You are on page 1of 8

Reviews and Overviews

Explanatory Models for Psychiatric Illness

Kenneth S. Kendler, M.D. How can we best develop explanatory sembly. Simple subunits of complicated
models for psychiatric disorders? Because mechanisms can be usefully studied in
causal factors have an impact on psychi- isolation. Reassembling these constituent
atric illness both at micro levels and parts into a functioning whole, which is
macro levels, both within and outside of straightforward for simple additive mech-
the individual, and involving processes anisms, will be far more challenging in
best understood from biological, psycho- psychiatry where causal networks contain
logical, and sociocultural perspectives, multiple nonlinear interactions and
traditional models of science that strive causal loops. Our field has long struggled
for single broadly applicable explanatory with the interrelationship between bio-
laws are ill suited for our field. Such mod- logical and psychological explanatory per-
els are based on the incorrect assumption spectives. Building from the seminal work
that psychiatric illnesses can be under- of the neuronal modeler and philosopher
stood from a single perspective. A more David Marr, the author suggests that biol-
appropriate scientific model for psychia- ogy will implement but not replace psy-
try emphasizes the understanding of chology within our explanatory systems.
mechanisms, an approach that fits natu- The iterative process of interactions be-
rally with a multicausal framework and tween biology and psychology needed to
provides a realistic paradigm for scientific achieve this implementation will deepen
progress, that is, understanding mecha- our understanding of both classes of pro-
nisms through decomposition and reas- cesses.

(Am J Psychiatry 2008; 165:695–702)

T his essay addresses two fundamental questions about


explanatory models for psychiatric disorders. In the first
Traditional models of science view the discovery of fun-
damental laws as the ultimate goal. That is, science should
section, I propose a central role for multilevel mecha- seek to explain vast details of the workings of our universe
nisms. I show how progress can be made using the ap- from a few basic principles, such as Newton’s laws of mo-
proach of decomposition and reassembly despite the tion and gravity. The traditional model of science sees ex-
complexity and nonadditive nature of the etiological pro- planation as emanating from such fundamental princi-
cesses involved. In the second section, I address how to ples outward into the workings of the observed world.
optimally interrelate biological and psychological explan- Although deeply influential in 20th-century science,
atory perspectives. While the first section deals with relat- this model was developed from physics and does not eas-
ing parts to wholes in the context of intricate etiological ily apply to the biological and social sciences relevant to
mechanisms, the second part struggles with understand- psychiatry. Indeed, a fundamental implication of this
ing the relationship between two distinct perspectives on model of science, namely, that all real causal processes
the same basic phenomenon. should be understood from one perspective and one set of
laws, has been counterproductive in the field of mental
Levels of Explanation health and has indirectly encouraged the rise of two per-
spectives that I argue have been counterproductive: “hard
First Principles reductionism” (“all psychiatric illness is best explained
Rather than adopting a single explanatory perspective, solely in terms of molecular neuroscience”) and “hard
as is often advocated in traditional theories of science, eti- emergentism” (e.g., “all psychiatric illness is best ex-
ological models for psychiatric disorders need to be plu- plained solely in terms of specified mental or social mech-
ralistic or multilevel (1, 2). A range of compelling evidence anisms and cannot be deduced from biology”). Emergent
indicates that these disorders involve causal processes properties of a system are properties that cannot be pre-
that act both at micro levels and macro levels, that act dicted from individual elements but arise only when the
within and outside of the individual, and that involve pro- elements act together as a group.
cesses best understood from biological, psychological, A central tenet of this essay is that psychiatry should
and sociocultural perspectives. move away from this law-based model of science to one

This article is the subject of a CME course (p. 783).

Am J Psychiatry 165:6, June 2008 ajp.psychiatryonline.org 695


EXPLANATORY MODELS FOR PSYCHIATRIC ILLNESS

that focuses on mechanisms. Such a move—from laws to ceptualize how the whole thing works together, and this
mechanisms as the fundamental explanatory goal of our will always mean more than simply clarifying the opera-
science—produces a more coherent and practical concep- tion of the lowest level of the mechanism. By “levels” I
tual framework. In particular, while the integration of bio- mean pieces of a mechanism that exhibit a part-whole (or
logical, psychological, and social elements into causal component-system) relationship. Because molecules make
processes was a tortured one using law-based models of up a membrane, neurons make up a circuit, higher-order
science, it flows easily from a multilevel mechanistic ap- neural systems (in a still mysterious way) make up an indi-
proach. This approach to psychiatric illness is a conceptu- vidual, and individuals make up a society, we can usefully
ally rigorous descendant of a distinguished lineage of ear- talk of causal mechanisms with lower and higher levels.
lier integrationist accounts (e.g., references 3, 4). Ultimately we face the task of figuring out how the entire
What do I mean by a mechanistic approach? The differ- system works. But how do we get there?
ences between a mechanistic, reductionist, and emergent
approach can be illustrated with a simplified story: Our task
Decomposition
is to understand a home heating system. The hard reduc- This process typically begins with a “mechanistic
tionist identifies the thermostat and furnace as the funda- sketch,” one that describes how the system might possibly
mental features of the system—those that drive the basic work. The sketch is then filled in, characteristically in
processes. He takes them apart and explains their key work- stages, to form an increasingly comprehensive mechanis-
ing parts through well-understood engineering principles. tic model. That is, science moves from “how possibly” to
That, he argues, “is all there is to it.” The hard emergentist “how actually” descriptions of the mechanism (6).
graphs temperature fluctuations in the home—the key out- The main workhorse in the traditional scientific ap-
put variable—and discovers important circadian rhythms proach to multilevel systems has been decomposition.
and predicts them with a complex statistical model. That, First, the scientist tries to disassemble the system, break-
he concludes, “is all there is to it.” The mechanistically ori- ing it down into its constituent parts (7, 8). Second, the sci-
ented researcher analyzes the home as a complex multi- entist tries to understand each part in turn, starting with
level system including thermostat, furnace, ducts, heat gain the simplest and working toward the most complex.
and loss, degree of insulation, weather patterns, heat- Sometimes an additional cycle of decomposition is re-
generating appliances, and human activity. She develops a quired, as components often have subcomponents. The fi-
complex working model based on an understanding of the nal phase then is one of integration—the understanding of
many component parts and their interactions. That, she how all of the parts work together to produce the complex
summarizes, “provides the best explanation.” mechanism. Such an approach can be used to understand
In suggesting that we adopt a mechanistic approach to mechanisms as diverse as your car engine, the metabo-
explanation in psychiatry, I mean that explanation requires lism of a particular carbohydrate in a cell, and auditory
the explication of causal mechanisms and the understand- perception in an owl.
ing of how those mechanisms are actually instantiated in The ease of decomposition varies in different kinds of
the world. Our task is to clarify the mechanisms that un- systems. One conceptually important class of systems is
derlie and have an impact on central mind/brain processes “easily decomposable” (7). Such systems demonstrate “ag-
such as mood, perception, belief formation, and hedonic gregativity” (9), meaning that their constituent parts inter-
processes so that we can understand the causal processes relate with each other in a simple additive manner (10).
whereby they become disordered in psychiatric illness. Each module is “intersubstitutable,” meaning that it has a
Mechanistic models occupy a middle ground between discrete intrinsic function that can be understood when
the views of hard reduction and hard emergence. As Bech- separated from the entire system and studied on its own or
tel succinctly summarizes: “The decomposition required when placed in different systems—that is, actions of the
by mechanistic explanation is reductionist, but the recog- parts are not context dependent. Easily decomposable sys-
nition that parts and operations must be organized into an tems lack “causal loops.” Such loops can be either intra-
appropriate whole provides for a robust sense of a higher level—when a component’s actions can alter its own prop-
level of organization” (5, p. 130). erties or those of nearby elements—or interlevel. The most
Understanding mechanisms requires a reductionist de- important kind of interlevel causal loop is where the output
scent into the nitty-gritty of the world to figure out how of the entire system feeds back to its own constituent com-
things actually work. But in biological systems, events are ponents. This is called recursive, or top-down, causality.
always situated within contexts and causal processes are
typically multilayered. Mechanistic explanations therefore Alcohol Dependence as an Example
require the integration of multiple organizational levels. To illustrate and concretize the principles outlined
For simple mechanisms—like your house thermostat— above, I here develop a much simplified explanatory
this can be a relatively easy job. More complex mecha- sketch of a mechanistic understanding of alcohol depen-
nisms can be much more challenging, but the basic prin- dence. I chose this syndrome because it well illustrates
ciple still holds. An adequate scientific account must con- multilevel causal processes. The first task in understand-

696 ajp.psychiatryonline.org Am J Psychiatry 165:6, June 2008


KENNETH S. KENDLER

ing a mechanism is to localize different components. the additivity and “intersubstitution” assumptions. Their
Where do the causal pieces lie? Empirically supported risk effects are dependent on both biochemical and psychoso-
factors for alcohol dependence occur on at least four cial contexts.
broad levels: biological/genetic, psychological, social, and Next, we examine the evidence for “causal loops” in the
cultural/economic. etiology of alcohol dependence. Genes strongly influence
Biological/genetic. Risk for alcohol dependence may be the initial response to ethanol (37). At one extreme, indi-
altered by prenatal exposure to alcohol (11). Aggregate ge- viduals with a variant of aldehyde dehydrogenase metab-
netic factors strongly influence liability to alcohol depen- olize acetaldehyde so slowly that they develop a dysphoric
dence (12). We are learning that genetic factors can have flushing reaction after significant ethanol consumption
an impact in many places on the pathway to alcohol de- (38). This genetic effect substantially reduces the chances
pendence, ranging from specific effects on alcohol metab- that such individuals will repeatedly reexpose themselves
olism (13) and brain systems that interact directly and in- to the large doses of ethanol needed to develop depen-
directly with ethanol (e.g., γ-aminobutyric acid [GABA], dence (38, 39). At the other extreme, individuals who ge-
glutamate, and opioid systems) (14) to broader liabilities netically have reduced sensitivity to ethanol’s effects are
to the abuse of all forms of psychoactive drugs (15) and an more likely to drink frequently and have an elevated risk of
even broader disposition toward externalizing behaviors developing alcohol dependence (37, 40). So genes influ-
(16, 17). ence subjective ethanol effects, which influence alcohol
expectations, which in turn loop out into the environ-
Psychological. A range of psychological constructs also
ment, influencing consumption patterns, which in turn
affect risk for alcohol dependence, including several per-
affect risk of alcohol dependence.
sonality traits, such as neuroticism, impulsivity, and extra-
Exposure to ethanol produces physiological tolerance
version (18, 19), and several dimensions of alcohol expec-
both from increased metabolic rates and decreased CNS
tancies (20, 21).
sensitivity (41). This can produce a positive feedback loop
Social. As confirmed by twin studies (which show adoles- in which early phases of heavy drinking permit an individ-
cent alcohol use to be strongly influenced by environmen- ual to better “hold their liquor,” which in turn encourages
tal factors [22, 23]), alcohol consumption and risk for alco- yet greater consumption.
hol dependence are robustly predicted by social factors, Impulsive, risk-taking adolescents seek out similar
such as peer substance use, drug availability, and social peers who provide support for and access to further anti-
class (18, 24). social and drug-taking behaviors (42, 43). Genetic factors
Cultural/economic. Cultural, religious, and economic influence this process (44, 45). So genetically influenced
factors affect risk for alcohol dependence. Culture influ- temperament causes individuals to select themselves into
ences the forms of ethanol commonly consumed (25), the high-risk environments, which feed back on their risk for
acceptability of public drunkenness (26), and the appro- alcohol dependence by providing easy access to ethanol
priateness of drinking by men versus women (which influ- and encouragement for its excessive use. As one wag has
ences the vastly different ratios of alcohol dependence in put it, for us humans, who go out into the world to actively
men and women across cultures) (27). Rates of alcohol de- create our environments, our “brain has feet.”
pendence often rise with the breakdown of traditional cul- Finally, at the “highest” level, a top-down causal loop is
tural beliefs and practices in migrant and native popula- reflected in “reverse” (or “aversive”) cultural transmission
tions (19, 28). In the United States, religious beliefs for drinking behavior. The rate of abstention from alcohol
influence both alcohol consumption and the risk for pro- is increased in the offspring of heavy-drinking parents (46,
gression to alcoholism (24). Levels of taxation of alcoholic 47). Individuals at high genetic risk for alcohol depen-
beverages and statutes controlling the sizes of alcoholic dence see the syndrome’s ravages in a parent, are aware of
beverage containers permitted for sale both have an im- their own high risk, and consciously decide to abstain
pact on the frequency of alcohol-related problems (29, from ethanol consumption, thereby eliminating their risk
30). for dependence.
Given these component parts, we must understand the
nature of their interactions. How aggregative are they? It Examples of Nonaggregative Properties in Other
will be sufficient for our purposes to look only at that part Psychiatric Disorders
of the picture involving genetic effects. At a biochemical Similar nonaggregative properties are common in the
level, interaction in risk for alcohol dependence has been mechanisms that lead to other psychiatric disorders. For
seen for variants in genes at different stages of the ethanol example, individuals differ in sensitivity to the patho-
metabolic pathway (31). Using twin designs, genetic ef- genic effects of adversity as a result of their prior experi-
fects on risk for drinking or alcohol dependence have been ences (48), genetic constitution (49–51), personality (52,
shown to vary as a function of religious beliefs (32), marital 53), and social class (54). The impact of genes on liability
status (33, 34), and social environment (35, 36). Thus, the to psychiatric illness varies as a function of environmen-
impact of genetic risk factors for alcohol dependence fails tal exposure (55) and other genetic loci (56). Depending

Am J Psychiatry 165:6, June 2008 ajp.psychiatryonline.org 697


EXPLANATORY MODELS FOR PSYCHIATRIC ILLNESS

on a range of background factors, the same stressful expe- parts in isolation and a detailed explanation will fall into
rience can result in sensitization or habituation (57). That place because the parts simply fit together. It will not and
is, the impact of many risk factors for psychiatric illness is they do not.
context dependent. Indeed, hard reductionists have typically argued that in-
Disorders other than alcohol dependence also demon- creased understanding will bring greater simplicity and
strate robust causal loops, especially of the top-down vari- reductive power—that the more we understand about the
ety. For example, an individual with high levels of the per- basic biology of psychiatric illness, the simpler and more
sonality trait of neuroticism—strongly associated with risk potent will be our causal predictions. By contrast, I agree
for major depression (58)—is more prone to conflictual in- with Wimsatt when he writes, “The degree and kinds of
terpersonal relationships, reduced levels of social support, emergence postulated of system proprieties should tend
and increased rates of stressful life events, all of which in- to increase with increasingly detailed specification of the
crease risk for depression (59). The fearful child, after a internal structure and environmental relations of the sys-
single mildly traumatic experience with a neighborhood tems in the model” (63, p. 287). That is, the more details we
dog, avoids further contact with dogs, thereby preventing learn about the etiology of psychiatric disorders, the
the habituation of the initial fear response. Feedback greater will be the number and importance of cross-mod-
loops may also involve expectational sets. Anxiety-prone ule interactions and causal loops. Etiological pathways for
individuals selectively perceive danger (60), which in turn psychiatric disorders will be “deeply recursive,” moving
can increase symptoms. In a lovely illustration of top- many times between levels and forming what Wimsatt has
down control, panic patients were randomized into evocatively called a “causal thicket” (64).
groups who were told or were not told that they could con- Scientists who brave this process—the stitching to-
trol the level of inhaled CO2-enriched air. Although both gether of the initially disjoint subsystems—will likely ex-
groups received the same CO2 concentration, those with perience what Craver has called “explanatory oscillation”
the illusion of control reported fewer and less intense (6) as they move iteratively back and forth across levels. As
panic symptoms (61). a model for what we hope to develop in psychiatry, we
might consider how this integrative (or “stitching”) pro-
Implications of Nondecomposability cess has worked in the clarification of the mechanisms of
What are the main lessons from this abbreviated ex- memory where the phenomenal and neural decomposi-
planatory sketch for alcohol dependence and brief review tions of memory were mutually informative and synergis-
of relevant examples from other areas of psychopathol- tically interactive over time (5).
ogy? First, hard reduction will not work because of the
nonaggregativity and causal loops. The explanatory prop- The Nesting of Biological and
erties of these mechanisms are not reducible to any single
Psychological Explanatory Perspectives
level, molecular or otherwise. Second, although this non-
decomposability greatly complicates our search to under- A complete picture of psychiatric illness must confront
stand explanatory mechanisms in psychiatry, cynicism another even subtler dilemma faced by many other sci-
and pessimism are as premature and unwarranted as is ences (65)—how to integrate distinct perspectives on the
zealous oversimplification. Bechtel documents how scien- same underlying process. For our field, the most promi-
tists, with care and persistence, have made major ad- nent perspectival dilemma is that of how brain- versus
vances in understanding nondecomposable complex bio- mind-based approaches will interrelate in explanations of
logical systems (5, 7, 62). Causal loops are not irrevocable psychiatric disorders.
barriers to detailed scientific understanding, as is well il- My approach to this question begins with the work of
lustrated by the ability of early 20th-century biochemistry Marr (66), who proposed that a biologically complex infor-
to clarify the citric acid cycle (62). mation-processing system like the mammalian visual sys-
The initial phase of these successful approaches has al- tem can be realized (or understood) from three comple-
ways been to find subareas of local decomposability—rel- mentary perspectives. These three perspectives are as
atively simple subsystems that could be profitably studied follows, with Marr’s original description of them in quotes
in isolation. This approach allows local causal processes to and my rephrasing in italics (66, p. 25):
be clarified while ignoring other parts of the system. De- 1. Computational theory: “What is the goal of the com-
spite the rising call for “translational research,” simple de- putation … and what is the logic of the strategy by which it
composition remains a critical first strategy toward ap- can be carried out?” What is the task this mind/brain sys-
proaching the etiology of psychiatric disorders. The naive tem is designed to accomplish?
emergentism that opines that the system is so complex 2. Representation and algorithm: “How can this compu-
and interrelated that we cannot possibly study any part in tational theory be implemented? In particular, what is the
isolation is just plain wrong. But it is no less wrong than representation for the input and the output and what is
the equally misinformed idea—often professed by the the algorithm for the transformation?” What functional
hard reductionists—that all we have to do is study the processes are required to accomplish the task?

698 ajp.psychiatryonline.org Am J Psychiatry 165:6, June 2008


KENNETH S. KENDLER

3. Hardware implementation: “How can the representa- contains, this view suggests, many different neural sub-
tion and algorithm be realized physically?” How are those systems, all of which evolved to accomplish distinct tasks.
processes actually implemented in brain “wetware”? Such tasks range from the relatively simple—such as
The key feature of Marr’s approach—which provides a maintaining an appropriate respiratory rate—to the ex-
hierarchy of explanation—is that the biology (“hardware tremely complex, such as the perception of meaning in
implementation” in his terminology) is understood in the human speech.
context of functional explanations that articulate the Imagine coming upon an old machine full of gears,
goals of the system. Note that Marr’s implementation per- sprockets, springs, and levers. What would be required to
spective focuses on the biological means by which a “explain” the workings of this machine? The concept of
mechanism is executed while the representational and reverse-engineering provides a simple answer. To “ex-
computational perspectives examine content. (To reem- plain” it, you must understand what its purpose is. Once
phasize, Marr is proposing different perspectives on the you know the purpose, you can, with patience and inge-
same psychobiological process—here the mammalian vi- nuity, “reverse-engineer” what the components of the
sual system. This is in contrast to the first part of this es- machine are doing. So understanding the function of a
say, which examined different parts of a single broad machine forms the framework for an explanation of how
mechanism.) it works. While the human brain is not a machine de-
To try to build models of brain function from the bottom signed by a human, it is, functionally, a machine designed
up, Marr suggests, is hopeless. If you took such an ap- by evolution. So once we decide to try to understand what
proach and began at the level of individual molecular pro- the brain is doing, we find that we cannot proceed with-
cesses as they occur within neurons and tried to work up out considering higher levels of analysis such as cogni-
from there to higher functions such as perception or mo- tion, emotion, and perception.
tor behavior, let alone mood or “reality testing,” you would How can we conceptualize what different parts of our
not be able to see the forest for the trees. Rather, you also brains are supposed to do? We can do that only in the lan-
need a top-down perspective, beginning with the task that guage of function, which means using psychological con-
the neural machinery was designed to execute. structs. Neurochemical terms will not work. So a reverse-
Marr’s levels were designed for neural systems that pro- engineering approach to understanding how brains make
cess information. However, at a deeper level, his approach minds also suggests that biological explanations for the
implements the old physiological distinction between un- disturbed brain/mind systems that underlie psychiatric
derstanding structure (hardware/brain) and function disorders have to be placed within the context of psycho-
(processes/algorithms). These two complementary ap- logical processes.
proaches have often been used iteratively in the scientific The second perspective on this problem contrasts two
approach toward understanding complex biological sys- different ways in which a more abstract (or higher-order)
tems and have, for example, been central to the develop- theory can relate to a more basic (or lower-order) theory.
ment of cell biology (62). One possible form of that relationship is replacement, an-
Marr’s three perspectives could be used unaltered for other term for hard-core reduction. Consider the physical
guiding our approach toward understanding the mecha- concepts of temperature and mean kinetic energy. Once
nisms underlying certain psychiatric symptoms, such as you know the mean kinetic energy of a gas, you learn noth-
auditory hallucinations or biased threat perception. Al- ing more by knowing its temperature. The higher-order
though many psychiatric problems are not currently ame- construct (temperature) becomes redundant and is re-
nable to an information-processing perspective, Marr’s placed by the more basic construct (mean kinetic energy).
underlying logic is nonetheless valid for psychiatry across The second possible form of this relationship is imple-
the board. Obtaining a complete explanation of psychiat- mentation. Here, the more basic theory provides the
ric disorders will require detailed understanding from a mechanistic details of how the functions proposed by the
biological perspective. But this will not emerge from the more abstract theory actually get accomplished. In this
bottom up—wherein biology would replace psychology— case, the higher- and lower-order theories work together
as predicted by the hard reductionists. Rather, it will hap- to provide a complete explanation. The lower-order the-
pen by supplementing such strategies with top-down ap- ory does not replace the higher-order theory.
proaches, which allow biological explanations to be pur- Which of these two relationships best describes how
sued and understood in the context of prior models psychology and biology will interrelate in the explanation
articulated using psychological constructs. of psychiatric disorders? I argue that implementation is
Let me come at this key concept—that biological expla- the more accurate depiction and fits well within the mech-
nations need to be understood top-down in a context anistic framework here advocated. Following Gold and
defined by mental constructs—from three additional, Stoljar (69), we can gain some confidence about the cor-
interrelated vantage points. First, both cognitive and evo- rect answer to this question by examining recent neurobi-
lutionary psychology advocate a “reverse-engineering” ological research. For this purpose, they examine the work
approach to brain/mind functioning (67, 68). The brain of Kandel on learning in Aplysia species (69) and conclude

Am J Psychiatry 165:6, June 2008 ajp.psychiatryonline.org 699


EXPLANATORY MODELS FOR PSYCHIATRIC ILLNESS

that his research program is best understood as an exam- ology—will be needed to reach a more complete under-
ple of implementation, not replacement—that is, his work standing. In short, biological and psychological perspec-
is best seen as “the fleshing out of a psychological story in tives will coevolve.
neurobiological terms” (69, p. 822). Along the same lines, These arguments do not imply that useful insights can-
Hatfield (70) and Bechtel (5) have shown, respectively, that not come from the hard reductive or emergent perspec-
for three areas of visual perception (binocular single vi- tives. Indeed, effective therapies can be developed from
sion, stereopsis, and color vision) and for memory, neuro- basic biological research (such as associated genes) with-
scientists have progressed by figuring out how the brain out having any idea of how the gene variant produces
has implemented processes first worked out by psycholo- symptoms. Furthermore, important approaches to treat-
gists. ment, such as cognitive-behavioral therapies, have
Our third perspective on the relationship between bio- emerged from psychological constructs that contained no
logical explanations and mental constructs can be best il- biology. However, these perspectives will leave us with
lustrated with a hypothetical story: A research team shows only part of the picture.
definitively that gene X is associated with schizophrenia.
The results are widely replicated. This research team then Summary
shows that gene X produces protein Y. A large definitive
study shows that protein Y is abnormal in schizophrenia. A comprehensive etiological understanding of psychiat-
This too is replicated, at which point they call a press con- ric disorders will require the integration of multiple ex-
ference to declare that they have “solved the riddle” of planatory perspectives. Law-based theories of science de-
schizophrenia. Amid the triumphalist rhetoric, a young rived largely from physics, in which explanation arises
psychiatric resident raises her hand and asks, “But how from a few simple laws, poorly match the nature of the
does this abnormality in protein Y lead to the characteris- problems confronting psychiatry. Instead, I advocate a
tic symptoms of schizophrenia—delusions, hallucina- mechanistic approach—where the chief goal is to under-
tions, thought disorder, and negative symptoms?” The stand the mechanisms that derail the key mind/brain
lead scientist, a bit stunned by the questions, replies, “We functions that are disordered in psychiatric illness. Simple
have no idea.” methods of decomposition will not work, because the
A more comprehensive explanation of a psychiatric dis- causal networks underlying psychiatric illness are not ag-
order must include an understanding of the production of gregative and contain multiple nonlinear interactions and
the key symptoms and signs underlying that disorder. causal loops. However, as in other areas of biology and
Parts of these explanations will have to be framed in psy- neuroscience, progress can be made through the study of
chological terms. Genes and molecules will surely prove to subsystems of local decomposability followed by the chal-
be critical causes of schizophrenia and thus will explain lenging task of integration.
important things about the illness. But alone, they cannot Biology will not replace psychology within our explana-
explain it completely. tory systems. Rather we will slowly clarify, through
To say this in another way, psychology frames questions progress in neuroscience, how the brain implements psy-
about how biological processes implement psychological chological functions. That iterative process will deepen
functions. Moreover, as we understand the brain pro- our understanding of both biological and psychological
cesses, we need to “back-translate” the biology into an un- processes.
derstanding—in psychological terms—of the key psycho-
Received July 4, 2007; revision received Jan. 3, 2008; accepted Feb.
pathological constructs under investigation (e.g., sad
17, 2008 (doi: 10.1176/appi.ajp.2008.07071061). From the Virginia
mood, drug craving, hallucinations, and compulsions). Institute of Psychiatric and Behavioral Genetics and Departments of
Merely showing a strong odds ratio between a particular Psychiatry and Human Genetics, Medical College of Virginia/Virginia
Commonwealth University. Address correspondence and reprint re-
genetic or molecular variant and illness is not enough. As
quests to Dr. Kendler, Virginia Institute of Psychiatric and Behavioral
Hatfield writes, “Researchers seek to understand the mi- Genetics, Virginia Commonwealth University Medical School, Box
croactivities of neurons by asking how they contribute to 980126, 800 East Leigh St., Rm. 1-123, Richmond, VA 23298-0126;
kendler@vcu.edu (e-mail).
one or another more global brain function, psychologi-
Dr. Kendler reports no competing interests.
cally described” (70, p. 257). Supported in part by NIH grants MH-068643, AA-011408, DA-
Thus, eschewing hard reduction or hard emergence, we 011287, and MH-41953. The author thanks Peter Zachar, Ph.D., and
John Campbell, Ph.D., for helpful comments on earlier versions of
have the most to hope from a perspective in which biolog-
this manuscript.
ical explanations will sit within and implement “wetware”
functions that are articulated in the language of psychol-
ogy. This will not be a one-step procedure, as psycholo- References
gists will not always “get it right.” An iterative relationship
1. Kendler KS: Toward a philosophical structure for psychiatry.
between psychology and biology—where initial psycho- Am J Psychiatry 2005; 162:433–440
logical constructs are better defined and subdivided by 2. Schaffner KF: Psychiatry and molecular biology: reductionistic
initial biological findings, which in turn help clarify the bi- approaches to schizophrenia, in Philosophical Perspectives on

700 ajp.psychiatryonline.org Am J Psychiatry 165:6, June 2008


KENNETH S. KENDLER

Psychiatric Diagnostic Classification. Edited by Sadler JZ, Wig- 22. Maes HH, Woodard CE, Murrelle L, Meyer JM, Silberg JL, Hewitt
gins OP Jr, Schwartz MA. Baltimore, Johns Hopkins University JK, Rutter M, Simonoff E, Pickles A, Carbonneau R, Neale MC,
Press, 1994, pp 279–294 Eaves LJ: Tobacco, alcohol, and drug use in eight- to sixteen-
3. Engel GL: The need for a new medical model: a challenge for year-old twins: the Virginia Twin Study of Adolescent Behav-
biomedicine. Science 1977; 196:129–136 ioral Development. J Stud Alcohol 1999; 60:293–305
4. Meyer A: Psychobiology: A Science of Man. Springfield, Ill, 23. Kendler KS, Schmitt JE, Aggen SH, Prescott CA: Genetic and en-
Charles C Thomas, 1957 vironmental influences on alcohol, caffeine, cannabis, and nic-
5. Bechtel W: Mental Mechanisms: Philosophical Perspectives on otine use across the life span. Arch Gen Psychiatry 2007 (in
Cognitive Neuroscience. Hillsdale, NJ, Lawrence Erlbaum Asso- press)
ciates, 2007 24. Kendler KS, Liu X-Q, Gardner CO, McCullough ME, Larson D,
6. Craver CF: Explaining the Brain. Oxford, UK, Clarendon Press, Prescott CA: Dimensions of religiosity and their relationship to
2007 lifetime psychiatric and substance use disorders. Am J Psychia-
7. Bechtel W, Richardson RC: Discovering Complexity: Decompo- try 2003; 160:496–503
sition and Localization as Strategies in Scientific Research. Prin- 25. World Drink Trends 2002: International Beverage Consump-
ceton, NJ, Princeton University Press, 1993 tion and Production Trends. Henley-on-Thames, Oxfordshire,
8. Darden L: Strategies for discovering mechanisms: construction, Produktschap voor Gedistilleerde Dranken, 2002
evaluation, revision, in Reasoning in Biological Discoveries: Es- 26. Room R, Makela K: Typologies of the cultural position of drink-
says on Mechanisms, Interfield Relations, and Anomaly Resolu- ing. J Stud Alcohol 2000; 61:475–483
tion. Edited by Darden L. New York, Cambridge University 27. Wilsnack RW, Vogeltanz ND, Wilsnack SC, Harris TR, Ahlstrom S,
Press, 2006, pp 271–312 Bondy S, Csemy L, Ferrence R, Ferris J, Fleming J, Graham K,
9. Wimsatt WC: Aggregativity: reductive heuristics for finding Greenfield T, Guyon L, Haavio-Mannila E, Kellner F, Knibbe R,
emergence. Philos Sci 1997; 64:S372–S384 Kubicka L, Loukomskaia M, Mustonen H, Nadeau L, Narusk A,
10. Boogerd FC, Bruggeman FJ, Richardson RC, Stephan A, Wester- Neve R, Rahav G, Spak F, Teichman M, Trocki K, Webster I,
hoff HV: Emergence and its place in nature: a case study of bio- Weiss S: Gender differences in alcohol consumption and ad-
chemical networks. Synthese 2005; 145:131–164 verse drinking consequences: cross-cultural patterns. Addic-
11. Molina JC, Spear NE, Spear LP, Mennella JA, Lewis MJ: The inter- tion 2000; 95:251–265
national society for developmental psychobiology 39th annual 28. Zemore SE: Acculturation and alcohol among Latino adults in
meeting symposium: alcohol and development: beyond fetal the United States: a comprehensive review. Alcohol Clin Exp
alcohol syndrome. Dev Psychobiol 2007; 49:227–242 Res 2007; 31:1968–1990
12. Dick DM, Bierut LJ: The genetics of alcohol dependence. Curr
29. Farrell S, Manning WG, Finch MD: Alcohol dependence and the
Psychiatry Rep 2006; 8:151–157
price of alcoholic beverages. J Health Econ 2003; 22:117–147
13. Shen YC, Fan JH, Edenberg HJ, Li TK, Cui YH, Wang YF, Tian CH,
30. Mohler-Kuo M, Rehm J, Heeb JL, Gmel G: Decreased taxation,
Zhou CF, Zhou RL, Wang J, Zhao ZL, Xia GY: Polymorphism of
spirits consumption, and alcohol-related problems in Switzer-
ADH and ALDH genes among four ethnic groups in China and
land. J Stud Alcohol 2004; 65:266–273
effects upon the risk for alcoholism. Alcohol Clin Exp Res 1997;
31. Chen CC, Lu RB, Chen YC, Wang MF, Chang YC, Li TK, Yin SJ: In-
21:1272–1277
teraction between the functional polymorphisms of the alco-
14. Edenberg HJ, Dick DM, Xuei X, Tian H, Almasy L, Bauer LO,
hol- metabolism genes in protection against alcoholism. Am J
Crowe RR, Goate A, Hesselbrock V, Jones K, Kwon J, Li TK, Nurn-
Hum Genet 1999; 65:795–807
berger JI, Jr, O’Connor SJ, Reich T, Rice J, Schuckit MA, Porjesz B,
32. Koopmans JR, Slutske WS, van Baal GC, Boomsma DI: The influ-
Foroud T, Begleiter H: Variations in GABRA2, encoding the al-
ence of religion on alcohol use initiation: evidence for geno-
pha 2 subunit of the GABA(A) receptor, are associated with al-
type x environment interaction. Behav Genet 1999; 29:445–
cohol dependence and with brain oscillations. Am J Hum
453
Genet 2004; 74:705–714
15. Kendler KS, Myers J, Prescott CA: Specificity of genetic and en- 33. Heath AC, Jardine R, Martin NG: Interactive effects of genotype
vironmental risk factors for symptoms of cannabis, cocaine, al- and social environment on alcohol consumption in female
cohol, caffeine, and nicotine dependence. Arch Gen Psychiatry twins. J Stud Alcohol 1989; 50:38–48
2007; 64:1313–1320 34. Dick DM, Agrawal A, Schuckit MA, Bierut L, Hinrichs A, Fox L,
16. Slutske WS, Heath AC, Dinwiddie SH, Madden PA, Bucholz KK, Mullaney J, Cloninger CR, Hesselbrock V, Nurnberger JI Jr, Al-
Dunne MP, Statham DJ, Martin NG: Common genetic risk fac- masy L, Foroud T, Porjesz B, Edenberg H, Begleiter H: Marital
tors for conduct disorder and alcohol dependence. J Abnorm status, alcohol dependence, and GABRA2: evidence for gene-
Psychol 1998; 107:363–374 environment correlation and interaction. J Stud Alcohol 2006;
17. Kendler KS, Prescott CA, Myers J, Neale MC: The structure of ge- 67:185–194
netic and environmental risk factors for common psychiatric 35. Dick DM, Rose RJ, Viken RJ, Kaprio J, Koskenvuo M: Exploring
and substance use disorders in men and women. Arch Gen gene-environment interactions: socioregional moderation of
Psychiatry 2003; 60:929–937 alcohol use. J Abnorm Psychol 2001; 110:625–632
18. Sher KJ, Grekin ER, Williams NA: The development of alcohol 36. Rose RJ, Dick DM, Viken And RJ, Kaprio J: Gene-environment in-
use disorders. Annu Rev Clin Psychol 2005; 1:493–523 teraction in patterns of adolescent drinking: regional residency
19. Szlemko WJ, Wood JW, Thurman PJ: Native Americans and alco- moderates longitudinal influences on alcohol use. Alcohol Clin
hol: past, present, and future. J Gen Psychol 2006; 133:435– Exp Res 2001; 25:637–643
451 37. Heath AC, Madden PA, Bucholz KK, Dinwiddie SH, Slutske WS,
20. Goldman MS: Expectancy and risk for alcoholism: the unfortu- Bierut LJ, Rohrbaugh JW, Statham DJ, Dunne MP, Whitfield JB,
nate exploitation of a fundamental characteristic of neurobe- Martin NG: Genetic differences in alcohol sensitivity and the in-
havioral adaptation. Alcohol Clin Exp Res 2002; 26:737–746 heritance of alcoholism risk. Psychol Med 1999; 29:1069–1081
21. Goldman MS, Del Boca FK, Darkes J: Alcohol expectancy the- 38. Thomasson HR, Li TK: How alcohol and aldehyde dehydroge-
ory: the application of cognitive neuroscience, in Psychological nase genes modify alcohol drinking, alcohol flushing, and the
Theories of Drinking and Alcoholism. Edited by Leonard KE, risk for alcoholism. Alcohol Health Res World 1993; 17:167–
Blane HT. New York, Guilford, 1999, pp 203–246 172

Am J Psychiatry 165:6, June 2008 ajp.psychiatryonline.org 701


EXPLANATORY MODELS FOR PSYCHIATRIC ILLNESS

39. Thomasson HR, Edenberg HJ, Crabb DW, Mai XL, Jerome RE, Li 54. Essex MJ, Kraemer HC, Armstrong JM, Boyce WT, Goldsmith HH,
TK, Wang SP, Lin YT, Lu RB, Yin SJ: Alcohol and aldehyde dehy- Klein MH, Woodward H, Kupfer DJ: Exploring risk factors for the
drogenase genotypes and alcoholism in Chinese men. Am J emergence of children’s mental health problems. Arch Gen
Hum Genet 1991; 48:677–681 Psychiatry 2006; 63:1246–1256
40. Schuckit MA, Smith TL: An 8-year follow-up of 450 sons of alco- 55. Tienari P, Wynne LC, Sorri A, Lahti I, Laksy K, Moring J, Naarala
holic and control subjects. Arch Gen Psychiatry 1996; 53:202– M, Nieminen P, Wahlberg KE: Genotype-environment interac-
210 tion in schizophrenia-spectrum disorder: long-term follow-up
41. Koob GF, Le Moal M: Alcohol, in Neurobiology of Addiction. Ed- study of Finnish adoptees. Br J Psychiatry 2004; 184:216–222
ited by Koob GF, Le Moal M. London, UK, Academic Press, 56. Corvin A, McGhee KA, Murphy K, Donohoe G, Nangle JM,
2006, pp 173–242 Schwaiger S, Kenny N, Clarke S, Meagher D, Quinn J, Scully P,
42. Gordon RA, Lahey BB, Kawai E, Loeber R, Stouthamer-Loeber Baldwin P, Browne D, Walsh C, Waddington JL, Morris DW, Gill
M, Farrington DP: Antisocial behavior and youth gang mem- M: Evidence for association and epistasis at the DAOA/G30 and
bership: selection and socialization. Criminology 2004; 42:55– D-amino acid oxidase loci in an Irish schizophrenia sample.
87 Am J Med Genet B Neuropsychiatr Genet 2007; 144:949–953
43. Dishion TJ, Patterson GR, Griesler PC: Peers adaption in the de- 57. Levine S: Developmental determinants of sensitivity and resis-
velopment of antisocial behavior: a confluence model, in Ag- tance to stress. Psychoneuroendocrinology 2005; 30:939–946
gressive Behavior: Current Perspectives. Edited by Huesmann
58. Kendler KS, Neale MC, Kessler RC, Heath AC, Eaves LJ: A longi-
LR. New York, Plenum, 1994, pp 61–95
tudinal twin study of personality and major depression in
44. Kendler KS, Jacobson KC, Gardner CO, Gillespie NA, Aggen SH,
women. Arch Gen Psychiatry 1993; 50:853–862
Prescott CA: Creating a social world: a developmental study of
59. Kendler KS, Gardner CO, Prescott CA: Personality and the expe-
peer deviance. Arch Gen Psychiatry 2007; 64:958–965
rience of environmental adversity. Psychol Med 2003; 33:
45. Gillespie NA, Kendler KS, Prescott CA, Aggen SH, Gardner CO Jr,
1193–1202
Jacobson K, Neale MC: Longitudinal modeling of genetic and
environmental influences on self-reported availability of psy- 60. Pine DS: Developmental psychobiology and response to
choactive substances: alcohol, cigarettes, marijuana, cocaine, threats: relevance to trauma in children and adolescents. Biol
and stimulants. Psychol Med 2007; 37:947–959 Psychiatry 2003; 53:796–808
46. Harburg E, Davis DR, Caplan R: Parent and offspring alcohol 61. Sanderson WC, Rapee RM, Barlow DH: The influence of an illu-
use: imitative and aversive transmission. J Stud Alcohol 1982; sion of control on panic attacks induced via inhalation of 5.5%
43:497–516 carbon dioxide-enriched air. Arch Gen Psychiatry 1989; 46:
47. Harburg E, DiFranceisco W, Webster DW, Gleiberman L, Schork 157–162
A: Familial transmission of alcohol use, II: imitation of and 62. Bechtel W: Discovering Cell Mechanisms: The Creation of Mod-
aversion to parent drinking (1960) by adult offspring (1977): ern Cell Biology. New York, Cambridge University Press, 2005
Tecumseh, Mich. J Stud Alcohol 1990; 51:245–256 63. Wimsatt WC: Emergence as non-aggregativity and the biases of
48. Kendler KS, Kuhn JW, Prescott CA: Childhood sexual abuse, reductionisms. Foundations of Science 2000; 5:269–297
stressful life events, and risk for major depression in women. 64. Wimsatt WC: The ontology of complex systems: levels of orga-
Psychol Med 2004; 34:1475–1482 nization, perspectives, and causal thickets, in Biology and Soci-
49. Cadoret RJ, Yates WR, Troughton E, Woodworth G, Stewart MA: ety: Reflections on Methodology. Edited by Matthen M, Ware
Genetic-environmental interaction in the genesis of aggressiv- RX. Can J Philosophy 1994; 20(suppl):207–274
ity and conduct disorders. Arch Gen Psychiatry 1995; 52:916– 65. Giere RN: Scientific Perspectivism. Chicago, University of Chi-
924 cago Press, 2006
50. Kendler KS, Kessler RC, Walters EE, MacLean C, Neale MC,
66. Marr D: The philosophy and the approach, in Vision: A Compu-
Heath AC, Eaves LJ: Stressful life events, genetic liability, and
tational Investigation Into the Human Representation and Pro-
onset of an episode of major depression in women. Am J Psy-
cessing of Visual Information. San Francisco, WH Freeman,
chiatry 1995; 152:833–842
1982, pp 3–38
51. Caspi A, Sugden K, Moffitt TE, Taylor A, Craig IW, Harrington H,
67. Pinker S: How the Mind Works. New York, WW Norton, 1997
McClay J, Mill J, Martin J, Braithwaite A, Poulton R: Influence of
life stress on depression: moderation by a polymorphism in 68. Duchaine B, Cosmides L, Tooby J: Evolutionary psychology and
the 5-HTT gene. Science 2003; 301:386–389 the brain. Curr Opin Neurobiol 2001; 11:225–230
52. Kendler KS, Kuhn J, Prescott CA: The interrelationship of neu- 69. Gold I, Stoljar D: A neuron doctrine in the philosophy of neuro-
roticism, sex, and stressful life events in the prediction of epi- science. Behav Brain Sci 1999; 22:809–869
sodes of major depression. Am J Psychiatry 2004; 161:631–636 70. Hatfield G: Mental Functions as constraints on neurophysiol-
53. Blatt SJ, Zuroff D: Interpersonal relatedness and self-definition: ogy: biology and psychology of vision, in Where Biology Meets
two prototypes for depression. Clin Psychol Rev 1969; 12:527– Psychology. Edited by Hardcastle VG. Cambridge, Mass, MIT
562 Press, 1999, pp 251–272

702 ajp.psychiatryonline.org Am J Psychiatry 165:6, June 2008

You might also like