You are on page 1of 23

Volume 55 Number 4 October 2012

ARTICLE

The Museum and Its Relationships as a Loosely Coupled System


JAY ROUNDS

Abstract Currently dominant ideas about the social accountability of museums demand that muse-
ums produce ‘‘intended outcomes’’: positive changes to visitors. Proponents commonly depict this
process as a ‘‘logic model,’’ a tightly controlled sequence of events that moves from goal to intended
outcome. A tightly coupled system obliges all elements to work toward a common goal. But studies in
a variety of fields have shown that tightly coupled systems are achievable only under specific envi-
ronmental conditions, which are not met within the network of relationships in which museums work.
Instead, this article views the museum and its relationships as a loosely coupled system. Each ele-
ment has its own purposes, and strives to maintain its own autonomy. Interests overlap, but are not
identical. In the loosely coupled system, encounters generate a wide and unpredictable range of
events. This approach offers advantages for the long-term sustainability of museums.

Movies have superheroes. Museums have logic This seems reasonable, in a general way.
models. Moviegoers enjoy watching heroes We all set goals in our everyday lives, and much
whose extraordinary powers bend the world to of the time we achieve them—especially when
their will and who make things come out right. those goals are modest, and the means are under
In museums, logic models serve much the same our direct control. Our routine success in
function. Logic models are used by museum achieving small goals encourages us to assume
planners who have specific intentions in mind, that the same approach can be scaled up to big
and these planners, too, want to make things things of much greater complexity. We expect
come out right. But movie fans—once they to be able to accomplish whatever needs to be
depart the Cineplex—don’t expect to find actual done, if we think through the problem ratio-
superheroes at work in the world. In the case of nally, design our technology properly, and
logic models, expectations about outcomes are implement it rigorously. There is now an exten-
more ambiguous. sive literature telling museums how to do just
Logic models and related beliefs in the that—and warning that museums that fail to do
utility of rational action are deeply embedded so will be held accountable.
within current thinking about museum account- But if success in achieving goals is an every-
ability. These commonly held ideas make it day experience, so too is failure. Every new
clear that museums worthy of public support human learns quickly that desires are sometimes
will plan their activities rationally; adopt impor- not satisfied, and that we are dependent on
tant goals; specify in advance what outcomes other people who have their own desires. Life
will constitute achievement of those goals; and teaches us that there are some things we can’t
document actual achievement of the intended do, and that most of what we can do involves
outcomes. negotiation and compromise. Given the right

Jay Rounds (rounds@umsl.edu), University of Missouri-St. Louis.

413
CURATOR THE MUSEUM JOURNAL

circumstances, we can accomplish a lot; but of accountability. Weil told us that museums
there are limits. The ‘‘Rationalist Model’’ tells ‘‘are, or at least ought to be, rationally organized
museums how to go about achieving their goals, institutions directed toward articulable pur-
but is largely silent on the question of potential poses—institutions that, at their most excellent,
limits on the ability of museums to control the both can and do accomplish those purposes with
flow of events. Since the limits are real, we need maximum effect and with minimum waste’’
to take them as seriously as we take our inten- (2002, 3).
tions and abilities. Various other writers and agencies have
Museums do their work in the midst of an promoted programs or methodologies to advance
extremely complex network of relationships and this vision. These methodologies include out-
interdependencies. The Rationalist Model calls come-based evaluation, holistic intentionality,
upon museums to impose their own intentions theories of change, and logic models. Each has
on all elements of that network, producing a its own character, virtues, and emphases. My
tightly coupled sequence of controlled events concern here is with what they have in com-
leading to predicted, desired outcomes. If mon. To emphasize that commonality, and
museum goals are of significant scope, achiev- because these ideas have become clustered
ing control over the flow of events requires together in practice, I have joined them under
heroic cognitive abilities, implausible technical the label ‘‘The Rationalist Model.’’
mastery, and a willingness to prioritize the The Rationalist Model depicts a system in
museum’s intentions despite the possibility of which things happen because the museum
conflict with everyone else involved. intended that they should happen and took the
This article argues that the complexity of proper actions to make them happen. A goal is
modern multicultural society, and the changing formulated, and an exhibition is designed to
expectations of the new century, should encour- achieve that goal. Visitors experience the exhi-
age museums to adopt more expansive ways of bition, and they change in the ways intended.
understanding and explaining the value they Those changes constitute the ‘‘outcomes’’ pre-
provide to society and to their individual users. dicted by the museum, and so constitute
Museums need to take intentionality seriously, achievement of the goal. The accountability of
as the Rationalist Model says, but they also need the museum is measured by the reliability with
to go beyond that model’s narrow focus on the which the museum’s actions consistently pro-
intentions of the museum in order to address duce the intended outcomes.
the intentionality of everyone in the system. As a way of thinking about what museums
This article will propose an ‘‘Emergence Model’’ do, this model has the virtues of simplicity, con-
that shifts our perspective to a more holistic pic- sistency, and plausibility. However, it is an extre-
ture of the museum and its relationships. mely narrow perspective. We can see what has
been left out by using the analytical distinction
THE RATIONALIST MODEL OF between tightly and loosely coupled systems.
ACCOUNTABILITY
COUPLING, TIGHT AND LOOSE
The late Stephen Weil gave us an admira-
bly clear and succinct précis of the fundamental The analytical distinction between ‘‘tight’’
assumptions that dominate current discussions and ‘‘loose’’ coupling was introduced by the

414 Article: The Museum and Its Relationships as a Loosely Coupled System
Volume 55 Number 4 October 2012

biologist Robert Glassman in 1973 to describe ing each of its elements, would be driven by a
types of linkages that he observed in living sys- single, shared goal.
tems at all levels. The concept was quickly Loose coupling describes a relationship or
imported into organization theory, and spread system in which the elements interact, but are
rapidly after publication of Karl Weick’s highly only weakly bonded together. This does not
influential article ‘‘Educational Organizations mean that they have no relationship at all; if
as Loosely Coupled Systems’’ (1976).1 Since that were the case, there would be nothing to
then it has become incorporated into a wide analyze, and no point in characterizing them as
variety of disciplines. elements in a system. But compared with tightly
Tight coupling describes a relationship or coupled systems, the variables that loosely bind
system in which the elements are strongly the elements are weak relative to other influ-
bonded together and highly interdependent. ences on their behavior. Where tightly coupled
Changes in a single variable, or in a group of human systems may be built around an identity
related variables, will cause the same or related of interests (that is, a common purpose), loosely
changes in all of the elements of the sys- coupled systems are built around interests that
tem—making at least some aspects of the overlap but are not necessarily identical. Each
behavior of the system highly predictable. of the autonomous elements has its own pur-
The ‘‘tightness’’ of the coupling is evident in the poses, but those separate purposes can all be
degree to which the shared variables exercise advanced by some sort of limited interaction or
stronger influence over the system than do other exchange. When they do interact, each element
factors that influence only individual elements ‘‘preserves its own identity and some evidence
of the system (Glassman 1973). When fully of its physical or logical separateness’’ (Weick
coupled, the elements are seen primarily as parts 1976, 3).
of a whole, working together in common cause. Because the bonds among elements of a
Flick the switch, and the light comes on. The loosely coupled system are limited in specific
coupling between the switch and the light in ways, failure of any one element is less likely to
this simple system is stronger than other influ- impact the other elements. Software designers,
ences—most of the time. But this simple system for instance, exploit this feature of loosely cou-
also illustrates a key vulnerability of tightly cou- pled systems. The different programs in a suite
pled systems. Failure of any one element in the have different purposes, but need to exchange
system can cripple the whole. If a vandal data. Loosely coupled designs facilitate that
smashes the bulb, the switch is useless. exchange while protecting the autonomy of the
When we describe a human system as component programs, reducing the likelihood
tightly coupled, we are asserting that one vari- that a failure in one program will take the others
able—or a group of related variables acting in down with it.
concert—is sufficiently powerful to determine Glassman, and the analysts who followed
the actions of the system, regardless of what him, were drawing on a general principle of life:
other influences are in play. In the case consid- You cannot—and need not—relate to everyone
ered here, proponents of the Rationalist Model and everything in the same way and at the same
cast ‘‘intentionality’’ in that role. In a system level of intensity. Some aspects of life thrive on
that completely fulfilled the conditions of the tight coupling, while others thrive on loose cou-
model, the actions of the entire system, includ- pling. One is not intrinsically better or more

Jay Rounds 415


CURATOR THE MUSEUM JOURNAL

virtuous than the other. It depends upon the Neither the tightly coupled system of traf-
combination of purpose and circumstance. fic laws nor the loosely coupled system of vaca-
For instance, some functions of society tioning is perfect. But there can be little doubt
require a high degree of standardization of that each would be much worse if it were orga-
behavior, and in those cases a tightly coupled nized like the other. Society has a compelling
system will probably be advantageous. Traffic public interest in overriding the personal prefer-
law clearly requires standardization. Every time ences of its citizens regarding which side of the
we drive, we bet our lives on the prediction that road to drive on. It has no such interest in regu-
other drivers will be following the same set of lating vacation preferences. Thus, the preferred
rules that we are. To make the roads as safe as type of coupling is dependent on the task, on
possible, society makes an enormous effort to the environment within which the task is car-
achieve standardization in the way people drive. ried out, and on the interdependencies among
Laws are passed and promulgated. Driver edu- the elements of the system. Theorists in a vari-
cation is mandated. Licenses are required, and ety of disciplines have worked out specifics of
tests are given. Signs specify how the laws apply the situations in which one or the other form of
on the ground, and police enforce the law. coupling is most advantageous.
Every element of this system must be consistent
and tightly coupled with all the others. If you THE RATIONALIST MODEL AS A TIGHTLY
change the speed limit, every other part of the COUPLED SYSTEM
system must change in conformity.
Even with all that, people violate the rules Models, like maps, are abstractions from
with distressing frequency. Nonetheless, the reality, not representations of reality. They seek
system works well enough that people are will- to make some aspect of reality more under-
ing to drive, and most of the time they get to standable by leaving out everything that you
their destination safely. don’t need to know for your present purpose.
Contrast this program of standardization The aspiring gambler does not need to know
with activities that instead require that people be about every rock, lizard, and scrubby little tree
distributed across a range of alternative behav- between Los Angeles and Las Vegas. The best
iors. Taking a vacation is very much a recognized map for his purpose is one that eliminates
part of our culture, but it is not subject to stan- everything but the roadways that will lead him
dardization. We can’t have everyone wanting to most quickly to the gaming tables.
take exactly the same vacation at the same time. The Rationalist Model chooses to disre-
Instead of a tightly coupled bureaucracy, society gard everything about museums and their net-
leaves this function to a loosely coupled system works of relationships except those that show a
of venues, agents, advertisers, reporters, travel tightly coupled path from a goal to an outcome.
services, and friends with photos. Each of these This path is usually depicted as a ‘‘logic model,’’
elements has interests that overlap with those of visualized as a series of boxes connected by
the others, but none has the power to control the arrows:
others. People sort themselves out through this
system, matching opportunities to their personal
preferences, resources, and available time. It too
works well enough.

416 Article: The Museum and Its Relationships as a Loosely Coupled System
Volume 55 Number 4 October 2012

Step by step, the activities represented by The most explicit level of tight coupling in
each box lead to the initial conditions of the fol- the Rationalist Model is the one that leads from
lowing box. All are arrayed on a straight line, specified goals to predicted outcomes:
the shortest distance from the stated goal to the
intended outcome. Such a system, if it is exe-
cuted properly, should make the outcomes in
the final box highly predictable. If you know All elements must be tightly coupled to
what your goal is, and what success in achieving ensure consistency. Weil was uncompromising
it will look like, and if you know how to go about the purpose of the system as a whole: ‘‘[I]t
about doing it, and if you do it correctly, then is those outcomes that matter—not good will,
you will reliably get the desired result. not an accumulation of resources, not good pro-
This reflects Weil’s assertion (quoted cess, and not even highly acclaimed programs,
above) that museums ought to be ‘‘rationally but actual outcomes, impacts and results’’
organized.’’ Presumably no one (including (1999, 240).3
myself) wants to argue that museums should be At the next level, Weil attached specific
irrationally organized. However, we note that virtues to each methodological element:
Weil is not using the word in its everyday sense
of something like ‘‘to think and act wisely and
judiciously, rather than stupidly’’ (Sen 2002, 42).
Rather, he is drawing on a technical definition He wrote that the goals (or purposes) of
of rationality lifted from the discipline of eco- museums must be ‘‘external to themselves.’’ The
nomics and known as Rational Choice Theory.2 basis for this stipulation requires some explana-
Rational Choice Theory narrowly defines tion. In a purely formal sense, it comes along
the best way to achieve a given goal. As we will with Weil’s use of Rational Choice Theory
see, it requires us to believe things considerably (RCT) in developing his approach. RCT
less plausible than the simple proposition that describes a tightly coupled system for achieving a
we don’t want to be stupid. I have labeled the goal, but the goal itself is considered ‘‘exogenous’’
model under discussion here as ‘‘rationalist’’ to the system. In other words, the goal comes
rather than ‘‘rational’’ to emphasize that it refers from outside, and is treated as a given. Nothing
to the narrow technical concept rather than to in the methodology of RCT questions the valid-
common parlance. ity or significance of the goal itself (Sen 2002).
Weil expanded the passage quoted earlier But Weil also had in mind something more
to specify that rationally organized museums: specific to museums. In various writings he
‘‘have a clear sense of what purposes external to repeated a claim that museums have in the past
themselves they are seeking to accomplish’’; ignored their obligations to society, and have
‘‘command the means required to accomplish retreated inward, concentrating on their own
those purposes’’; ‘‘are demonstrably able to esoteric interests. As a result, they have pro-
accomplish the purposes they seek to accom- vided little useful benefit to the society that
plish’’; and ‘‘are able to accomplish those pur- funded their operations. Thus, when museums
poses in a maximally economic way’’ (2002, 7). organize their activities around goals that are
We can distinguish three different levels of solely for the good of the museum itself, they
tight coupling implied by these brief passages. violate the principle of accountability. Instead,

Jay Rounds 417


CURATOR THE MUSEUM JOURNAL

they should pursue goals that produce benefits Weil was concerned primarily with the social
‘‘external to themselves.’’ accountability of museums.
Weil compared the museum to a mouse- By the logic of the Rationalist Model, the
trap, observing that one needs a mousetrap only outcomes of the museum’s work must consti-
if one has mice. The value of the museum, in tute the benefits derived. But outcomes are
other words, cannot be something intrinsic. The defined as intended changes in visitors, and the
museum can never be ‘‘its own excuse for being’’ logic model shows that the process starts with
(Weil 2003, 27). Rather, its value comes only the goal or intention, which eventually leads to
from the importance of the external needs and the intended changes in visitors. This means
issues to which it attaches itself, and for which it that the goals or intentions that guide exhibi-
provides (or helps to provide) solutions. Other tion design cannot be those of the visitors, since
writers have described this as ‘‘relevance.’’ at the time the goals are formulated the
Given a relevant goal, the museum must museum has no way of knowing who the actual
then have the right technology (the ‘‘means’’) visitors will be, or what their goals will be on
that can be deployed to bring the goals to fru- the day they visit.
ition. But Weil emphasizes that it is not enough In any case, ‘‘relevance’’ is usually taken in
simply to have a way to get the job done. The this literature to refer to society, the public good,
chosen means must be an efficient way to do the public interest, or some other term referring
so—preferably, the most efficient. Society will to the collectivity. All of these terms are ambig-
not provide resources beyond what is needed to uous and problematic (Mansbridge 1998; Cal-
do the job ‘‘with minimal waste.’’ houn 1998), but ‘‘society’’ seems the most useful
Finally, the outcomes must meet the crite- for the present purpose. To be accountable, a
rion of effectiveness. That is, they must be valid museum must be accountable to someone or
realizations of the original goal, and must be something able to assess the museum’s perfor-
what the museum intended to make happen. mance and to make decisions—a criterion not
Thus, relevant goals must be tightly coupled to fulfilled by abstract concepts such as the public
efficient means, and are also tightly coupled to good or the public interest. While ‘‘society’’ is
effective outcomes. not a unitary, discrete entity, it at least includes
So much is explicit, both in Weil’s writings institutions potentially capable of acting to
and in those of other proponents of the Ration- enforce accountability.
alist Model. However, there is a great deal of Furthermore, ‘‘society’’ at least evokes a
ambiguity in this formulation. When Weil said position that is prominent in the literature of
that the goals that drive the system must be the Rationalist Model: an emphasis on the col-
external to the museum itself, he might have lective interests of the whole, in opposition to
meant only that the benefits of the museum’s those of the individual members of that whole.
activities must accrue to someone or something That position was argued with particular clarity
other than the museum and its staff. That could by Carol Stapp, who wrote: ‘‘When examined
be interpreted as referring to the visitors or closely, the governance and message of Ameri-
other users of the museum. There is no doubt can museums typically have promoted the ethos
that Weil (like everyone else) thought that visi- of individual entitlement rather than of com-
tors should benefit from their time in the munity responsibility’’ (1998, 232). She attrib-
museum, but in the writings I am citing here uted this ‘‘extraordinary level of individualism’’

418 Article: The Museum and Its Relationships as a Loosely Coupled System
Volume 55 Number 4 October 2012

to the Declaration of Independence, ‘‘which has intentions. Logic models show what the world
engendered a sense of personal entitlement in would look like, and what would happen, if the
Americans’ consciousness—the right to ‘life, world could in fact be subdued by rational
liberty and the pursuit of happiness’ that over- thought and action.
rides the collective good’’ (1998, 230). Now However, like everyone else, museums
museums must shift their focus to promoting (and those who oversee them) frequently
‘‘communal economic and cultural well-being’’ underestimate how much their work will be
(1998, 233). affected by events that can neither be antici-
pated nor controlled. Human efforts have
Therefore, museums, which have a history accomplished a great deal in this world, but the
of embodying an individualistic ethos despite limits of our ability are equally apparent, and
their declared intention of community service, have been a persistent theme in human litera-
are viewed as vehicles for reorienting the values ture. From our deep past, the voice of the vener-
of Americans—helping people convert from able preacher of the Old Testament warns us,
behaviors that result in a fragmented society to ‘‘The race is not to the swift, nor the battle to
actions that contribute to a cooperative social the strong, neither bread to the wise, nor yet
order (Stapp 1998, 231). riches to men of understanding, nor yet favor to
men of skill; but time and chance happeneth to
We can now see another level of tight cou- them all’’ (Ecclesiastes ix:11).
pling implied by the Rationalist Model: The poetic realism of the ancient preacher is
echoed by the language of modern scholarship:
‘‘[I]ndividuals find themselves in a more com-
plex, less stable, and less understood world than
The Rationalist Model defines the museum that described by standard theories of organiza-
as the agent of society, a tool used by the collec- tional choice [that is, rationalist approaches];
tive to pursue some aspect of the public good. they are placed in a world over which they often
Since the model defines outcomes as ‘‘positive, have only modest control’’ (March and Olsen
intended changes in program participants’’ 1979, 21). A social theorist says that: ‘‘It is not
(museum visitors), the museum must also be just that more or less continuous and profound
tightly coupled to the individuals who use its processes of change occur; rather, change does
offerings—tightly enough, at least, to make the not consistently conform either to human expec-
intended changes possible. The Rationalist tation or to human control. The anticipation that
Model sees the museum as a tool used by society the social and natural environments would
to change individuals in ways that will make increasingly be subject to rational ordering has
them better members of the collective. not proved to be valid’’ (Giddens 1991, 28). A
The logic models of the Rationalist meth- psychologist concludes that the working of the
odology depict a world that is tidy and under- human mind ‘‘makes us see the world as more
standable. Most important, the Rationalist tidy, simple, predictable, and coherent than it
Model declares that the world can be controlled really is. The illusion that one has understood
by the power of the rational mind, and by the the past feeds the further illusion that one can
technology it creates. The whole point, after all, predict and control the future’’ (Kahneman 2011,
is to make events coincide with the museum’s 205). And a museologist finds that although

Jay Rounds 419


CURATOR THE MUSEUM JOURNAL

visitor experiences are influenced by ‘‘events the museums (most of the time) to use the offerings
museum can design for and count on,’’ they are of the museum in service of something that is
also influenced by ‘‘random events beyond the personally meaningful and important. Whatever
control of the museum’’ (Falk 2009, 102). it is that the user is doing, she would be doing it
It is useful to remind ourselves of some sali- anyway; but she is at the museum today because
ent features of the underlying reality within she thinks that the museum will be a good place
which museums do their work. Since Rational- to do it. The museum owes it to her to ensure
ist logic models focus on controlling the flow of that it is.
a narrow sequence of events, they should be
contrasted to models that focus on how muse- AN EMERGENCE MODEL OF THE
ums can do useful work within a larger flow of MUSEUM AS A LOOSELY COUPLED
events that is only partially amenable to the SYSTEM
museum’s control. The educational theorist
John Stephens captured the difference neatly in Models are abstractions simplified from
a meditation on schools: the complexity of the real world, designed to
make some aspect of reality more visible and
[W]e would be making a great mistake in
understandable. They focus our attention on
regarding the management of schools as similar
what their creators have deemed significant,
to the process of constructing a building or
and so encourage us to ignore what they have
operating a factory. In these latter processes
not. What is shown is defined as ‘‘signal,’’ and
deliberate decisions play a crucial part, and the
what is not shown is defined as ‘‘noise.’’
enterprise advances or stands still in proportion
The Rationalist Model depicts a single
to the amount of deliberate effort exerted. If we
path of action, proceeding from goal to out-
must use a metaphor or model in seeking to
come. Proponents of the model are of course
understand the process of schooling, we should
aware that there is a great deal more going on;
look to agriculture rather than to the factory. In
but the purpose of the model is not to depict the
agriculture we do not start from scratch, and we
complexity of the underlying reality. Rather, it
do not direct our efforts to inert and passive
is designed to show a pathway that purports to
materials. We start, on the contrary, with a
cut through that complexity, leading most
complex and ancient process, and we organize
directly to the museum’s preferred outcomes.
our efforts around what seeds, plants, and
The ‘‘Emergence Model’’ depicted on page
insects are likely to do anyway (Stephens 1967,
421 restores attention to more complex aspects
9-11; quoted in Weick 1976, 2).
of reality. Where the Rationalist Model is
The Rationalist Model echoes Stephens’s designed to show how to control the flow of
metaphor of the factory, drawing in raw mate- events, the Emergence Model is designed to
rial so that it can be processed into something show how people and organizations work within
more useful—in this case, a product better a flow of events that is only partially amenable to
suited (in Stapp’s terms) to the ‘‘communal eco- their control. In contrast to the tightly coupled,
nomic and cultural well-being.’’ I will propose deterministic thrust of Rationalism, the Emer-
an alternative—the ‘‘Emergence Model’’—that gence Model depicts a loosely coupled system
resonates with Stephens’s metaphor of the that accommodates a multiplicity of agents,
organic farmer. It assumes that people come to intentions, influences, and circumstances.4

420 Article: The Museum and Its Relationships as a Loosely Coupled System
Volume 55 Number 4 October 2012

gent properties cannot be predicted directly


from the known characteristics of the elements
that intersect to generate them.
In any real life event, there will be some
incalculable number of streams that converge.
For clarity, here, I have lumped all the possible
streams into five categories: 1) the museum, 2)
the focal visitor (the one we’re focusing on at
the moment, for analysis), 3) society; 4) other
people, and 5) physical and cultural factors.5
Each of the streams flowing into the encounter
is depicted as a process unfolding in time. Each
is in a more or less constant state of change.
Had the visitor intersected with this museum a
day earlier, she would have found a somewhat
different museum—just as the visitor herself
was different yesterday from the way she is
today. The differences might be quite small, or
The diagram pictures several ‘‘streams,’’ something quite significant may have happened
flowing more or less independently of one to one or both. Depending on which day she
another. These streams happen to converge at the visited, she will be surrounded by different peo-
moment labeled ‘‘the museum encounter,’’ when ple in the exhibition, will have read different
‘‘each visitor’s individual, subjective life experience news in the morning paper or on her smart
encounters that of the exhibition’s makers’’ phone in the train, will have come through dif-
(Hennes 2010, 26). The word ‘‘encounter’’ is used ferent weather and traffic conditions to reach
to capture some important qualities of this the museum, will be in a different mood, will
moment, for ‘‘it is a word redolent with the have different things on her mind, and so on.
unexpected, the unpredictable, the unplanned’’ The precise timing of the encounter is a signifi-
(Hennes 2010, 25). cant determinant of what happens. What sticks
Where the Rationalist Model depicts together during the encounter can be drawn
events as driven by the intentionality of the only from what exists in the current states of
museum, the Emergence Model depicts events each of the interacting streams.
as driven by simultaneity—by the momentary Some factors in the stream will exercise real
convergence of different lives and contexts. influence on what happens—and some more so
Where the Rationalist Model tracks only a sin- than others. Some streams might have exercised
gle intention—that of the museum—the Emer- influence, but didn’t—though if circumstances
gence Model depicts multiple actors, each had been slightly different, they could have. As
bringing a different stream of intentions into James G. March has shown, we tend to assume
the encounter. What happens will be an emer- that what did happen had to happen—that
gent property of the intersection of all of those ‘‘realized events are seen as necessary conse-
intentions, and the circumstances in which that quences of antecedent historical conditions.’’
intersection takes place. By definition, emer- But, he argued, it is important to also consider a

Jay Rounds 421


CURATOR THE MUSEUM JOURNAL

second perspective, in which ‘‘realized events individual humans, organizations grow and
are seen as draws from a distribution of possible change over time, integrating new experiences,
events’’ (1999, 142). The analogy is to ‘‘draw- information, and know-how into their struc-
ing’’ one card from a full deck. The probability tures and operations. Within the organization,
of drawing any other card was the same, though people come and go, new technologies some-
in fact you drew the Ace of Spades. Even if that times displace the old, new leadership sometimes
was your actual goal, you did not learn anything demands new directions for the organization’s
from this success that would help you draw the efforts. Markets change, resources are sometimes
same card the next time you try. Repeated tries abundant and sometimes scarce, ideas about
would show you instead that the result of any proper management practice shift, and a host
given try is only loosely coupled to your original of other considerations impinge on what the
goal, or to your past experiences. Add to that organization does. As museums mature, and
the possibility that the deck from which you their situations change, their goals often change
make your draw changes in composition ran- as well.
domly between each draw, and you have some- Still, museums do adopt formal intentions,
thing akin to the world depicted in the create things such as logic models, and take
Emergence Model. In such a world, it is dan- actions to produce intended outcomes. The
gerous to stake the accountability of museums Emergence Model does not deny this obvious
on their ability to beat the workings of time and reality. Rather, the stream of intentionality
chance. depicted by the Rationalist Model is subsumed
The following sections briefly review some within the museum stream of the Emergence
of the ways each stream changes as it flows Model, along with other salient features of the
along, thus contributing to the unique particu- museum. The logic model is present, but it is
larity of every museum encounter. not assumed to be the only thing about the
museum that affects the visitor’s experience.
The museum For instance, the exhibition designed to
carry the museum’s intention may differ from
The Rationalist Model depicts the museum day to day in what is actually available for the
as the carrier of an intention, and of the visitor to experience. Interactives have broken
resources needed to fulfill that intention. To the down. Certain objects have been removed tem-
degree that it deals with visitors at all, the model porarily for conservation. Yesterday the new
sees the museum as a relatively fixed place manager of visitor services held a training ses-
through which visitors flow—as if the museum sion for floor staff, who today are unusually
were a train station, where trains (the visitors) attentive. In one gallery a television news crew
come and go, stopping long enough to take on is interviewing the museum director, who is
some baggage before proceeding to their various hotly denying rumors that the painting behind
destinations. him may be Nazi loot. Changes of that sort may
In the alternative model presented here, be less frequent than those of the more volatile
the museum is seen not as a fixed point, but as streams, but when they do happen they change
one of the streams that flow through the what the museum offers to the visitor.
encounter. The Emergence Model depicts the Beyond those sorts of changes, each
museum as a process unfolding in time. Like museum encounter is unique because the visitor

422 Article: The Museum and Its Relationships as a Loosely Coupled System
Volume 55 Number 4 October 2012

participates in constructing the experience. mental models of the world. We meet new peo-
William James wrote a century ago that: ‘‘My ple, read some more news, discover new
experience is what I agree to attend to’’ (quoted changes in the world around us, and get a day
in Csikszentmihalyi and Rochberg-Halton older. From day to day our mood may change,
1981, 5). Visitors typically agree to look at only our mental focus and alertness will vary, and we
20 to 40 percent of what is available in a given will have different things on our minds.
exhibition (Serrell 1998), and they appear to do Since these factors are constantly evolving,
so strategically, to maximize the personal value the character of the museum experience will
of the visit (Rounds 2004b). In this sense a depend not only on who comes to visit, but also
dozen visitors in a gallery at the same time may on when that specific person visits.
be experiencing a dozen different exhibitions. If
achievement of the museum’s intended out- Other visitors
comes is dependent upon each visitor having
the same experience, then success will be rare. This stream comprises all of the other peo-
ple present in the exhibition. Any one of them
The ‘‘focal visitor’’ could have been picked as the focal visitor, and
we might switch our attention to focus on each
It is necessary to focus on individual visi- person in turn. But while we are focusing on
tors, rather than on statistical aggregations, to some other visitor, the people of this stream are
understand the implications of the Emergence of interest primarily for the ways in which they
Model for visitor behavior. The Emergence might affect the experience of the focal visitor.
Model depicts one stream as the ‘‘focal visitor,’’ The eminent organizational theorist James G.
the one we’re focusing on at this particular March described decision processes in terms
moment. It is only the researcher’s temporary that are equally applicable to museum encoun-
attention that distinguishes the focal visitor ters:
from any other visitor.
Each visitor to a museum has a somewhat Any decision process involves a collection
different experience, most essentially because of individuals and groups who are
each is a different person. John Falk argued that simultaneously involved in other things.
any specific museum experience comes at a par- Understanding decisions in one arena requires
ticular moment ‘‘within the larger framework of an understanding of how those decisions fit into
a person’s total life,’’ and so is influenced by ‘‘the the lives of the participants. . . . The apparent
person’s prior experiences, prior learning, stage confusion is understandable as resulting from a
of intellectual, physical and emotional develop- shifting intermeshing of the demands on the
ment, cultural and social history, and interests attention and lives of the whole array of actors.
and expectations’’ (Falk 2004, 88). Any person It is possible to see any particular decision as
is, in some sense, the same person from day to the consequence of combining different
day; but, as we all know from our own experi- moments of different lives (1999, 32).
ences, we are also somewhat different every day.
Each day adds to our stock of experiences, pre- While it is possible to predict some aspects
sents new opportunities for learning, deepens of the statistical abstraction ‘‘museum visitors,’’
our integration of past experiences into our it is impossible to predict exactly which real

Jay Rounds 423


CURATOR THE MUSEUM JOURNAL

human beings will flow into an exhibition at factors that are controlled neither by the visitor
any given moment. Any particular combination nor by the museum, but such factors nonethe-
of individuals in a gallery is likely to last only for less may influence the experience. Such factors
a few moments. The focal visitor’s experience are significant ways that ‘‘time and chance’’
may be affected by the exact timing of a friend’s impact what happens.
comment, or a stranger’s sudden laughter, or a
moment of awkwardness in maneuvering Society
through the crowd around a famous painting.
Such events are highly unpredictable. In the Rationalist Model, society provides
the ‘‘relevant’’ goals that drive the process, and
Physical and cultural factors at least some of the necessary resources for car-
rying out that process. It also monitors the out-
Visitors react to the totality of the museum comes, to ensure accountability. But what,
environment, rather than solely to the content concretely, is this ‘‘society’’? Unlike museums
of the exhibitions they view. Changes in the and individual humans, ‘‘society’’ is not some
exhibition itself were treated in the above sec- physical thing with a material existence and dis-
tion, ‘‘The museum.’’ The present stream cernible boundaries. Even in sociology—the
includes changes in the larger physical environ- science of society—it has long been recognized
ment of the museum, and of the world beyond that: ‘‘The very notion of plural societies as dis-
the museum’s doors. Natural lighting in a tinct, discrete entities forming coherent wholes
gallery may vary from moment to moment as or systems has been widely and justly criticized’’
clouds cross the sun. The janitor is ill today, and (Wrong 1994, 8).
the restrooms have not been cleaned. Noise Nor is ‘‘society’’ simply the sum of all of the
from a construction project across the street individuals who make their lives within it.
penetrates into the galleries. Whatever else it may be, society does include
I quoted James March’s observation such real entities as government agencies, insti-
(above) that the forces affecting an organiza- tutions, and organized interest groups. What
tional decision include what is happening in the flows into the museum encounter may in some
rest of the lives of the participants in the deci- cases include ‘‘real’’ things such as regulations,
sion. Similarly, museums are visited by whole mandates, and legal requirements. Such require-
people, whose minds are buzzing with things ments may impact what the visitor experiences.
extraneous to the museum. Those things may Moreover, visitors themselves may carry societal
nonetheless influence how the visitor behaves, imperatives into the museum encounter. Ideas
and how she interprets what she sees. Today, about what qualities constitute society’s priorities
some of the visitors read the glowing review of or the public good are not uniformly distributed
the exhibition in the local newspaper, and arrive through the population. Different visitors
looking for specific features. Some visitors are will carry with them differing standards and
elated—and others are seething—about the values that will impinge on the museum’s
results of yesterday’s elections. Last Sunday a claims of social relevance. Since priorities in the
prominent cleric denounced the ‘‘immorality’’ public arena change—sometimes with startling
of a new exhibition. The museum experience speed—the social relevance of a museum
happens in the context of a host of exogenous encounter may thus be dependent on when that

424 Article: The Museum and Its Relationships as a Loosely Coupled System
Volume 55 Number 4 October 2012

encounter occurs. Given all these factors, the likely to occur than others. Some may have been
stream labeled ‘‘Society’’ will be highly volatile. intended by certain players, but not by others.
Some events may have thwarted the intentions
‘‘What Happens’’ of certain players. Some, while not intended by
anyone, may seem of immediate significance to
The term is deliberately vague. It is meant some players. And others just happened, and no
to contrast with the Rationalist Model, which one will ever care.
offers seemingly concrete ‘‘outcomes’’ as the end Some events that seemed of no significance
point of the process. In the Rationalist Model, at the time nonetheless become part of the visi-
outcomes are what museums produce, in the tor’s memory, and at some later date they may
same sense that a widget factory produces wid- combine with new experiences and suddenly
gets. But what exactly are outcomes? Propo- take on significance. Such later moments
nents of the Rationalist Model sometimes write should not be classified as ‘‘outcomes.’’ As the
as if outcomes were a particular kind of event, word is used in Rationalist accountability, an
recognizably different from events of other outcome must, by definition, have been pre-
types. This is unjustified. The only thing that dicted, and the experience must have been
distinguishes an outcome from other events is designed specifically to bring about precisely
that you predicted it would occur as a result of that event. But significance that only emerges at
your deliberate, goal-oriented action. It has some later date, as a result of surprising juxtapo-
significance to you because it is what you sitions with later experiences, cannot be pre-
wanted to happen. ‘‘Outcome’’ is a label placed dicted. Thus, on top of the distribution of
on certain events, not a special type of event. events, we can overlay a second distribution that
The Emergence Model pictures the eva- charts significance as it emerges across time.
nescent museum encounter as a vortex spinning Where the tightly coupled Rationalist
out ‘‘What Happens.’’ In the world depicted by Model values control and the production of
the Emergence Model, many things are hap- predicted outcomes, the Emergence Model val-
pening at once. Rather than a unitary, predicted ues ‘‘generativity’’—the capacity for generating
outcome, we instead see a distribution of events surprising and interesting emergent properties
spun off by the encounter. Some of those events such as insights, attitudes, concepts, or ways of
may be labeled ‘‘outcomes’’ by some of the play- being that in principle could not have been
ers, but not by other players. Different events anticipated by the designers of the exhibition.
may be labeled outcomes by other players. In Rationalist terms an exhibition is considered
Much of What Happens will be random, to be a failure if it does not produce the pre-
intended by no one, and perceived by no one as dicted outcomes. The Emergence Model shifts
having significance. the unit of analysis to the encounter, which is
Where the Rationalist Model narrows our judged to be disappointing if it does not gener-
attention to looking only for the events we pre- ate something surprising. If generativity can be
dicted, the Emergence Model encourages measured at all, it can be measured only in terms
openness to wider observation. ‘‘What hap- of richness and diversity of the distribution of
pens’’ can be pictured as a distribution of events events across the universe of possibilities, and
across some unpredictable range. Within that the distribution of significance as it emerges
distribution, some events might have been more across time.

Jay Rounds 425


CURATOR THE MUSEUM JOURNAL

In the museum encounter we step into the challenge is to develop creative strategies for
river (that famous river that you can’t step into doing meaningful and important work within
twice) at the moment that a number of tributar- the constraints presented by the world as it is.
ies flow together. Some of those streams carry Rethinking the work of the museum from the
conscious intentions with them, and each may perspective of a loosely coupled system gives us
strive to use the encounter to achieve those access to opportunities foreclosed by the narrow
intentions. Other streams are natural forces that logic of Rationalism.
just happen. They have no intentions of their
own, and they don’t care about ours. RESTORING CONFIDENCE IN THE
This is, after all, the sort of world we all live INHERENT VALUE OF MUSEUMS
in. We each have our intentions, and in the
small ways of everyday life we often achieve Weick noted that an important advantage
them. Sometimes we achieve big intentions as of a loosely coupled system is its capacity for
well, through talent, persistence, and (more accommodating change in some elements with-
often than we care to recognize) good luck. But out threatening the persistence of others. This
the mundane reality is that most things we do facilitates ‘‘local adaptation,’’ a process by which
require the cooperation of other people, and ‘‘one element can adjust to and modify a local
that means negotiating and compromising and unique contingency without affecting the whole
settling for what we can get. Time, chance, system. These local adaptations can be swift,
and other people ‘‘happeneth’’ to us all. relatively economical, and substantial. By defi-
Such a world does not appear compatible nition, the antithesis of localized adaptation is
with the kind of tightly coupled system called standardization’’ (1976, 6–7).
for by the Rationalist Model. The multiplicity The Emergence Model gives us a structure
of intentions carried into the museum encoun- within which to reassert the inherent value of
ter cannot be reduced solely to the intentions of museums. American museums, and their pro-
the museum. The technology of the encounter fessional associations, have been too ready to
is not under the exclusive control of the acquiesce in pronouncements that have ques-
museum. The museum cannot control, and is tioned the value of their core functions, misrep-
not justified in ignoring, the wide and unpre- resented their history, and denigrated the
dictable distribution of events spun off by that professionalism of their staff. Certainly the
encounter. It cannot completely impose its will insights of various critics, and the evolving
on time, chance and other people, and should social and technical environments, have pointed
not be held accountable for their workings. to things that museums do need to change. But
Nonetheless, if the actual world within the logic of the Rationalist Model has extended
which museums do their work is less controlla- the implications of those changes to demands
ble and predictable than is suggested by the that are unjustified. That argument is necessi-
Rationalist Model, it is still a world within tated only if we start from the premise that the
which great things may be accomplished. As is museum must be understood as a tightly cou-
suggested by Stephens’s metaphor of agricul- pled system.
ture, the challenge is not to somehow change As we have seen, standardization is a key
the world to make it conform with the require- feature of the tightly coupled logic model of
ments of the rationalist model. Rather, the Rationalism. That model describes accountabil-

426 Article: The Museum and Its Relationships as a Loosely Coupled System
Volume 55 Number 4 October 2012

ity in terms of outcomes. The goals that drive albeit to a different kind of need than is cur-
the outcomes are defined in terms of intended rently emphasized.
changes in visitors or participants in programs. The sociologist Dennis Wrong distin-
This implies that other functions of museums guished between the sorts of social problems
are of value only insofar as they contribute to the that are the focus of the Rationalist Model, and
development of exhibitions, programs, or any more fundamental ‘‘problems for society,’’ prob-
other offering that is designed for end use by lems ‘‘that are inherent in the very existence of
‘‘visitors,’’ broadly defined. Core museum tech- human societies and that cannot therefore be
nologies—collecting, collections management, finally ‘solved’ in the way that particular social
conservation, curatorial research—have thus problems perhaps can be’’ (1961, 184). He is
been depicted as esoteric concerns of narrow spe- talking about the fundamental and enduring
cialists who have forgotten their responsibility to challenges that arise when humans live together
the community that supports the museum. in large-scale societies. One such challenge is
Because this type of work is not tightly coupled the necessity of balancing short-term invest-
to current priorities ‘‘external to the museum ments in current priorities with investments in
itself,’’ it is dismissed as an inefficient use of long-term sustainability.
resources that would be better employed in pro- In the Rationalist Model, efficiency is
ducing useful outcomes that would benefit soci- taken to mean accomplishing your goals with
ety immediately. Weil argued that this alleged the least possible consumption of resources. But
inefficiency of museums had brought on new many organization theorists treat efficiency in a
demands for accountability, as the public had more nuanced way. Of particular interest in the
become increasingly aware that ‘‘managers of current context, ‘‘efficiency’’ is frequently
both governmental agencies and third-sector depicted as existing in a permanent state of ten-
organizations—lacking in common the reality sion with ‘‘adaptiveness.’’ James G. March, who
checks of a competitive marketplace as well as has written extensively on this issue, explained:
the operational discipline required to demon-
strate consistent profitability—have rarely been Efficiency refers to the short-term
required to apply their resources with the same improvement, refinement, routinization, and
effectiveness and efficiency that would be elaboration of existing ideas, paradigms,
demanded of them in a for-profit context’’ technologies, strategies, and knowledge. It
(1999, 238). This attitude has not only resur- thrives on focused attention, precision,
faced in museum-studies literature; it has also repetition, analysis, sanity, discipline, and
often induced major shifts in museum operating control. Adaptiveness refers to the long-term
budgets, staffing patterns, policies, and practices. substitution of new ideas, paradigms,
In the past, many museums did under- technologies, strategies, and knowledge for old
invest in their public functions. Increased ones. It thrives on serendipity, experimentation,
investments in education and exhibitions have novelty, free association, madness, loose
paid substantial dividends. But getting better at discipline, and relaxed control (1994, 1).
our public functions should not have to entail
getting worse at the work conducted in the back Thus, efficiency is a way of getting better at
of the house. Those back-of-house functions exploiting the potential of what we already know
are particularly relevant to the needs of society, how to do. In large part, becoming more

Jay Rounds 427


CURATOR THE MUSEUM JOURNAL

efficient is a matter of eliminating activity that exploration requires flirting with the ambigu-
does not advance our progress toward the desired ous, the exotic, and the unknown. Organiza-
outcome, or that does so less effectively than tions (as well as societies and individuals) must
another alternative. Thus, increased efficiency find a way to maintain a balance between the
reduces variation in the organization’s activity, two (March 1994b).
suppressing everything except the ‘‘best.’’ But organizations, like individuals, tend to
Efficiency is a good thing, but it is not the overemphasize short-term needs, to the detri-
only good thing. Adaptiveness is another good ment of maintaining long-term adaptability.
thing, but of a very different kind. To maintain Corporate executives who are accountable to
adaptiveness, an organization needs to invest shareholders tend to focus their efforts on the
some resources in exploration—activities that short term, aiming to ‘‘maximize shareholder
increase the range of variation or diversity in the value’’ for the next quarterly report. Politicians
organization’s stock of knowledge and technol- vote for short-term solutions, even knowing that
ogy. It is the organizational equivalent of diver- they compromise long-term viability, because
sity in the gene pool of a biological species. their horizon is defined by the next election and
That diversity is what allows a species to adapt voters decide on the basis of the here-and-now.
rapidly to a sudden change in environmental Investment in exploration and maintenance of
conditions. Efficiency can preclude adaptive- adaptability is routinely sacrificed in favor of
ness, in just the same way that a species can be immediate efficiency. And why not? That rainy
over-adapted to a narrow ecological niche. day may never come, and anyway, as Keynes
March goes on: said, ‘‘In the long run we all are dead.’’
Investment in adaptability thus requires
Efficiency and adaptiveness are linked in an considerable discipline. To ensure attention to
enduring symbiosis. Each requires the other in the future, many corporations establish
order to contribute effectively to an organization’s Research and Development units that are
survival and prosperity. At the same time, administered separately from the production of
however, each interferes with the other. Not only current products. Often R&D is even separated
do they compete for scarce organizational energy physically from the rest of the plant. Its job is
and other resources, the processes of one interfere exploration of possibilities for the future, and it
with the other (1994b, 1). needs to be protected from demands for short-
term engineering of improvements in existing
Exploration is inherently inefficient. A products. As such, R&D is inherently ineffi-
totally efficient organization will not spend a cient. It demands expenditures now, but any
dollar on any activity unless it anticipates a revenues that result are in the future, and are far
short-term return on that investment. But there from certain. Most businesses under-invest in
is no way to know if any specific effort at explo- the future, or slash R&D budgets when times
ration will ever produce income. In fact, most get tough. Just as they should be focusing on
do not. Exploration demands expenditures in exploration, they hunker down and try to
the present, in the hope that some of those become even more efficient (Staw, Sandelands
efforts will produce income at some unknown and Dutton 1981; Rounds 2004a).
point in the future. Efficiency demands clear Society (however we choose to define it) is
goals and unambiguous technologies, but no better than corporations or individuals at

428 Article: The Museum and Its Relationships as a Loosely Coupled System
Volume 55 Number 4 October 2012

resisting the tyranny of present demands. We THE MUSEUM’S RELATIONSHIP WITH


find an abundance of agencies, programs, and INDIVIDUAL USERS
other resources devoted to addressing the needs
of the present, but few institutions that are Museums are visited by people. Each person
devoted to maintaining the capacity of society is an individual who has spent his entire life
to adapt to new and surprising environments becoming the particular person he is at the
when that need arises. Like corporations, socie- moment he arrives at the museum. No one
ties need to establish and tolerate zones of inef- will have had exactly the same experiences, nor
ficiency, as a kind of hedge fund for the future. will have interpreted them in exactly the same
They need reasons for investing in some things way as anyone else. If we really want to under-
for which they have no known use at present. stand museum visitors, and how they take value
Museums are admirably equipped for this role. from their museum encounters, we must con-
They are both storehouses and generators of sider them as individuals (Doering and Pekarik
diversity, of alternatives, of possibilities. They 1996).
have a distinctive competence for building and From the point of view of the Rationalist
maintaining society’s capacity for adaptation in Model, a visitor is simply a piece of raw mate-
an uncertain future. rial, waiting to be transformed into an outcome.
The Rationalist Model asks us to abandon Outcomes are what the model is interested in,
that unique and vital function in order to pursue and the questions it considers important are
relevance in terms of the short-term priorities about whether the outcomes really took place.
of others. Museums that seek to reinvent them- By contrast, the Emergence Model treats all of
selves as solvers of current social problems find the elements of the system on the same footing.
those niches already crowded with agencies, Both the museum and the individual visitor are
programs, and other resources that have been each depicted as an independent stream, flow-
designed for expertise on those specific issues. ing along its own path before and after the
Museums may have difficulty in demonstrating moment of encounter. That is, each is under-
any distinctive competence that is not already stood to be an active agent that selectively enters
being applied. The fact that the existing experts into these moments of encounter when it per-
have not solved the issues is not, in itself, a rea- ceives a reason for doing so. The model assumes
son to believe that museums are likely to do that each will interact in the ways required to
better. serve the overlapping interests that have
Instead, museums should emphasize their brought them together, but will avoid more
usefulness as society’s equivalent to the indus- extensive commitments that might compromise
trial Research and Development unit, protected autonomy without concomitant benefits. The
from the demands of efficiency so that they can boundary is likely to be fuzzy. It is negotiated in
provide the rich depth of diversity that may the course of the encounter itself, and may vary
be essential in times of change. There is little in subsequent encounters—but it will be there.
competition for that niche. Such a role is not The museum has the same responsibility to
‘‘irrelevant.’’ It is, simply, relevant to a type of protect its autonomy in regard to individual
issue—Wrong’s ‘‘problems for society’’—that is users as it does in regard to society. The long-
different, but no less compelling, than the hot term efficacy of its core technology must be buf-
priorities of the day. fered from efforts to enlist it inappropriately in

Jay Rounds 429


CURATOR THE MUSEUM JOURNAL

service of short-term private interests. Simi- if too great, they threaten to keep the results
larly, the visitor is responsible for the steward- from ‘‘reaching significance’’ (Barash 2010, B10).
ship of his own life, and in his encounter with
the museum he will seek value from the experi- From the perspective of loosely coupled
ence without compromising that stewardship. systems, the museum visitor is seen as an active
In museum discourse—including ‘‘visitor agent who has a job to do. The job we are con-
research’’—individuals are not much in evi- cerned with here is not how she makes a living,
dence. The distinguished scientist David but how she makes her life. Visiting the
Barash, best known for his work in evolutionary museum is one of the ways that she has chosen
biology, recently wrote: to do that job, but it is unlikely to be the only
one. Her relationship with the museum will be
One of the unspoken secrets in basic loosely coupled because her visit(s) will occupy
scientific research . . . is that, nearly always, only a small portion of her time and attention.
individuals turn out to be different from one Museum visiting may be influential, but that
another, and that—to an extent rarely admitted influence will be weak compared with the total-
and virtually never pursued—scientific ity of other influences that go into her work.
generalizations tend to hush up those The reason why she is there, and the value she
differences. It can be argued that that is what takes from her encounter with the museum, will
generalizations are: statements that apply to a probably not be the same as the reasons that led
larger class of phenomena and must, by the museum to create the exhibition. Their jobs
definition, do violence to individuality. But since are different, and neither can do the job of the
science seeks to explain observed phenomena, it other. Rather than seeking to become tightly
should also be able to explain the granular coupled around a common goal, the visitor and
particularity of such phenomena. In fact, the museum seek a loosely coupled encounter
generalities lose potency if they occur at the cost serving interests that overlap rather than coincide.
of artificially leveling otherwise significant In other articles I have dealt at length with
features of reality (2010, B9). some of the ways that visitors take value from
museum encounters that are only loosely cou-
Barash noted that textbooks on animal pled to the purposes of the museum (Rounds
behavior (including his own) are filled with 2004; 2006). Here I will expand on a single
descriptions of categories of behavior, but say issue that particularly exemplifies the appropri-
nothing at all about behavioral individuality ateness of loosely coupled relationships in the
(2010, B9). He explained that scientists use sta- museum system.
tistical methods to acknowledge variation from The eminent social theorist Anthony Gid-
means and medians. dens described the special burden placed on
individuals who live in the multicultural socie-
But let’s face it: We are overwhelmingly ties of ‘‘High Modernity’’ (1991). Giddens con-
more interested in measures of central tendency. trasted modern society to the small scale,
. . . We give at best only passing attention to relatively isolated communities of earlier times.
statistical measures of dispersion, largely as There each person was born into an ascribed
unavoidable indices of irrelevant noise . . . such status and role. Everyone did much the same
measures are considered with trepidation, since thing (allowing for role differentiation between

430 Article: The Museum and Its Relationships as a Loosely Coupled System
Volume 55 Number 4 October 2012

men and women), and faced the same behavori- Fortunately, we don’t need to worry much.
al expectations. Because of their isolation from The museum may try to control things, and may
other societies, people seldom encountered oth- try to draw visitors into a tightly coupled rela-
ers who were pursuing different ways of life. tionship in which the visitor is subordinated to
Everyone knew what their lives were going to the intentions of the museum. But the museum
be like, so no one had to deal with the kind of faces formidable defenses that protect the
identity issues so central in our own times. autonomy of the visitor. For the museum visitor,
In High Modernity, Giddens wrote, we are free choice does not stop at the door; personal
constantly encountering other people who have competence and judgment are not checked at
adopted very different ways of living. While the the cloak room; individual intentions are not
early influences of our childhood are real, people surrendered to make room for the intentions of
today have greater freedom to choose their own the museum. However clear the museum’s goals
way of being than ever before. But the blessing might be, however logical its models, however
of freedom entails the burden of choice. There skilled its designs, all the visitor has to do is look
are many ways to lead a good life, and each of us away (or walk away) and the museum’s inten-
must find our own way among the many possi- tionality crumbles. The concern that has led me
bilities. If we do not make that choice for our- to write this article is not a fear that the Ration-
selves, to whom would we entrust it? alist museum might actually succeed in forcing
Certainly there is no shortage of others its intentions onto visitors. Rather, I’m con-
willing to tell you who you are and how you cerned that, in attempting to force visitors to
ought to live—each of whom claims to repre- accept ‘‘outcomes,’’ museums may deprive visi-
sent your ‘‘true’’ identity, your only hope for tors of the museum’s potential as a powerful ally
authenticity and fulfillment. No one could be all in the critical task in which each person finds his
those things simultaneously. For some people, or her own way to a good life.
choosing allegiance to one of those voices seems We should hope that whatever life any
to be the best path. Most of us, though, work at individual adopts will include commitments to
constructing our own ways out of bits and pieces the public good, to social order, and to social
drawn from multiple sources (Giddens 1991). justice. If we knew exactly what such commit-
In facing this burden—in creating the right ments should entail, perhaps we could justify a
life for themselves—individuals need allies, not tightly coupled museum system designed to
more bosses. The Rationalist Model, by insist- impose that knowledge on others. But we don’t,
ing that accountability requires predetermined and there is no disinterested authority we can
goals and predicted outcomes, presses museums ask. As Calhoun says, ‘‘the public good is not
to become one more strident voice, loudly tell- objectively or externally ascertainable’’ (1998,
ing people who they really are and how they 32). Even an expert strongly committed to the
should live. It would be a real loss if they were importance of the public good as an ideal found
to succeed, for the museum is uniquely posi- it necessary to issue a warning:
tioned to serve instead as an ally for individuals
doing their ‘‘identity work,’’ as a safe place for The public good is a dangerous concept.
exploration, as a rich source for expanding one’s Asking people to act in the public good and not
sense of possibilities, and for vicarious flirting in their self interest asks them to leave a terrain
with other ways of being (Rounds 2006). in which their everyday experience gives them

Jay Rounds 431


CURATOR THE MUSEUM JOURNAL

relatively reliable messages on what is good for administrator of his small island realm. He
them and to enter a terrain in which, because yearns to return to the glorious adventures that
uncertainty is far greater, authoritative others brought him fame in youth, that defined his
play a far greater role in suggesting what the character as one who ‘‘strove with gods.’’ That,
public good should be (Mansbridge 1998, 17). he knows, is his proper job.
Fortunately, his son Telemachus has a dif-
The museum faces demands from all direc- ferent temperament, one suited to the quiet
tions. In the loosely coupled system it listens care- grind of ruling. Ulysses vows to hand Telem-
fully, but ultimately must rely upon its own achus ‘‘the scepter and the isle’’ while himself
judgment and vision regarding how it can best setting back to sea. ‘‘He works his work, I
contribute to both society and the individual. mine.’’
Who is better qualified to make that judgment? That, I think, perfectly captures the spirit
Who can be trusted to provide a more objective of the loosely coupled museum system. The
voice? How would we choose someone else to set museum works its work; society and the indi-
our course, when we know that the decision vidual each works its own. None could do the
would exclude other legitimate voices with differ- job of the others, and none should try to do so.
ent opinions? We can commit ourselves to serv- But each can help the others, in ways that
ing the public good, without shackling ourselves respect the work and the autonomy of the
to a single, unitary version of what it demands. others.
If this seems an implausible challenge, Thinking of the museum and its relation-
remember that it is what all of us do as individu- ships as a loosely coupled system offers us a
als. This is the task that has been set for us by humane alternative to the constricting imagery
the conditions of human life in High Moder- of the Rationalist Model. It defines a mode of
nity. Whether as museum visitors or in any operation that is sustainable, useful, and honor-
other role, every individual has to take charge of able, and that respects the integrity and profes-
his or her own life, listen to the clamor of com- sionalism of those who have dedicated their
peting voices, and make choices. Museums can careers to the specialized work of museums. It
take the Rationalist path, and attempt to protects a resource that is of value to both
impose a specific choice onto visitors; or they society and to the individuals who use the
can adopt the model of a loosely coupled sys- museum.
tem, and become a resource for individuals who One type of museum encounter occurs in
are exploring who they are, and who they might the limited zone of overlap between the work of
become. If the public good does not provide the the museum and the work of the visitor. The
opportunity for individuals to lead good lives museum creates exhibitions that move from the
within that society, of their own choosing, then particularity of material things to more general-
what is it good for? ized expressions of meaning. Having done so,
the work of the museum is completed, and the
TOWARD A MODEL OF THE MUSEUM AS work of the visitor begins. The museum has cre-
A LOOSELY COUPLED SYSTEM ated a new thing, and the visitor will use it to
create another new thing. Her work will have
In Lord Tennyson’s poem Ulysses, the the character of the ‘‘localized adaptation’’ that
aging king laments having ended up as the Weick identified as one of the strengths of

432 Article: The Museum and Its Relationships as a Loosely Coupled System
Volume 55 Number 4 October 2012

loosely coupled systems. Where the museum’s the intentions. John Dewey argued long ago
work moved from the particular to the general, that intentions and outcomes are inseparable.
the visitor’s work moves in the opposite direc- He defined an ‘‘aim’’ as ‘‘a foreseen end [that]
gives direction to the activity’’ (1916, Chapter
tion, adapting the generalized themes of the
8). It is, Dewey wrote, ‘‘nonsense to talk about
exhibition to its implications for the unique
the aim of education—or any other undertak-
particularities of her own life. ing—where conditions do not permit of fore-
What she will create, and what other visitors sight of results, and do not stimulate a person
will create, cannot be predicted by the museum, to look ahead to see what the outcome of a
and so cannot guide the conceptualization of the given activity is to be’’ (1916, xx). The phrase
exhibition. The work done by the museum is ‘‘intended outcome’’ is thus redundant, and the
loosely coupled to ‘‘what happens’’ because the phrase ‘‘unintended outcome’’ is oxymoronic.
4. The Emergence Model was inspired by a num-
visitor intervenes. She creates her own unique
ber of sources, but I am particularly indebted to
encounter by choosing how to allocate her atten-
‘‘The Garbage Can Model of Organizational
tion among the offerings of the exhibition. Choice,’’ an important concept in organiza-
Whatever she chooses, the influence of that tional theory that has provided significant alter-
experience will be modest compared with the natives to overly rationalized models of
cumulative impact of all her long years of per- organizational processes (Cohen, March, and
sonal identity work. Thus, the impact of the Olsen 1972).
exhibition will take as many paths as there are 5. These categories are arbitrary. There are good
reasons for lumping things in this particular
visitors. The power of the exhibition must be
way; but the categories could be defined differ-
measured not by production of a preordained
ently, for instance by treating each of the
endpoint—the notorious intended outcome— ‘‘physical, social, and cultural factors’’ as a sepa-
but by the wealth of new possibilities that have rate stream. Since my present purpose is to
entered the world. The success of museums illustrate the potential of the model as an alter-
should be counted in beginnings, not in native to Rationalist models, the relative sim-
endings. END plicity of five categories seems justified. Other
research questions might require a more fine-
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS grained application.

The author has benefited from comments by REFERENCES


Antoniette Guglielmo and Ikuko Uetani on earlier
drafts of this article. Calhoun, C. 1998. The public good as a social and
cultural project. In Private Action and the
Public Good, W.W. Powell and E.S. Clemens,
NOTES eds. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Cohen, M.D., J.G. March, and J.P. Olsen. 1972.
1. I have emphasized my intellectual debt to A garbage can model of organizational choice.
Weick’s article by echoing his title in the title Administrative Science Quarterly 17: 1–25.
of the present article. Csikszentmihalyi, M., and E. Rochberg-Halton.
2. For detailed explanations and critiques of 1981. The Meaning of Things: Domestic Symbols
Rational Choice Theory, see Sen (2002); and the Self. Cambridge: Cambridge Univer-
March (1999); and Pfeffer (1997). sity Press.
3. It makes little difference whether we say that Dewey, J. 1916. Democracy and Education. New
the model is defined by the outcomes, or by York: The Macmillan Company.

Jay Rounds 433


CURATOR THE MUSEUM JOURNAL

Doering, Z., and A. Perkarik. 1996. Questioning Stapp, C. 1998. Museums and community devel-
the entrance narrative. The Journal of Museum opment. Curator: The Museum Journal 41(4):
Education 21(3): 20–23. 228–234.
Falk, J. 2009. Identity and the Museum Visitor Expe- Stephens, J. M. 1967. The Process of School-
rience. Walnut Creek, CA: Left Coast Press. ing. New York: Holt, Rinehart and
Giddens, A. 1991. Modernity and Self-Identity: Self Winston.
and Society in the Late Modern Age. Stanford: Staw, B., L. Sandelands, and J. Dutton. 1981.
Stanford University Press. Threat-rigidity effects in organizational behav-
Hennes, T. 2010. Exhibitions: From a perspective ior: A multilevel analysis. Administrative
of encounter. Curator: The Museum Journal Science Quarterly 26: 501–524.
53(1): 21–33. Weick, K. 1976. Educational organizations as
Kahneman, D. 2011. Thinking, Fast and Slow. loosely coupled systems. Administrative Science
New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux. Quarterly 21: 1–19.
Mansbridge, J. 1998. On the contested nature of Weil, S. 1999. From being about something to
the public good. In Private Action and the being for somebody: The ongoing transforma-
Public Good, W.W. Powell and E.S. Clemens, tion of the American museum. Daedalus
editors. New Haven: Yale University Press. 128(3): 229–258.
March, J.G. 1994a. A Primer on Decision Making. ——— 2003. Five meditations. Museum News
New York: The Free Press. (Jan. ⁄ Feb.): 27ff.
——— 1994b. Three Lectures on Efficiency and Wrong, D. 1961. The oversocialized conception of
Adaptiveness in Organizations. man in modern sociology. American Sociological
Helsinki: Swedish School of Economics and Review 26(2): 183–193.
Business Administration.
——— 1999. The Pursuit of Organizational Intelli-
gence. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishers.
Pfeffer, J. 1997. New Directions for Organization
Theory: Problems and Prospects. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Rounds, J. 2004a. The best of practices, the worst
of times. In Are We There Yet? Conversations
About Best Practices in Science Exhibition
Development, K. McLean and C. McEver,
eds., 5–10. San Francisco: The Exploratorium.
———. 2004b. Strategies for the curiosity-driven
museum visitor. Curator: The Museum Journal
47(4): 389–412.
———. 2006a. Creativity: Are things getting bet-
ter or are things getting worse? Exhibitionist
25(1): 12–17.
———. 2006b. Doing identity work in museums.
Curator: The Museum Journal 49(2): 133–150.
Sen, A. 2002. Rationality and Freedom. Cam-
bridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard
University Press.
Serrell, B. 1998. Paying Attention: Visitors and
Museum Exhibitions. Washington, DC: Amer-
ican Association of Museums.

434 Article: The Museum and Its Relationships as a Loosely Coupled System
Copyright of Curator is the property of Wiley-Blackwell and its content may not be copied or emailed to
multiple sites or posted to a listserv without the copyright holder's express written permission. However, users
may print, download, or email articles for individual use.

You might also like