You are on page 1of 18

See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.

net/publication/227599572

Education or Pedagogy?

Article in Journal of Philosophy of Education · February 2000


DOI: 10.1111/1467-9752.00208

CITATIONS
READS
41
24,587

1 author:

Geoffrey Hinchliffe
University of East Anglia
32 PUBLICATIONS 482 CITATIONS

Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:

Liberty and Education View project

All content following this page was uploaded by Geoffrey Hinchliffe on 11 December 2017.

The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file.


Journal of Philosophy of Education, Vol. 35, No. 1, 2001

Education or Pedagogy?

GEOFFREY HINCHLIFFE

This paper explores the meaning of education in contrast with


'pedagogy'. Whereas education can be defined as 'learning
for its own sake', pedagogy can be defined as learning
oriented towards social goals. An attempt to find an adequate
conceptualisation is first of all sought in Aristotle, but
his concept of education is found to depend on too narrow
a concept of rational activity. A more adequate
conceptualisation is found in Michael Oakeshott's contrast
between morality and enterprise associations. However
Oakeshott's definition of education needs modifying if it is
to take account of the idea of critical knowing, which is
seen as crucial to any definition of education.

INTRODUCTION
Ever since antiquity, there have always been two traditions in teaching
and learning. The first-instrumental learning, or, in a sense to be
explained, pedagogy-places learning at the service of government,
political power and the economy. The second-education-represents
that more disinterested endeavour in which teacher and pupil engage in
a form of enquiry. Whereas the former has specific objectives, the latter-
though it indeed must provide certain skills and knowledge-is
underpinned by the idea that the outcome of education is essentially
open. Just as we cannot predict the outcome of good conversation, this
inability being one of the prime reasons for engaging in the pursuit,
so the outcome of an educative experience must be left, in part, to
the interaction between learners and teacher. Construed as education,
the results of learning can never be measured according to a common
standard. But construed as a pedagogy, those results must be measur-
able because the whole point of learning is to equip people for specified
social, political and economic requirements. The implication is clear:
those interested in education have always had to fight their corner
against the proponents of pedagogy. Free spirits usually have a hard
time of it: but now, more than ever, is the time to recover and re-state
those ideals associated with the tradition of education against the time-
servers of pedagogy.

© The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain 2001. Published by Blackwell Publishers,
108 Cowley Road, Oxford OX4 1JF and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA.
32 G. Hinchliffe
This view was proposed by the classicist, Oswyn Murray in a recent
Times Literary Supplement review (Murray, 1999). The review is of a
book entitled Pedagogy and Power (Too and Livingstone, 1998) which
contains a number of essays on the ways in which classical learning and
teaching have been used and deployed in a number of social and
political contexts since the times of antiquity. Murray uses the review to
advance the case (a case, it should be noted, not advanced anywhere in
Pedagogy and Power itself) that there are two traditions in education:
the pedagogic and the educative. And the tradition of pedagogy can be
traced back to Isocrates, who taught rhetoric and other arts to young
Greek aristocrats in order to equip them properly for a career in public
life. On the other hand, the tradition of education can be traced squarely
back to Plato, who (according to Murray) advocated that learning and
the pursuit of knowledge be unsullied by the pursuit of worldly
affairs.
It is difficult not to find Murray's view attractive. For who wants to
find themselves ranged against 'the freedom of the human spirit' apart
from those so mired in a world of assessment strategies and quality
reviews that they cannot see beyond it? And it is a good, anti-
Popperian move to enlist Plato on the side of free spirits in
opposition to Isocrates and his tracts on rhetoric. After all, who today
reads the latter apart from a few scholars? Of course, some might try
to argue that the Republic also serves political ends; but this seems
unfair. Its arguments cannot be construed as a set of guides and
prescriptions for future rulers since the Guardians are only entitled to
rule because of the knowledge and wisdom they possess. Those who
posses real knowledge take up the reins of power reluctantly because
they know that although their gaze is directed towards the sources of
wisdom, they are still of this world and cannot avoids its
imperatives.
Murray also urges certain etymological considerations: the Latin
educare means to lead out, to raise up, whereas the Greek paidagogia
means the leading of a slave or child. Thus the term 'pedagogy' seems to
be connected with ideas of training and discipline with the purpose of
developing the well-formed person. We are accustomed, perhaps, to
thinking of the aims of pedagogy as directed to certain 'micro-ends',
relating to individual discipline, comportment and norms of presenta-
tion. Nevertheless, what we are being invited to consider is an extended
meaning to 'pedagogy' so that the term incorporates the idea of training
for political, social and economic ends.
It is all too easy to see how the distinction has a reverberation today:
we need only examine the methods used to raise education standards to
realise very swiftly that what is involved is an exercise in pedagogy,
with specific means employed to hit identifiable targets. The importance
for the teacher of producing evidence of learning so that assessment
criteria can be applied-learning which has been deliberately structured
pre- cisely so that it can be assessed and monitored-shows us why so
many teachers are unhappy. They are no longer teachers or lecturers but
mere pedagogues. The introduction of the National Curriculum in
© The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain
Education or Pedagogy 33
England

© The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain


34 G. Hinchliffe
and Wales has reduced considerably the scope of teachers to engender
creative and critical learning. Teachers at all levels-but especially those
subject to the greatest scrutiny of all, namely primary-level teachers-
may well feel that the pupil or student who attains a level of critical
awareness will not even have this recognised, just because it is not
something that is currently measured. In other words, the very things
that education is supposed to produce-critical awareness, creativity, an
imaginative response-simply do not count for anything very much
from the standpoint of pedagogical considerations and, indeed, may
very well count against the student.
Yet the view just sketched could be seen as merely a response to
recent events, and one which relies on a number of well-worn contrasts:
creativity/regimentation, freedom/discipline, critical/conformist. If the
pedagogy/education contrast simply amounts to yet another contrast of
the same order then it must be doubted that it could ever advance our
understanding even though it may be welcome as another weapon in the
embattled teacher's armoury of counter-offensive rhetoric.
And indeed, the distinction could be questioned on a number of
counts. In the first place, it must be fairly clear that historically a great
deal of what has been termed 'education' has had little to do with
'leading out' children or students and everything to do with training and
discipline. Must we now accept that we have been misusing the term and
start to get into the habit of calling the bulk of what goes on in our
schools and colleges pedagogy rather than education? If not, is anyone
seriously going to maintain that prior, say, to the introduction of the
National Curriculum there was a regime of education and freedom until
the government came along and squashed everything with its pedagogy?
But perhaps the distinction may turn on a more traditional contrast
between academic and vocational instruction so that the term 'pedagogy'
cleaves to the vocational. If this is accepted then are we supposed to
admit that critical awareness and creativity can be achieved by philo-
sophers and scientists but not by chefs, engineers or doctors? For if this
is all the distinction amounts too then it turns out to be rather
uninteresting. We are all familiar with the claims of those who wish to
protect liberal learning and its accompanying venerable humanism from
the depredations of 'training'. In any case, it seems perfectly reasonable
to say that one needs to be trained in the right way if one wants to
become a philosopher or a historian, implying a pedagogy right at the
heart of liberal learning itself. And to confuse matters still further, was it
not Michael Oakeshott, passionate defender of liberal learning, who
eloquently spoke of his army instructor teaching him that gymnastics
could be an 'intellectual art'?

And if you were to ask me the circumstances in which patience, accuracy,


elegance and style first dawned upon me, I would have to say that I did
not come to recognise them in literature, in argument or in geometrical
proof until I had first recognised them elsewhere; and that I owed this
recognition to a Sergeant gymnastics instructor who lived long before the

© The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain


Education or Pedagogy 35
days of 'physical education' and for whom gymnastics was an
intellectual art-and I owed it to him, not on account of anything he
ever said, but because he was a man of patience, accuracy, economy,
elegance and style. (Oakeshott, 1967, p. 176)

Does the distinction between education and pedagogy make any


sense from a political perspective? This may seem promising for it
might be that the distinction, if embedded in wider concepts, may
both give those concepts an extra content and take on a wider
meaning as a result. Take, for example, Louis Althusser's idea of the
ISA-'Ideological State Apparatus'-which he introduced in order to
specify the 'relative autonomy' of the Marxian concept of the
superstructure (Althusser, 1971, pp. 151-152). Undoubtedly,
pedagogy fits squarely into an ISA, but where does this leave
education? Are we to conclude that education is that form of politics,
in the Althusserian scheme of things, which conducts revolutionary
struggle against the ruling class? Or do we conclude that education
exists in a misty world over and beyond the reality of the ISA-not to
mention the RSA (Repressive State Apparatus)? Althusser might
have replied that 'education' is merely pedagogy trying to convince
itself that it is free from all those determinants which produce
pedagogy; a delusional pedagogy which thinks of itself as soaring in
the sky whilst only succeeding in affirming the very power of
ideology.
But could we, nevertheless, view pedagogy's relation to truth as
essentially strategic? Consider, for example, Oswyn Murray's
statement that 'Isocratean pedagogy is incompatible with freedom,
whereas Platonic philosophy, with its emphasis on truth wherever it
may lead, is indeed the path to freedom'. Leaving aside the
questionable relation between truth and freedom in Plato (for
whom, surely more than for any other philosopher, the path to
truth had its own imperatives and requirements compared to which
the demands of freedom were irrelevant) could we say, then, that
education (but not pedagogy) enables us to pursue truth wherever it
may lead? But such truths can only be recognised and
acknowledged in terms of the practices governing activity in the
classroom or seminar room: and this amounts to subject- ing truth to
a pedagogic interrogation. It is difficult, that is, to see how such
practices are likely to generate 'truths' which somehow surmount the
very conditions in which they arise. On this argument, therefore, the
distinction amounts to very little, perhaps little more than one of
style. Perhaps, then, the distinction could be defended along the
following lines. Pedagogy relates to those social, economic and
political require- ments which a state requires from its education
system; pedagogy addresses those skills which society needs. But an
element of education is needed to complement all this; and what
education does is to focus on the needs and development of the
individual. Education, then, is 'person-centred', and focuses on the
personal development of the individual, whilst pedagogy sees to the
© The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain
36 G. Hinchliffe
social and economic role which that individual might play. (I have in
mind the ideas of Carl Rogers (see

© The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain


Education or Pedagogy 37

Rogers, 1983, pp. 283-296) though, of course, Rogers himself would


have had nothing to do with pedagogy at all in any form, believing that
education, in the way he understood it, could achieve all learning goals.)
Education and pedagogy are not exclusive but complementary. But this
approach really seems to be just wishful thinking; for if pedagogy is
dominant then the kind of individual qualities to be developed and
encouraged are precisely those suitable for a social and economic role.
On the other hand, if an education is genuinely person-centred then it is
difficult to see how pedagogic demands can be met properly without
making very big assumptions about the fit between personal well-being
and social efficiency (it is just this sort of assumption that Rogers seems
to make). In any case, one could just as easily reverse the application of
the terms, so that pedagogy becomes the training and disciplining of the
person (with a suitable element of self-training and self-discipline to
satisfy liberal claims for autonomy) whilst education concerns itself with
the macro-issue of knowledge.
It seems, then, that there is no easy, consistent way to apply the
distinction between education and pedagogy. I propose, therefore, to put
on one side how the two terms are actually used or might be used in
order to examine possible conceptual contrasts. One that immediately
suggests itself is this: pedagogy views learning instrumentally whereas
education views learning for its own sake.

THE ARISTOTELIAN ARGUMENT


This kind of contrast appears in Aristotle's Politics (see Aristotle, 1948),
where learning which is needed to produce the necessities of life is
compared to the kind of learning needed for a life of leisure. Aristotle
contrasts leisure (schole-) with war and action: 'It is true that citizens
must be able to lead a life of action and war; but they must be even more
able to lead a life of leisure and peace' (Politics, p. 373). Leisure implies
self-directed, reflective activity. He contrasts leisure with work, saying
that 'the growth of goodness and the pursuit of political activities' is
bound to be inhibited by any mechanical (banausos) occupation which
'keeps men's minds too much and too meanly occupied' (Politics,
p. 393). Aristotle also states that leisure is the end to which occupation
is directed, but nowhere does he suggest that work is the kind of pursuit
which is both worthy in itself and worthy as a means to an end. He is
disinclined to give work or occupation any independent value at all.
Consequently, the kind of learning which a citizen should undertake is
of the kind which brings about the cultivation of the mind (Politics,
p. 395). For only then will persons be able to develop the virtues,
including the crucial virtue of practical wisdom ( phrone-sis) which will
enable them to lead a full life as a citizen.
I do not wish to pursue at length Aristotle's view that mechanical
or menial occupations make one unfit to be a citizen. For one thing,
of course, this view was contradicted by the experience of Athenian
democracy itself when citizenship was extended to all Athenian-born

© The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain


38 G. Hinchliffe
males. Moreover, Aristotle himself concedes that not all menial work
makes a person's character menial and even grants that such work is
permissible when it is for a 'fine end', for example, when one performs a
service for a friend (see Politics, pp. 371, 393). There seems no reason
why this could not be generalised to include any kind of 'menial' task
which provides for the comforts of citizens. Nor is it clear that the
performer of such tasks could not be included within the ambit of
citizenship providing he or she had enough time to devote to leisure
(Irwin, 1988, pp. 414-416).
The key point is that, once we make allowance for all these local
historical features it looks as though there is a real argument here for
a distinction between the kind of education which is for its own sake
and the kind of education which is not. And the argument is that
education-'cultivation of the mind'-is the kind of activity which
brings about and sustains rational activity and which, indeed, can be
considered as one facet of rational activity. The argument takes on
depth once we are aware of the connotations of 'rational activity' in
the Aristotelian scheme of things. For it is the kind of activity which
needs other rational agents in order to complete it, which needs the
political space afforded by the polis for it to exhibit its public
dimension and which requires a shared acknowledgement of those
values which sustain the common good of a shared life. By contrast
with this, then, we get an education-or rather pedagogy-governed by
narrow ends and driven by a conception of humankind as precisely
not destined to a live a public, shared life amongst equals. This kind
of contrast is, of course, the kernel of the version of Aristotelianism
which was developed by Hannah Arendt, amongst others.
One possible objection to this viewpoint is that it does not give
enough weight to those occupation-related activities of which Aristotle
was so dismissive. It might be urged that working with modern
technology, for example, transforms lives and yields the kind of satis-
factions, both personal and social, of which Aristotle could not have
possibly known. But this objection cannot, I think, be sustained. For the
Aristotelian argument precisely puts all this into question by asking
what kind of worth these satisfactions could possibly have. If they are
the kind of satisfactions associated with work or privacy then they
cannot possibly be accorded a high valuation, because they are not
expressions of full rational activity in the Aristotelian sense. On this line
of reasoning, then, the knowledge associated with technology belongs to
the public domain (in exactly the same way as scientific knowledge) but
technology-related occupations are still essentially instrumental in
nature. Therefore the mere assertion of the value of occupations does
nothing to alter their secondary status with regard to the public realm.
Another objection is more serious and addresses the way in which
rational activity is seen by Aristotle in terms of its finality as far as
human ends are concerned. Rational activity is seen as a natural feature
of human kind. This emerges clearly in the Nicomachean Ethics
(Aristotle, 1980, 1097b22-1098a18) when Aristotle asks what the

© The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain


Education or Pedagogy 39

'function' of man is, declaring that there must be one in just the same
way that the eye's function is that of seeing. His conclusion that man's
function is that of rational activity implies that it is a natural, non-
negotiable end of human kind. We discover what our ends and purposes
are as human beings and through this discovery we can then realise our
own true natures. Those whose powers of discovery are deficient are not
complete human beings. This is why slaves deserved their fate, a fate of
enslavement being fitting for humans lacking self-mastery.
The point to these observations lies in the suspicion that all learning,
including the learning of citizens, may end up being pedagogic rather
than educative. Is this simply because the kind of learning Aristotle has
in mind is simply a means to an end, the end here being citizenship?
This thought, I believe, accounts for part of the suspicion. For
though it is true that the life of a citizen involves wider and more
varied concerns than a life solely concerned with business occupations,
one still needs to be trained and fashioned for citizenship. The fact that
one's horizon's are much wider qua citizen need not, of itself, prevent
the kind of learning at issue being pedagogic in character. We
observed earlier on that pedagogy can be seen as learning which
serves political ends. On this definition, it does not matter if those
ends are of an impeccably democratic kind: what we have is still
pedagogy rather than education. But there are further considerations
which strengthen the suspicion that what we are dealing with here is,
after all, a species of pedagogy. These arise from the observations
made with respect to the way in which rational activity is made a
natural, functional quality of human kind. For what is striking about
Aristotle is the way in which he advocates the development of rational
powers but not really a critique of those powers. There is lacking in
Aristotle the element of reflexivity, of reason's awareness of itself and
of its willingness to put itself into question. And maybe it is just this
that differentiates pedagogy from education. Pedagogy is always sure
of itself, it always knows where it is going and it takes for granted that
what it takes to be knowledge really is knowledge. Pedagogy, by its
very nature, can never be self-critical. Of course, pedagogy will-
especially these days-emphasise the need for students and learners to
develop critical powers. But these powers of critique are ultimately
concerned with developing the learner in a certain direction so as to
develop the appropriate personal qualities of creativity, adapt- ability
and flexibility. What pedagogy can never do is develop a radical
critique of itself and its aims.
I want to suggest that what can be said of pedagogy can be said in the
same way of an Aristotelian concept of education. It too does not carry
within itself a critique of its own aims. It too is oriented towards the
production of a certain type of individual whose character and comport-
ment serve ends of a socio-political nature. Of course, we might well
prefer the ends that such an education serves, compared with those of
pedagogy. For example, it seems indubitable that education is more
likely to produce a type of character with a broader range of concerns
and sensibilities than pedagogy ever could. If one accepts the

© The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain


40 G. Hinchliffe
Aristotelian concept of rational activity then this apparently gives one
good reason to suppose that education is indeed different from and
ultimately superior to, pedagogy. My suggestion, however, is that
because the Aristotelian notion of rational activity lacks the element of
self-critical knowing, the contrast between pedagogy and education
cannot be drawn strongly enough.
By contrast with the Aristotelian conception, could there be a
different concept of education which flows from the idea that rational
activity itself could be self-critical? This would imply that what is
distinctive about education is that it is willing to put itself into question.
It is willing to ask whether the knowledge it is concerned with really is
knowledge and what it presumes to be of value really is of value. But
how could education do this? If we construe all the activities related to
the concept of education as a form of practice, then my question is: How
can a practice call itself into question and still remain a practice? Before
I go on to consider this question, we need first of all to consider the
nature of a practice.

OAKESHOTT'S CONCEPT OF A PRACTICE


The concept of a practice lies at the heart of Michael Oakeshott's On
Human Conduct and helps us to make a decisive contrast between
education and pedagogy. Moreover, correctly understood, Oakeshott's
concept of a practice takes us beyond the Aristotelian notion of rational
activity. It therefore helps us to understand the idea of education as a
practice which questions its own foundations and which, indeed, holds
out the possibility of doing without foundations altogether.
Any conduct which amounts to a form of transaction between human
beings may be considered as a form of practice: 'A practice may be
identified as a set of considerations, manner, uses, observances,
customs, standards, canons, maxims, principles, rules and offices
specifying useful procedures or denoting obligations or duties which
relate to human actions and utterances' (Oakeshott, 1975, p. 55). A
practice, then, consists of those meanings which agents acknowledge in
acting. These meanings may be formally codified in terms of prescribed
procedures or they may amount to unwritten understandings. For
example, the con- dition of 'neighbourliness' denotes the kind of
understandings accepted by agents insofar as they are related to each
other in the capacity of neighbours. As such, in recognising themselves
as 'neighbours', agents subscribe to certain conditions which govern the
character of relations which holds between neighbours. These conditions
pertain to respect for privacy, sensibilities concerning the acceptable
boundaries of intrusion, appropriate concern for the other's welfare and
security, and so on.
A vital aspect of Oakeshott's theory is that the conditions or terms of
a practice have to be learned. This need not imply formal conditions of
learning; rather it denotes that the terms of a practice, encapsulated as
they are in a series of meanings, must be understood. Whether this
understanding is reflective, deliberate or intuitive; whether it takes a

© The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain


Education or Pedagogy 41

lifetime or a few seconds to achieve; and whether this understanding is


imperfect or incomplete-all these considerations merely reflect the fact
that learning can take many different forms. But whatever form this
learning takes, it is exhibited by a recognised capacity to deploy these
meanings insofar as and whenever one agent relates to another. There is,
for Oakeshott, no such thing as social conditioning if by this term is
meant that agents reach certain understandings without ever learning
them. Thus crime-related behaviour associated with the life of some
juveniles on run-down housing estates has to be learned just as much as
do the very different protocols of conduct at an old-fashioned finishing
school for young ladies.
Another feature of a practice is that it imposes upon an agent no
demands that he or she should think certain thoughts or adopt certain
sentiments. And although Oakeshott does not anywhere discuss at
length the idea of a degenerate practice, it would appear that a practice
becomes degenerate at the moment when the agency of persons is
denied or diminished. Regimes which impose on their unfortunate
victims requirements that they should have certain beliefs do not, in this
respect, amount to a practice. For Oakeshott, a practice 'is an instrument
to be played upon, not a tune to be played . . . the requirements of a
practice are not obeyed or disobeyed; they are subscribed to or not
subscribed to' (ibid., p. 58). But it should be noted that agency for
Oakeshott, is not to be seen as the expression of 'choice' emanating from
a sovereign free will. Rather, agency can only be manifested and
expressed within the terms of a practice.
No logical priority or privileged status attaches to the concept of a
subject. Subjects do not 'support' practices. Rather, the condition of
being a 'subject' (supposing we take concept of a subject in the liberal
sense of a rational, autonomous person) is itself something which arises
through and is constituted by the terms of a practice. To acknowledge
oneself as rational and autonomous, and as the self-directed author of
one's actions, is indeed a recognisable feature of certain discourses since
the Enlightenment. But such a conception goes well beyond Oakeshott's
idea of agency. For agents may well subscribe to a practice which is
disinclined to recognise the claims of individual autonomy (such as
certain collectivist experimental communities which insist that the
claims of community come before any individual claims) whilst still
retaining their agency.
Now, Oakeshott claims that there are two types of practice. There is
the kind of practice which amounts to 'a prudential art concerned with
the success of the enterprises of agents'; but there is also the kind of
practice which has no extrinsic purpose as far as the satisfaction of
wants is concerned and which amounts to 'the practice of agency without
further specification' (ibid., p. 60).
A prudential art may, of course, take on a number of different forms.
Perhaps the self-help texts written by Dale Carnegie on how to make
one's life a success now belong to a different era; but in any event they
have only been replaced by a host of prescriptions, texts and courses

© The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain


42 G. Hinchliffe
designed to achieve for their users a range of benefits from undreamed-
of physical pleasures on the one hand to advice on how to balance the
competing claims from home and work on the other. A self-help manual
teaches a prudential art, and an individual may read it in privacy; but if
he or she joins up with other individuals in order to advance some
mutually-sought satisfactions then they will have brought into existence
what Oakeshott terms an 'enterprise association'. He describes this as
follows:

Agents thus related may be believers in a common faith and concerned


or not concerned to propagate it, or they may be partners in a
productive undertaking (a bassoon factory); they may be comrades or
allies in the promotion of a 'cause'; they may be joined in belonging to
the same profession or in having the same trade; . . . they may
comprise an army, a 'village community', a sect, a fellowship, a party,
a fraternity, a sodality, a collegium or a guild'. (ibid., p. 114)

But whatever form the enterprise association takes, agents are related in
terms of a common substantive purpose. However, we must not suppose
that the decisions and actions of particular persons in an enterprise
association are anything more than only contingently connected with the
common purpose of the association. Oakeshott does not suppose that
each individual has permanently within his or her sights the common
purpose of the association. Hence there is a need for some kind of
managerial engagement which attempts, either well or badly, to relate
individual decisions to the overall purpose and well-being of the
association. It need scarcely be added that the precise character of this
management is not dictated by the concept of the enterprise association
itself, and therefore the managerial role can take many different forms,
including a democratic one.
But the type of practice which most interests Oakeshott (though he
freely conceded the importance of enterprise associations) is the kind
where there is not an extrinsic substantial purpose to the practice.
This type of practice is typified above all by what is termed as ars
artium, namely a morality. Because a morality is not governed by a
substantive purpose, it cannot prescribe performances. Nevertheless,
it is by means of a practice that agents can undertake certain
performances in certain circumstances, and can devise for
themselves rules of conduct. Oakeshott says that a practice must be
understood as a series of adverbial quali- fications of conduct; and
action may be said to be done considerately, kindly, gracefully or
charmlessly. And he defines a moral relationship as one 'solely in
respect of conditions to be subscribed to in seeking the satisfaction of
any want' (ibid., p. 62). These conditions could be thought of as
meanings and interpretations which may be shared or contested but
which are nonetheless understood. For Oakeshott, it is precisely the
lack of a common substantive purpose which enables a practice to be
used and explored by persons. It is through a practice that we
become agents.
© The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain
Education or Pedagogy 43

For ease of terminology, let me refer to the practices associated with


enterprise associations as 'instrumental practices' and the kind of
practice construed along the lines of a morality as an 'open practice'.
For Oakeshott, the distinction has ramifications which go well beyond
its conceptual origins. Briefly, there is a tendency for open practices to
be converted into instrumental practices. This tendency is a permanent
feature of modernity-that is to say the 'long' concept of modernity as a
period with us since the seventeenth century. For example, Oakeshott
identifies Francis Bacon as one of the early villains, since it was he who
advocated the usefulness of learning and its role in 'the relief of man's
estate' (see Fuller, 1989, p. 75). For Oakeshott, by contrast, education
belongs very firmly in the realm of an open practice, since it is an
endeavour which has no extrinsic purposes or goals but is an activity of
understanding pursued for its own sake. The understanding that is
yielded is one which refers to those meanings and interpretations which
constitute not just the world of culture and knowledge but the human
world itself. Education is an engagement in learning how to live, how to
be human. In particular, education and learning initiate the student or
pupil into an understanding of the terms which must be subscribed to if
one is to articulate choices and decisions and to reveal one's self-identity
(Fuller, 1989, pp. 63-73).
The relevance of Oakeshott's distinction between the two kinds of
practice to thinking about education and pedagogy should now start to
become clear. If learning is construed as a pedagogy then it takes on the
characteristics of an instrumental practice. This seems to fit in with the
term as it is used customarily, that is to denote a range of techniques and
styles designed to achieve some desirable outcome. Indeed, it may seem
perfectly proper to talk of pedagogic techniques when considering how a
particular piece of learning is to be achieved. However, the suggestion is
that the term 'pedagogy' can be used to refer to the whole of teaching
and learning where this is construed along the lines of an instrumental
practice. In accordance with Oakeshott's ideas, this would mean not
only according education an 'extrinsic goal' (to achieve better employ-
ability, to raise the economic performance of the nation, to produce
well-disciplined and trained citizens, and so on) but also the 'manage-
ment' of that goal: namely a range of procedures, rules and prescriptions
which are all designed to ensure that individual actions of both teacher
and learner tend to contribute to those external goals.

A SELF-CRITICAL PRACTICE
Oakeshott's account of a practice helps us to get to a position where we
can understand the pedagogy/education contrast rather more deeply.
It seems superior to the account of the contrast provided by the
Aristotelian interpretation because it is less dependent on local historical
factors (such as the structure of the Greek polis, the position of the
aristocracy, the cultural status of skilled work). But how does the idea of
an open practice help us to go beyond the Aristotelian idea of rational

© The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain


44 G. Hinchliffe
activity? For it is easy-too easy-to see Oakeshott's concept of an open
practice as nothing more than a deepening and refinement of the
Aristotelian idea. But as long as this is thought to be the case then the
pedagogy/education contrast will be conceived in a conservative way.
Oakeshott used the distinction between instrumental and open practices
to mount (amongst many of his concerns) a sophisticated defence of
liberal learning. The problem for us, today, is that liberal learning is too
closely linked with elitist institutions and practices which have the
luxury of being able to keep the world at bay, a luxury increasingly
denied to most. Now, if we can push the idea of an open practice a bit
further to include the idea of a practice which contains its own self-
questioning at its very heart we shall be able to furnish a concept of
education for which the pedagogy/education contrast is still pertinent
but which recasts the concept of education in a radical direction, thus
escaping the position of being an easy target of criticism that liberal
learning has turned out to be.
It will be recalled that the specification of an open practice is that
agents subscribe to the terms of the practice. A practice is the condi-
tions of human engagement, without prescribing beliefs and actions.
Oakeshott's prime concern was to identify the conditions under which
agency could flourish and to show how education could be considered as
an initiation into an understanding of those terms. But to what extent
can the terms themselves be subject to questioning and critique? When
directed to the open practice that is education, this question addresses
the terms of educational engagement. We are therefore led to an enquiry
into the nature of a practice which is not merely content to use its terms
in differing ways but also seeks to interrogate those terms themselves.
What kind of practice would education be if it interrogated its own
terms? In part, it would be one in which current meanings and inter-
pretations are discussed and evaluated and where some are to be
considered as more salient than others. It is also a practice in which the
term 'knowledge' is scrutinised: for example, the distinction between
'new' and 'traditionally accepted' knowledge would be expected to shift.
And we might also expect shifts in emphasis in how the relation
'student- teacher' is perceived and performed. But over and above all this
there is another dimension to education considered as an open practice:
in the questioning of the very terms that constitute it, this is a practice
which self-consciously re-constitutes itself as a practice. Consequently,
the terms of this practice are authoritative only provisionally. In this
sense, the practice of education is closer to aesthetic pursuits than to a
morality, for in the latter the authority of its terms is taken to be
enduring, and questioned only in extremis.
In thinking through the idea of a practice which interrogates its own
terms it may be tempting to cite the well-known metaphor of rebuilding
a ship at sea, but this can be misleading on two counts. First, the terms
of a practice do not amount to anything like as cohesive and interlocking
as the fabric of a ship; and second, the critique of terms need not be
undertaken with a view to constructing a fresh set of terms. Agents in an

© The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain


Education or Pedagogy 45

open practice are not like architects and they do not have a blueprint
of a new building in front of them as they set about demolishing the
old one. It would be better to think of a practice as having no internal
structure and no centre. Thus the questioning of terms should not
imply that agents are unduly motivated to build up an entirely new
set of terms. They are not inspired to build an even bigger and better
practice. Since the 'end' of this practice is nothing more than the
critique of its terms, such a 'new' or 'superior' practice would itself be
immediately subject to the most searching interrogation.
Since we are dealing here with the recycling of interpretations and the
creation of new meanings, it must not be thought that proposed under-
standings must submit immediately to the full rigour of evidential
requirements. For whilst, in the course of certain activities, evidence is
required in order to help us decide what it is that counts as knowledge,
this requirement must be handled with care lest interesting and (who
knows) fruitful lines of enquiry are suppressed at birth. The use of
evidence can also have a controlling and even policing function which
though entirely appropriate in the sphere of pedagogy (because of the
way in which learning must be demonstrated to be fit or adequate to
some purpose) may easily have an inhibiting effect when misapplied in
the context of an open practice.
Oakeshott also draws our attention to the emancipatory possibilities
of an open practice in the following way:

An educational engagement is at once a discipline and a release; and it


is one by virtue of being the other. It is a difficult engagement of
learning by study in a continuous and exacting re-direction of attention
and refinement of understanding which calls for humility, patience and
courage. Its reward is an emancipation from the mere 'fact of living', from
the immediate contingencies of place and time of birth, from the tyranny
of the moment and from the servitude of the merely current condition.
(Fuller, 1989, p. 93)

But it should be noted that these emancipatory possibilities do not


espouse notions like 'self-empowerment' or 'self-development', both of
which can be perfectly catered for by pedagogy. The possibility of a
release from the 'servitude of the merely current condition' is precisely a
release from the kind of self which pedagogy constructs in its own
image. This is a self which is nothing unless equipped with plans and
goals in its search for opportunities and challenges. It is the kind of self
which mistakes the purposelessness of an open practice for confusion
and indolence calling for a strategy of rectification.

CONCLUSION
Oakeshott's emphasis tended to be placed on the opening up and
recovery of existing or past understandings. Yet if an open practice is to
have within itself that element of self-criticism, as I have suggested, then

© The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain


46 G. Hinchliffe
it also needs to create and invent different kinds of learning. The idea of
the bricoleur evokes something of what is meant here. It will be recalled
that Claude Le' vi-Strauss explained how myths were formed through the
bricolage metaphor, in which the mythmaker gathers up elements of
existing myths, combining them in new and different ways. Of course,
the bricoleur is constrained by the signs which lie to hand, and Le' vi-
Strauss makes it clear that the activities of the mythmaker are not to be
confused with that of the 'engineer' who, by dint of the concepts he uses,
'is always trying to go beyond the constraints imposed by a particular
state of civilisation' (Le' vi-Strauss, 1972, p. 19). But, says Le' vi-Strauss
(ibid., p. 22), there are some advantages to the bricoleur approach:

Mythical thought for its part is imprisoned in the events and experiences
which it never tires of ordering and re-ordering in its search to find them a
meaning. But it also acts as a liberator by its protest against the idea that
anything can be meaningless with which science at first resigned itself to
a compromise.

In this spirit, in which both the engineer and the bricoleur have a role, I
propose the following:

• The continued questioning of the division of knowledge into


traditional subject areas (bearing in mind that interdisciplinary
subject areas can take on the guise of a traditional subject after a
few years).
• Reflection on how the creation of new skills, and the redeployment
of old skills, can help open up new areas of knowledge (e.g. the
way that computer-based and televisual graphics have helped to
open up the new knowledge-domain of the 'virtual').
• The deliberate 'recovery' of historically out-moded practices in
order to provide fresh perspectives (e.g. the way in which Foucault,
e.g. 1988, pp. 39-68, tried to suggest an 'ethics of care' by going
back to accounts from antiquity of a fashioning and stylistics of the
self).
• A deliberate undermining of the 'education/vocational'
distinction, especially by introducing theoretical components
into vocational training (e.g. modules in chef training courses on
the History of Taste, French/Italian language, Food as Signifier
in Poetry and the Novel, etc.)

Oakeshott thought that the corruption of education by instrumental


practices was an historic disaster which during the course of the
twentieth century gathered increasing pace. We need not trouble
ourselves with his explanation of how this came to pass, because, I
think, he was mistaken to think that education ever was in an unsullied
state. The imperatives of pedagogy, it could be said, have always been a
part of education, though what may count as such an imperative in one
period may be viewed as an untrammelled luxury in another (e.g.
compare the role played by the

© The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain


Education or Pedagogy 45

classics one hundred years ago with that played today). What Oakeshott
never seemed to countenance was that instrumental and open practices
could both be embedded within certain institutional settings. He was
unable to see this since he held that education, considered as an open
practice, must be pursued in its own location-'School'-set apart from
the pressures and cares of economic life. Whether this was ever
historically the case is a difficult question which I cannot pursue here.
But the suggestion that instrumental and open practices can be pursued
together in the same institutional-even departmental setting-does not
seem far-fetched.
Moreover, it seems inevitable that the profile of pedagogy will be
raised in proportion as the number of students in higher education
increases. The way to deal with this, I have suggested, is not to defend a
retrenched position of liberal learning but to adopt an openly self-critical
position as to what counts as knowledge and learning. In this way,
attempts to formulate sets of expectations and outcomes in the
pedagogic endeavour of ensuring a 'fitness for purpose' will never be
complete. If education is to survive, it must keep ahead of the game.

Correspondence: Geoffrey Hinchliffe, Department of Continuing


Education, University of East Anglia, NR4 7TJ, UK. E-mail:
G.Hinchliffe@uea.ac.uk

REFERENCES
Althusser, L. (1971) Lenin and Philosophy, trans. Ben Brewster (London, New Left Books)
Aristotle (1948) Politics, trans. Sir Ernest Barker (Oxford, Clarendon Press)
Aristotle (1980) Nicomachean Ethics, trans. D. Ross (Oxford, Oxford University Press)
Foucault, M. (1988) Care of the Self (Harmondsworth, Penguin)
Fuller, T. (ed.) (1989) The Voice of Liberal Learning: Michael Oakeshott on Education (Princeton,
NJ, Yale University Press)
Irwin, T. H. (1988) Aristotle's First Principles (Oxford, Clarendon Press)
Le' vi-Strauss, Claude (1972) The Savage Mind (London, Weidenfeld & Nicolson)
Murray, O. (1999) The voice of Isocrates, Times Literary Supplement, August 6th, pp. 3-4
Oakeshott, M. (1967) Learning and teaching, in: R. S. Peters (ed.) The Concept of Education
(London, Routledge & Kegan Paul)
Oakeshott, M. (1975) On Human Conduct (Oxford, Clarendon Press)
Rogers, Carl (1983) Freedom to Learn (Columbus, OH, Merrill)
Too, Yun Lee and Livingston, N. (1998) Pedagogy and Power (Cambridge, Cambridge University
Press)

© The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain 2001.

View publication stats

You might also like