tickles Your Happy Nerve’’ (Graham 2007).
so-called ablative, or lesioning, surgeries in The Washington Post writes: ‘‘modeled on heart
which doctors use heat probes to burn and pacemakers routinely implanted in people’s chests to
permanently damage small regions of the automatically regulate heart rhythms, brain pacemak-
brain—in the case of Parkinson’s, regions ers were first developed in the late 1980s to treat
Parkinson’s, a devastating brain disorder in which
7
This ‘‘monster’’ rhetoric is displayed most notably in victims inexorably lose control of their muscles’’
discourse surrounding Walter Freeman, recently the subject (Stein 2004). And perhaps most striking, the Cleveland
of a biography by Jack El-Hai (2005) who comments, ‘‘aside Clinic and the US Department of Health and Human
from the Nazi doctor Josef Mengele, Walter Freeman ranks as Services Office on Disability recently co-sponsored a
the most scorned physician in the twentieth century’’ (p. 1).

123
A Dark History 375

conference on DBS in May 2008 using the analogy as distinction between ‘‘psychosurgery’’ and neurosti-
the title: ‘‘Brain Pacemakers: A Promising Approach mulation: ‘‘DBS is not ‘psychosurgery’ even though
and a New Era of Hope for Neurological Disorders.’’ it involves neurosurgery for the treatment of psychi-
Emphasizing the initial use of DBS for neurolog- atric illness. This is because no brain lesion is
ical conditions rhetorically sites the surgery’s devel- created, except for any inadvertent damage produced
opment in a medical lineage less likely to provoke an by the insertion of electrodes’’ (p. 28). For Sachdev
ethical maelstrom. The ‘‘pacemaker’’ analogy works and Chen, the distinction between psychosurgery and
by associating something the audience doesn’t know DBS lies in the function of ablation. Although the
with something they do know and which, importantly, authors admit that tissue damage is part of every
is ethically neutral. I must point out that by examining operation, they do not classify DBS as ‘‘psychosur-
these two strategies as rhetorical is not to suggest there gery’’ because the ultimate purpose of tissue damage
is something fallacious or specious about these is to insert the electrode; any damage to brain tissue is
claims, but to emphasize a potential effect on the only a means to a continually stimulating end, not an
audience. It is true that DBS was developed to treat end in itself (as is the case in ablative surgeries like
Parkinson’s, and the stimulator clearly resembles the lobotomy and amygdalotomy). To further their argu-
cardiac pacemaker in many respects. There’s nothing ment, Sachdev and Chen turn to the familiar pace-
less truthful about calling a neurostimulator a brain maker analogy: ‘‘the insertion of a cardiac pacemaker
pacemaker, or more truthful about calling DBS a form is not ‘cardiac surgery.’ Although this may be a
of psychosurgery. What matters here is not the trivial distinction, it is important so as not to tar DBS
procedure, per se, but the language used to shape with the lobotomy brush’’ (p. 8). Interestingly, the
the audience’s knowledge about and attitudes toward authors note the difference between ablation-as-ends
the procedure: the making-present of one lineage, the and ablation-as-means is ‘‘trivial’’: what is ‘‘impor-
making-absent of another. tant’’ in the name change is not semantic precision,
The final strategy this article will examine is the but the rhetorical management of memory—a clear
argument made by DBS advocates to aband on the anxiety that DBS, if regarded as psychosurgery, will
term ‘‘psychosurgery,’’ which I call the semantic be ‘‘tarred with the lobotomy brush.’’
strategy. ‘‘Perhaps no other word in the field of Sachdev (2008) speaks directly to these concerns in
neurosurgery, or medicine for that matter,’’ writes a second article, in which he argues that ‘‘psychosur-
surgeon Paul Larson, ‘‘conjures up a more negative gery’’ should be abandoned because of ‘‘the emotive
connotation than the word ‘psychosurgery’’’ (2008, p. nature of the term… The bad press for psychosurgery
50). Faced with a collective memory of lobotomy too originated from the period of ‘lobotomy,’ which
strong to be effectively managed by the strategies involved the removing or lesioning of large parts of
above, some advocates have argued that the field the frontal lobes and which is thankfully behind us’’ (p.
should replace the term ‘‘psychosurgery’’ with ‘‘psy- 97). Although Sachdev again focuses his attention on
chiatric neurosurgery,’’ ‘‘neurosurgery for psychiatric the different functions of ablation in order to make the
disorders,’’ ‘‘neurosurgery for mental disorders,’’ or case for the name change, he also makes it clear that the
‘‘limbic system surgery.’’ Although ‘‘limbic system primary reason driving the name change is not a
surgery’’ denotes the same class of procedures as difference in technique, but the ‘‘pejorative connota-
‘‘psychosurgery’’ (and it must be noted that lobot- tions’’ psychosurgery received during the lobotomy
omy, too, was ‘‘limbic system surgery’’) it simply era. He ultimately recommends that the term ‘‘psy-
does not bear its connotative weight. To put it another chosurgery’’ be ‘‘firmly replaced by ‘neurosurgery for
way, we do not remember ‘‘limbic system surgery.’’ psychiatric disorders’’’ (p. 98). The name change is not
There might be a history of limbic system surgery just advocated for DBS. Rosenfeld and Lloyd (1999)
familiar to a few surgeons and historians of medicine, also write strongly in favor of a name change for
of course, but there is no collective memory of the ablative psychosurgery as well: ‘‘the term psychosur-
term ‘‘limbic system surgery,’’ and this is precisely gery is imprecise and is burdened with the connotation
why the term is preferred. of destructive lobotomy operations. The term should be
Sachdev and Chen (2008) argue that the name replaced with the phrase ‘Neurosurgery for Mental
change is warranted because there is a categorical Disorder’ (NMD); ‘Limbic System Surgery’ is another

123
376 J. Johnson

alternative’’ (p. 106). Again, the authors express granted that words, especially scientific terms
concern that the term ‘‘psychosurgery’’ is ‘‘imprecise’’; and terms used in legal statutes and government
however, the primary motivation underlying the name regulations, have an objective meaning. On the
change is to unload the ‘‘burden’’ of connotation. other hand, it is often assumed that when there
Whether DBS is termed ‘‘psychosurgery’’ or ‘‘neu- are verbal disputes about the definitions of
rosurgery for psychiatric disorders’’ seems to have words, that such disputes are relatively trivial,
little impact in the day-to-day treatment of patients. and can easily be resolved by simply clarifying
Where the name matters a great deal, however, is in the the meanings of the words (p. 117).
public and political perception of the surgery. ‘‘Words
There is no objective meaning of ‘‘psychosurgery’’
can have great power,’’ Sachdev observes, and
that can be appealed to in this debate; ‘‘psychosur-
‘‘…because of the prohibition on psychosurgery in
gery’’ finds meaning, as Wittgenstein reminds us, by
many jurisdictions, the development of DBS as a new
how it is used in the language. Whether DBS is
therapeutic technique would be severely thwarted’’
‘‘really’’ psychosurgery is not a matter to be resolved
(p. 98). In other words, in areas where psychosurgery
by an appeal to objective reality or the dictionary,
is specifically prohibited, what is recommended is not
although the Oxford English Dictionary, I might note,
to petition officials to create an exemption for DBS, but
does not support Sachdev’s case. ‘‘Psychosurgery’’ is
to change the name in order to avoid any hindrance to
defined broadly as ‘‘neurosurgery performed to treat
programs of research or clinical application.
mental illness and alter behaviour.’’ If the definitional
It bears mention that the distinction of ablation-as-
issue turns on the meaning of ‘‘surgery,’’ even this
means and ablation-as-end is already written into a
definition does little to clear things up, for ‘‘surgery’’
number of regulations about psychosurgery. An
is defined as ‘‘the art or practice of treating injuries,
Oregon statute against psychosurgery, for example,
deformities, and other disorders by manual operation
defines ‘‘psychosurgery’’ as ‘‘any operation designed
or instrumental appliances.’’ What is deep brain
to irreversibly lesion or destroy brain tissue for the
stimulation if not the use of an instrumental appliance
primary purpose of altering the thoughts, emotions or
to treat a disorder? Ultimately, debates over a word’s
behavior of a human being. ‘Psychosurgery’ does not
‘‘real’’ meaning are unproductive, for what a word
include procedures which may irreversibly lesion or
means will always come back to how it is used. From
destroy brain tissues when undertaken to cure well
a rhetorical perspective, far more interesting than
defined disease states such as a brain tumor, epileptic
whether DBS is ‘‘really’’ psychosurgery is the ques-
foci and certain chronic pain syndromes’’ (Oregon
tion of why this question matters, to whom, and for
1973, my emphasis). The language of the Oregon
what effect. The semantic strategy is a rhetorical issue
statute is also cited by the Psychosurgery Review
that goes far beyond ‘‘mere semantics.’’ As Sachdev
Board in Melbourne, Australia, the country in which
points out, if DBS is called ‘‘psychosurgery’’ in
Sachdev practices. Given this distinction, which
certain jurisdictions, regulations will prohibit its
clearly uses the purpose of ablation to delimit
research and clinical use. For clinical researchers
psychosurgery, it would seem as though regulations
who believe strongly in the therapeutic potential of
like these would already make an exception for
DBS, as Sachdev clearly does, a ‘‘careless approach
procedures like DBS. The chief concern, then,
with our terminology can have adverse conse-
appears to be the public perception of DBS.
quences’’ on the lives of people suffering deeply from
As rhetorical scholars have argued for millennia,
intractable forms of depression (2008, p. 98).
all definitions are persuasive. All language is bur-
dened with connotations and implicit values, and any
definition of a term involves ‘‘claims of ‘ought’
Conclusion
instead of ‘is’’’ (Schiappa 2003, p. 5). Writes
philosopher Douglas N. Walton (2001),
In this article, I have argued that the collective memory
popular opinions tend to take certain assump- of lobotomy era requires advocates of deep brain
tions about definitions for granted, without stimulation to engage in a variety of rhetorical
reflecting on them too deeply. It is taken for strategies in order to persuasively articulate its lineage.

123
A Dark History 377

In many of these arguments, lobotomy is a productive attitudes and actions. If biomedicine truly valorizes
ghost: its memory is marshaled as a touchstone by dialogue that extends beyond the pages of its
which contemporary forms of psychosurgery can be journals, it is essential to examine its persuasive
evaluated. Although some stimulation advocates wish communication practices and to investigate the
to avoid its constraints, it is clear that a significant different forms that this persuasion may take. To
number also use the powerful collective memory of simply call for dialogue without asking how it
lobotomy as an impetus to engage in reflection about operates risks replacing meaningful dialogue with
psychosurgery’s past, present, and future, a move an empty word.
echoed by a number of histories of psychosurgery that
have appeared in the medical literature in recent years
(Feldman and Goodrich 2001; Koppell and Rezai References
2003; Mashour et al. 2004; Fins et al. 2006; Stone
2008; Wind and Anderson 2008). Fins et al. (2006) Abosch, A., and G.R. Cosgrove. 2008. Biological basis for the
praise this renewed interest in psychosurgery’s history, surgical treatment of depression. Neurosurgical Focus 25:
1–12.
because it provides Assmann, A. 2006. History, memory, and the genre of testi-
mony. Poetics Today 27: 261–273.
a good opportunity for us to reflect on the
Assmann, J. 1995. Collective memory and cultural identity.
legacy of psychosurgery and its modern itera- New German Critique 65: 125–133.
tion under the guise of neuromodulation. The Barker-Benfield, G.J. 1999. The horrors of the half-known life:
seriousness of their scholarship allow a dia- Male attitudes toward women and sexuality in 19th cen-
tury America. London: Routledge.
logue for which all readers of this journal
Bryant, D.C. 1973. Rhetorical dimensions in criticism. Baton
should be appreciative, whether or not one Rouge: Louisiana State University Press.
agrees with the piece. In consideration of the Davis, K., and D. Stewart. 2008. Rev. of the lobotomist.
complexity of the topic, a diversity of views American Journal of Psychiatry 165: 457–458.
El-Hai, J. 2005. The lobotomist: A maverick medical genius
should be welcomed and open debate encour- and his tragic quest to rid the world of mental illness.
aged. Nothing less will provide the ethical New York: Wiley.
justification for achieving a therapeutic future Feldman, R.P., and J.T. Goodrich. 2001. Psychosurgery: A
for neuromodulation (p. 713). historical overview. Neurosurgery 48: 647–657.
Fins, J.J., A.R. Rezai, and B.D. Greenberg. 2006. Psychosur-
While Rezai et al.’s call for more debate about gery: Avoiding an ethical redux while advancing a ther-
psychosurgery is laudable, it is also important that the apeutic future. Neurosurgery 59: 713–716.
Foucault, M. 1977. Language, counter-memory, practice:
dialogue they encourage not be limited to members of selected essays and interviews by Michel Foucault. Ed.
the biomedical professions. In this article, I have Donald F. Bouchard. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
attempted to show what a rhetorical perspective Freeman, W. 1954. Transorbital lobotomy in state mental
might bring to this discussion by arguing that any hospitals. Journal of the Medical Society of New Jersey
51: 148–149.
invocation of medicine’s past involves an element of Freeman, W., and J. Watts. 1950. Psychosurgery in the treat-
persuasion. The rhetorical dynamics of collective ment of mental disorders and intractable pain, 2nd ed.
memory also leads us to ask questions about the Springfield, IL: Charles C. Thomas.
dialogue between patients/companions and physi- Geary, P. 1994. Phantoms of remembrance: Memory and
oblivion at the end of the first millennium. Princeton:
cians that leads to decision making about DBS as a Princeton University Press.
treatment option (or electroconvulsive therapy which, Goodman, W.K., and T.R. Insel. 2009. Deep brain stimulation
like psychosurgery, is also burdened with a ‘‘dark’’ in psychiatry: Concentrating on the road ahead. Editorial.
history). How do clinicians address questions gener- Biological Psychiatry 65: 263–266.
Graham, M. 2007. Brain ‘pacemaker’ tickles your happy nerve.
ated by collective memory? Are they dismissed or Wired. http://www.wired.com/science/discoveries/news/
used as a point of departure to engage in dialogue 2007/05/nerve. Accessed 10 April 2009.
about patient concerns? If these memories are Gronbeck, B.E. 1998. The rhetoric of the past: History, argu-
engaged, how are they managed rhetorically, and ment, and collective memory. In Doing rhetorical history:
Concepts and cases, ed. K.J. Turner. Tuscaloosa, AL:
for what reasons? What rhetoric brings to the University of Alabama Press.
interdisciplinary table of medicine studies is an Halbwachs, M. 1980 [1951]. The collective memory. New York
emphasis on the power of language to shape our and London: Harper and Row.

123
378 J. Johnson

Hall, S.S. 2001. Brain pacemakers. Technology Review. http:// Reverby, S.M. 2001. More than fact and fiction: Cultural
www.technologyreview.com/biomedicine/12553. Accessed memory and the Tuskegee study. Hastings Center Report
5 April 2009. 31: 22–28.
Hardesty, D.E., and H.A. Sackheim. 2007. Deep brain stimu- Richards, S.E. 2008. Neuromodulation. Slate. http://www.slate.
lation in movement and psychiatric disorders. Biological com/id/2184699/pagenum/all. Accessed 5 April 2009.
Psychiatry 61: 831–835. Rosenfeld, J.V., and J.H. Lloyd. 1999. Contemporary psycho-
Klein, K.L. 2000. On the emergence of memory in historical surgery. Journal of Clinical Neuroscience 6: 106–112.
discourse. Representations 12: 127–150. Roskies, A. Neuroethics for the new millennium. Neuron 35:
Koppell, B.H., and A.R. Rezai. 2003. Psychiatric neurosurgery: 21-23.
A historical perspective. In Neurosurgery clinics of North Sachdev, P.S. 2008. Is deep brain stimulation a form of psy-
America—surgery for psychiatric disorders, ed. A.R. chosurgery? Australasian Psychiatry 15: 97–99.
Rezai, S.A. Rasmussen, and B.D. Greenberg, 181–197. Sachdev, P.S., and X. Chen. 2008. Neurosurgical treatment of
Philadelphia: Saunders. mood disorders: Traditional psychosurgery and the advent
Larson, P. 2008. Deep brain stimulation for psychiatric disor- of deep brain stimulation. Current Opinion in Psychiatry
ders. The Journal of the American Society for Experi- 22: 25–31.
mental NeuroTherapeutics 5: 50–58. Safire, W. 2002. The but-what-if factor. New York Times. http://
Lewenstein, B.V. 1995. From fax to facts: Communication in the www.nytimes.com/2002/05/16/opinion/16SAFI.html.
cold fusion saga. Social Studies of Science 25: 403–436 Sartin, J.S. 2004. J. Marion Sims, the father of gynecology:
Mashour, G.A., E.E. Walker, and R.L. Martuza. 2004. Psy- Hero or villain? Southern Medical Journal 97: 500–504.
chosurgery: Past, present, and future. Brain Research Schiappa, E. 2003. Defining reality: Definitions and the politics
Reviews 48: 409–419. of meaning. Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University
Mayberg, H., A. Lozano, V. Voon, H. McNeely, D. Semi- Press.
nowicz, C. Hamani, J. Schwalb, and S. Kennedy. 2005. Segal, J.Z. 2005. Health and the rhetoric of medicine. Car-
Deep brain stimulation for treatment-resistant depression. bondale: Southern Illinois State University Press.
Neuron 45: 651–660. Song, S. 2006. How deep-brain stimulation works.Time. 16
Moran, M. 2004. Psychosurgery evolves into new neurosurgery July 2006. http://www.time.com/time/magazine/article/
approaches. Psychiatric News 39: 28. http://pn.psychiatry 0,9171,1214939,00.html. Accessed 5 April 2009.
online.org/cgi/content/full/39/1/28. Accessed 5 April 2009. Stein, R. 2004. The potential of ‘brain pacemakers.’ Wash-
Neergaard, L. 2008. Brain pacemakers tackle depression. ington Post. 6 March 2004: A1, A6.
Discovery Channel News. http://dsc.discovery.com/news/ Stone, A.A. 2008. Psychosurgery: old and new. Psychiatric
2008/05/27/depression-pacemaker.html. Accessed 5 April Times 25 http://www.psychiatrictimes.com/display/article/
2009. 10168/1163539?pageNumber=2. Accessed 6 April 2009.
Nora, P. 1989 [1984]. Between memory and history: les lieux Thomas, S.B., and S.C. Quinn. 1991. The Tuskegee syphilis
de mémoire. Representations 26: 7–25. study, 1932–1972: Implications for HIV education and
O’Leary, J.P. 2004. J. Marion Sims: a defense of the father of AIDS risk programs in the Black community. American
gynecology. Southern Medical Journal: 427–429. Journal of Public Health 8: 1498–1506.
Oregon Senate. 1973. Oregon psychosurgery bill (SB) 298. United States National Commission for the Protection of
Portland, OR: Oregon Legislative Assembly. Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research.
Pressman, J.D. 1998. Last resort: Psychosurgery and the limits 1977. Psychosurgery: Report and recommendations.
of medicine. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Washington, DC: US Government Printing Office. DHEW
Psychosurgery Review Board (Australia). http://www.prb.vic. publication (OS) 77-0001.
gov.au. Accessed 11 April 2009. Walton, D. 2001. Persuasive definitions and public policy
Quality of Health Care in Human Experimentation. 1973. arguments. Argumentation and Advocacy 37: 117–132.
Senate subcommittee on health United States senate. Wind, J.J., and D.E. Anderson. 2008. From prefrontal leukot-
Washington, DC: U.S. Government Printing Office. omy to deep brain stimulation: The historical transfor-
Ricouer, P. 2006. Memory, History, Forgetting. Trans. K. mation of psychosurgery and the emergence of
Blamey and D. Pellauer. Chicago: University of Chicago neuroethics. Neurosurgical Focus 25: 1–5.
Press.

123

You might also like