You are on page 1of 11

Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 50 (2015) 43–53

Contents lists available at ScienceDirect

Studies in History and Philosophy


of Modern Physics
journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/shpsb

Dissecting weak discernibility of quanta


Tomasz Bigaj a,b
a
University of Warsaw, Institute of Philosophy, Warsaw, Poland
b
Department of Philosophy, University of California, San Diego, La Jolla, CA, USA

art ic l e i nf o a b s t r a c t

Article history: In this paper I critically examine latest attempts to formalize quantum-mechanical relations that are
Received 8 October 2014 supposed to weakly discern elementary particles. I argue that all of them make illegitimate and
Received in revised form unavoidable reference to numerical identity, and therefore cannot be used as a means to ground (or
6 February 2015
derive) quantitative facts of identity/distinctness in the qualitative characteristics of quantum systems.
Accepted 18 February 2015
I compare my criticism of weak discernibility with the general circularity objection known from the
Available online 17 March 2015
literature, and I show that my argument is more specific, as it is based on a particular criterion which
Keywords: differentiates between legitimate and illegitimate uses of identity. In the end I suggest that we should
Weak discernibility reevaluate the role of permutation invariance in expressing the facts of qualitative differences between
Identity
particles. Taking into account the inevitable symmetrization requirement applied to operators in tensor
Individuality
product spaces, it may be claimed that particles of the same type can be absolutely discerned in some
Elementary particles
accessible states.
& 2015 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.

When citing this paper, please use the full journal title Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics

1. The weak discernibility program: an overview Before we plunge into a detailed exegesis of the technical
aspects of the WD program, it may be appropriate to remind the
It has been more than 10 years since the emergence of the idea reader of the historical development of this approach. For the
to exploit the logical concept of weak discernibility in discussions purpose of bookkeeping I suggest distinguishing four stages of
on the ontological status of quantum particles. During these years development of the WD program. The first stage, which may be
the original suggestion has grown into a full-blown metaphysical called Promising beginnings, is associated with the name of Simon
program aiming at deriving useful lessons regarding the identity Saunders. At the time when the dominating view among physicists
and individuality of fundamental entities from our best physical and philosophers had been that the PII is violated in quantum
theories, and making connections with other far-reaching meta- mechanics, and that quanta most probably lack any individuality
physical programs, such as ontic structuralism. In this critical due to their indiscernibility, Saunders had the audacity to go
survey I would like to focus on some technical aspects of weak against the flow and argue that there is a largely forgotten sense of
discernibility in the context of non-relativistic quantum theory. discernibility which may be applicable even to elementary parti-
One of the main conclusions of my analysis will be that the weak cles (Saunders, 2003, 2006). Saunders rediscovered the Hilbert–
discernibility (WD) program applied to quanta is actually incap- Bernays method of defining identity using qualitative predicates
able of reaching all of its ambitious goals. The weak discernibility only, and argued that Quine’s weak discriminability on which this
claims advanced with respect to quantum particles of the same method is implicitly based is attainable for fermions of the same
type (bosons and fermions) are toothless as a tool for establishing type. Fermions in antisymmetric states can be discerned by the
interesting metaphysical conclusions regarding their status relation of having opposite spins, and therefore are legitimate
as full-fledged objects, and regarding the validity of non-trivial objects. On the other hand, bosons in symmetric product states
metaphysical principles, such as the Principle of the Identity of remain utterly indiscernible, and as such can be interpreted as
Indiscernibles. aggregates only.
The second stage of the program, which I refer to as Sharpening
the arguments is marked by the arrival of Fred A. Muller on the
E-mail addresses: t.f.bigaj@uw.edu.pl, tfbigaj@gmail.com scene. Many critics of Saunders’ early attempts to weakly discern

http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsb.2015.02.003
1355-2198/& 2015 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.
44 T. Bigaj / Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 50 (2015) 43–53

fermions pointed out that it is strictly speaking incorrect to claim preferred metaphysics of relationals, and as such does not extend
that the relation of having opposite spins can connect two to all forms of PII, only the ones based on relational discernibility.
fermions in the singlet state, since individual particles do not The third adduced reason is that PII supplies us with clear identity
possess any precise values of spin. In order to repel similar criteria. This observation is echoed by Saunders in (2003, pp. 289–
objections, Muller and Saunders (2008) joined forces and made 291), where he stresses that the truth of the PII enables us to
an effort to develop a technically rigorous and conceptually sound reduce numerical identity to qualitative facts, and therefore
method of weakly discerning fermions in all admissible states eliminates the need for identity as a primitive predicate. Saunders
using categorical (i.e. non-probabilistic) properties only. In this insists that while in general there is nothing wrong with identity
approach bosons remained at a slight disadvantage, since their taken as primitive, in the context of physics it is better to see it as
discernibility was achieved only with the help of probabilistic derivative. He points out that physical objects are known to us
relations. However, in a follow-up paper Muller and Seevinck through descriptions as objects of predications, and not as some
(2009) strengthened even this claim, showing how to discern formal constructs. Thus descriptions in terms of pure physical
fermions, bosons and any other particles in terms of eigenvalues of properties should enable us to recognize objects of physical
particular quantities, and hence categorically. theories as entities numerically distinct from one another.
After this major victory, the program took a sharp Metaphysical I hope it would not be a gross distortion of the WD program to
turn, and therefore entered its third stage, punctuated by two sum up the above ideas as follows. We need the validity of (some
papers (Muller, 2011, 2015). In them, the technical results achieved form of) PII, because we want to be able to ground facts regarding
in the previous phase are elevated to the status of sweeping numerical distinctness (numerical identity) of objects in some
metaphysical claims about the ultimate nature of physical reality qualitative facts pertaining to their arrangements.4 And the pos-
and its governing principles. Muller abandons the traditional sibility of achieving such grounding (or reduction, to use another
dichotomy between individuals and non-individuals, introducing fashionable term) in a principled manner can ensure some
a third category of entities: relationals. Fundamental objects in important metaphysical conclusions regarding the status of the
physical theories are determined by the relations they participate entities in question (that they are objects, or individuals, or at least
in, and this gives support to the broad structuralist stance. On the relationals). Moreover, specific methods of achieving the required
other hand, far from being committed to the trash heap of history grounding can give support to independent metaphysical claims,
by the development of quantum mechanics, PII actually receives a such as the claim of the ontological primacy of relations (struc-
boost and comes out victorious as one of the most scientifically tures) over objects, commonly known as ontic structuralism.5
justified metaphysical principles. The notion of discernibility figuring in the formulation of PII
I suggest that the fourth stage in the development of the WD admits various interpretations.6 The standard version of PII
program be identified with Friendly criticism done by authors who employs discernibility by properties, typically referred to as
do not question the main goal and general results of the program absolute. The two other grades of discernibility are: relative and
but notice some gaps in the arguments by Muller, Saunders and weak discernibility. Two objects are relatively discernible if there
Seevinck that need to be filled out.1 Two recent papers by Adam is a relation that connects them in one direction but not the other.7
Caulton (2013) and Nick Huggett and Josh Norton (2014) are Weakly discerning relations, on the other hand, are such that they
representative of this stage.2 Both papers aim at improving rather hold between two distinct objects, but do not hold between an
than rejecting the WD program by selecting new discerning object and itself. Note that from this characterization it trivially
relations that are better suited for the task. Later in the text we follows that if objects a and b are weakly discerned by relation R,
will discuss the details of these critiques, and we will see that they must be distinct entities: aa b. This fact may be seen as the
some of the objections raised in them reveal much more serious formal basis of the grounding claim: the non-qualitative fact that a
problems with the WD program which cannot be easily remedied and b are numerically distinct can be reduced to (or inferred from)
by simply choosing a new discerning quantity. the fact that they are connected by the qualitative relation R.
The ostensible goal of the WD program is to rehabilitate the However, we should keep in mind that the grounding is successful
Principle of the Identity of the Indiscernibles, which has fallen on
hard times in quantum mechanics.3 This in itself is a worthy
4
undertaking. However, one can ask why we should be so keen to In my Bigaj (2015) I point out that there is yet another possible use that PII
can be put to: it can namely help distinguish one object from the rest of the
save the venerable Leibnizian principle, if not out of the respect for universe in a way which makes it possible to uniquely refer to it. I argue that weak
one of the greatest minds in philosophy and science. The PII tells discernibility is incapable of reaching this goal; however, there are grades of
us, in rough outline, that all numerically distinct objects have to discernibility weaker than absolute but stronger than weak discernibility that may
differ qualitatively from one another (this is what we usually mean achieve such identification of objects.
5
I admit that some pronouncements of the proponents of the WD program can
by “discernibility”). Muller (2015) formulates three reasons why
be interpreted as claims of a more methodological than metaphysical character.
we should care about such a claim. The first reason given by That is, the existence of weakly discerning relations may be seen as ensuring that
Muller is not so much a motivation why we should want PII to be facts regarding numerical identity and distinctness can be derived from empirical,
true, as an explanation of why we should not ignore it if it is qualitative statements, without presupposing that the latter facts ground the
indeed true (“because it teaches us an ontological lesson” is the former. However, my subsequent criticism of the WD program can easily be
showed to apply to its methodological interpretation as well. If, as I claim it to
submitted answer). The second reason is associated with Muller’s be the case, the relations used to weakly discern quantum particles make
inescapable reference to numerical identity, the derivation of the non-qualitative
facts of identity from qualitative facts involving weakly discerning relations is
1
In my current exposition of the WD program I largely ignore the not-so- circular. Thus, in order to argue that particles a and b are numerically distinct, we
friendly criticism of weak discernibility advanced e.g. by Hawley (2006, 2009), have to presuppose the very fact we want to establish.
6
French & Krause (2006), van Fraassen & Peschard (2008), Dieks & Versteegh (2008), For recent logical analyses of the variety of grades of discernibility see
and Ladyman & Bigaj (2010). However, some echoes of these critiques will Ketland (2011), Caulton & Butterfield (2012), Ladyman, Linnebo, & Pettigrew (2012)
reverberate later in the text, mostly in Section 5. and Bigaj (2014).
2 7
It should be added here that Caulton no longer supports the WD program Huggett & Norton in (2014, p. 40) mistakenly define relative discernibility of
(private communication). See footnote 19 for reference to his latest unpublished objects a and b by the formula ( ℛ, c ℛ(a, c) 4 ℛ(b, c). This formula can be actually
work on the problem of discernibility of quantum particles. proven to be equivalent to weak discernibility (under the assumption that variable
3
Some of the key authors responsible for exposing the apparent plight of PII in ℛ ranges over all two-place formulas definable in given language). I am grateful to
QM are Margenau (1944), French & Redhead (1988), Giuntini & Mittelstaedt (1989), Chris Wüthrich for bringing that error to my attention and for a subsequent
Redhead & Teller (1992), and Butterfield (1993). discussion.
T. Bigaj / Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 50 (2015) 43–53 45

Pd
only if the used relation R is a legitimate one. In particular, P ijð1Þ P ð2Þ
ij Pj ψ  〉 ¼ i;j ¼ 1 P ð2Þ ð1Þ
ij P ij j ψ  〉 ¼ 2j ψ  〉. From this it can be
reduction fails if R itself contains numerical identity as an essential
concluded that the relation R–2 weakly discerns fermions, since
component. In such a case an inference of the statement of
the following is the case: :R  2 ð1; 1Þ, :R  2 ð2; 2Þ and R  2 ð1; 2Þ,
numerical distinctness a ab from the fact that R(a, b) is clearly
R  2 ð2; 1Þ.
circular.
The result achieved above does not extend to bosons, because
the operator (6) does not act on symmetric states as a multiple of
the identity. Muller and Saunders suggest using a probabilistic
2. Weakly discerning relations in quantum mechanics
weakly discerning relation for bosons, but their theorem to the
effect that weak probabilistic discernibility of bosons is attainable
In this section I will give a brief outline of the details of the
has been superseded by the later and stronger result presented in
weakly discerning methods used by Muller, Saunders and See-
Muller and Seevinck (2009), to which we will turn now.
vinck, starting with Muller and Saunders’ 2008 paper. They begin
Muller and Seevinck make a surprisingly strong claim, announ-
their construction by selecting a complete set of one-dimensional
cing that they can define perfectly legitimate quantum–theoretical
orthogonal projectors Pi in a single-particle Hilbert space ℋ, i.e.
P relations which categorically discern particles in any joint states
such that P i ¼ I and P i P j ¼ δij P i . Using the family of projectors Pi,
whatsoever, not limited to symmetric or antisymmetric ones. They
they introduce operators of the form Pij ¼Pi Pj. In the case when
consider two cases: spinless particles with infinitely-dimensional
the number of identical particles is assumed to be 2, the states of
state spaces, and particles characterized by spin states defined in
composite systems are represented by vectors (or, more generally,
finitely-dimensional Hilbert spaces. In the first case they consider
density operators) in the tensor product ℋ  ℋ. The operator Pij
the position Q and momentum P of each individual particle.
when applied to the first particle will have the form P ijð1Þ ¼ P ij  I,
Limiting ourselves to the case of two particles we can introduce
while P ð2Þ
ij ¼ I  P ij will represent the same property of the second the usual notation:
particle. With the help of these notions we can now define the
following binary relation on the set of particles: P ð1Þ ¼ P  I; P ð2Þ ¼ I  P;
X
d
Q ð1Þ ¼ Q  I; Q ð2Þ ¼ I  Q ;
Rt ðx; yÞ iff P ðxÞ ðyÞ
ij P ij j ψ 〉 ¼ tj ψ 〉 ð1Þ
i;j ¼ 1
and then define relation C:
where tA ℝ. As should be clear from the above formula, relation Rt h i
is supposed to hold between objects x and y iff the system is in an C ðx; yÞ iff P ðxÞ ; Q ðyÞ j ψ 〉 ¼ cj ψ 〉 for some c a 0: ð7Þ
P
eigenstate for the operator di;j ¼ 1 P ijðxÞ P ðyÞ
ij with the corresponding The relation C can be presented informally as “The commutator
eigenvalue equal t. This, given the standard interpretation of the
of x’s momentum and y’s position is a non-zero number”. The
quantum formalism, reflects the fact that the system possesses the
standard commutation relation between the position and momen-
definite value t of the property described by the operator.
tum of a given particle implies that [P(1), Q(1)] ¼[P(2), Q(2)] ¼–iħI  I.
For complete clarity we have to explain how to interpret the
P On the other hand, the position of one particle commutes with the
formula di;j ¼ 1 P ðxÞ ðyÞ
ij P ij . In the most general case when the number momentum of another particle, thus [P(1), Q(2)] ¼[P(2), Q(1)] ¼0.
of particles equals n, the above shorthand expression can be From these facts and definition (7) it follows immediately that
expanded as follows: C(1, 1), C(1, 2), :C(1, 2), :C(2, 1), and consequently :C(x, y) weakly
X
d d 
X   discerns particles 1 and 2. It has to be stressed that this fact is
P ijðxÞ P ðyÞ
ij ¼ I  …  P ðijxÞ  …  I I  …  P ðijyÞ  …  I ; independent of the exact form of the state |ψ〉, therefore weak
i;j ¼ 1 i;j ¼ 1 discernibility holds for any particles in any state.
ð2Þ For particles with spin sa0 there is yet another option
available to weakly discern them. We start with the definition of
where variables x and y indicate that the xth and the yth places in
the spin for a single particle (with a spin number assumed to be s)
the n-fold tensor product are occupied by appropriate one-particle
as S¼ Sx þSy þSz, where Sx, Sy, and Sz are spin components in
operators. In particular, when n ¼ 2, we end up with two distinct
directions x, y, z. As usual, spins characterizing separate particles in
possibilities:
a two-particle system will be represented by appropriate tensor
X
d X
d X
d
products with the identity as one component:
P ð1Þ ð2Þ
ij P ij ¼ P ð2Þ ð1Þ
ij P ij ¼ P ijð1Þ  P ð2Þ
ij ð3Þ
i;j ¼ 1 i;j ¼ 1 i;j ¼ 1 S1 ¼ S  I

X
d X
d S2 ¼ I  S:
P ð1Þ ð1Þ
ij P ij ¼ ðP ðij1Þ Þ2  I ð4Þ
i;j ¼ 1 i;j ¼ 1
The weakly discerning relation is defined as follows:
 2
It is relatively easy to check that the following equalities hold: T ðx; yÞ iff Sx þ Sy  j ψ 〉 ¼ 4sðs þ 1Þħ2 j ψ 〉 ð8Þ
X
d X
d
P ð1Þ ð1Þ
ij P ij ¼ P ð2Þ ð2Þ
ij P ij ¼ 2ðd  1ÞI  I ð5Þ Note that subscripts x and y in (8) indicate variables ranging
i;j ¼ 1 i;j ¼ 1
over particles to be discerned, and not directions in space. Two
! particles can be said to be connected by relation T iff they are in a
X
d X
d X
d
P ð1Þ ð2Þ
ij P ij ¼ P ð2Þ ð1Þ
ij P ij ¼ 2 Pi  Pi  I  I ð6Þ joint state such that their total spin squared takes on a definite
i;j ¼ 1 i;j ¼ 1 i¼1 value equal 4s(sþ1)ħ2. In order to see that it is possible to weakly
discern particles with the help of relation T we should recall first
When the considered state j ψ  〉 of the system belongs to the
that the square of a single’s particle spin is a multiple of the
antisymmetric section ℋ– of the tensor product of Hilbert spaces,
Pd identity: |S|2 ¼s(s þ1) I, and therefore relation T holds between any
the result of the action of the part i ¼ 1 P i  P i of operator (6) particle and itself. On the other hand, when the particles are
equals zero, and hence we have the following equations: distinct, we have |S1 þS2|2 ¼2s(s þ1)ħ2I  I þ2S  S. This implies
Pd ð1Þ ð1Þ Pd ð2Þ ð2Þ Pd
i;j ¼ 1 P ij P ij ψ  〉 ¼ i;j ¼ 1 P ij P ij ψ  〉 ¼ 2ðd  1Þj ψ  〉 and i;j ¼ 1 that the eigenvalues of |S1 þS2|2 never exceed 2s(2s þ1)ħ2, which
46 T. Bigaj / Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 50 (2015) 43–53

is less than 4s(sþ 1)ħ2. Therefore relation T never holds between a well. But they do not formulate any specific demands regarding
pair of distinct particles, and T weakly discerns them. the operators and states used in physically meaningful formulas.
Weak discernibility done with the help of relations R–2 (Def. 1) Thus it seems that any Hermitian (self-adjoint) operator defined in
and C (Def. 7) has the nice feature of relying entirely on facts an appropriate Hilbert space should be acceptable as a means to
involving possessing definite values of a particular physical quan- discern particles.
tity (being in an eigenstate for the corresponding operator). As With respect to the condition of Permutation Invariance, its
explained above, the fact that the relation R–2 holds between two official formulation places the restriction of being invariant under
objects means that the system is in an eigenstate of the operator permutations on the discerning relation only. However, the
(2) with the corresponding eigenvalue equal –2. On the other discussion given by Muller and Saunders may suggest a stronger
hand, what underlies the cases for which R–2 does not hold is the interpretation: the operators and states used to construct a
fact that the system is in an eigenstate for the operator (2) but discerning relation should obey the postulate of permutation
with a different eigenvalue (equal 2(d  1)). The situation with the invariance as well. Of course the latter condition implies that the
relation C is analogous, with positive instances of the relation discerning relation will be symmetric, but a symmetric relation
being associated with the eigenvalue –iħ, and negative instances could also be built out of non-permutation-invariant operators.
corresponding to the eigenvalue 0. Consequently, we can adopt a As we will soon see, the distinction between a weak and a strong
minimalistic interpretation of quantum mechanics and still retain interpretation of Permutation Invariance will play a central role in
the needed discernibility result. This minimalistic interpretation the latest friendly critiques of Muller and Saunders and Muller and
assumes only that being in an eigenstate implies possessing the Seevinck.
corresponding eigenvalue (the less controversial half of the eigen- In spite of the apparent care with which Muller, Saunders and
value/eigenvector link), and that one observable cannot possess Seevinck treat the issue of the physical meaningfulness of dis-
two distinct values simultaneously. cernment, it has become the focal point of the critiques delivered
In comparison, relation T (Def. 8) requires stronger assumptions by Caulton (2013), and by Huggett and Norton (2014). Both papers
in order to successfully discern particles. While cases in which a center their objections around the observation that the relations
pair of particles exemplifies T are instances where the assembly is used to weakly discern elementary particle fall short of being
in an eigenstate of the squared total spin operator, nevertheless physically meaningful despite claims to the contrary. Two reasons
particles that do not stand in relation T do not usually possess a are adduced to support this evaluation: (1) the violation of the
definite value of the selected quantity. This means that we have to condition of permutation invariance, and (2) the inappropriate use
assume the full e/e link,8 in order to conclude from the fact that a of multiples of the identity. We will consider these objections
system is not in an eigenstate that it does not possess the in turn.
corresponding eigenvalue. Huggett and Norton direct their criticism entirely against the
relation Rt defined in Muller and Saunders (2008). They point out
P
that the operator di;j ¼ 1 P ðxÞ ðyÞ
ij P ij violates the condition of permuta-
tion invariance when the number of particles is greater than or
3. Friendly criticism equal 3. This can be clearly seen when we look at formula (2).
Applying any permutation that exchanges particle x with any
Most critics stress that the results presented by Muller & particle other than y will get us a different operator. Huggett and
Saunders and Muller & Seevinck are mathematically unassailable. Norton admit that this problem does not affect cases in which we
However, the exact physical and philosophical meaning of these limit ourselves to antisymmetric, fermionic states, for in such
technical results remains open to debate. Admittedly, Muller and cases, thanks to Eqs. (5) and (6), our operators reduce to multiples
Saunders go to great lengths to prove that the relation of weak of the products of the identity, which are obviously permutation
discernibility introduced in their paper satisfies the condition of invariant. However, they point out that operators (2) clearly act in
physicality, and Muller and Seevinck follow suit. To facilitate this an asymmetric way in the subspace of bosonic (symmetric) states.
task, Muller and Saunders explicitly introduce two conditions of They give a simple example showing that the subspace of sym-
physical admissibility: Physical Meaning and Permutation Invar- metric states ℋ þ is not invariant under the action of operators of
iance (2008, pp. 527–528). Physical Meaning requires that all type (2), and therefore they do not count as operators on ℋ þ . As a
properties and relations used to discern objects should be “trans- consequence, the admittance of such operators makes it theore-
parently defined in terms of physical states and operators that tically possible to devise measurements which could produce
correspond to physical magnitudes”. Permutation Invariance, on bosons in non-symmetric states, and that is clearly non-physical.
the other hand, stipulates that relations used to discern particles It may be observed that this does not mean that the relation
ought to be permutation invariant, which in the case of binary Rt(x, y), defined with the help of the non-symmetric operators
Pd ðxÞ ðyÞ
relations means their symmetricity.9 i;j ¼ 1 P ij P ij , is itself non-symmetric. The symmetricity of Rt(x, y)
In their discussion preceding the formulation of the two is ensured by the straightforward fact that the permutations
conditions of physical admissibility, Muller and Saunders give exchanging x and y preserve the operators in question. Thus
some more detailed explanations of how to understand Physical Muller and Saunders’ Permutation Invariance in its weaker form
Meaning and Permutation Invariance. Regarding the “transparent” is still satisfied. But Huggett and Norton have a point in claiming
method of defining discerning properties and relations in terms of that the condition of physicality may require a stronger inter-
physical states and operators, their emphasis is placed squarely on pretation of Permutation Invariance. Caulton in his critical analysis
negative instances. That is, they insist that no labeling predicates makes a similar point regarding the symmetricity of operators
(as opposed to labels themselves) should be used in physical used to weakly discern particles. He uses an analogous argument
discernment. Similarly, purely mathematical or formal concepts, not only against the relation Rt, but also against the relations
such as being a member of a particular set, are to be excluded as introduced by Muller and Seevinck, or at least their relation C.
However, his specific remarks on that topic are slightly baffling.
8
It may be worthwhile to spend some time pondering over their
Muller & Saunders (2008, p. 513) refer to the full e/e link as the Strong
Property Postulate, and the one-way implication mentioned above as the Weak
exact meaning.
Property Postulate. At first glance it looks like Caulton favors a super-strong
9
Both conditions are repeated verbatim in Muller & Seevinck (2009, p. 185). interpretation of Permutation Invariance, according to which not
T. Bigaj / Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 50 (2015) 43–53 47

only the entire operator used directly to weakly discern particles, that the identity operator does not represent any physically
but its components (“building blocks”) as well, should remain significant property due to its “triviality”. Caulton similarly agrees
invariant under arbitrary permutations. Here is a fragment from with the triviality claim, noting that the identity operators corre-
his paper confirming this stance: spond to experimental questions that yield the same answer on
every physical state (p. 56). And yet Eqs. (5) and (6) clearly show
But Rt is defined in terms of nonsymmetric projectors Pi  I, and P
that the operators di;j ¼ 1 P ðxÞ ðyÞ
ij P ij are multiples of the identity when
so forth. And it is compulsory—that is a necessary condition for applied to antisymmetric states. Thus the relation Rt does not
representing a physical quantity—that the quantities obey the seem to be physically meaningful.
Indistinguishability Postulate (IP), which demands that all Remaining on a rather general level of analysis one may
physical quantities be permutation invariant (p. 55—I changed complain that the charge of triviality should be distinguished
the original notation for consistency). from the charge of non-physicality. It does not seem inconsistent
Pd ðxÞ ðyÞ to claim that a trivial concept is nevertheless physically mean-
Later in the text Caulton admits that quantities i;j ¼ 1 P ij P ij
are symmetric (provided that the number of particles equals 2, as ingful. I do not see anything unphysical in asking an experimental
we can recall from Huggett and Norton’s analysis), but he still question of the sort “What is the probability that the spin of this
insists that they are not admissible, because electron will be either þ or –?”, as such a question clearly admits
an experimental procedure aiming at answering it, even though
…the physical significance of these quantities was supposed to the answer is already well known in advance. This question is
rest on their being constructions out of quantities like Pi I, yet clearly more physical than asking whether this electron bears label
it is precisely these quantities that run afoul of IP (p. 56, again 1 or 2. Thus in my opinion Huggett and Norton’s objection should
my change in notation).10 not be construed as showing that the relation Rt does not satisfy
Muller and Saunders’ requirement of physical meaningfulness, but
Caulton forcefully repeats the same charge with respect to the rather as suggesting the need for a third requirement (Non-
relation C, pointing out that it is defined in terms of inadmissible, triviality), separate from the original two. But what can justify
non-symmetric operators P(x), Q(y). However, in a surprising twist such a need?
he refuses to apply the same criticism to the third weakly Here both Huggett with Norton and Caulton give an interesting
discernible relation T (Def. 8). While noting that the definition of argument, based on the specific method of defining the weakly
T employs unacceptable non-symmetric operators Sx and Sy, he discerning relation R–2. They observe that because of Eqs. (5) and
nevertheless states that his usual objection does not hold in this (6) the relation R–2 when applied to fermions can be restated as
case. The reason for this assessment that he provides is that “it follows:
seems reasonable to take T(x, y) as a natural physical relation”
(p. 59). This is so, because T can be easily parsed in English as the R–2 ðx; yÞ iff ðx ¼ y and 2ðd–1Þj ψ〉 ¼ –2j ψ〉Þ or ðx ay
relation involving the combined total spin of two particles, which
and –2j ψ〉 ¼ –2j ψ〉Þ; ð9Þ
is symmetric and has obvious physical significance.
I cannot say that I am entirely clear on the difference between which, in turn, can be reformulated in an even simpler way as
relations C and T with respect to the applicability of the super-
strong requirement of permutation invariance. Why cannot we R–2 ðx; yÞ iff ðx ¼ y and 2 ðd–1Þ ¼ –2Þ or ðx ay and –2 ¼ –2Þ:
give an analogous argument to the effect that C should be exempt ð10Þ
from the requirement exactly as T is supposed to be? After all, the
relation C(x, y) can be parsed in English as “the commutator of x’s This is clearly a non-physical relation, as there is not a single
momentum and y’s position equals –iħ”, and the commutator is term on the rhs of the equivalence which would refer to any
symmetric. Without further insight into the meaning of the term physical property of discerned particles whatsoever. Note that
“a physically significant quantity” it is hard to say whether the even reference to the physical state |ψ〉 of the system is missing
commutator of position and momentum (which in the case of one from the formula. Essentially, what we have here is a disjunction
particle reduces to a multiple of the identity) is a physically whose components contain identities/non-identities and trivial
significant quantity. (Later we will see that Huggett and Norton arithmetic equalities. Discernment by such a relation should
consider all quantities of that type physically inadmissible.). evidently be disallowed.
However, it may be pointed out that the requirement of super- I entirely agree with this assessment, even though I think the
strong permutation invariance is in itself rather implausible. Based problem we have just discovered runs much deeper than the mere
on such a requirement we would have to exclude symmetrized triviality issue. But for the time being let us play along. We can
operators of the form ð1=2ÞðA  I þ I  AÞ, which are clearly built observe that exactly the same problem affects the discerning
out of non-symmetric components A I and I  A, and this looks relation C, as its definition can be reformulated analogously as
too extreme, as they have a clear physical interpretation (we will
see that later in the text). So I suggest that we adhere to the C ðx; yÞ iff ðx ¼ y and –iħ a 0Þ or ðx a y and 0 a 0Þ: ð11Þ
original requirement introduced by Huggett and Norton that the However, with respect to relation T the situation looks differ-
whole operator (and not its components) used in the definition of ent. Here the operator defining T (the total spin squared |Sx þSy|2)
a weakly discerning relation ought to be permutation invariant. is a multiple of the identity only when x ¼y. In the remaining cases
And it has to be admitted that this requirement is violated by all the operator acts differently on different symmetric and antisym-
three relations Rt, C, and T when the number of particles is greater metric states. This fact is actually responsible for the above-
than 2. discussed need to invoke a non-minimalistic interpretation of
Let us now move on to the second type of criticism. Huggett quantum mechanics which accepts both implications of the e/e
and Norton observe that not all operators definable on an appro- link. However, it turns out that the very same feature can protect
priate state space represent meaningful physical quantities, even if us now against the threat of triviality.
the condition of symmetricity is satisfied. For instance, they insist To sum up, all three proposals of how to weakly discern
elementary particles turn out to be open to some serious objec-
10
A similar thought occurs also in (Huggett & Norton, 2014, p. 48), but they do tions. Now it is the time to evaluate the alternative solutions put
not make it a focal point of their criticism. forward by the critics themselves.
48 T. Bigaj / Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 50 (2015) 43–53

4. Alternative proposals arbitrary fermionic states, and they admit that they do not know
whether an alternative procedure of weak discernment by a
Following their criticism of Muller, Saunders and Seevinck, relation of the form (14) exists. On the other hand, Huggett and
both teams of authors wheel out their own preferred methods of Norton prove that the relation St defined for any A¼ B does not
discerning elementary particles. However, they clearly decide to go discern bosons in symmetric product states. This is a consequence
in different directions. Huggett and Norton’s strategy can be seen of the fact that if such a state is an eigenstate of (13), it has to be an
as more radical, while Caulton essentially repeats the standard eigenstate for (12) with the same eigenvalue.13
approach of Muller, Saunders and Seevinck with a slightly differ- There is a clear trade-off between the scope of Huggett and
ent choice of the main operator on which the discerning relation is Norton’s discernibility result on the one hand and the purported
based. In their novel approach, Huggett and Norton opt to ensure superiority of their applied method. While the achieved discern-
the satisfaction of the strong Permutation Invariance by comple- ibility of quanta is much more limited in scope than that
tely symmetrizing the appropriate operators. But such a move has announced by Muller and Seevinck, supposedly the used method
one unwelcome consequence: namely, it eliminates any reference should be impervious to any possible objections by obstinate
to specific particles x and y from the definition of such operators. critics of weak discernibility. But is it really? I agree that Huggett
How, then, can we construct a formula in two variables Φ(x, y) out and Norton’s own standards of a proper physically discerning
of expressions that do not even contain any variables? The relation are indeed satisfied by their proposed definition (14).
solution submitted by Huggett and Norton is to make use of the However, in some important respects the suggested strategy may
formulas of the kind given in (9)–(11), with the trivial arithmetic be argued to be inferior to the original ones. In all truthfulness,
equalities replaced by legitimate physical conditions. the only real benefit of Huggett and Norton’s new proposal that I
More specifically, Huggett and Norton consider two arbitrary can think of is that it (unintentionally) draws our attention to a
Hermitian operators representing meaningful physical quantities A serious but so far neglected conceptual problem that afflicts to a
and B. If we wanted to formally represent the fact that A is a certain degree all known attempts to weakly discern quantum
property of particle x while B is a property of particle y, we would objects. Here is what I mean.
have to use non-symmetric operators of the form I  …  A  … One of the most conspicuous features of definition (14) is that it
 B  …  I. But Huggett and Norton insist that we have to characterizes the weakly discerning relation St in terms of two
properly symmetrize such operators to satisfy the Invariance separate conditions, one of which is applied when the considered
Principle. However, this cannot be done at one stroke—we have objects are identical, while the other when they are distinct. This
to consider separately cases when x¼y and cases when xay.11 As immediately raises the worry that we are defining here not one
a result we obtain the following two fully symmetric operators: relation but two distinct relations only artificially conjoined in a
disjunctive manner. A similar objection is briefly considered by
1X
ðAB  I  …  IÞ ð12Þ Caulton in his analysis of the relation Rt, when he discusses its
np A P
disjunctive definitions of the form (9) and (10). Recognizing the
and possibility of an opposition from a critic he rushes to explain that:

1 X
  ðA  B  I  …  IÞ; ð13Þ so long as we have a definition of the Rt in terms of quantities
n pAP
2 that seem (i.e. from the point of view of the syntax) to treat the
2 x ¼y and x ay cases equally, the fact that a different quantity
where the summation is done over the set of all permutations of n (…) underlies each of these two cases is tolerable (p. 57).
particles. Now we can define the weakly discerning relation as
follows: In other words, provided that we have the original definition
! (1) of Rt at our disposal, there is nothing wrong in reformulating it
P in terms of a disjunction. But note that this condition is not
St ðx; yÞ iff x ¼ y4 1n ðAB  I  …  IÞj ψ 〉Þ ¼ tj ψ 〉 3
pAP satisfied in Huggett and Norton’s case. There is no alternative,
0 1 uniform way of characterizing the relation St which would not
B C consider the separate cases x ¼y and xay. Even more curiously,
B 1 X C
Bx a y4   ðA  B  I  …  IÞ ¼ tj ψ 〉C ð14Þ the conditions corresponding to these cases do not mention
@ n pAP A objects x and y at all (this is a direct consequence of the
2
2 symmetrization procedure applied beforehand). Thus it looks like,
Relation St weakly discerns two objects in cases when the speaking metaphorically, the only formulas that do any discerning
eigenequation in the first disjunct of the rhs of (14) is false while jobs in (14) are the identities x ¼y and x ay. From a logical point of
the second eigenequation is true.12 Thus in order to discern view, any two conditions T and F such that one is true while the
particles occupying a joint state |ψ〉 we have to find two Hermitian other is false would do equally well. The expression “(x ¼y and F)
operators A and B such that |ψ〉 is an eigenstate for both operators or (x ay and T)” weakly discerns objects, but it does so in a purely
(12) and (13) but with different corresponding eigenvalues. Hug- formal and quite trivial way, regardless of what fancy restrictions
gett and Norton show how this can be done under the assumption we impose on the mathematical and physical meaning of condi-
that |ψ〉 is a fermionic state obtained by antisymmetrizing a direct tions T and F. The only strategy that could rescue such a
product of orthogonal vectors (in their proposal they assume A disjunctive characterization is proving that T and F are actually
and B to be identical). However, their result does not extend to instances of one and the same condition Φ(x, y) applied, respec-
tively, to the cases x ay and x ¼y. But this is not an option for the
relation St.
11
This is a telltale sign of a very significant underlying fact, and I do not want
the reader to miss it. We will return to this issue soon.
12 13
Note that the reference to the selected particles x and y that was initially One may note in passing that, logically, Huggett and Norton’s result obtained
included in the description of the quantities A and B has now been completely lost for symmetric product states is rather weak, as it shows only that one particular
due to the symmetrization procedure. This is striking, since as a result the only method fails to achieve weak discernibility in that case. This of course falls short of
remaining occurrence of variables x and y in formula (14) is in the context of the proving generally that there is no method of weak discernment for bosons in
identity relation. We will return to this problem soon. product states that satisfies the conditions imposed by Huggett and Norton.
T. Bigaj / Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 50 (2015) 43–53 49

It has to be admitted that Huggett and Norton acknowledge the discerning relation V has clear physical meaning that does not
existence of the above-mentioned difficulty in the context of the depend on A(1) and A(2) having physical meaning as separate
original relation Rt. But they are strangely dismissive about the entities. This may be so, but it turns out that definition (17) has
whole issue, noting only that “[we don’t] see any problem with one fatal flaw which is closely related to the earlier discussed
constructing sensible relations in this way [i.e. disjunctively]” (p. problem afflicting Huggett and Norton’s definition (14). To see that
8). However, they slightly misidentify the problem as being mostly let us reformulate (17) in a disjunctive form as follows:
about creating legitimate properties using disjunctions. In fact, the    
V ðx; yÞ iff x; y and ΔA j ψ 〉 a0 or x ¼ y and 0j ψ 〉 a 0 : ð18Þ
2
problem is, primarily, that in order to introduce relation St we have
to make use of the identity symbol, and in a way which seems to
be essential (indispensable). And this in turn shatters any hope of The fact that such a reformulation is possible is in itself incon-
using the weak discernibility of quanta in any metaphysically sequential, as long as the physical conditions attached to the cases
meaningful way, for instance as the qualitative basis for grounding x¼ y and x ay can be seen as instances of the same physical
their numerical distinctness and their individualities. If we are property of the system. But here lies the rub: it may be argued that
happy with weakly discerning relations of the form (14), then why the trivially false inequality 0 a0 associated with the x ¼y case
cannot we go all the way and accept weak discernibility by the does not represent the same type of physical condition as the
inequality ΔA j ψ 〉 a 0. The operator ΔA measures dispersion
2 2
relation x ay? As I argued above, the fact that we conjoin the x ¼y
and xa y cases with meaningful physical conditions is a red between the values of the same quantity for two particles. But in
herring—the real job of weak discernment is done entirely by order to measure the dispersion of the value of a quantity for a
the identity relation. single particle we do not use the trivial zero operator
2
4 ðA  I  A  IÞ . Instead, we resort to the earlier defined opera-
1
One important lesson that can be drawn from the above
analysis of Huggett and Norton’s weakly discerning relation is tor (A  〈A〉)2, and it is an elementary fact that if the state of a single
that we have to beware of the inappropriate use of the identity particle is not an eigenstate for A, its dispersion is non-zero in such
relation while formulating such relations. And under closer scru- a state. Thus the formula V(x, y) does not represent a single,
tiny it may be discovered that even the original proposal of a physical relation, but rather a gerrymandered entity consisting of
weakly discerning relation by Muller and Saunders is not entirely two unrelated relations conjoined with the help of the identity
free from a similar problem. But before we get to this point, let us relation.
briefly review Caulton’s alternative strategy of weakly discerning But what is with the intuition of “measuring anticorrelations”
quantum particles. His idea is to use the well-known concept of between eigenstates? I think that the terminology used by Caulton is
the variance (dispersion) of a given quantity A, which is commonly misleading. To see this more clearly, let us consider an example of a
defined as the expectation value of the following quantity: symmetric product state of two bosons |φ〉|φ〉. What anticorrela-
(ΔA)2 ¼(A  〈A〉)2 (see Sakurai & Napolitano, 2011, pp. 33–34). tions can be present in such a symmetric state? The only reason that
the operator ΔA can assume a non-zero expectation value in such a
2
It can be easily verified that the dispersion of A can be alternatively
presented as 〈(ΔA)2〉¼〈A2〉 〈A〉2. Caulton uses this familiar con- state is that |φ〉 may not be an eigenvector for A, and hence the states
cept to measure the anticorrelations between eigenvalues of A for of individual particles are not dispersion-free for A. But this is
two particles. He introduces the variance of a quantity A as an precisely the same reason why A is not dispersion-free in a single-
operator (q-number, not a c-number): particle state |φ〉. If we used the proper concept of dispersion for both
cases x¼y and xay, we would have to come to the conclusion that
1
Δ2A ¼ ðA  I  I  AÞ2 ð15Þ the appropriately defined relation does not discern weakly at all.
4
Defining a new operator A as a measure of the statistical mean of
A: 5. Weak discernibility and identity
A ¼ 12 ðA  I þ I  AÞ ð16Þ
2
As should be clear now, the critical feature of weakly discerning
it can be quickly calculated that Δ ¼ A  A , which justifies the
2 2
A relations, on which their admissibility should depend, is the use of
term “variance”. Moreover, it can be observed that if |φi〉 and |φj〉 the identity relation. But we have to be more precise as to what
are eigenvectors of A with eigenvalues equal, respectively, to ai and uses of identity should be banned from weakly discerning rela-
aj, then the product |φi〉  |φj〉 will be an eigenvector of ΔA , and its
2
tions. The key term here is “essential”: all non-essential uses of
corresponding eigenvalue will be 1=4(ai  aj)2. identity may be permitted. An obvious example of a non-essential
The idea to use the above-introduced notion of the variance of use is as follows: we can always present a legitimate weakly
a quantity A as a means to weakly discern particles is based on the discerning relation R(x, y) in the form of the disjunction (x¼ y and
observation that the anticorrelation between eigenstates for a R(x, x)) or (xa y and R(x, y)). But no one should be bothered by
single particle is always equal to zero. Hence the discerning such artificial and easily eliminable reference to identity. However,
relation can be defined as follows: the general distinction between essential and non-essential uses
ðxÞ ðyÞ 2 of identity is not easy to draw, and we have to proceed with care in
V ðx; yÞ iff 4 ðA A Þ j
1
ψ 〉 a 0; ð17Þ
order not to exclude otherwise acceptable instances of weak
(x)
where A is defined in the usual way as either A  I or I  A, discernibility. I would like to stress first that, in contradistinction
depending on whether x equals 1 or 2. Note that when x ay, the to some authors who criticize weak discernibility en bloc, I am
rhs of (17) reduces to Δ2A j ψ〉 a 0. On the other hand, with x¼ y we willing to grant that there are legitimate, acceptable cases in
get the zero operator acting on the vector j ψ 〉. The weak discern- which two entities may be said to have acquired their numerical
ment by the relation V is guaranteed if we can find for all joint distinctness (and objecthood) via an appropriately selected weakly
states j ψ 〉 a physical quantity A whose dispersion in j ψ 〉 is non- discerning relation connecting the two. The case of Max Black’s
zero. And, as Caulton argues, this can be done thanks to the fact spheres, weakly discerned by the relation “being 5 feet apart” is a
that no particle state is dispersion-free with respect to both prime example of such a situation. The existence of the relation of
position and momentum. spatial separation ensures that there are two objects and not one,
Caulton insists that the use of nonsymmetric components A(x) even though we are still unable to label them individually, or make
and A(y) in (17) is not a problem, since the quantity used in the reference to one and not the other.
50 T. Bigaj / Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 50 (2015) 43–53

Some critics of weak discernibility argue that all attempts to languages. But I believe that it would be unfair to hold this fact
weakly discern two objects inevitably fall victim to the problem of against the proponents of weak discernibility. The use of the
circularity.14 That is, in order to apply a weakly discerning relation identity symbol in general, abstract characterizations of the con-
we have to make sure that there are indeed two objects and not cepts we apply to weakly discern seems to me rather innocuous.
one, and therefore we have to find a way to discern them before- What is problematic is when we resort to the facts of identity/
hand. Or, to put it differently, we have to include the fact that the distinctness when applying a weakly discerning relation to a
two objects are numerically distinct in our description of the particular, concrete case. If we have to know that a specific object
arrangement to which we will subsequently apply the weak x is distinct from an object y before we can apply a weakly
discernibility strategy. But I do not see why this has to be the discerning relation to x and y, the procedure becomes unaccep-
case. Let us consider the Black’s spheres scenario again. We can table. Of course we have to keep in mind that the notion of
describe it as neutrally as possible in the following way: consider a acceptability used here is a relative one. What we mean in this
universe in which there is nothing more than a sphere x with context is that weak discernment achieved in such an “unaccep-
such-and-such dimensions, weight, chemical structure etc., and a table” way does not have any interesting metaphysical conse-
sphere y qualitatively indistinguishable from x. At this point I do quences regarding the status of the objects in question. Yet from a
not decide whether x is distinct from y: they may very well turn formal perspective even discerning objects directly with the help
out to be one and the same object, in which case no trouble for PII of the relation x ay is as good as any other discernment. But I take
arises. But now I introduce one more element to my description: x it that the proponents of the WD program are interested not in
and y are 5 feet apart. Bingo! Now we know that there are two merely “formal” discernment but something metaphysically more
spheres, and the reason we know this is precisely because the substantial.
relation of being 5 feet apart is weakly discerning! To put it in
metaphysical terms, the quantitative fact regarding the numerical
distinctness of x and y has emerged out of the qualitative and 6. Some generalizations
relational fact involving the non-zero distance between x and y.15
But a critic may insist that the relation of being separated by a I will now try to spell out the procedure of weak physical
non-zero distance used in the above example still hides some discernment in more general terms capable of covering the
inappropriate reference to identity. It may be argued for instance specific cases presented so far. The aim of this exercise is to draw
that the reason why such a relation is capable of weakly discerning a reasonably clear line between acceptable and unacceptable
objects in the first place is that ultimately the formal characteristic forms of weakly discerning relations, following the general dis-
of the distance between points contains as one of its axioms the cussion in the previous section.
postulate that the distance between points x and y is zero if and The procedures described in earlier sections can be subsumed
only if x is identical with y. Without the notion of identity we under the following general pattern. The starting point is a
would not be able to properly introduce the mathematical notion definition of a mapping σ : P  P-ℳ from ordered pairs of
of metric, or distance. Does that mean that discerning objects with physical entities to mathematical objects of a particular kind.
the help of their spatial separation is inadmissible? The object σ(i, j)A ℳ assigned to entities i and j is supposed to
This argument may be extended for any arbitrary relation that represent a legitimate, meaningful physical property of the pair.
purports to weakly discern all objects in a given domain. It may be Then a statement E[σ(i, j)] is formulated, which involves the
pointed out that any attempt to formally characterize a relation R selected mathematical object. With only a slight loss of generality
in a way which would guarantee that all distinct objects are we may assume that E[σ(i, j)] is a mathematical equation expres-
indeed weakly discerned by R is bound to contain reference to the sing the fact that the property σ(i, j) takes on a particular
identity relation. This is so, because otherwise we would be able to admissible value (categorical discernment), or a particular prob-
define purely qualitatively an absolute notion of identity, and this abilistic distribution over all admissible values (probabilistic dis-
is impossible, at least when we restrict ourselves to first-order cernment). Finally, a binary relation is defined as follows: R(i, j) iff
E[σ(i, j)] is true. This relation can be said to weakly discern objects
a and b iff R(a, b) but :R(a, a) and :R(b, b).
14
The circularity charge is leveled e.g. by Hawley (2006, 2009), French & One obvious condition which has to be satisfied is that the
Krause (2006, pp. 169–171), and, in the context of the metaphysical debate on
spacetime, by Wüthrich (2009). An extensive response to this charge can be found
equation E[σ(i, j)] is not supposed to include the identity symbol
in Muller (2013). I have no room here for a detailed analysis of Muller’s defense connecting object-variables i, j (for obvious reasons identities
against the circularity charge. However, I believe that his argument is ineffective connecting terms referring to mathematical objects are not only
against my criticism of the weakly discerning relations used in the context of permitted but even indispensable). But this is not sufficient to
quantum mechanics. As I understand it, Muller effectively argues that the
ensure the acceptability of the relation R. After all, illegitimate
proponents of WD do not commit a petitio principii, since they simply conclude
that two numerically distinct objects are qualitatively discerned by a permissible reference to identity may be already included in the description of
relation. I, on the other hand, question precisely this conclusion: in the case of the mapping σ(i, j). One method of revealing such a forbidden use
purported weakly discerning relations of QM particles are not qualitatively of identity may be suggested as follows. If the mapping σ(i, j) is
discerned, since the relations themselves make unavoidable reference to numerical defined in a way which treats differently cases when i¼j from
distinctness, ergo are not purely qualitative. Incidentally, this shows that my
criticism of WD, while related to the general charge of circularity, is nevertheless
cases when iaj, it may be suspected that illegitimate hidden
different in character. I do not argue that in order to apply any weakly discerning reference to identity is made. But how are we supposed to tell
relation we have to know in advance that the objects in question are numerically when this happens? And what does it precisely mean that cases
diverse; only that the weakly discerning relations used in quantum mechanics are i¼j and i aj are “treated differently”? Looking at the explicit
inappropriate, because they themselves are not purely qualitative.
15 formalization of the mapping σ is of little help here, because a
Of course the derivation of the fact that there are two spheres from the fact
that they are weakly discerned by the relation of being 5 feet apart is a matter of notation can always be craftily devised to unify distinct cases into
pure logic (I assume here that the relation of spatial separation is truly irreflexive, a seemingly uniform formula which appears not to contain
and thus I ignore the possibility that the spheres could be identified with bundles identity. A marginally better solution could be to stipulate that
of universals for which it is possible to be multiply localized). However, this does objects σ(i, j) should not belong to separate mathematical cate-
not mean that the extralogical, metaphysical assumption of PII does not play a role
here. The universal truth of PII ensures that in every case when two distinct objects
gories depending on whether i¼ j or ia j. For instance, we would
are present their distinctness can be reduced to (or derived from) some pure not intuitively accept as uniform a mapping which would assign a
qualitative facts. vector in ℂ3 to pairs of identical objects, and a 4  4 matrix of reals
T. Bigaj / Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 50 (2015) 43–53 51

to pairs of distinct objects. Unfortunately, cases that we have To sum up, the condition that we have introduced here is that all
already encountered are more subtle. While it may be claimed that mathematical operations involved in creating the object σ(i, j) should
operators (3) and (4) differ in an important respect, they never- be insensitive to the facts of numerical identity/distinctness regarding
theless belong to the same broad category of linear operators objects i and j, or in other words that the execution of all the required
acting on the tensor product of n identical Hilbert spaces. We need operations should be essentially the same regardless of whether i¼ j or
a more refined approach. iaj. I am willing to admit that these characterizations do not exactly
The key to the new requirement introduced below is the observa- live up to the standards of precision found in mathematical logic, but it
tion that the object σ(i, j) is typically the result of some mathematical seems to me that the intended meaning should be sufficiently clear for
operations performed on components related to objects i and j taken anybody familiar with mathematical practice. And now it can be easily
separately. In the case of Muller and Saunders’ relation Rt(i, j), these verified that the variety of relations proposed in order to weakly
operations include multiplication and addition of Hermitian operators discern quantum particles of the same type unambiguously violate the
acting in the tensor product of spaces. But it has to be noted that in aforementioned condition. That is, the operators introduced to weakly
order to properly execute an appropriate operation we have to know discern quanta clearly arise as a result of different procedures
in advance exactly which place in the product is occupied by which depending on whether we are dealing with one object or two distinct
single-particle operator. To illustrate this, let us consider again the objects. This problem may be the most conspicuous in the case of
familiar example: Huggett and Norton’s proposal, where the quantum-mechanical
conditions corresponding to the x¼y and xay cases are openly
AðiÞ ¼ I  …  Ai  …  I;
different, but it affects all the other strategies equally strongly.
BðjÞ ¼ I  …  Bj  …  I; At the risk of being repetitious, I would like to emphasize that the
formulas (1), (7), (8) and (17) are not built with the help of a single
where A and B are Hermitian operators in the single-particle space.
operator, as the notation might suggest. Rather, the equations defining
What is the result of the multiplication of these two operators? We
appropriate relations cover two separate instances involving two
can write it down simply as A(i)B(j), but we should not forget that the
distinct operators. It has to be underscored that my criticism does not
actual result depends in a non-trivial way on whether i is the same
rely on the additional premise that these distinct operators necessarily
number as j. If i¼j, then the result of the multiplication will be given as
correspond to distinct physical properties. In fact, I have to admit that I
I … AiBi  … I, i.e. the product of n–1 identities and one multiple
do not know how to decide whether for instance operators (5) and (6)
operator AB in the ith place. However, when iaj, the multiplication
represent distinct properties or the same property of the system of
algorithm is quite different: I … Ai  … Bj  … I (assuming that
many particles, and I do not care. But what is important is that in order
ioj), and thus A and B are not multiplied, as they do not act in the
to decide whether relation R–2 holds between two quantum particles x
same single-particle space. Without prior knowledge regarding the
and y, I have to perform a mathematical operation which requires from
identity of i and j we cannot even properly execute the required
me that I already know in advance whether x is identical with or
operation. I would like to stress that the problem is not merely that
distinct from y. Thus the successful application of R–2 to the pair (x, y)
the result of the prescribed operation is different, depending on
cannot ensure that they are distinct objects, since I have to know that
whether i¼j or iaj. After all, this is to be expected from a weakly
even before I start the whole procedure. Again, there is nothing wrong
discerning relation. I make a stronger claim: the operation itself is
in admitting that R–2 does discern x and y weakly, as there is nothing
meaningfully defined through an executable algorithm only when we
wrong in admitting that the relation xay discerns them too. But the
know which case obtains.16
metaphysical moral from the discernment achieved in such a way is
In order to make this crucial point clearer, let us contrast the
meager. If we wanted to find a way to reduce facts of numerical identity
above-mentioned case with the already mentioned case of a
and distinctness to some qualitative, genuinely physical states of affairs,
perfectly legitimate weakly discerning relation: spatial separation.
we should look elsewhere.
We start with defining for each physical object i its corresponding
And I submit that this “elsewhere” would have to be a theory other
position encoded as a 3-vector ri (relative to a particular coordi-
than the standard quantum theory of many particles. The way the
nate system). The mapping σ will be naturally characterized as
qffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffi standard formalism represents properties of systems of many particles
follows: σ(i, j)¼|ri  rj|¼ ðxi  xj Þ2 þ ðyi  yj Þ2 þ ðzi  zj Þ2 , and the makes it virtually impossible to find a way of encoding relations that
corresponding weakly discerning relation will receive the follow- would not be prone to the problem of the sensitivity to the facts of
ing characterization: D(i, j) iff |ri  rj| 40. It is easy to observe that identity. This is so, because in the tensor product formalism each
particle is assigned its own unique Hilbert space, and operators acting
the definition of the operation leading to the object σ(i, j) (i.e. the
in the total product consist of components each of which acts in its
subtraction of one vector from another, followed by taking its
individual space. Thus operators representing properties of the system
modulus) does not depend on the assumption regarding the
when x¼ y are bound to look and behave differently than operators
numerical identity of i and j. I do not have to know whether i is
representing “the same” properties in the case when xay—the former
the same object as j in order to execute the operation of subtract-
will have their components limited to one Hilbert space of states for
ing the vector associated with j from the vector associated with i.
particle x¼ y, whereas the latter will contain two types of components,
Thus no use of identity seems to be essential in order to mean-
ingfully introduce the relation D.17

(footnote continued)
16
For those who are not fully convinced by this claim I have the following should be permitted, as I explained previously, otherwise no meaningful weak
question to consider. Suppose that you are satisfied with the universal character- discernibility would ever be attainable. Another possible objection to this example
ization of the product A(i) B(j) which is neutral with respect to the identity of i and j. could be that it actually makes the weak discernibility of distinct spatial points a
What would you do if someone insisted that they still do not understand the consequence of their absolute discernibility by position vectors ri. But this is
procedure involved in this product? I am sure that you would ask them to consider incorrect. As is well known, vectors ri do not represent legitimate physical
separate cases and come up with the two results discussed above. This shows to me properties of objects, since they are not invariant under the symmetries of the
that our understanding of the universal multiplication formula is actually depen- underlying theory, i.e. the Galilean transformations. Only differences between
dent on the understanding of individual cases. vectors taken at the same time are invariant, and therefore can be interpreted as
17
I would like to stress that the theory in which the locations of individual representing genuine properties of systems. In order to avoid this confusion, we
points are introduced may very well make an indispensable use of identity. For could resort to an alternative, and more general method of defining the distance
instance, it seems necessary that this theory be able to express the fact that no two between two points as the length of the shortest of all continuous curves
distinct entities can have the same location function. But such a use of identity connecting these points (cf. Maudlin, 2007, p. 87ff).
52 T. Bigaj / Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 50 (2015) 43–53

one acting in x’s space, the other in y’s space. And to decide which individual particles will be translated into one and the same state-
“global” operator to choose, we have to rely on the previous knowl- ment “Some particle possesses property P”. Under such an analysis
edge regarding which is the case: x¼y or xay. the thesis that no particles of the same type can be absolutely
Interestingly enough, this problem may be avoided when we move discerned becomes a trivial logical truth, since the above-mentioned
to the Fock space formalism. Here the states of multiparticle systems statement cannot be both false and true.
are represented by occupation numbers associated with certain But can we not do any better than that? I submit we can. There are
properties of individual particles (see Sakurai & Napolitano, 2011, p. clear and simple methods of expressing the thought that some objects
460ff). If |ki〉 are eigenvectors for a selected single-particle quantity K, are discernible in a way that does not infringe upon the principle of
then the state of a system can be given as the vector |n1, n2, …, ni, …〉, permutation invariance and yet does not trivialize the problem of
where ni is the number of particles occupying state |ki〉. Supposing that discernibility. Instead of using labels, or unbound variables, we can
K is an additive quantity, we can define a multiparticle operator K resort to the well-known logical procedure of Ramsification, which
representing the corresponding property of the entire system as can get us for instance from the statement “a is absolutely discernible
P
follows: K ¼ i ki N i , where ki is an eigenvalue of K and Ni is the from b” to its Ramsey version “There are objects x and y such that x is
number operator associated with state |ki〉: Ni ¼ a†i ai. It is characteristic absolutely discernible from y” (or, equivalently, “Some objects are
that the form of the operator K remains the same regardless of the absolutely discerned from some objects”). And the last Ramsified
actual number and distribution of particles among the available states. sentence can in turn be explicated as “There are objects x and y and a
Thus we do not have to know in advance how many particles occupy property P such that x possesses P while y does not possess P”. So
which states in order to be able to apply K to a given state. That way there is hope that the last sentence could be expressed in the
we can hope to be able to find a property K such that it will produce a permutation-invariant language of the quantum theory of many
different value for a state in which some selected particles a and b are particles. But can this hope be realized? The answer is “yes”, if only
identical, and different when these particles are distinct (this differ- we resist the temptation to find a direct quantum-mechanical
ence can be of course reflected only in different occupation numbers, translation of the separate components of the above-stated sentence.
since the Fock space formalism does not admit individual labels). For As we already know, there is no quantum-mechanical formalization of
instance, a state in which a¼b may be given as |0, 0, …,1, …〉, whereas the expression “x possesses property P” satisfying the principle of
states for aab can take the form of either |0, 0, …, 2, …〉 (available permutation invariance. However, the whole sentence has a clear PI-
only for bosons) or |0, 0, …,1, …,1,…〉 (for bosons and fermions). The preserving representation in the quantum formalism.
fact that K looks and acts the same regardless of which state we are Let P be a projector in a single-particle space representing a given
applying it to (of course the results of its actions will generally be quantum-mechanical property P. For the sake of simplicity let us
different!) makes it possible to dodge the problem of an essential use consider a system consisting of two particles of the same type. If we
of identity in definitions of weakly discerning formulas. wanted to find an operator representing the joint property of the
system “particle 1 possesses P and particle 2 does not possess P”, this
could be easily done with the help of the following tensor product:
7. Further reflections P  ðI–PÞ. However, in order to satisfy PI we have to symmetrize this
product, thus arriving at the following projector acting in
So far the results of the analysis of the numerous attempts to ℋ  ℋ : P  ðI–PÞ þ ðI–PÞ  P. It should be evident that the last
implement the WD program have been rather negative. Is there not operator encodes the property of the entire system expressed in the
anything positive that can be learned from the sustained effort of so statement “Some particle possesses property P and some particle does
many proponents of weak discernibility? I believe there is. To see not possess property P”. And if the system is in a state which makes
that let us go back to the requirement of permutation invariance that this whole sentence true, this can mean only one thing: the objects in
was so vigorously argued for by Huggett and Norton. This is an question are absolutely discernible by property P.
important take-home lesson: the only physically meaningful state- It is an elementary fact that there are some antisymmetric/
ments about systems of particles of the same type are those which symmetric states which are eigenstates for appropriately selected
can be formulated with the help of fully symmetric operators and operators of the form P  ðI–PÞ þðI–PÞ  P. Thus bosons and
states. Even though everybody pays lip service to this principle, not fermions can be absolutely discerned in some states, contrary to the
all of its consequences are properly acknowledged and accepted. And commonly accepted Indiscernibility Thesis. It is true that this absolute
one of the crucial but often neglected consequences is that the very discernibility result does not extend to all bosonic and fermionic
question of discernibility of particles has to be cashed out in a states. It is also true that there are some thorny issues pertaining to the
language that obeys the principle of permutation invariance.18 But fermionic states. It turns out for instance that in some states fermions
can the question “Is particle a discernible from particle b?” even be can be simultaneously discerned by sets of incompatible properties,
properly formulated without violating the fundamental principle on which raises the question of whether the well-known no-go theorems,
which the whole theory of quantum particles is based? such as the Bell or Kochen–Specker theorems, are infringed upon.
To see more clearly what the source of the problem is, let us However, the prospect of even partially rehabilitating PII in its
start with the standard way of parsing the question of absolute strongest, most traditional guise, seems worth the effort put in an
discernibility. As absolute discernibility regards the possession of attempt at a solution. The WD program was an ambitious undertaking
properties by individual objects, we have to be able to express to reverse the dominating trend in the philosophical analysis of the
statements of the form “Particle a possesses property P”. But such problem of identity and individuality in quantum mechanics. I suggest
statements blatantly violate the principle of permutation invariance. that now is the right time to embark on a new and even more
And if we try to apply to them the procedure of symmetrization, ambitious program: the Absolute Discernibility (AD) program.19
suggested by Huggett and Norton as a way to accommodate PI, the
result will be that all ascriptions of a given property to distinct
19
There are good reasons to believe that the AD program is already under way.
Statements to the effect that quantum particles of the same type can differ with
18
Huggett (2003) acknowledges the fact that the well-known proof of the respect to their properties are occasionally made by physicists and philosophers
Indiscernibility Thesis given in French & Redhead (1988) relies on an inappropriate alike (see e.g. Ghirardi, Marinatto, & Weber, 2002; Pooley, 2006). Recently the idea
formalization of the properties of individual particles which violates PI. He that the permutation-invariant states of similar fermions and similar bosons admit
proposes an alternative method using the so-called conjugacy condition, which the possibility of their absolute discernibility has been noted and analyzed from a
unfortunately trivializes the problem of discernibility, as I explain in the main text. philosophical point of view in Dieks & Lubberdink (2011), Friebe (2014), Saunders
T. Bigaj / Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 50 (2015) 43–53 53

The AD program, as I see it, should primarily aim to clarify the Bigaj, T. (2015). Exchanging quantum particles. In: P. E. Bour, G. Heinzmann,
metaphysical consequences of the fact that some states of “identical” W. Hodges, & P. Schroeder-Heister (Eds.), 14th CLMPS 2011 Proceedings, 19
(pp. 185–198). Philosophia Scientiae.
fermions and bosons make it possible to discern them by individual Butterfield, J. (1993). Interpretation and identity in quantum theory. Studies in
properties, where their discernibility is encoded in an appropriate History and Philosophy of Science, 24, 443–476.
symmetric operator for which the state is an eigenstate. The first Caulton, A. (2013). Discerning “indistinguishable” quantum systems. Philosophy of
Science, 80, 49–72.
observation that has to be made here is that the particles discerned in
Caulton, A. (2014), Qualitative individuation in permutation-invariant quantum
such a way cannot be associated with the indices used in the mechanics. arXiv:1409.0247v1 [quant-ph].
symmetric/antisymmetric mathematical representation of the state. Caulton, A., & Butterfield, J. (2012). On kinds of indiscernibility in logic and
Instead, they should be identified by descriptions involving precisely metaphysics. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 63, 27–84.
Dieks, D., & Lubberdink, A. (2011). How classical particles emerge from the
those properties that were used to discern the particles in question.20 quantum world. Foundations of Physics, 41, 1051–1064.
However, it would be premature to conclude that in the current Dieks, D., & Versteegh, M. (2008). Identical quantum particles and weak discern-
approach particles should simply be considered bundles of properties. ibility. Foundations of Physics, 38, 923–934.
French, S., & Krause, D. (2006). Identity and physics: A historical, philosophical and
For one, if in a given state there are two (or more) distinct properties P formal analysis. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
and Q discerning two particles (as is certainly the case for fermions), French, S., & Redhead, M. (1988). Quantum physics and the identity of indiscern-
we cannot say for sure whether P and Q are bundled together or not, ibles. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 39, 233–246.
Friebe, C. (2014). Individuality, distinguishability and (non-)entanglement: A
as we can only state that one (but not the other) particle possesses P,
defense of Lebiniz’s principle. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern
and one (but not the other) particle possesses Q, without identifying Physics
which is which. Thus the question of the metaphysical nature of Ghirardi, G., Marinatto, L., & Weber, T. (2002). Entanglement and properties of
quanta in the AD approach remains open and should be subject to composite quantum systems: a conceptual and mathematical analysis. Journal
of Statistical Physics, 108(112), 49–122.
further investigations. Giuntini, R., & Mittelstaedt, P. (1989). The Leibniz Principle in quantum logic.
Another issue which merits further investigation is whether the International Journal of Theoretical Physics, 28, 159–168.
limited validity of the strong property-based variant of PII can restore Hawley, K. (2006). Weak discernibility. Analysis, 66, 300–303.
Hawley, K. (2009). Identity and indiscernibility. Mind, 118, 101–119.
the individuality of quantum particles. For it is still true that in some Huggett, N. (2003). Quarticles and the identity of indiscernibles. In: W. K. Brading, &
states (for instance in symmetric product states for bosons and in E. Castellani (Eds.), Symmetries in physics (pp. 239–249). Cambridge: Cambridge
some genuinely entangled states for fermions and bosons21) particles University Press.
Huggett, N., & Norton, J. (2014). Weak discernibility for quanta, the right way.
possess the exact same quantum-mechanical properties. It is unclear
British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 65, 39–58.
to me whether we need the unconditional and universal validity of PII Ketland, J. (2011). Identity and indiscernibility. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 4(2),
in order to speak about individual objects. For instance Dieks and 171–185.
Lubberdink (2011) speak about individual particles as “emerging” the Ladyman, J., & Bigaj, T. (2010). The Principle of the Identity of Indiscernibles and
quantum mechanics. Philosophy of Science, 77, 117–136.
moment the joint state shifts from a PII-violating to a PII-preserving Ladyman, J., Linnebo, O., & Bigaj, T. (2013). Entanglement and non-factorizability.
one. An alternative solution (which, under closer scrutiny, may turn Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 43(3), 215–221.
out to be just a variant of Dieks and Lubberdink’s emergence Ladyman, J., Linnebo, O., & Pettigrew, R. (2012). Identity and discernibility in
philosophy and logic. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 5, 162–186.
hypothesis) is to apply one of the well-known strategies to defend
Margenau, H. (1944). The Exclusion Principle and its philosophical importance.
the validity PII in the troublesome cases. For instance Friebe (2014) Philosophy of Science, 11, 187–208.
uses the summing defense, arguing that in the non-discerning states Maudlin, T. (2007). The metaphysics within physics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
there are no numerically distinct particles but an undivided (or even Muller, F. A. (2011). Withering away, weakly. Synthese, 180, 223–233.
Muller, F. A. (2015). The rise of relationals. Mind, 124, 201–237.
undividable) whole. These proposals are at a very early stage of Muller, F. A., & Saunders, S. (2008). Discerning fermions. British Journal for the
development, and much has to be done in order to turn them into a Philosophy of Science, 59, 499–548.
viable metaphysical conception of quantum particles. Muller, F. A., & Seevinck, M. P. (2009). Discerning elementary particles. Philosophy of
Science, 76, 179–200.
Pooley, O. (2006). Points, particles, and structural realism. In: D. Rickles, S. French, &
J. Saatsi (Eds.), The structural foundations of quantum gravity (pp. 83–120).
Acknowledgments Oxford: OUP.
Redhead, M., & Teller, P. (1992). Quantum physics and the identity of the
indiscernibles. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 43, 201–218.
I would like to thank the members of the Southern California
Sakurai, J. J., & Napolitano, J. (2011). Modern quantum mechanics (2nd ed). San
Philosophy of Physics Group at Irvine, and two anonymous referees, Francisco: Adison-Wesley.
for their useful comments to earlier versions of this paper. The work Saunders, S. (2003). Physics and Leibniz’s principles. In: K. Brading, & E. Castellani
on this paper was supported by the Marie Curie Grant FP7-PEOPLE- (Eds.), Symmetries in physics: Philosophical reflections (pp. 289–307). Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
2012-IOF-328285. Saunders, S. (2006). Are quantum particles objects? Analysis, 66, 52–63.
Saunders, S. (2013). Indistinguishability. In: R. Batterman (Ed.), Oxford handbook of
References philosophy of physics (pp. 340–380). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
van Fraassen, B., & Peschard, I. (2008). Identity over time: Objectively, subjectively.
Philosophical Quarterly, 58, 15–35.
Bigaj, T. (2014). On discernibility and symmetry, Erkenntnis, http://dx.doi.org/10. Wüthrich, C. (2009). Challenging the spacetime structuralist. Philosophy of Science,
1007/s10670-014-9616-y. 76, 1039–1051.

(footnote continued)
(2013), and Caulton (2014). I have given my own “metaphysical” arguments for the
absolute discernibility thesis based on the assumption of essentialism in Bigaj
(2015).
20
This contention is explicitly formulated and endorsed in Dieks & Lubberdink
(2011) and Friebe (2014).
21
An exhaustive analysis of the difference between genuinely and non-
genuinely entangled states of many particles of the same type is the main topic
of the extensive paper (Ghirardi et al., 2002). For a different approach to the same
problem see Ladyman, Linnebo, & Bigaj (2013) and (Caulton 2014). It should be
mentioned here that Caulton’s unorthodox approach to the problem of permuta-
tion invariance leads to an even stronger conclusion than the one presented above;
namely that fermions of the same type are discernible in all states (even
“genuinely” entangled ones).

You might also like