You are on page 1of 5

Essay Review

Present Tense: Working with Cavell

BY TIMOTHY GOULD

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/65/2/229/5957655 by University of Hong Kong user on 03 August 2022


crary, alice, and sanford shieh, eds. Reading reading Cavell is still a matter of contention and,
Cavell. Routledge, 2006, x + 262 pp., $105.00 moreover, of contending with Cavell himself. To
cloth, $31.95 paper. contend with such a body of work is not just
goodman, russell b., ed. Contending with Stanley a matter of arguing with its arguments but also
Cavell. Oxford University Press, 2005, x + 205 of having to reckon with the comprehensive in-
pp., $45.00 cloth. terconnection of its projects. Reminders of the
professional riskiness of Cavell’s work crop up
rothman, william, ed. Cavell on Film. SUNY in all three volumes.1 Garrett Stewart (CSC) ex-
Press, 2005, xxvii + 399 pp., $89.50 cloth, $27.95 plores Cavell’s happy and unhappy engagements
paper. with Stewart’s disciplines (film, poetics, and nar-
These three books offer a look at recent crit- rative theory). Richard Rorty (CSC) refers to
ical literature inspired or provoked by Stanley Cavell’s quarrel with his profession, and he urges
Cavell. The two critical anthologies contain work him to leave the landlocked squabbles of aca-
by Cavell, and Russell Goodman offers Cavell a demic philosophy and head for the open seas of
chance to respond to his interlocutors. William otherness.
Rothman has compiled Cavell’s previously uncol- Cavell still inspires controversy, though per-
lected writing on film. The thoughts echo beyond haps less melodramatically than in the earlier days.
the books that contain them. Nearly twenty essays His defenders no longer betray the sense that
about Cavell and almost thirty pieces by Cavell Cavell’s opponents are trying to quarantine his
yield a range of writing that permits a serious en- work, rather than refute it—as if to prevent his
gagement with his work. infectiousness from spreading. It is probably good
For Cavell, aesthetics exists not merely on the that this melodramatic image is passing. But the
margins of philosophy but at its core. This de- sense that Cavell’s influence, like Ludwig Wittgen-
mands a more immediate engagement with the stein’s, is somewhat illicit and not controllable by
arts than is common, which has left Cavell at odds ordinary measures of intellectual hygiene has not
with professional philosophers and also with some really dissipated, though it may have diminished.
aestheticians. In his move to enlarge the register A loss of the urgency that Stewart and Rothman
of the aesthetic as it might be, he seems to slight recall may betoken a faded perception of the in-
aesthetics as it is. Cavell’s “Crossing Paths” (in tellectual forces still mobilized to keep Cavell at a
Rothman) declares his sense, shared with Arthur distance.
C. Danto, that the immediacy of the arts initially Cavell has suggested why his work is unlikely
undermines the more standard approaches of uni- to settle into a comfortable niche of the profes-
versity aesthetics. sion. First, there is his modernist ambition, shared
Beginning in the early 1960s, Cavell attracted with Wittgenstein and Martin Heidegger but cast
intense controversy. Goodman’s Contending with in terms adapted from the arts. Cavell has de-
Stanley Cavell echoes this critical situation, as if scribed philosophy as existing in the condition of

The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 65:2 Spring 2007


230 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

the modernist arts and of having constantly to de- Cavell’s sentences but for those who are staying
fine itself against its past accomplishments to pre- the course. (This is very clear in Stephen Mulhall
serve those very accomplishments. He wants to [RC, CSC], James Conant [RC, CSC], and Stew-
divide his readers into those who are formed by art.) But from time to time even his friendly read-
the canons of academic philosophy and those who ers will also feel shut out, or preempted, by the
wish to uncover what such philosophy has con- very attraction and comprehensiveness of Cavell’s

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/65/2/229/5957655 by University of Hong Kong user on 03 August 2022


cealed and preserved. Cavell speaks both to our prose. So what is one to say? How do we continue
willingness to give up the profession’s sense of the work of such a writer? To continue a conver-
progress, including its standards of prose, and to sation we must include some response to the top-
our fear that to relinquish professional rigor is to ics proposed by the writer, and we must be able
give up philosophy. When Stewart speaks of Cavell to respond to the tone of voice or at least allow
as exploring the drive to the unparaphrasable or for a comprehensible shift or break in the tone.
Rothman picks up Cavell’s remark on the “un- Cavell makes a point of including writing as one
teachable point” of any enterprise, they are each of his topics. Accordingly, many of the contribu-
elucidating an aspect of Cavell’s writing that we tors comment on Cavell’s modes of writing. But
cannot accurately address within the profession many of the essays hit on other topics central to
as it stands. Cavell’s work: everydayness, skepticism, and the
To join in the conversation that Cavell invites is Other; film; Shakespeare, Romanticism, and the
to risk exclusion from the body of discourse that conflict between the false and frozen complete-
holds the profession together—and pays the bills. ness of moralism and the transient completeness
But this profession also constitutes a part of the that “Emersonian perfectionism” is striving for.
intellectual world that Cavell wants to remain in The role of film in Cavell’s work is empha-
touch with, even as he periodically departs from sized in Stuart Klawans (RC), Andrew Klevan
it and resists its self-stultification. For Cavell, “the (CSC), and especially in Rothman. Psychoanal-
problems of philosophy”—which Rorty wants us ysis remains on the fringes of both books, though
to leave behind—remain the alternative to taking one can sense its presence in Nancy Bauer’s (RC)
philosophy as a series of texts to be read. With- readings of speech and film in the context of the
out this idea of a “problem” as a correlative to the debates about pornography. Her juxtaposing of
idea of a “text,” both ideas are philosophically im- the perlocutionary effects of words and the more
poverished. “Text” on its own says no more than primitive, or less articulated, power of the image is
“reading” on its own. If anything can be read, then illuminating, and it invites further work. Her anal-
anything can be a text, and conversely. The range ysis reinserts an aesthetic dimension to psycho-
extends from Henry David Thoreau reading a car- analysis and politics, as well as a kind of would-be
load of sails to our reading, potentially, the stars. therapeutic dimension to pornography.
The question now becomes not what to read but Stewart and Simon Critchley (CSC) say some-
why and when is reading begun? And when is it thing about Cavell’s address to Shakespeare and
done? Shakespeare criticism and to Ralph Waldo Emer-
Cavell says that he conceived The World Viewed son and the Americanists. Except for Rothman,
as contributing to two conversations, the one that there seems little sense of how the movies allow
called for his contribution and the one that his us to see both Shakespeare and the opera as antic-
writing calls for. A decade later, he delineated ipating the absorptive power of film and its genres.
a mode of philosophical reception and rigor—he Rothman and Klevan both suggest how Emerson’s
called it “reading”—that is the other face of a writ- attention to the “low” and “the near” allow Cavell
ing responsive to its own unrelenting implications. to link the perception that film demands—and the
Such reading and writing demand a responsibility perception that film permits—to our readings of
as heavy as logic and as conclusive as a musical the everyday. This points to the transcendentalist
cadence. But if the reader’s responses are already underwriting of ordinary language, something that
anticipated in the text, then (as Cavell predicted) renders more intelligible the fact of our ordinary
some readers will find themselves shut out, and vulnerability to skepticism and our intermittent
they will find the writing to be not self-responsive ability to turn it aside.
but self-indulgent. Many contributors say something about the
Many contributors are clearly writing not for “philosophy of the ordinary,” but there is almost
those who quit at the first inward turning of no actual philosophizing from the ordinary use of
Essay Review 231

words. The practice of working from the ordinary as a sign that skepticism has already succeeded
things we have to say, in their ordinary circum- within our ordinary lives—as if she has equated
stances, seems to be the hardest thing in the world the Romantic sense of self-division with our more
to learn from Cavell (or J. L. Austin or Wittgen- mundane vulnerability to skepticism. Cavell sug-
stein). As a set of procedures, it has never been that gests her perspective is representatively European
easy to characterize (compare Cavell’s “Austin at and hence a useful measure of our own inheri-

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/65/2/229/5957655 by University of Hong Kong user on 03 August 2022


Criticism”). Cavell’s perception of the shortcom- tance.
ings in the various descriptions of such philoso- Sanford Shieh (RC) works to locate the starting
phizing explicitly leads him to the idea of Thoreau points of skepticism, which is already a major part
and Emerson as “underwriting” the ordinary. It is of locating the motive to skepticism. Apart from
as if the Romantic wish for an intimacy of the word this motive, we cannot hope to find skepticism’s
and the world can find satisfaction in the most or- “truth.” He works within the issues raised by Mul-
dinary moments of our ability to put the world into hall’s response to Steven Affeldt’s essay (unfortu-
words. This links the skeptical distance and the Ro- nately not reprinted in this anthology) concerning
mantic wish to overcome the alienation and per- whether criteria form a framework for judging cor-
versity of speech. This marks another difference rectness and incorrectness. These papers force us
from Rorty’s perception of skepticism as wholly to think about the relation of criteria to concepts
other than Romanticism. Unlike Rorty, Cavell has and their frameworks. Some idea of a framework
consistently been aware of the proximity of Ro- goes way back in the discussion of skepticism. In
manticism to the genesis of the aesthetic and of Individuals, P. F. Strawson writes of the skeptic:
their mutual effort to provide a human ground for “He pretends to accept a conceptual scheme, but
utterance, judgment, and feeling. at the same time quietly rejects one of the condi-
It sometimes seems as if, in their impatience to tions of its employment.”2
get to the meatier topics, Cavell’s readers invoke This is perhaps a version of what Shieh calls the
the power of the ordinary in a kind of nostalgic traditional interpretation. Mulhall seems to share
memory or hope of what it might be like to philos- the tendency to interpret criteria as belonging to or
ophize like that. Here our hope for making sense even constituting such a framework. In turn, that
lies in the fact that the memory of the everyday suggests that the primary use of criteria is to al-
(like Baudelaire’s “memory of the present”) is it- low us to justify our uses of words, our utterances,
self still somewhere in the vicinity of the every- based on something independent of those utter-
day. Rothman and Klawans address the everyday ances. Of course, in a great many cases, the source
that film evokes and reveals. The everyday world of our responses will be precisely the criteria that
of film is fated to occur at a distance—hence a are alive in our utterances. Shieh and Affeldt ask:
nearness—whose relation to the world of our ev- Can a framework composed of criteria form a gen-
eryday words remains largely unassessed. eral response to the threat of skepticism? Here,
Conant does his level best to make a man- the appropriate path must find a way of saying
ageable topic out of “America.” He compares “no” without denying the truth that Mulhall is
Cavell’s reflections to the role of nationality and invoking.
language in other philosophical projects, preemi- Cavell reads Wittgenstein as reminding us that a
nently in Greece and Germany. Such philosophi- scheme or “framework” (Gurüst also means ‘scaf-
cal projects have remained locked up in Heideg- folding’) is not a structure on which agreement is
gerian, nationalist, and fascist tendencies. To take based. “It is what human beings say that is true and
it up in a democratic spirit seems a true continua- false; and they agree in the language they use. That
tion of Cavell’s aspirations (chastened somewhat is not agreement in opinions but in form of life.”3
by Critchley’s strictures). We can read Wittgenstein as saying that the agree-
Sandra Laugier (CSC) provides a perspective ment in our forms of life gives rise to a framework
on the ordinary, deepened by her Continental of concepts, which in turn makes possible certain
experience of the past and its emerging analytic judgments of right and wrong, correct and incor-
elements. She moves quickly to shore up the ordi- rect. Or we can read him as saying that in certain
nary with its transcendental underwriting. She ap- regions, like mathematics, there is something like a
parently takes the divergence in Emerson of “the framework, so that “disputes do not break out . . .
world that I think from the world I converse with” over whether a rule has been obeyed or not.”4 That
232 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

framework is made possible by our agreement in one “way” that Cavell writes, any more than there
judgments, our attunements in those forms of life is “one voice” that needs to be recovered. What is
we call counting, measuring, factoring, finding the “aesthetic” in Cavell’s work is equally a matter of
square root or the differential. In certain regions of our knowledge of the world: every act of writing
our language, our agreement makes possible fur- is already a kind of judgment of the world.
ther agreement that for certain purposes we could If few contributors respond directly to the de-

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/65/2/229/5957655 by University of Hong Kong user on 03 August 2022


call “more precise.” And so we are lead to the idea mands of Cavell’s voice, most of them seem to have
of a framework, which seems designed to sharpen heard the resonance of Cavell’s tuning fork. They
our sense of the articulation among our concepts felt themselves tested by it. Without pretending to
and the greater precision that this articulation per- cover all the interesting material in these volumes,
mits when we are using our concepts to map the I single out Paul Franks (RC), who has done more
world. This does no harm as long as we do not than most to go over the post-Kantian problem-
take the framework as the foundation of the judg- atic of the Other that lies within the Kantian moral
ments, rather than the other way around. The idea consciousness. Eli Friedlander (RC) reverses the
of a framework is, on this reading, no more funda- direction of the problematic by taking the aes-
mental than the idea that, ideally, we use words in thetic exemplar both as a given and as a possibility
a kind of calculus. For certain purposes, this is also that cannot be dismissed. The exemplar thus be-
a useful comparison. comes a kind of fact that cannot be circumvented.
Shieh refuses to take the attunement that al- Where the moral consciousness demands of itself
lows criteria to be manifested in our utterances to a knowledge of the Other, we gain access to the
be a consequence of the existence of criteria. That exemplar only by its influence on us, its ability to
refusal may seem too small an achievement, as if stir us to the height of activity.
“attunement” just repeated that we are in accord Hilary Putnam (RC) stands as Rorty’s an-
in these uses of words or perhaps this moment of tipodes, urging Cavell on the profession rather
shared laughter. This seems much less than claim- than urging Cavell to take his leave of it. Good-
ing to discover a framework. It is in some such man, analogously, urges Cavell to repair the rup-
spirit that Cavell speaks of our disappointment tures in the American tradition—above all be-
in criteria, which is also presumably a disappoint- tween Emerson and various pragmatisms. Cavell
ment in our attunement in the use of these criteria. persists in finding the ruptures and repressions of
It becomes important to remember that we need Emerson as essential to the possibility of recover-
to reaffirm this attunement above all when it is ing our tradition. While not disagreeing that a re-
broken, when we are trying to recall it, or when paired possibility of continuity would be desirable,
our wish to make it into something stronger ends it would distort the possibilities of actually using
up undermining it. that tradition, in the way Cavell has received it. Yet
Of course, it is sometimes critical that saying it is in this very conversation with Goodman that
or doing something is right or wrong, grammatical these claims about rupture and repression, found-
or ungrammatical, foul or fair, safe or out. Then ing and reception, become most vivid. So there is
we may look to our criteria as if they formed a after all perhaps a kind of interrupted conversa-
framework. What we cannot do is take our attune- tion that begins to be heard again, in the act of
ment, our agreement in judgments, and make that deferring it.
agreement in turn the arbiter of correct and in- Crary extends Cavell’s interest in Austin to-
correct, as if we had thereby taken a further step ward perfectionism, preparing a path for Cora Di-
toward grounding the agreement of our judgments amond’s (RC) sense that this project is both puz-
in something deeper than our mere agreements. zling and absorbing from the ground of language
A rejuvenated discussion of skepticism might up. Here, too, the aesthetic, the ethical, and our
lead to our understanding that the way Cavell knowledge of the Other are found to be painfully
writes is not simply an exhibition of the will to inextricable. Diamond displays the kind of pro-
elaborate or qualify the bald assertions of analytic ductive puzzlement in her engagement with Cavell
philosophy. The “way he writes” grows precisely that few philosophers have wanted to work with—
from the task of tracing the skeptic’s claims to their even within the main circuits of Cavell’s influence.
human roots, of restoring the voice that was will- All honor to those who put their perplexity to
ing to utter the (literally) unutterable. There is no use and, in this case, who apply the pain of hard
Essay Review 233

philosophy to the painful problems of human ex- 1. Essays included in Russell B. Goodman, Contending
istence. with Stanley Cavell, will be noted as CSC, and those in Alice
Crary and Sanford Shieh, Reading Cavell, as RC. William
Rothman, Cavell on Film, is referred to as “Rothman.” Co-
nant and Mulhall appear in both volumes.
TIMOTHY GOULD
2. Stanley Cavell, The Claim of Reason: Wittgenstein,
Department of Philosophy Skepticism, Morality, and Tragedy (Oxford: Clarendon,
Metropolitan State College of Denver

Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/65/2/229/5957655 by University of Hong Kong user on 03 August 2022


1979, reprinted with a new preface, 1999), p. 47.
Denver, Colorado 80204 3. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations,
3rd ed. (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1968), § 241.
internet: gouldt@mscd.edu 4. Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, § 240.

You might also like