You are on page 1of 100

THEORIES OF CONSCIOUSNESS

ANIMAL AND HUMAN MINDS


THE SELF AND FREE WILL
SLEEP AND DREAMING

ESSENTIAL ALTERED CONSCIOUSNESS


CONSCIOUSNESS AND REALITY

GUIDE№12 AND MORE

CONSCIOUSNESS
UNDERSTANDING THE GHOST IN THE MACHINE

EDITED BY

RICHARD WEBB
NEW
SCIENTIST
ESSENTIAL
GUIDE
CONSCIOUSNESS fascinating but elusive phenomenon;

“A it is impossible to specify what it is,


what it does, or why it evolved. Nothing
worth reading has been written about it”.
So wrote psychologist Stuart Sutherland
of consciousness in the International Dictionary of
Psychology a little over three decades ago.
Much has changed in the past years. Imaging
technologies have given fresh insights into what goes
on in the brain as we experience sensations from love
to colour to hunger to fear. Biologists have traced where
subjective experience first appeared in the tree of life,
and the sensations other animals have. Mathematical
models are providing new angles on consciousness.
But in all this, there is much we still don’t understand
about consciousness and its place in the cosmos – not
least, the “hard problem” of why there is something it is
to be like us at all. This 12th New Scientist Essential Guide
looks at this most fascinating and elusive phenomenon
in the round, and I do hope it provides food for thought.
The other titles in the Essential Guide series can be
bought by visiting shop.newscientist.com; feedback
is welcome at essential guides@newscientist.com.
Richard Webb

NEW SCIENTIST ESSENTIAL GUIDES EDITOR Richard Webb ABOUT THE EDITOR
NORTHCLIFFE HOUSE, 2 DERRY STREET,
DESIGN Craig Mackie Richard Webb is executive editor of New Scientist
LONDON, W8 5TT
+44 (0)203 615 6500 SUBEDITOR Bethan Ackerley
© 2022 NEW SCIENTIST LTD, ENGLAND PRODUCTION AND APP Joanne Keogh ADDITIONAL CONTRIBUTORS
NEW SCIENTIST ESSENTIAL GUIDES
TECHNICAL DEVELOPMENT (APP) Anil Ananthaswamy, Philip Ball, Michael Brooks, Andy Coghlan, Sofia Deleniv,
ARE PUBLISHED BY NEW SCIENTIST LTD
ISSN 2634-0151 Amardeep Sian Liam Drew, Liz Else, Linda Geddes, Alison George, Bob Holmes, Rowan Hooper,
PRINTED IN THE UK BY PUBLISHER Nina Wright Joshua Howgego, Simon Makin, Tiffany O’Callaghan, Sean O’Neill, David Robson,
PRECISION COLOUR PRINTING LTD AND
EDITOR-IN-CHIEF Emily Wilson Per Snaprud, Laura Spinney, Helen Thomson, Richard Webb, Caroline Williams,
DISTRIBUTED BY MARKETFORCE UK LTD
+44 (0)20 3148 3333 DISPLAY ADVERTISING +44 (0)203 615 6456 Clare Wilson, Emma Young
COVER: PABLO HURTADO DE MENDOZA displayads@newscientist.com
ABOVE: LUMEZIA/ISTOCK
NEXT PAGE: BASHTA/ISTOCK

New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness | 1


CHAPTER 1 CHAPTER 2 CHAPTER 3

WHAT IS CONSCIOUS YOUR


CONSCIOUS- MINDS CONSCIOUS
NESS? SELF

Consciousness is the ghost in By asking what the outward signs A sense of self and its related trait of
our machine. It is all there is: the of consciousness are, and tracing metacognition, the ability to monitor
world, the self, all experience. But back where they first appeared in your own mental states and those of
beyond that, the very subjectivity of the history of life, we might begin others, are often regarded as the
consciousness makes it hard to define to understand why the phenomenon pinnacles of consciousness. In fact,
and harder still to characterise. exists – and so learn a little more they might be evolutionary accidents,
about what it is. and perhaps even figments of our
p. 6 The easy and hard problems own imaginations.
p. 8 Five ways to think about p. 20 Why did consciousness evolve?
consciousness p. 25 Ten signs of consciousness p. 36 The evolution of the self
p. 10 Seeking the seat p. 26 Inside animal minds p. 39 What animals are self-aware?
of consciousness
p. 28 Five elements of consciousness p. 40 Is the self an illusion?
p. 12 INTERVIEW: David Chalmers
p. 29 Could a robot ever be conscious? p. 42 Metacognition: Knowing
“Why is there something
p. 30 PERSPECTIVE: Michael Graziano that you know
it’s like to be us?”
“Consciousness is an p. 44 Your conscious body
p. 14 Consciousness and
engineering phenomenon” p. 48 Free will and the self
the networked brain
p. 16 PERSPECTIVE: Christof Koch
“Physics overwhelmingly
favours consciousness”

2 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


CHAPTER 4 CHAPTER 5 CHAPTER 6

SLEEP AND ALTERED CONSCIOUS-


DREAMING CONSCIOUS- NESS AND
NESS REALITY

The true purpose of sleep remains Many altered states of consciousness The relationship between our
unclear, but among organisms with exist, from anaesthesia and natural internal world and the external one –
some degree of consciousness, it or drug-induced hallucinations to how the processes of physics contrive
seems near-universal that they spend minimally conscious states such as to produce consciousness and
some time in a reduced state of it. comas. In all cases, what is going also, perhaps, how consciousness
Exactly why is a big question – as on in our brains is far from clear-cut. influences the processes of physics –
is the meaning of the many different is another of the great mysteries
states of consciousness we seem p. 62 The mystery of anaesthesia of consciousness, with as yet
to enter in our non-waking hours. p. 66 The power of hallucination few answers.
p. 68 Psychedelia: A higher state?
p. 52 Why do we sleep? p. 69 Curiosities of consciousness p. 80 The physics of consciousness
p. 55 Your brain while sleeping p. 70 Free won’t p. 84 Does consciousness
p. 57 Hypnagogia p. 71 Covert consciousness create reality?
p. 57 The meaning of dreaming p. 73 Six reduced states p. 88 Is the universe conscious?
p. 58 When dreams happen of consciousness p. 93 PERSPECTIVE: Anil Seth
“We need to solve the real
p. 74 What happens to consciousness
problem of consciousness”
when we die?
p. 75 PERSPECTIVE: Daniel Bor
“Consciousness is about
combining information”

New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness | 3


CHAPTER 1

Consciousness is the ghost in the machine. It is, for each


of us, all there is: the world, the self, all experience.

But the very subjectivity of consciousness makes it difficult to


define, and harder still to characterise. How do our brains create
conscious experiences and a feeling of being? Why do we have
these sensations at all? These are unanswered questions that
lie at the heart of the mystery of consciousness.

4 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


Chapter 1 | What is consciousness? | 5
THE EASY AND
HARD PROBLEMS
Among scientists and philosophers grappling ONSCIOUSNESS is a slippery concept.
It isn’t just the stuff in your head; it is
with the mystery of consciousness, a popular the subjective experience of some of
division has sprung up in recent decades – that stuff. When you stub your toe,
your brain doesn’t merely process
between asking what it is made of, and why it information and trigger a reaction:
exists at all. Neither question is easy to answer, you have a feeling of pain. Being in
pain; experiencing joy; smelling
but one is distinctly harder than the other. onions frying; feeling humiliated;
recognising a friend in the crowd;
reflecting that you are wiser than you were last year –
all of these are examples of conscious experiences,
sometimes termed “qualia”.
The mysteries starts with what those experiences
are made of. In the 1600s, the philosopher René
Descartes famously divided the universe into “mind
stuff” (res cogitans) and “matter stuff” (res extensa),
raising the conundrum of how the two might ever
interact. He was convinced that the body and
conscious mind are two different substances:
the first is made of matter, the latter is immaterial.
Today, most – although not all – scientists reject this
PABLO HURTADO DE MENDOZA
PREVIOUS PAGE: LUMEZIA/ISTOCK strict “dualist” perspective. The relatively orthodox >

6 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


Chapter 1 | What is consciousness? | 7
FIVE WAYS TO
THINK ABOUT
CONSCIOUSNESS
DUALISM
Brain and mind are two separate things,
and conscious experiences can’t, in all
probability, be fully explained through the
workings of physical matter.

MONISM
Brain and mind are the same thing, and
consciousness is ultimately a phenomenon
that derives from the workings of matter –
in humans, the matter of the brain. The
dominant subgenre of monism today is…

PHYSICALISM
Existing laws of physics governing electrical
scientific view today goes by the name of physicalism and chemical signalling in our brains are
(see “Five ways to think about consciousness”, right). ultimately enough to explain consciousness
Consciousness is related to or emerges from physical and the workings of our minds. Understand
matter, in particular the firing of neurons in our brains. these workings, and we should be able to
But how does the brain, a physical object, generate “see” the physical markers of different
the non-physical essence that is consciousness? conscious experiences, and so know what
In the final years of the 20th century, philosopher other people are experiencing.
David Chalmers at New York University made an
influential distinction between two aspects of PANPSYCHISM
consciousness: the “easy” and the “hard” problems. Deriving from the idea that consciousness
The “easy” problem consists of explaining the brain is a fundamental component of the universe
processes associated with consciousness, such as the in its own right, this suggests that all matter –
integration of sensory information, learning, thinking perhaps even inanimate objects like rocks –
and the states of being awake or asleep. These problems are imbued with some degree of consciousness
are called easy not because they are trivial, but because that may or may not be explained by current
there seems no reason why they can’t be solved in matter-based physics. If we can find a
terms of physical mechanisms – albeit potentially measure of consciousness, we can quantify
very complex ones. how much different objects have.

→- ILLUSIONISM
Chapter 4 looks at sleep and dreaming in more depth- Illusionists agree with physicalists that our
conscious experiences have a physical basis
The hard problem, which Chalmers introduced at a in the workings of the brain, but argue these
scientific meeting in 1994, is to explain why we have are illusory experiences derived from our
subjective experiences at all. “Consciousness poses brain’s processes for monitoring itself, and
the most baffling problem in the science of the mind,” don’t themselves represent “real” properties
TIM UR/ISTOCK

said Chalmers. When we think and perceive, there is of the world.


a “whirr of information-processing” in the brain, as
he put it, but also very distinctive, subjective states

8 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


What does the colour red
look like to someone else?

of mind. We don’t just perceive the world; we feel it. because the real world is like that, but because our
Conscious thought can influence the body and the visual systems effectively colour-code the world
world: a conscious desire to move your arm results for us to simplify it.
in physical movement. And much as colour is an illusion created by
the brain, so, too, is consciousness and our sense
→- of self. “Consciousness is a user illusion designed by
Chapter 6 discusses consciousness and- evolution to make life easier for the brain that must
reality in more depth- guide a body through a perilous life,” says philosopher
Daniel Dennett at Tufts University in Massachusetts,
These experiences seem, to an external observer, a prominent illusionist. If our brain is a smartphone,
fundamentally unknowable. What is someone else’s consciousness is the screen and individual experiences
experience of grief, or pain, or the smell of onions, or are icons on it, our interface to the brain.
the colour red actually like? Thomas Nagel, also at New
York University, expressed this conundrum famously →-
in the 1970s when he asked: “What is it like to be a bat?” See chapter 3 for more on the conscious self-
You could know every detail of the physical workings
of a bat’s brain, but still not know what that bat is The metaphor isn’t exact: when we feel dizzy or
experiencing. pinpoint where a sound is coming from, for example,
When it comes to the hard problem, opinions differ it is the result of physical processes in the brain. In
wildly. Adherents of the illusionist school of thought that sense, you might think of consciousness as more
dismiss the problem out of hand, and say that the hard like a smartphone screen that presents different apps
problem creates an issue where there is none. We don’t according to the amount of battery left or how much
normally talk about our qualia, they say: we talk about it has been shaken.
things such as being tired, needing to eat or even That remains a minority view, however: most
being in love. All of these phenomena have relatively researchers believe that consciousness is a real
straightforward, non-spooky biological origins in phenomenon, and that by delving into the mysteries
things such as the workings of hormones in our body. of the brain’s workings, we can illuminate its nature.
And if we experience a strawberry as “red”, say, it isn’t But that is far easier said than done.  ❚

Chapter 1 | What is consciousness? | 9


SEEKING THE SEAT
OF CONSCIOUSNESS
What is being in love, feeling pain or seeing colour made of? How our brains construct
our conscious experience has long been a riddle – but we are slowly uncovering clues.

ACK in 1998, two young men sat consciousness might be explained using a
in a smoky bar in Bremen, northern similar approach. Imaging techniques such as
Germany. Neuroscientist Christof Koch electroencephalography (EEG) provided tools with
and philosopher David Chalmers, which researchers could look at the brain’s patterns
originator of the “hard problem” of activities while performing all sorts of different
of consciousness, had spent the tasks, in the hope of finding physical signatures of
day lecturing at a conference about specific conscious experiences.
consciousness, and they still had One early surprise was that the cerebellum, a sort
more to say. After a few drinks, Koch of mini brain hanging off the back of your cortex that
suggested a wager. He bet a case of contains about three-quarters of the 86-billion-odd
fine wine that within the next 25 years, someone neurons in the brain, seems to have almost nothing
would discover a “neural correlate of consciousness” – to do with consciousness. One reason we know this is
a particular pattern of brain activity that relates to because some people are born without a functioning
a given conscious state, such as the experience of cerebellum, and while they experience some problems,
a painful toothache. Chalmers said it wouldn’t a lack of consciousness isn’t one of them.
happen, and bet against. Frustratingly, similar observations have undermined
The wager was rooted in the dominant physicalist most suggestions of a “seat of consciousness” within
school of consciousness – that consciousness is a the brain. Take the notion, which Koch and Crick
real phenomenon whose physical origins can be favoured for a while, that a sheet-like structure
uncovered – and particularly in an approach to the beneath the cortex called the claustrum is crucial for
problem that Koch, now president and chief scientist consciousness. There was reason to be optimistic: a case
of the Allen Institute for Brain Science in Seattle, study in 2014 showed that electrically stimulating this
Washington, had pioneered together with the structure in a woman’s brain caused her to stare blankly
co-discoverer of DNA, Francis Crick. ahead, seemingly unconscious, until the stimulation
In his work on DNA, Crick had reduced the mystery stopped. But another study described someone who
of biological heritability to a few intrinsic properties remained fully conscious after his claustrum was
of a small set of molecules. He and Koch thought destroyed by encephalitis, undermining that idea.

10 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


Many brain regions are implicated in aspects of our conscious experience,
meaning the hunt for a single seat of consciousness has been so far fruitless

FRONTAL LOBE MOTOR CORTEX


Complex behaviours, communication, Planning and control of
memory, attention and personality voluntary movement
PREFRONTAL CORTEX
PARIETAL LOBE
Emotion regulation, Language, attention and senses
intuition, insight, empathy

BASAL GANGLIA THALAMUS


Movement, reward and emotion Central station of sensory input

GLOBUS PALLIDUS INTERNA OCCIPITAL LOBE


Regulation of voluntary movement Vision
TEMPORAL LOBE
STRIATUM
Memory and senses
Involved in diverse aspects of
PEDUNCULOPONTINE NUCLEUS behaviour and movement
Initiation of movement

Some bundles of neurons do appear to be vital colleagues conducted a review of the evidence and
for consciousness, however. If damage occurs to concluded that stimulation of only two regions of
specific parts of the thalamus, or to a particular the PFC, the orbitofrontal cortex and the anterior
region of the brainstem, for instance, the result can cingulate cortex, sometimes alters reports of conscious
be permanent unconsciousness. But the question experience. It seems likely that they support emotional
remains whether these brain regions are central to aspects of conscious experience, as well as self-
generating conscious experiences, or whether they consciousness and meta-consciousness (the awareness
are more like a power socket that simply allows of being aware), but may not be involved in more
whatever is plugged into it to work. fundamental sensory perceptual awareness. It appears
Some researchers ascribe a vital role to the prefrontal that an area towards the rear of the brain’s cortex – the
cortex (PFC), which is responsible for sophisticated “posterior hot zone”, as Koch calls it – is crucial for this.
cognitive processes including attention, decision- One posterior region apparently important for
making and planning. They argue that for information consciousness is the parietal cortex, which processes
from the outside world to become a conscious sensory information from the body. In 2021, Mohsen
perception – for you to actually see a red apple, say – Afrasiabi and Michelle Redinbaugh at the University
it has to be processed not just by the part of the brain of Wisconsin-Madison and others reported research
responsible for that, the sensory cortex, but also by the on macaques that were sleeping, anaesthetised or
PFC. Neuroimaging studies of people and macaques awake. They concluded that connectivity between
support this idea, but sceptics say that the PFC activity the parietal cortex, the striatum and the thalamus
these show could relate to thinking about a stimulus is a “hallmark” of conscious states.
and planning a response, rather than being conscious All in all, it remains a confusing picture – and with
of it. And again, there are people who have had large the clock ticking on his wager, Koch is anticipating
regions of their PFC surgically removed due to tumours defeat. “The extent to which more frontal regions of
or epileptic seizures. “They go on living, by and large, the cortex, let alone other brain regions, contribute
a normal life, never complaining that they have been to consciousness will remain open for many years to
turned into zombies,” says Koch. come,” he says. “After all, the brain is the most complex
In 2021, Omri Raccah at New York University and his piece of active matter in the known universe.”  ❚

Chapter 1 | What is consciousness? | 11


INTERVIEW

Although we have made some progress understanding how patterns


of brain activity relate to conscious experiences, the basic question
of why we have them remains unresolved, says David Chalmers

“WHY IS THERE SOMETHING


IT’S LIKE TO BE US?”
How does someone become a philosopher of consciousness?
To me, the problem of consciousness is the most
PROFILE interesting unsolved problem in the universe –
DAVID a central aspect of our existence that we almost
CHALMERS entirely fail to understand. I actually started out as a
mathematician and got part way through a doctorate
in mathematics, but I gradually became obsessed by this
The originator of question of why there is consciousness in the world.
the “hard problem” I thought, how am I going to study this from a big-
of consciousness, picture perspective? Philosophy is the field that allows
philosopher David you to integrate science and technology, history and
Chalmers is co-director everything together, so I ended up switching to study
philosophy, cognitive science and artificial intelligence,
of the Center for Mind,
and eventually became a philosopher of consciousness.
Brain and Consciousness
at New York University Concerning your bet with Christof Koch about finding neural
correlates of consciousness: you’ve won, haven’t you?
It’s looking pretty good for me. I’m quite open to the
idea that eventually we’ll find some system or property

12 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


JENNIE EDWARDS

in the brain that correlates with consciousness – promising. But in my experience, the further you go
which plays the role DNA plays for the gene, if you down these paths, the more problems you find. I’ve not
like. That wouldn’t fully explain consciousness, found anything that I’m actually satisfied with yet.
but it would be a huge step.
But the bet was that some intrinsic property or Do you have any hunches about where a solution might lie?
small number of properties of neurons would be In general, I’ve argued for views that don’t try to reduce
acknowledged as the neural correlate of consciousness consciousness to, say, a brain process or something
by 2023. I was always very sceptical about that: simpler, but take it as something fundamental in the
I thought it was going to be a lot more complicated way that space and time, or mass and charge, might
and take a lot more time. be. I do take panpsychism especially seriously, the
idea that some element of consciousness at the
Meanwhile, the wider hard problem of consciousness fundamental level of physical reality somehow adds
seems as intractable as ever. Why is it so hard? up to and produces our consciousness. Also, the idea
The hard problem is the problem of explaining that maybe consciousness is distinct from any physical
subjective experience. Why is there something process that plays a role in the physical world.
it’s like to be us? When we see, when we hear,
information strikes our sensory organs and gets →-
processed by our brains, and that leads to behaviour. Chapter 6 has more on consciousness-
We can tell a nice mechanistic story about all of that, and reality-
and how it might explain things like learning or
language or memory. But why does this feel like Isn’t the basic problem that we don’t have a brain that can
something from the inside? Why is there subjective understand itself?
experience of hearing and seeing? Why doesn’t it go What’s the old saying here? If the mind was so
on in the dark without consciousness? That just simple that we could understand it, we’d be too
looks like a different kind of question. simple to understand the mind. Some people think
it’s a miracle that we can understand nature at all,
Have we made any progress towards answering it? so maybe there are some things that we’re just too
Although we haven’t nailed the neural correlates of dumb to understand. I’d like to think that’s not the
consciousness, we’re on the way to understanding the case. I don’t see any obstacle in principle to eventually
correlations between brain activity and consciousness having a scientific theory of consciousness. Science
better. When it comes to the question of why there is and philosophy is a process that takes centuries or
consciousness at all, we’ve explored some theoretical millennia. Probably even in 100 years’ time, all this
options, many of which are very interesting and is going to look very different.  ❚

Chapter 1 | What is consciousness? | 13


CONSCIOUSNESS AND
THE NETWORKED BRAIN
As searches for the seat of consciousness have failed to turn up convincing answers,
attention has shifted to the idea that consciousness depends on networked properties
of neurons, and how they deal with information. That is the starting point of two leading
models of consciousness: the global workspace, and integrated information theory.

ACK in 2005, a team of neuroscientists “global workspace” – which then reverberates in


led by Giulio Tononi at the University a flash of coordinated activity. The result is a mental
of Wisconsin-Madison and Marcello interpretation of the world that has integrated all
Massimini at the University of Milan the senses into a single picture, while filtering out
injected a pulse of energy into the conflicting pieces of information (see diagram, right).
brain via transcranial magnetic A popular version of this concept is that special
stimulation, then used “workspace neurons” in the cortex, primarily in the
electroencephalography to monitor front of the brain, broadcast information through
the response. They found that the their long-range connections. Global workspace theory
electrical echo generated by the seems to fit with a lot of findings about the brain.
energy pulse will bounce all around a conscious brain, Critics ask, however, whether it explains subjective
but stays very localised in an unconscious one. In other experience itself, or just indicates when information
words, the conscious brain is much more connected. is available for reasoning, speech and bodily control.
Such insights have come to be plugged into more Other network-based ideas suggest that
sophisticated ideas that see consciousness arising consciousness is the result of information being
not from the workings of specific cells or any single combined so that it is more than the sum of its parts.
area of the brain, but from the properties of networks One that has grabbed much attention is integrated
of neurons. information theory (IIT), the brainchild of Tononi. It
Global workspace theory has perhaps been the is based on the observation that each moment of our
most influential of these ideas. First floated in 1983 conscious awareness is unified. When you contemplate
by Bernard Baars at The Neurosciences Institute in a bunch of flowers, say, it is impossible to be conscious
San Diego, California, it proposes that non-conscious of the flower’s colour independently of its fragrance
experiences are processed locally within separate because the brain has integrated the sensory data.
regions of the brain, such as the visual cortex. We only Tononi argues that for a system to be conscious, it must
become conscious of this information if these signals integrate information in such a way that the whole
are broadcast to an assembly of neurons distributed contains more information than the sum of its parts.
across many different regions of the brain – the He proposed a measure of how a system integrates

14 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


The global workspace theory suggests that consciousness arises
from highly coordinated, widespread activity in the brain

PERCEPTIONS
Sight, sound, taste and touch are first processed in small, localised areas of the brain

CONSCIOUS GLOBAL NON-CONSCIOUS


When signals are broadcast to a wider WORKSPACE When signals remain localised,
network of neurons across much of the the associated sensations are not
cortex – the global workspace – we become perceived consciously
conscious of the sensation

information – a proxy for the “amount” of →-


consciousness in any system – that he called phi.
Very approximately, phi will be high in a system of
Turn to page 88 for more on the-
specialised modules that can interact rapidly and
conscious universe-
effectively. This is true for large parts of the brain’s
cortex. In contrast, phi is low in the cerebellum, These are far from the only theories of consciousness
which is composed of modules that work largely out there. The “attention schema” model proposed
independently of each other. by Michael Graziano at Princeton University, for
In this way, IIT reflects some observations about example, is closely associated with the illusionist
the brain – for example, how a stroke or tumour may school of thought. It proposes that the brain evolved
destroy the cerebellum without significantly affecting to contain a model of how it represents itself.
consciousness, whereas similar damage to the cortex This attention schema is like a self-reflecting mirror,
usually disrupts subjective experience. Among IIT’s and is what creates the subjective feeling of
high-profile supporters are Christof Koch, who thinks consciousness. There is no “ghost in the machine”;
it fits with his work pointing to activity in a highly consciousness is just a mirage created by sophisticated
connected “hot zone” of the posterior cortex with neural processing.
high phi being a neural correlate of consciousness. Anil Seth at the University of Sussex in the UK,
Among IIT’s problems, however, is that there meanwhile, proposes an idea called “predictive
are so many ways to divide up a system as complex processing”: the brain is a prediction machine,
as the human brain, or even constituent parts of it, meaning that what we perceive is the brain’s best
that calculating phi is as good as impossible in any guesses about the causes of its sensory input. As a
real situation. It suggests that something inanimate result, much of conscious experience and selfhood
like a grid of electronic logic gates may have an is based on what we expect, not what is there.  ❚
extremely high degree of consciousness because
it integrates information in the same way, and →-
might even imply that the universe itself has Michael Graziano and Anil Seth explain their ideas-
some form of consciousness. in more depth on pages 30 and 93 respectively-

Chapter 1 | What is consciousness? | 15


PERSPECTIVE CHRISTOF KOCH

“PHYSICS OVERWHELMINGLY
FAVOURS CONSCIOUSNESS”
Mathematical models of consciousness, such QUICK glance at the thousands
of books that purport to explain
as integrated information theory, can lead us consciousness makes the real
to a better understanding of what it is. understanding of it look like a
Herculean task. There is, after
all, a profound explanatory gap
between neural activity of any sort
and subjective feelings. The first
belongs to the realm of physics, to
space and time, energy and mass;
the second to experience. And while experiences are
ephemeral, they are the very stuff of life. The only
way we know about the world, about space and time,
about energy and mass, about anything in fact is by
seeing, hearing and smelling, by lusting and hating,
by remembering and imagining.
PROFILE That these two realms are closely related is revealed
CHRISTOF by the effects of a stroke, a strong blow to the head or
KOCH a neurosurgeon electrically stimulating some part of
a person’s brain and evoking a childhood memory.
Yet consciousness doesn’t appear in the equations
Christof Koch is chief of physics, nor in chemistry’s periodic table, nor in
scientific officer at the the A-T-G-C molecular chatter of our genes. Somehow,
Allen Institute of Brain it emerges from the nervous system.
Science in Washington I have spent more than three decades – the first
and author of books on 16 years working with my mentor, colleague and friend
Francis Crick – linking specific aspects of consciousness
consciousness including
to the mammalian brain. We popularised the idea
The Feeling of Life Itself of the neuronal correlates of consciousness (NCC):
the minimal neuronal mechanisms – the synapses,
neurons and brain regions – that are jointly sufficient
for any one conscious percept.
Since then, much progress has been made. We now

16 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


know that some sectors of the cerebral cortex making neocortex is about twice as thick that of the mouse,
up the bulk of the brain (for its size, the most complex and has about 1000 times the surface area. It is a
organ in the universe) have a privileged relationship highly versatile, computational tissue that excels at
to consciousness, that not all of its many regions processing sensory information, making and storing
participate equally in generating the content of a associations, and planning and producing complex
conscious experience. Micro-electrodes and magnetic motor patterns. The neocortex is partitioned into
scanners have also shown us that the neocortex can multiple areas, made up of smaller columns with
be active without necessarily giving rise to a conscious reasonably similar cell types and architectures
experience. This is the domain of the non-conscious. across species and brain regions.
Yet Crick and I looked deeper. Why did a particular Our brain “observatories” aim to identify, record and
NCC give rise to one specific conscious experience? intervene in the cortical networks underlying visually
Why should particular vibrations of highly organised guided behaviours in the mouse, including visual
matter trigger conscious feelings? It seems as magical perception, decision-making, and even murine
as rubbing a lamp and having a genie emerge. consciousness. The fast-developing technology of
What is needed is a fundamental account of how optogenetics allows us to control defined events in
activity in any system can give rise to consciousness. defined neurons at defined times in mouse brains –
We therefore turned to the ideas of Giulio Tononi at that is, to move from correlation to causation. Building
the University of Wisconsin-Madison. these observatories is a large-scale effort to synthesise
He advocates a sophisticated information theory anatomical, physiological and theoretical knowledge
account of consciousness, called integrated information. into a model of the cerebral cortex, which has the
The idea introduces a precise measure, called phi, potential to revolutionise our understanding of
which captures the extent of consciousness. Expressed the mammalian brain.
in bits, phi quantifies the extent to which any system of Throughout my quest to understand consciousness,
interacting parts is both differentiated and integrated I never lost my sense of living in a magical universe. I do
when that system enters a particular state. believe some deep and elemental organising principle
This is the heart of phenomenal experience: any one created the universe and set it in motion for a purpose
conscious experience is both highly differentiated from I cannot comprehend. I grew up calling this god.
any other one and also unitary, holistic. The larger the A pioneering generation of stars had to die in
phi, the richer the conscious experience of that system. spectacular supernovae to seed space with the heavier
Integrated information makes specific predictions elements needed for the rise of self-replicating bags of
about which brain circuits are involved in chemicals, on a rocky planet orbiting a young star at just
consciousness and which ones are peripheral players, the right distance. The competitive pressures of natural
even though they might contain many more neurons. selection made possible the accession of creatures with
The theory should let doctors build a consciousness nervous systems. As the complexity of these systems
meter to measure the extent to which severely brain- grew to staggering proportions, some of the creatures
injured patients are in a vegetative state, and which evolved the ability to reflect on themselves, to
ones are partially conscious but unable to signal contemplate their beautiful but cruel world.
their pain and discomfort. While the rise of sentient life was inevitable,
At the Allen Institute for Brain Science in Seattle, it doesn’t mean Earth had to bear life or that bipedal,
Washington, we have been pursuing a different tack. big-brained primates had to walk the African grasslands.
Our goal is to understand how information is encoded, But I do believe the laws of physics overwhelmingly
transformed and represented in the mouse and the favoured the emergence of consciousness, and that
human cerebral neocortex and its satellites. those laws will lead us to a more or less complete
The neocortex is a layered structure: the human knowledge of it.  ❚

Chapter 1 | What is consciousness? | 17


CHAPTER 2

18 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


We know – or we think we know – that we are conscious.
But how about your pet dog or cat, or a tool-making crow,
or a playful octopus or writhing worm?

It might seem impossible to answer these questions. We have


yet to identify any distinctive pattern of brain activity that
indicates consciousness even in humans, and we can hardly
ask other animals about their experiences.

But posing these questions does provide another way to approach


the phenomenon of consciousness. By asking what its outward
signs are, and tracing back where they first appeared in the
history of life, we might begin to understand why consciousness
exists – and so learn a little about more what it is.

Chapter 2 | Conscious minds | 19


WHY DID
CONSCIOUSNESS
EVOLVE?
Until recently, the question of what ONSCIOUSNESS could have evolved
for multiple reasons – or perhaps
consciousness is for has been largely ignored. none. Some think that, rather than
But now evolutionary biologists are starting having a survival advantage, it is an
“epiphenomenon”, simply emerging as
to feel their way around the tree of life to an automatic property of intelligence.
consider when and where elements of our own For most, however, that is a bit of a cop-
out. “My guess is that consciousness,
consciousness emerged – and therefore why. because of its complexity and
costliness, in fact conferred adaptive
value on its possessors,” says David Barash, a
psychologist at the University of Washington in Seattle.
Tracking the evolution of what we call consciousness
has its own difficulties, however. “Consciousness
doesn’t leave any fossil record,” says Anil Seth at
the University of Sussex, UK. We must infer its
evolutionary history by comparing animals alive
today and working back to what their common
ancestor might have been able to do. But because
we don’t really know what we are looking for, we have
to grope our way around the evolutionary tree, with
only our own experience of consciousness as a guide.
Some signs seem obvious. Chimpanzees recognise
themselves in the mirror. Scrub jays will sneak back and
re-cache food if another bird watched them hide it the
first time – unless the watcher is their mate. Rats that
push the wrong lever and fail to get a food reward gaze
regretfully at the lever they should have pushed. In
PABLO HURTADO DE MENDOZA
PREVIOUS PAGE: LUMEZIA/ISTOCK these cases, we can infer some sort of awareness of >

20 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


Chapter 2 | Conscious minds | 21
self, of others and of what might have been, which associated with reward pathways. He believes
looks a lot like what we recognise in ourselves as this is evidence that the ability to assign value to
consciousness (see “10 signs of consciousness”, an experience arose around 300 million years ago
page 25). If this were the sole criterion, however, in the common ancestor of modern reptiles, birds
there would be precious few non-human animals that and mammals – the first fully terrestrial vertebrate.
cleared the bar, as not many show more than a few of the It makes sense. This ancestor would have faced
outward signs we might relate to our consciousness. challenges that its aquatic cousins didn’t, like
temperature regulation and water conservation.
→- Simple animals have reflex, or “unconscious”,
Chapter 3 has more on the sense of self- responses, and even a worm can learn a fixed
behaviour pattern by trial and error, but an individual
There is reason to consider a broader benchmark: with hedonic valuation is capable of much more
not every conscious experience is as complex as flexible behaviour. In this new environment, such
regret or self-awareness, even for us. “If you ask adaptability would have been a big advantage.
yourself, what are you conscious of… you see colours, Not that it doesn’t have disadvantages, too.
you smell coffee, you feel your aches and pains,” says Compared with unconscious processing of sensory
Jesse Prinz, a philosopher at the CUNY Graduate Center data, it is slow and energy intensive, and can only
in New York. “Consciousness looks like it’s largely do one thing at a time. What’s more, it can lead to
about perception and emotion: it’s not about thought behaviours that are capricious or even detrimental
or higher, more human capacities.” These basic to the individual – for example, there would be no
components of conscious experience could be self-harm without conscious thought.
widespread, even in animals that lack our mental Nevertheless, it seems to be useful enough that it
sophistication and brainpower. might have evolved more than once. In 2020, Andreas
Consider emotion – or “hedonic valuation”, to Nieder at the University of Tübingen in Germany
use a less anthropocentric term. As Prinz points conducted an ingenious experiment to discover the
out, much of our conscious experience consists brain processing underpinning visual consciousness
of perceptions with shades of feeling: objects are in corvids such as crows. The birds were trained to
comforting or scary, sounds are pleasing or annoying, respond to different coloured squares, some of them
our body feels good or bad. Such evaluations play almost imperceptibly faint. Neurons in a region called
a crucial role in guiding our behaviour. the pallial endbrain lit up whenever the crows reported
“Behaviour is about moving toward what is seeing the squares, but not when they failed to spot
beneficial or moving away from what isn’t. Feelings them, suggesting that this area is essential for their
are meant to guide us by offering positive and negative conscious visual perception. In humans and primates,
rewards,” says evolutionary biologist Bjørn Grinde at a different part of the brain, the prefrontal cortex,
the Norwegian Institute of Public Health in Oslo. That performs the same job. For this reason, Nieder thinks
makes hedonic valuation a useful evolutionary tool. that consciousness probably emerged separately on
Grinde believes this sensation – the awareness multiple occasions, in much the same way that wings
that something good (or bad) is happening to you – appeared separately in insects, birds and bats.
may represent the dawn of consciousness. Surveying
the vertebrate family tree, he sees a clear pattern: ←-
mammals, birds and reptiles all show signs of Turn back to page 10 for more on locating-
emotional responses, such as an increased heart the seat of human consciousness-
rate and elevated body temperature when handled,
while fish and amphibians don’t. The brains of higher While many researchers agree that mammals, birds
vertebrates are also much richer in receptors for and reptiles have something special, many others
dopamine, the neurotransmitter most closely believe consciousness is found elsewhere in the animal

22 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


Signs of consciousness have been found in animals from at kingdom too. They point out that the signs of emotion
least three different phyla, suggesting it evolved more than become harder to discern the further we get from
once and is far more common than most people think ourselves. Would we recognise the expression of
feelings in a fish, let alone a fruit fly? Instead, many
researchers are converging on another indicator.
Forget about sophisticated abilities like emotion,
CHORDATES reason or imagination. An animal is conscious,
they propose, if it experiences the world subjectively:
if it has the distinctive “me, here, now” element of
ECHINODERMS our own experience.
Like hedonic valuation, subjective experience
allows behavioural flexibility that goes beyond mere
ARTHROPODS reflex responses. It sounds like a plausible basis for
consciousness, but how can you measure an animal’s
subjective experience? Bruno van Swinderen thinks
he has found a way. A neuroscientist at the University
ROUNDWORMS of Queensland in Brisbane, Australia, he believes the
essence of subjectivity is selective attention – focusing
on just a few elements among all the sensory
ANNELIDS information available – because it indicates that an
individual is taking control of its perception. “I’m
not sure there’s really much difference between
MOLLUSCS subjective experience and selective attention,” he says.
To discover whether fruit flies are capable of selective
attention, van Swinderen trained them to walk on a
trackball suspended on a cushion of air, in front of a
ROTIFERS
virtual scene projected onto a wrap-around wall of
LEDs. By rotating the trackball, the flies could shift the
scene and choose which of two objects to pay attention
FLATWORMS to. The images flickered at different rates, so that
when a fly was paying attention to a particular object,
it produced telltale frequencies in its neural activity,
CNIDARIANS recorded by probes implanted in its brain. The results
were remarkable. “It’s like a spotlight. There’s a
dynamic window of attention that’s moving around,
SPONGES and other competing objects are being suppressed,”
says van Swinderen. “The small fly brain really has
a capacity for attention. That is, to me, the dawn of
consciousness.”
Measuring attention like this is very labour
intensive, but there might be an easier way: so far,
it  seems like the animals that can pay attention
are also the ones that need to sleep. These include
vertebrates, insects, crustaceans and octopuses, but
probably not more lumpen animals such as starfish,
worms, and jellyfish. >

Chapter 2 | Conscious minds | 23


→- that you are focusing on something and understand
Chapter 4 has more on sleep and dreaming- how quickly you can shift focus and so forth. According
to Graziano’s “attention schema” idea, this model –
Intriguingly, van Swinderen has also found that not selective attention per se – is responsible for our
insects and vertebrates respond almost identically conscious awareness of the world. He speculates that
to general anaesthetics. “The concentration to knock such a level of mental sophistication may only be
out a fly is pretty much the same as the concentration found in vertebrates.
to knock out an elephant,” hinting that the two lose
consciousness in a similar way, he says. By contrast, ↓-
nematode worms, which are unlikely to have selective Michael Graziano explains his ideas on-
attention or anything approaching consciousness, page 30 later in this chapter-
require 10 times as much anaesthetic before they
stop moving. Evolutionary biologist Eva Jablonka at Tel Aviv
University, Israel, also thinks there is more to
→- consciousness than selective attention. She believes we
Turn to page 62 for more on anaesthetics- should be looking for “unlimited associative learning”
as a marker for the origin of consciousness.
The hunt for selective attention suggests that This is the ability to knit multiple cues into a single
something like consciousness occurs in vertebrates, perception that is more than the sum of its parts, and
insects and octopuses at the very least. We know that then use that compound cue to drive behaviour. This
the common ancestor of these three groups was a very allows animals to respond flexibly to the challenges
simple organism that resembled a flatworm. Modern they face, rather than relying on hardwired behaviours.
flatworms show few, if any, signs of rudimentary It means, for instance, that they can better discriminate
consciousness, so it seems a safe bet that the common between a healthy and a poisonous source of food
ancestor also lacked consciousness. If so, that means based on small perceptual differences. It is also what
consciousness evolved separately in the three groups. allows us to learn that a growling dog may be playful
That reinforces Grinde’s idea about the function in one context but threatening in another. “That
of consciousness. “When you step back and start to marks the beginning of minimal consciousness,”
reflect on why these systems arise where they do, the says Jablonka.
story seems to make sense,” says Prinz. All three groups Unlimited associative learning requires an array of
feature nimble, fast-moving animals that encountered brain functions, not only selective attention, but also
rapidly changing conditions as they moved. That the ability to combine sensations into one perception,
puts a premium on flexible decision-making. perform compound action patterns and distinguish
However, not everyone is convinced that being between self and environment. Scientists have found
able to direct focus is a signifier of consciousness. evidence that this complex learning is surprisingly
Selective attention is about data handling, says widespread throughout the animal kingdom. “Even
Michael Graziano, a neuroscientist at Princeton little fish are able to do this,” says Jablonka. Already,
University. To act on that data, an animal needs a researchers have documented it in almost every
mental model of that attention, for much the same vertebrate (except, possibly, lampreys); some
reasons it needs a mental model of its body. “It’s fine arthropods, such as insects and crustaceans;
for me to say ‘arm, go here’,” says Graziano. “But a few molluscs including octopuses; and, perhaps,
something in my brain needs to have a model of some snails. The jury is out on other groups, such as
what an arm is, its possible motions, and so on.” worms, since we don’t have enough evidence to be sure.
Similarly, a model of attention would recognise “There are huge gaps in our knowledge,” says Jablonka.

24 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


alive today, and Jablonka suggests that consciousness –
driven by selection for powerful learning ability –
TEN SIGNS OF might have helped drive that rapid evolution.
Predators, for example, would have been better at
CONSCIOUSNESS detecting their prey, which, in turn, would have needed
to find new ways to avoid detection – pushing the
Our assessment of the degree to which predators to become even more sophisticated in their
something is conscious is necessarily strategies. “There is a kind of ongoing co-evolutionary
anthropocentric, as we can go only on our – highly arms race,” says Jablonka. “I can’t think of many things
imperfect – understanding of what consciousness that could change adaptability that dramatically.”
is and what it relates to in ourselves. But some or But the emergence of consciousness didn’t just allow
all of these characteristics in other animals are animals to adopt more complex behaviours. Jablonka
often seen as indicating some degree of inner life. suggests that it is responsible for much of the beauty
• Recognises itself in a mirror that we see in nature too. It led different species to
• Has insight into the minds of others evolve camouflage, for example. And it pushed plants
• Displays regret at having made a bad decision to evolve colourful flowers that would stick out from
the competition to attract pollinating insects. “It
• Heart races in stressful situations
changed the world completely,” she says. “The world
• Has many dopamine receptors in
would have been a very different place, and a very
its brain to sense reward
much more boring place, without consciousness.”
• Highly flexible in making decisions It is early days when it comes to considering
• Has ability to focus attention consciousness in an evolutionary context. While
(selective experience) researchers have yet to reach a consensus on when
• Needs to sleep it arose and which animals possess it, they have
• Is sensitive to anaesthetics already enriched our understanding of what
• Displays unlimited associative learning consciousness is, and what is and isn’t distinctive
about our own version of it.
But the fact that the rudiments of consciousness are
all around us has come as a surprise to many. “When I
started, I was really sure we would find it in mammals.
↓- I was pretty convinced we wouldn’t find it elsewhere,”
See the next section for more on- says Prinz. “I have been absolutely convinced that the
other animals’ consciousness- contrary is true. The basic mechanisms can be found
in creatures of an enormous variety.”
Nevertheless, what we already know has led Jabonka to Another lesson we can draw from this approach is
suspect that consciousness evolved in early vertebrates that consciousness isn’t clear-cut. “I don’t think we’re
and early arthropods during the Cambrian explosion, ever going to find a single dividing line between those
about 540 million years ago, when these groups species that enjoy the glow of an inner universe and
diversified rapidly. Consciousness in octopuses, those that don’t,” says Seth. “There is not just one single
meanwhile, probably evolved about 250 million way of being conscious. The animal kingdom is going
years later, after their lineage diverged from other, less to be suffused with other kinds of minds and other
intellectually gifted molluscs such as clams and snails. kinds of consciousness, and they’re not going to be
This origin is interesting. The Cambrian explosion just mini versions of human consciousness. We’re
saw the emergence of most of the major animal groups not the centre of the universe.”  ❚

Chapter 2 | Conscious minds | 25


Evidence of what seem to be conscious behaviours is rife, not just among warm-blooded
mammals and birds, but in very different animals such as octopuses and even spiders.
Getting inside these alien minds is extremely challenging indeed.

INSIDE
HILDREN know the fun of throwing
a ball into the sea, only to watch the
waves fling it back. Jennifer Mather,
a comparative psychologist at the

ANIMAL
University of Lethbridge in Alberta,
Canada, and Roland Anderson,
a marine biologist at the Seattle
Aquarium in Washington, were

MINDS surprised to find octopuses playing


similar games. Their toy was a floating
pill bottle, which they were free to ignore or explore as
they wished. Six of the aquarium’s octopuses soon lost
interest, but two showed childlike curiosity, pushing
it with their arms or shooting jets of water to move it
against the tank’s current. It is hard to interpret this
as anything other than play, which many researchers
argue requires some form of conscious awareness.
Octopuses seem to play, plan and The challenge, of course, is to understand how the
learn by observation – all abilities we inner lives of these creatures differ from our own. In the
associate with conscious experience past, scientists spoke about “levels of consciousness”,
as if there were a hierarchy with humans on top.
Philosopher Jonathan Birch at the London School of
Economics has argued, however, that we would do
better to consider five separate broad aspects of what
we might call conscious experience (see “Five elements
of consciousness”, page 28). According to Birch and his
colleagues, it doesn’t make sense to ask whether one
animal is more or less conscious than another, since
each species may score highly on some of these facets
of consciousness, but low on others.
Research by Birch’s co-author Nicola Clayton at
the University of Cambridge offers a good example.
The propensity of scrub jays to bury food to eat later
demonstrates high temporality because it involves
planning for future scarcity and remembering the
location of caches. Their use of deception when
hiding food in the presence of a rival bird, meanwhile,
PIOLA666/ISTOCK

shows theory of mind, which suggests a relatively


sophisticated sense of selfhood, too.
Cephalopods, by contrast, haven’t yet shown

26 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


evidence of self-recognition. But the octopuses’ to his mate. These look a lot like conscious decisions
enjoyment of play may be a sign that cephalopods based on the information at hand.
can experience something akin to pleasure – Some octopuses also use tools, and will, for example,
evidence of some evaluative richness. They also hulk a heavy shell around all day in case it comes in
have extraordinary perceptual richness, with handy for shelter later on. This suggests an ability to
complex vision that can detect polarised light plan ahead, showing the kind of complex decision-
and the ability to taste by touch via their suckers. making that defines consciousness. “Tool use and
And if you consider essential elements of observational learning suggests to me that if you are
consciousness to be a notion of self in space and an able to look at another entity and know that it is ‘other’,
ability to make decisions based on information from then there’s likely to be a sense of self,” says Jennifer
previous experience and the current situation, then Basil, a cephalopod researcher at the City University of
cephalopods pass with flying colours. Experiments in New York. However, she warns that when a creature is
the 1980s, for example, involved offering octopuses a so different to us, it is difficult to have any idea of what
tasty hermit crab with a stinging anemone on its back. they are thinking, or even if they are thinking at all.
Unlike other predators, the octopuses didn’t back off Perhaps the most startling difference between
after the first sting. Instead, they tried various strategies species concerns the unity of their conscious
to get rid of the anemone: jetting water at it from their experience. Humans have two eyes, but we seamlessly
siphon, attacking from below and attempting to integrate the two visual fields into a single conscious
delicately extract the crab with one tentacle. experience, thanks to the thick nerve tract connecting
Octopuses show similar cunning when they are our left and right brain hemispheres. Birds lack that
presented with a clam. They will often try to get at the connective structure, leading Birch and his colleagues
meat inside by drilling a hole with their beak, before to speculate that within each individual, there may
injecting a poison to stop the clam’s heart or disable be “a pair of conscious subjects, intimately
the muscles that clamp the shell shut. “There is some cooperating with each other”.
evidence that the location of the hole that is drilled In the octopus, meanwhile, two-thirds of its
is learned – it is no use putting it in most places,” says neurons are located in its arms, and there is some
Mather. “I think that this has to be ‘decision-making’.” evidence that each limb operates semi-autonomously.
There are numerous other examples of the kinds “You could conceive of there being eight conscious
of advanced abilities that might constitute conscious experiences associated with the different arms, that
thought. Octopuses and cuttlefish can learn by are partially unified with the experience associated
observing each other, for example, something that with the brain,” says Birch.
suggests a notion of “self” and “other” and perhaps That is a consciousness so alien that it is almost
the ability to put themselves mentally in that position. impossible for us to imagine – but it is perhaps not
Cuttlefish also seem able to send contradictory signals even the most surprising evidence of consciousness
simultaneously: a male might show a courtship display we have found. The way web-spinning spiders tailor
to a female facing one side of his body and a “back off” their constructions to fit into restricted spaces or
display on the other to a challenging male, for instance. around obstacles suggests the abilities both to plan
At other times, a male might try to deceive his love and to form a mental representation of space. That is
rivals by wearing a female-like pattern that leads the particularly impressive when you consider that most
other males to believe he is no threat, as he edges closer spiders are almost completely blind. Other species of >

Chapter 2 | Conscious minds | 27


hunting spider also seem to plan routes, and even seem
capable of being surprised.
FIVE ELEMENTS OF Such findings, combined with new evidence of spider
sociability, indicate advanced cognition across many
CONSCIOUSNESS spider species. Yet the brains of these creatures are
often minute: most orb weaver spiders, for instance,
To avoid searching for traits specific to humans weigh between 50 and 80 milligrams, with some less
in other animals, Jonathan Birch, a philosopher than 1 milligram, and their brains are just a fraction
at the London School of Economics, and his of that. Spiders’ ancient origins also raise some
colleagues suggest we should concentrate profound philosophical questions about the evolution
on five broad aspects of conscious experience of the brain. Previously, we have tended to look for
that can be used to distinguish different intelligence in our closer relatives, but broadening the
animals’ degree of consciousness. web to animals like spiders has proved profitable. “The
success of this line of research shows that we should
be careful not to restrict our research questions or
PERCEPTUAL RICHNESS study species,” says Caroline Strang at the University
How well an animal can discriminate different of Texas at Austin, who investigates insect cognition.
details in each of its senses. It is exciting, too, because it means that spiders could
provide valuable information about which neural
EVALUATIVE RICHNESS structures are necessary for conscious experience, as
Broadly speaking, the capacity to differentiate well as how these evolved. In a vertebrate, the midbrain
between positive rewards and noxious stimuli, gathers sensory information and bodily signals, then
which could be analogous to human emotions integrates these to create a mental simulation of the
such as pleasure or pain. world and the creature’s place in it. This, in turn, directs
its attention and movement according to its needs,
UNITY creating an “experiential consciousness” on which to
The extent to which an animal integrates build other types of awareness, such as self-reflection.
the information from its sensory organs “It basically underpins everything,” says Andrew
into a single experience. Barron at Macquarie University, Australia.
Invertebrate brains take a different form, but a
TEMPORALITY structure called the central complex shows the same
Whether a creature’s past experience influences connectivity in insects, argues Barron. In spiders, a
its present behaviour, and whether it can plan region known as the arcuate body may have the same
for the future and make decisions. purpose. Detailed studies of spider brains have been
low on neuroscientists’ lists of priorities. However, if
SELFHOOD further evidence supports the idea that these regions
This may be tested by assessing whether create an inner representation of the world, this could
an animal recognises itself in the mirror, or help us pinpoint a date for the emergence of conscious
has so-called theory of mind – the ability to experiences – potentially more than half a billion years
understand that another animal has its own mind. ago, when the Cambrian explosion gave rise to almost all
the animal groups around today. It means consciousness
may be far more widespread than we thought.  ❚

28 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


Sentient machines are a science-fiction staple – but are they
possible, and would we know if one were? The answers may
depend on how you view consciousness.

COULD A ROBOT EVER


BE CONSCIOUS?
F THE subjective feeling of consciousness is humans, and what it is made of (brain organoids,
an illusion created by brain processes, then for example, are made of biological material).
machines that replicate such processes would Identifying consciousness in a machine may be
be conscious in the way that we are. How more straightforward if you subscribe to the integrated
would we know this? Daniel Dennett at Tufts information theory of consciousness. In principle, this
University in Massachusetts says a Turing test, simply entails ensuring that phi, a quantity indicating
in which a machine has to convince a human the degree of information integration within the
interrogator that it is conscious, should, system, is greater than zero. In practice, calculating
if conducted “with suitable vigour and phi is computationally intractable for anything but
aggression and cleverness”, be enough. the simplest of systems. So, even if a machine were
Michael Graziano at Princeton University thinks we designed to integrate information, it would be far
could take a more direct approach. His attention schema beyond our abilities to tell whether it is conscious.
hypothesis sees consciousness as the brain’s simplified
model of its own workings – a representation of how ←-
it represents things. He believes it is possible to build a Page 14 has more on the integrated-
machine that possesses a similar self-reflective model. information model-
“If we can build it in a way that we [can] see into its
guts, then we will know this is a machine that has a Phil Maguire at the National University of Ireland,
rich self-description,” he says. “It is a machine that Maynooth, goes further. He notes that, by definition,
thinks and believes it has consciousness. And those integrated systems can’t be understood by looking at
are confirmable because you can understand, in their parts. “Machines are made up of components
principle, how the machine is processing information.” that can be analysed independently,” he says. “They are
For Graziano, consciousness could appear in disintegrated. Disintegrated systems can be understood
any machine, whether it is purely in software or without resorting to the interpretation of consciousness.”
constructed of matter, biological or otherwise. In other words, machines can’t be conscious.
Anil Seth at the University of Sussex, UK, isn’t so sure. Selmer Bringsjord at Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute
“I think it is still an unknown whether consciousness in Troy, New York, agrees – but for different reasons. He
is substrate-independent,” he says. For him, thinks our subjective feeling of being conscious is the
determining whether a machine is conscious requires outcome of non-material stuff of some sort, and that this
making informed judgements based on whether, is crucial for some of our intelligent behaviour. For him,
for example, it has analogues of brain structures that machines can never possess this essence, so will never
we know are important for consciousness in be conscious or intelligent in the way that we are.  ❚

Chapter 2 | Conscious minds | 29


PERSPECTIVE MICHAEL GRAZIANO

“CONSCIOUSNESS
IS AN ENGINEERING
PHENOMENON”
One possible reason for the existence of NGINEERING, and the science of robotics
in particular, tells us that every good
subjective experience is that it emerges control device needs a model – a quick
from the way our brain regulates itself. sketch – of what it controls. We already
know from cognitive neuroscience
that the brain constructs many internal
models, bundles of information that
represent items in the real world. These
models are simplified descriptions,
useful but not entirely accurate.
For example, the brain has a model of the body,
called the body schema, to help control movement
of the limbs. When someone loses an arm, the model
PROFILE of the arm can linger on in the brain so that people
MICHAEL report feeling a ghostly, phantom limb. But the truth
GRAZIANO is, all of us have phantom limbs, because we all have
internal models of our real limbs that merely become
more obvious if the real limb is gone.
Michael Graziano is By the same engineering logic, the brain needs to
a neuroscientist and model many aspects of itself to be able to monitor and
psychologist at Princeton control itself. It needs a kind of phantom brain. One
University and the part of this self-model may be particularly important
author of books for consciousness. Here’s why.
Too much information flows through the brain at
including Rethinking
any moment for it all to be processed in equal depth.
Consciousness: To handle that problem, the system evolved a way to
A scientific theory of focus its resources and shift that focus strategically
subjective experience from object to object: from a nearby object to a distant
sound, or to an internal event such as an emotion or
memory. Attention is the main way the brain seizes
on information and processes it deeply. To control
its roving attention, the brain needs a model, which
I call the attention schema.

30 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


The attention schema theory explains why people artificial attention, a model of that attention, the right
think there is a hard problem of consciousness at all. range of content (information about things like senses
Efficiency requires the quickest and dirtiest model and emotions) and a sophisticated search engine to
possible, so the attention schema leaves aside all the access the internal models and talk about them.
little details of signals and neurons and synapses. The first component, attention, is one of the most
Instead, the brain describes a simplified version of basic processes in most nervous systems. It is nicely
itself, then reports this as a ghostly, non-physical described by the global workspace theory. If you look
essence, a magical ability to mentally possess items. at an object, such as an apple, the brain signals related
Introspection – or cognition accessing internal to the apple may grow in strength and consistency.
information – can never return any other answer. It With sufficient attentional enhancement, these signals
is like a machine stuck in a logic loop. The attention can reach a threshold where they achieve “ignition”
schema is like a self-reflecting mirror: it is the brain’s and enter the global workspace. The visual information
representation of how the brain represents things, about the apple becomes available for systems around
and is a specific example of higher-order thought. the brain, such as speech systems that allow you to talk
In this account, consciousness isn’t so much an about the apple, motor systems that allow you to reach
illusion as a self-caricature. for it, cognitive systems that allow you to make high-
A major advantage of this idea is that it gives a level decisions about it and memory systems that
simple reason, straight from control engineering, allow you to store that moment for possible later use.
for why the trait of consciousness would evolve in
the first place. Without the ability to monitor and ←-
regulate your attention, you would be unable to Turn back to page 14 for an explanation-
control your actions in the world. of global workspace theory-
That makes the attention schema essential
for survival. Consciousness, in this view, isn’t just Scientists have already built artificial versions of
smoke and mirrors, but a crucial piece of the engine. attention, including at least a simple version of
It probably co-evolved with the ability to focus the global workspace. But these machines show
attention, just as the arm schema co-evolved with no indication of consciousness.
the arm. In which case, it would have originated as The second component that our conscious machine
early as half a billion years ago. requires is an attention schema, the crucial internal
Sometimes, the best way to understand a thing is model that describes attention in a general way, and
to try to build it. According to this new idea, we should in so doing informs the machine about consciousness.
be able to engineer human-like consciousness into It depicts attention as an invisible property, a mind
a machine. It would require just four ingredients: that can experience or take possession of items, >

Chapter 2 | Conscious minds | 31


PERSPECTIVE MICHAEL GRAZIANO

something that in itself has no physical substance but other than as a statistical clustering of words. In
still lurks privately inside an agent. Build that kind of contrast, the human brain can translate speech into
attention schema, and you will have a machine that non-verbal information and back again. If someone
claims to be conscious in the same ways that people do. asks you how the taste of a lemon compares with that
The third component our machine needs is of an orange, you can translate the speech into taste
the vast stream of material that we associate with information and compare the two remembered tastes,
consciousness. Ironically, the hard problem – getting then translate back into words to give your answer.
the machine to be conscious at all – may be the easy This easy back-and-forth conversion between speech
part, and giving the machine the range of material and many other information domains is challenging
of which to be conscious may be the hard part. Efforts to do artificially. Our conscious machine would need
to build conscious content might begin with sensory to correlate information across every imaginable
input, especially vision, because so much is known domain, a problem that hasn’t yet been solved in
about how sensory systems work in the brain and artificial intelligence.
how they interact with attention. But a rich sensory Given all the promise and all the difficulties,
consciousness on its own won’t be enough. Our just how close are we to conscious machines?
machine should also be able to incorporate internal If the attention schema approach is correct, the first
items, such as abstract thought and emotion. Here, attempts at visual consciousness could be built with
the engineering problem becomes really tricky. Little existing technology. But it will take a lot longer to give
is known about the information content in the brain machines a human-like stream of consciousness. It will
that lies behind abstract thought and emotion, or take time to build a conscious machine that is capable
how they intersect with the mechanisms of attention. of seeing, hearing, tasting, touching, thinking abstract
Sorting out how to build a machine with that content thoughts and feeling emotions, with a single integrated
could take decades. focus of attention to coordinate within and between all
The final component that our conscious machine those domains, and that is able to talk about this full
requires is a talking search engine. Strictly speaking, range of content. But I believe it will happen.
talking isn’t necessary for consciousness, but for most To me, though, the purpose of this thought
people the goal of artificial consciousness is a machine experiment isn’t to advocate for conscious robots.
that has a human-like ability to speak and understand. The point is that consciousness itself can be
We want to have a good conversation with it. understood. It isn’t an ethereal essence or an
The problem is deceptively hard. We already have inexplicable mystery. The attention schema idea
digital assistants like Siri and Alexa, but these are puts it in context and gives it a concrete role in
limited in their functions. You give them words, they adaptation and survival. Instead of an ill-defined
search for words on the internet and they then give you epiphenomenon, a fog extruded by the brain and
back more words. If you ask for the nearest restaurant, floating between the ears, consciousness becomes
the digital assistant doesn’t know what a restaurant is, a crucial component of the cognitive machine.  ❚

32 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


ESSENTIAL GUIDES

NEW SCIENTIST
ESSENTIAL GUIDES
DELIVERED DIRECT TO YOUR DOOR
&EWIHSRXLIFIWXGSZIVEKIJVSQ2I[7GMIRXMWXXLI)WWIRXMEP+YMHIWEVI
GSQTVILIRWMZIRIIHXSORS[GSQTIRHMYQWGSZIVMRKXLIQSWXI\GMXMRK
XLIQIWMRWGMIRGIERHXIGLRSPSK]XSHE]
+IXXLIWIVMIWMRGPYHMRKXLIVIGIRXP]TYFPMWLIHMWWYISR0MJISR)EVXL
[MXLER)WWIRXMEP+YMHIWWYFWGVMTXMSR-XQIERW]SYHSR
XLEZIXSWIEVGLJSV
MWWYIWMRXLIWLSTWr[IGERHIPMZIVXLIQHMVIGXXS]SYVHSSV

FOR MORE INFORMATION ON FUTURE ISSUES AND SUBSCRIPTION OFFERS, VISIT:


NEWSCIENTIST.COM/ESSENTIALGUIDE
CHAPTER 3

34 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


A sense of existence is essential to consciousness as we
experience it. There is something it is like to be us, and
perhaps to be a scrub jay, or an octopus, or a newborn child.
Presumably, there is nothing it is like to be a table or an iPhone.

Self-awareness and its related trait of metacognition, the


ability to monitor your own mental states and those of others,
are often regarded as the pinnacles of consciousness. In fact,
they might be evolutionary accidents, and perhaps even figments
of our own imaginations.

Chapter 3 | Your conscious self | 35


ANY psychologists and

THE anthropologists hold to the


idea that there is a hierarchy of
consciousness that corresponds

EVOLUTION
with increasing brain complexity.
At its base is the minimal
consciousness attributed to
animals with simple nervous

OF THE SELF systems. These minds are thought


to be permanently adrift in a sea
of raw sensory experiences, tossed around between
perceptions such as colour, hunger, warmth and fear,
with little awareness of their meaning.
Look into a mirror and you may see pimples, ←-
wrinkles or unruly facial hair, but beneath the Turn back to chapter 2 for-
superficial lies something far more interesting. more on animal minds-
Every time you lock eyes with your reflection, Few minds are sophisticated enough to experience the
world differently – through an introspective lens. Even
you know exactly who is looking back at you. then, they may have a limited sense of self. Only at the
peak of mental complexity do we find minds able to
construct a lifelong narrative of experiences centred
around an abstract concept of “self”. These are the elite.
There is no question that some brains are much
bigger and more structurally complicated than others.
This disparity is mainly the result of the differing
evolutionary demands that animals must meet to
survive. For example, the nervous system of a sedentary,
filter-feeding oyster consists of just two cell clusters.
These allow it to do exactly what an oyster needs to do –
control its digestion and transmit signals from light-
sensing tentacles to the muscle that snaps it shut when
a predator looms. Meanwhile, at the other end of the
spectrum, there is one particular demand that seems to
have led to the evolution of complex brains. It could also
have created the conditions for a sense of self to arise.
That challenge is dealing with the minds of others –
be they prey, competitors or other members of your
social group. According to the social brain hypothesis,
developed by Robin Dunbar at the University of
Oxford, life in tight-knit communities hinges
PABLO HURTADO DE MENDOZA
PREVIOUS PAGE: LUMEZIA/ISTOCK on being able to understand what is going on >

36 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


Chapter 3 | Your conscious self | 37
Like humans, mice, ravens and chimps have
general intelligence, indicating that even animals
with small brains can think flexibly

MOUSE RAVEN CHIMP HUMAN

0.4g 10.2g 380g 1350g


71 million neurons 1.2 billion neurons 28 billion neurons 86 billion neurons

in another individual’s mind. of buffalo meat – and thereby deducing where the herd
That could be the basis of our distinctive human had been grazing. The key point is that, to achieve an
consciousness. In the 1970s, the idea emerged that it was understanding of the minds of others, brains needed
the need to understand other people’s minds that made to evolve from being simply things that experience
us aware of our own. “It is more difficult to anticipate sensations and thoughts to becoming their observer.
the perceptions of others if you cannot perceive your Not everyone thinks we should put a sense of
own,” says David Barash, a psychologist at the University self on a pedestal, however. “Self-awareness is not
of Washington in Seattle. That might suggest human higher-order, or intrinsically more complicated, than
consciousness scaled greater heights as our ape-like consciousness,” says neuroscientist Michael Graziano
ancestors started living in larger social groups, with the at Princeton University. “It is another example of
ensuing daily potential for aggression and competition. consciousness.” In his view, a mind is just an object
This isn’t the only hypothesis that relates the that some brains can model, and so become aware
evolution of “higher” consciousness to group living. of. And once the biological machinery for such model-
But for neuroscientist Chris Frith at University College building evolved, it could be used to represent not
London, the benefits concern cooperation rather than only the minds of others, but also one’s own mind.
competition. “It’s so that we can talk to each other Most researchers agree that the brain operates at
about experiences,” he says. least partly by generating simulations. However, some
Frith’s group has shown that people make better disagree that self-awareness is a functional piece of
decisions in laboratory tasks if they are allowed to the modelling machinery. Indeed, some think it is the
mull over the pros and cons of the evidence with unintended, “emergent” by-product of information
a partner. That might sound obvious, but it is hard rushing through the closed loop of connections that
to imagine a zombie with no inner life whatsoever is the brain. It serves no particular purpose, rather like
being able to do so, as it requires reflection and the noise emitted by a running engine has no bearing
introspection – key traits we associate with on the workings of the engine itself.
consciousness. “We have to be able to reflect upon our Rather, the tone of this noise reflects the predominant
experiences before we can talk about them,” says Frith. connections in our brains. There will be a huge
Frith’s colleague Geraint Rees gives the example of diversity of emergent mental patterns that serve the
two early humans regarding a distant dust cloud and various survival needs of different species. In bats, for
trying to work out if it signals a herd of buffalo or a pack example, it might be those transmitting information
of lions. The better they are at reflecting on their feelings from the echolocation clicks used to construct a 3D
and judgements, the better their collective decision- model of the world. In humans, it simply seems to
making about whether to hunt or flee. “If you can be the case that the predominant connections in our
combine the forces of your sensory systems, that brains seem to be those used to contemplate the minds
becomes a useful advantage,” says Rees. Yet Frith thinks of others – the same connections used to contemplate
a better example of the benefits of consciousness would ourselves. What emerges from this is a pattern that
be the early humans discussing the characteristic flavour seems constant. To you, that is your sense of self.  ❚

38 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


RUGLIG/ISTOCK

WHAT ANIMALS Magpies and other corvids


recognise themselves in the
ARE SELF-AWARE? mirror – whatever that means

IN THE most widely used test of instance, usually fail the test, yet with flying colours. That hints that
self-awareness, the so-called our more distant primate relatives, there could be many other species
face-mark test, researchers the orangutans, pass it. Also, the with undetected self-awareness.
stealthily apply a spot of odourless self-aware elite contains some Meanwhile, some developmental
dye to an animal’s forehead or bizarre anomalies, such as pigeons, psychologists working with young
cheek and observe its reaction manta rays and ants. Some of these children have long argued that
when it is in front of a mirror. The findings – particularly with ants mirror tests don’t necessarily reveal
underlying premise is that those and pigeons – are contested. an awareness of self that extends
with a firm sense of self can Researchers have tried to explain beyond the here and now.
acknowledge their reflection away others, arguing, for example, Experiments show that children
and attempt to scrub off the dye. that gorillas have mentally can acknowledge themselves in a
Animals that have passed this regressed since their split from mirror at the age of 3, yet cannot
test include chimps, bonobos, the other ape lineages because recognise themselves in videos
orangutans, Asian elephants and they face fewer pressures in taken a few months earlier, and
Eurasian magpies, a member of their environment. will struggle with the idea of existing
the notoriously clever corvid family. Then again, we have reason in the past for another year or two.
Killer whales and bottlenose to believe mirror tests are flawed. And the fact that the majority
dolphins also seem to recognise Rhesus macaques generally fail of animals that pass the self-
themselves in a mirror, although them, but experiments in 2017 by awareness test are either our
their anatomy means they can’t Liangtang Chang at the Shanghai primate relatives or animals with
remove a face mark. This apparent Institutes for Biological Sciences, complex social lives, like us, could
correlation with smarts is why China, and colleagues seem to mean that rather than reflecting
self-awareness has become a suggest this is simply because they mental complexity, the trait simply
sort of proxy for mental complexity. lack the hand-eye coordination to indicates that their minds have
But there are some puzzling rub the dye off. When trained how evolved to face similar challenges
evolutionary gaps. Gorillas, for to do it, they began to pass the test to our own.

Chapter 3 | Your conscious self | 39


IS THE SELF
AN ILLUSION?
We have a strong sense of continuous, E KNOW that we change over
time. Our bodies grow, then
coherent existence, yet from the cells that age; we mature and our views
make our bodies to our defining character shift; our memories sharpen
and fade. Yet for most of us,
traits, we are in a constant state of change. our sense of self is seamless
That suggests a rather different answer. and continuous. You remain
the same old you, right?
That just raises the
question of how. One
interesting perspective on the question is that, while
the cells in many organs in our body live for only days
or weeks before being replaced, the neurons in our
brain are with us from before birth, and can live more
than 100 years. “Most of the nerve cells in the brain are
actually as old as we are,” says molecular biologist
Jonas Frisén at the Karolinska Institute in Sweden.
And it is definitely our brains where we think our
sense of self resides, at least. When Christina Starmans
at the University of Toronto in Canada and her
colleagues showed people from the US and India
pictures of flies circling around a person, and asked
which flies they thought were closest, the results were
striking: regardless of cultural background, most
people pointed to flies near a person’s eyes. “This
suggests there is a universal sense of the self being
located in the head, near the eyes,” says Starmans.
Subjectively at least, the eyes being windows to the
self checks out. “The sense of where in our bodies we
are located is informed by our dominant experience

40 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


SKYNESHER/ISTOCK

Ask most of us where our sense


of self is located and we point to
somewhere near the eyes

of the world,” says Starmans. “Almost all of our input The illusory nature of the continuous self was
from the world comes in through our head.” backed up in 2016 when researchers at the University
And it squares with some objective evidence of Edinburgh, UK, investigated changes in the
too. In some extremely rare brain conditions, behavioural habits that make up our personalities
people have a sense of existing outside their bodies: across a span of 63 years. Previous studies, looking over
those experiencing heautoscopy, for instance, see a shorter periods, found only small changes, suggesting
doppelgänger, and feel they are located both in their that we largely stay the same. But the longer view was
own body and the doppelganger’s. “They are in two startling: measured over six decades, barely anything
places at one time. It’s very disturbing,” says Jane Aspell, about our personalities stays the same. We turn into
a cognitive neuroscientist at Anglia Ruskin University different people over time.
in the UK. Sometimes, people go through major changes all at
Similar illusions can be generated in the lab. once – “something big happens that turns their lives
For example, volunteers who have their back stroked upside down and very thoroughly shakes them up”,
while wearing a virtual reality headset showing a says psychologist Wendy Johnson, a co-author of that
simulation of themselves being stroked start to feel paper. Yet for the most part, our personalities drift
that they are closer to their virtual self than to their through “dribbles of change, conscious and not, in
actual body. Brain scans show that a region called the specific behaviours over long periods of time”, she says.
temporoparietal junction is affected. “This area is key We are strangely skilled at shifting our notions
for the brain computation that creates the perception of who we were or what we believed to maintain
of where your self is located in space,” says Aspell. an illusion of a continuous self. For example, we
So it is tempting to think the continuity of our sense scramble to rewrite history to get our previous
of self has something to do with the physical continuity attitudes to more closely match our current ones,
of our brains. And yet even our long-lived neurons are dismissing the idea that we once held strong
constantly in flux, rewiring themselves to generate political views, say, with which we now disagree.
new thoughts, memories and states of mind. The fact is “You make yourself up in the past,” says Gillmeister.
that what we learn, what we eat, how well we have slept At some level, we are also aware of the disconnect.
and countless other things influence our choices and Studies have demonstrated that we think about our
behaviours all the time. So, in many ways, “you are not future selves in a very different way to how we think
the same person from one moment to the next”, says of ourselves in the moment – in our brains, it is as if
Helge Gillmeister at the University of Essex, UK. future you is a completely different person.  ❚

Chapter 3 | Your conscious self | 41


METACOGNITION:
KNOWING THAT YOU KNOW
While debate rages as to which animals have a sense of self, there is one
trait that, as far as we know, is uniquely human – the ability to think about
what we are thinking and know what we know.

OUR pet dog, if you have one, is probably there could be other explanations for the results.
aware of many sensations at any given Scanning the brains of humans while they carry
moment: that it is hungry, that it is out metacognitive tasks suggests the seat of this ability
tired after a long walk, perhaps, and that lies in our prefrontal cortex, at the front of our heads.
there is a delicious smell emanating But this faculty has been hard to get the measure of.
from the kitchen. If we ask people how sure they are about their answers
As its owner, however, you are aware in a test, say, the results are muddled by the variation
of all those sensations and yet have in people’s ability to do the test. So are you measuring
an extra level of thought processes ability or awareness of that ability?
overlaying them. As a human, we can
be aware that we are aware of our basic sensory inputs, ←-
and that allows us to reflect on the accuracy or validity Turn back to page 10 for more on where-
of our feelings and judgements. That lets us think: the seat of consciousness lies in the brain-
“How tired I am after that long walk, it’s that satisfying
kind of tiredness you get after exercise. But I’m not too Back in 2010, Fleming, then based at New York University,
tired to walk to the pub tonight.” and his colleagues came up with a crucial extra step.
This faculty is often referred to as introspection They flashed two stripy images briefly onto a screen,
or metacognition. “It’s the ability to self-reflect, to separated by a blank image, and asked people to say
know about yourself,” says Steve Fleming, who studies which had the greatest contrast (see picture, top right).
consciousness at University College London. “This is After each question, subjects had to rate how confident
something that we think is, if not unique to humans, they were that they had chosen the right answer.
at least one of the most developed faculties of human Crucially, the contrast of the stripes was adjusted for
psychology.” Fleming dubs this capacity our super- each person so that, no matter how good their vision,
consciousness. “Metacognition seems to be quite everyone got about 70 per cent of the answers right. This
core to who we are,” he says. meant that for the confidence ratings, the only variable
Past research on metacognition has focused on was people’s metacognitive abilities, giving the first
whether it really is unique to humans or whether it demonstration in the lab that this ability varies widely.
is shared to some extent by more intelligent animals. As well as doing these tests, the volunteers also had
There have been hints of this capacity in dolphins their brain scanned, and this revealed that those with
and monkeys, for instance, although sceptics say the best metacognitive abilities had more grey matter

42 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


Metacognition can be tested by getting people to rate which of two images is sharper, and then asking them how
confident they are – but manipulating the images so they can only be right a certain proportion of the time

in an area at the very front of the prefrontal cortex just →-


behind the forehead, known as the anterior prefrontal Chapter 5 has more on altered states of the brain-
cortex. “What is it about this region that gives us
this ability?” asks Fleming. “Could the fact that it She has studied the metacognitive abilities of people
is more developed in humans mean that we have a with schizophrenia using a simple cursor-based
fundamentally different self-awareness to animals?” computer game. At first, the participants were as good
The other classic way of understanding how the brain at judging how well they performed as the group of
works is to look what happens when it isn’t functioning control subjects. But when Metcalfe started secretly
as it should. Take “blindsight”, a very rare condition moving the cursor herself, the control group quickly
usually caused by brain injury. Those affected act as recognised something strange was going on. People
though they are, to all intents and purposes, sightless. in the schizophrenia group, on the other hand, failed
But careful testing reveals they can take in some visual to realise that they were no longer completely
information about the world at an unconscious level. responsible for the cursor’s movements.
When asked to guess what object is in front of them, Some people with schizophrenia come to believe
for instance, they do better than if they had just that others are controlling their behaviour, thinking,
guessed randomly – insisting all the while that for instance, that a microchip has been implanted
they can see nothing. inside their head. “If you don’t know you’re controlling
Blindsight has always been thought to arise from your own behaviour, you could be open to that kind
damage to the visual cortex, at the back of the brain, of symptom,” says Metcalfe.
where information from the optic nerves first arrives. It may be possible to improve people’s metacognitive
But some brain imaging studies, however, suggest that abilities by giving them feedback after the kind of
the damage also affects connections to the prefrontal computer tasks used by Fleming. Metcalfe hopes this
cortex, the same region highlighted by Fleming. will help people with schizophrenia. But suppose the
Less extreme impairments of metacognition rest of us did the same kind of training. Would that give
may be involved in other more common conditions, us a turbocharged super-consciousness? “If you define
such as schizophrenia, which involves delusions and consciousness as what it’s like to see the colour red,
hallucinations. “Schizophrenics have a problem with then it’s not going to change that,” says Fleming. “But
that very central metacognition; that I know I’m me if it’s being able to accurately reflect on what you see,
and I know what I’m doing,” says Janet Metcalfe, also or whether you just made a good decision, then
at Columbia University. training could give it a boost.”  ❚

Chapter 3 | Your conscious self | 43


T HAS long been known that our internal

YOUR organs have lives of their own. They generate


electrical activity, which is conveyed by
neurons to the brain. As a result, signals

CONSCIOUS
from your heartbeat, your breathing, the
slow, regular pulses of your stomach and the
state of your muscles are all represented in
the brain’s electrical activity. The brain, in

BODY
turn, regulates these functions. In other
words, there is a neuronal loop in which
nerve cells carry information from the organs up
to the brain, and commands down to the organs.
However, in the 20th century, neuroscientists
tended to ignore the body. They associated mental
life exclusively with the brain – an approach epitomised
Increasingly, we are realising that conscious by the “brain in a vat” thought experiment, in which
a disembodied brain continues to have normal
experience isn’t just about the brain. Electrical
conscious experiences.
signals coming from your heart and other Things began to change at the turn of this
century, when neuroscientist Antonio Damasio
organs influence how you perceive the world,
at the University of Southern California pioneered
the decisions you take and your sense of the field of embodied consciousness. “I have been
defending the idea that the body is a critical player
who you are, providing a window on
in anything that has to do with mind,” he says. For
consciousness itself. years, he was more or less alone in this view, but now a
handful of researchers have joined him in his quest for
the bodily origins of our sense of self.
Their starting point is interoception, a sort of sixth
sense that we have about what is going on in our own
body. A simple way to measure interoception is to get
someone to count their heartbeats over a fixed time
and compare their count with the actual one measured
by an electrocardiogram (ECG). People’s ability to do
this varies a lot. Those who can sense their heartbeat
most accurately tend to make better intuitive decisions
and are better at perceiving the emotions of others.
What is going on? To tease it out, the researchers
needed a read-out of interoception in the brain. They
found one in the brain’s response to the heartbeat,
known as the heartbeat-evoked potential (HEP). Many
studies focus on this because the HEP is relatively easy
to measure: the heartbeat isn’t completely regular, so

44 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


it is possible to filter the HEP out from all the brain’s pronounced their HEP, the stronger the illusion.
other activity. The HEP can be found by simultaneously Here was the first neurophysiological evidence of a
recording a person’s heartbeat, via an ECG, and link between interoception and the brain’s notion
scanning their brain. It shows up as activity in various of self, claimed the researchers. “The HEP reflects
“resting-state networks” in the brain, which are active changes in bodily self-consciousness such as changes
even when a person isn’t consciously doing anything. in self-identification with – and displacement towards –
One clue as to what the HEP might be doing came the virtual body,” says Olaf Blanke, who heads
in 2016 when neuroscientist Hyeongdong Park at EPFL’s Laboratory of Cognitive Neuroscience.
the Swiss Federal Institute of Technology in Lausanne The EPFL group has gone on to show that our
(EPFL) and his colleagues measured it in people who bodily self is anything but passive – it intervenes in
were experiencing a full-body illusion. Volunteers every decision we make. Blanke’s team has built on
donned a virtual reality headset and watched a work by physiologist Benjamin Libet, who in 1983
simulation of themselves having their back stroked detected a signal that arose in the brain just before
as it was being stroked in reality. After a while, they a person became aware of their intention to act. Libet
described feeling as if they were now physically interpreted it as meaning that there is no such thing
located closer to where their virtual self was, rather as free will. The EPFL group has found that the same
than where they were actually sitting. The more signal is linked with a particular bodily act, breathing:
we are more likely to initiate a voluntary act when
exhaling. Blanke describes the finding as a clear
How accurately someone indication that “acts of free will are hostage to a
can count their own heartbeat is host of inner body states”.
a test of interoceptive ability
↓-
The next section has more on free will-
Such experiments have led Park and Blanke to propose
that signals from the organs, together with signals
from the outside world, feed a representation of the
bodily self to the brain. This includes self-identification
and self-location, as in the full-body illusion. They
also believe that the rhythmic nature of signals from
the organs helps generate a feeling of your self being
continuous in time. “The cyclic pattern of the heartbeat
is predictable,” says Blanke, “and this temporal element
could play a big role in that continuity of self.”
Catherine Tallon-Baudry, a neuroscientist at
the Ecole Normale Supérieure in Paris, France, has a
different conception of how the body contributes to
VOYAGERIX/ISTOCK

self-consciousness. The brain is constantly bombarded


by signals from inside and outside the body and as a
result of its own cognitive processes. The signals are
processed by different brain circuits. She thinks that >

Chapter 3 | Your conscious self | 45


Virtual reality headsets can
be used to create an illusion
of being outside your self

rhythmic signals from the organs impose a unified


frame of reference on the brain. This allows us to
perceive all that incoming information from the
perspective of a single, subjective “I”. “I think of
consciousness as a property that is generated by
the brain once it has integrated information from
the whole organism,” she says. And a series of
experiments supports her contention, she believes.
In 2014, Tallon-Baudry and Park, who worked in her
lab before he moved to Blanke’s, began by exploring
how the HEP might influence our conscious experience
of things. They asked people to fix their gaze on a
central point and to say whether they could see a faint
ring around that point. The bigger a person’s HEP just
before showing them the ring, the more likely they

MAX-KEGFIRE/ISTOCK
were to perceive it. “The heartbeat behaves like an extra
piece of visual information,” says Tallon-Baudry. It also
provides the intrinsic “mineness” of the conscious
experience. “In the person’s response – ‘I saw
something’ – there is that element of ‘I’,” she says.
“We shouldn’t ignore that element of ‘I’ in perception.”
Blanke sees this study as a beautiful demonstration
of the threshold of consciousness, but says there is no brain does indeed discern between the two concepts.
need to conclude that the self is involved. To address Tallon-Baudry’s group has also shown how the body
this issue, Tallon-Baudry and her group devised might contribute to our decisions on our personal
another study. This time, they homed in on the preferences, which in many ways define us in the eyes
distinction between “I” and “me”. Tallon-Baudry says of others. Volunteers saw 200 posters of well-known
“I” captures the most basic aspect of self – the aspect films and were asked to rate the ones they had seen.
that comes before thought, the unified entity that does Next day, they were shown pairs of posters from the
the thinking. It is fundamentally different from the films they had rated, and had to indicate which they
kind of reflection about “me” that implies monitoring preferred as they had their HEP tracked. As is usual
different bodily functions without that sense of unity. with these sorts of experiments, people’s responses
To see if they could show that the brain treats those weren’t wholly consistent. However, people with the
two concepts differently too, Tallon-Baudry’s team biggest HEP at the moment of choice gave answers
asked people who were having their brain scanned that were most in line with their original ratings.
to fixate on a point and then let their mind wander. Their choices were truest to themselves when their
Every now and then, they were interrupted and asked brains were listening most closely to their hearts.
whether – at that precise moment – they were thinking Blanke’s notion of a bodily self and Tallon-Baudry’s
about “me” or “I”, which they had been trained to notion of bodily consciousness may not be too far
recognise. Depending on which they reported, the apart. Indeed, they can imagine hitting on an
HEP occurred in different parts of the brain: a region overarching model of the embodied self that
near the front for “me” thoughts and one further back reconciles their findings.
for “I” thoughts. This showed for the first time that the Sarah Garfinkel at the University of Sussex in the

46 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


UK, meanwhile, has been approaching things from a brain and experienced as emotions or drives – the
different angle. She has been exploring two connected emotion of fear, say, or the drive to eat. Subjectivity
ideas: that bodily signals influence emotions and that evolved later again, he argues. It was imposed by the
emotions shape our sense of self through memory musculoskeletal system, which evolved as a physical
and learning. Working with autistic people, she has framework for the central nervous system and, in so
concluded that the issues they often encounter relating doing, also provided a stable frame of reference: the
to others stem from their brains being overwhelmed unified “I” of conscious experience.
with the visceral inputs associated with their own and While Damasio contemplates a synthesis, the
others’ emotions. other researchers are thinking about applications
Building on the idea of an overactive body-brain of their findings. Garfinkel intends to test her idea
axis, Garfinkel’s research has now turned to a sensation about an overactive heart-brain axis directly in
most of us feel to great or lesser degrees at stages in our people affected by trauma. Already, her results lend
lives: fear. In her most recent study, she has adapted a support to the rationale that drugs designed to act
classic psychology paradigm called fear conditioning, on the cardiovascular system might help treat post-
in which volunteers learn to associate neutral stimuli traumatic stress disorder – and indeed such drugs
with negative consequences. She measured people’s are now in clinical trials.
heartbeats and their skin’s electrical conductivity, Blanke and Park have filed a patent related to
which increases when we feel fearful. Her volunteers the use of breathing patterns to predict behaviour.
showed more fear when stimuli were presented as Among other applications, it could help in tuning
their heart was contracting than when it was relaxing. brain-computer interfaces to be more sensitive to
The phase of the heartbeat also affected how easily the choices of people with disabilities.
those fear responses were evoked later on. “These Tallon-Baudry is working with neurologist Steven
signals from the heart can really drive and override Laureys at the University of Liège in Belgium to study
conditioned fear responses,” she says. the HEP in people with conditions of consciousness,
Garfinkel doesn’t like to talk about consciousness such as coma. They have trained an artificial
because she thinks the concept is woolly. “Consciousness intelligence to learn how the HEP relates to measurable
operates on so many levels,” she says. But she does clinical signs in such patients, to test whether the HEP
believe she is trying to solve the same puzzles as Blanke alone could serve as a diagnostic tool in people whose
and Tallon-Baudry. For Damasio, all three approaches clinical signs are ambiguous – particularly those in
are reconcilable if we take an evolutionary perspective. the grey area known as a minimally conscious state.
Four billion years ago, the first primitive organisms There are philosophical implications to these
monitored changes in their bodily state – equivalent discoveries too. If consciousness is embodied,
to hunger, thirst, pain and so on – and had feedback that could affect how we think about death, which is
mechanisms to maintain equilibrium. The relic currently defined by the World Health Organization
of those primitive mechanisms is our autonomic as the irreversible loss of brain (but not body)
nervous system, which controls bodily functions function. The research also has implications for the
such as heartbeat and digestion, and of which we consciousness of other animals and how we treat them.
are largely unconscious. And if consciousness is embodied, it would mean that
Then, about half a billion years ago, the central a machine or robot with no way of integrating signals
nervous system, featuring a brain, evolved. “It was an from its body will never be truly conscious. “When
afterthought of nature,” says Damasio. But it became you start to think through the implications of the
the “anchor” of what had once been a more distributed embodied self,” says Tallon-Baudry, “they are really
mind. Changes in bodily state were projected onto the quite profound.”  ❚

Chapter 3 | Your conscious self | 47


FREE WILL
AND THE SELF
Our sense of self is based on an assumption so fundamental it seems unassailable:
that we are masters of our own destiny. But the more we unpick the subtle knot tying
conscious experience to the brain, the shakier that assumption feels.

ID I really just decide to up to electrodes. This found stirrings in the brain’s


have fish and chips for prefrontal cortex up to 10 seconds before someone
lunch?” Humans have became aware of having made a decision.
been wrestling with such Although Libet’s work remains controversial, it raises
questions for millennia. a big question: is our unconscious brain really in the
Maybe not about the driver’s seat, with our consciousness a mere passenger?
fish and chips, but about Even if we are driving, we may be on rails. Split-second
whether we are truly life-or-death decisions – a police officer choosing to fire
in control or whether a gun, say – are often made too quickly for conscious
some external agent – deliberation to play a part. Instead, such choices may
be that an omnipotent god or the laws of physics – be guided by hardwired, unconscious bias.
predetermines the trajectory of our lives. Neuroscientist John-Dylan Haynes at the Berlin
Unfortunately, there are no easy answers. Who is Center for Advanced Neuroimaging, who led the brain
the “I” who decided to have fish and chips? Your gut scanning study, warns against jumping to this
reaction might tell you that you are a conscious entity conclusion. “I wouldn’t interpret these early [brain]
controlling your physical body. But that physical body signals as an ‘unconscious decision’,” he says. “I would
includes the brain that generates your consciousness. think of it more like an unconscious bias of a later
There is no splitting the two. decision.” Others agree it is a big extrapolation to claim
The free will debate is an old one, but in the 1980s, that all of our actions are outside our control and there
psychologist Benjamin Libet really stirred things up. is no such thing as free will. “Libet deals with the very
He performed an experiment in which people were short-term precursors of very simple actions,” says
told to wait a little while and then press a button, and Patrick Haggard at University College London.
to note the exact time they decided to act on an ultra- Then again, even longer-term decisions and actions
precise clock. They also had electrodes placed on their are the result of specific brain processes, assuming you
scalp to measure electrical activity in their brain. buy into the physicalist notion that consciousness can
This set-up revealed that neuronal activity preceded be explained by the workings of physical matter at all.
people’s conscious decision to press the button In that view, biological material is nothing more than
by nearly half a second. More recently, a similar agglomerations of atoms and molecules that follow the
experiment placed people in a functional magnetic laws of physics. Whenever you decide something, a
resonance imaging scanner instead of hooking them certain pattern of neurons fires in your brain to turn

48 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


Experiments performed by psychologist Benjamin Libet
in the 1980s seem to challenge the notion of free will

People are asked to note the exact Button pressed


Subject becomes
time on an ultra-precise clock when aware of decision
they first decide to press a button to press

Electrodes on the scalp reveal


Voltage

activity in the brain about half a


second before they are conscious
of their decision to press
First stirrings
of brain activity
Resting

-200 ms 0 Time (ms)

your thought into action – moving towards the kitchen there’s all kinds of influences: cultural influences,
to make coffee, perhaps, or formulating an utterance psychological influences, influences that are
you will come to regret. Ultimately, that is all down to more formative of our psychology that we don’t
pulses of electrons – fundamental particles that follow control and so on.” Our choices are the result of a
the cast-iron laws of physics, under which everything bundle of predilections formed by genetic nature
is determined by what happened immediately before. and environmental nurture – a unique product
of circumstances we aren’t necessarily in
→- immediate control of.
Chapter 6 is all about consciousness and reality- But for Nicholas Humphrey, an emeritus psychologist
at the London School of Economics, acknowledging that
That doesn’t leave much room for free will, apparently. decisions have an involuntary, material cause in brain
“Physical laws, if they’re deterministic, tell me that processes doesn’t amount to denying free will. “On the
everything that I do, everything that happens in the contrary, I’m saying that I, myself, am the cause of it,”
world, including everything that I do, including every he says. Humphrey calls his “I” an “embodied self”:
decision I ever made, follows logically from the laws the sum of the thoughts, beliefs, desires, dispositions
of nature [and] the initial conditions of the universe,” and so on that live within him. The embodied self
says philosopher of physics Jenann Ismael at Columbia might not be conscious of every action, but it ultimately
University in New York. Since we control neither the determines them – a sort of free will on autopilot.
laws of nature nor the initial conditions of the universe, The crucial point is that you can still choose to
we can’t be fully in control of our actions – can we? go against the grain of what you just decided. That,
Not so fast. We should define our terms first, says after all, is the core of free will as we experience it.
philosopher Eleanor Knox at King’s College London. And to say that this sort of free will is incompatible
“There’s this really strong notion of free will, which with deterministic laws of physics is rather to get
is what my students all come into the classroom with,” things the wrong way round, unless you are a diehard
she says. “To have free will, I must right now be able dualist who advocates a non-physical essence of the
to behave just with no connection to any contingent mind. “Whatever we call free will must ultimately be
plan – so however I like.” explicable by the laws of physics,” says Knox. Unless, of
Even leaving physics aside, that clearly isn’t the case. course, you take the illusionist way out – that nothing
“We think that when we make a decision, the locus of we experience necessarily corresponds to anything
control for behaviour is inside,” says Ismael. “But really, happening out there in the real, physical world.  ❚

Chapter 3 | Your conscious self | 49


CHAPTER 4

50 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


Every night, we enter a netherworld of consciousness. The true
purpose of sleep remains unclear, but among organisms with
some degree of consciousness, it seems to be near-universal
that they spend some time in a reduced state of it.

It is also clear is that consciousness isn’t like a light switch,


on when you are awake and off when you are sleeping. Our brains
are in a variety of states of consciousness at different stages
of sleep, as is most obvious in the way we dream – another
great mystery of our brains’ night-time wanderings.

Chapter 4 | Sleep and dreaming | 51


WHY DO
WE SLEEP?
The average human spends about a third of their N THE face of things, it seems obvious
that we sleep so our brains and bodies
life sleeping. If deprived of sleep for too long, we can rest and recuperate. But why not
get physically ill. So it is puzzling that we still rest while conscious, so that we can
also watch out for threats? And if
don’t really know why it is so essential. recuperation means things are being
repaired, why can’t that take place
while we are awake? Scientists who
study how animals eat, learn or
mate are unburdened by questions
about the purpose of these activities. But for sleep
researchers, the “why” is maddeningly mysterious.
Sleep is such a widespread phenomenon that it
must be doing something useful. Even fruit flies and
nematode worms experience periods of inactivity
from which they are less easily roused, suggesting
sleep is a requirement of the simplest of animals.
But surveying the animal kingdom reveals no clear
correlation between sleep habits and some obvious
physiological need. In fact, there is bewildering
diversity in sleep patterns.
Some bats spend 20 hours a day slumbering, while
large grazing mammals tend to sleep for less than 4 hours
a day. Horses, for instance, take naps on their feet for a
few minutes at a time, totalling only about 3 hours daily.
PABLO HURTADO DE MENDOZA
PREVIOUS PAGE: LUMEZIA/ISTOCK In some dolphins and whales, newborns and their >

52 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


Chapter 4 | Sleep and dreaming | 53
One theory about the purpose of sleep says it is to stop our brains being
overloaded by the new memories we form each day

NIGHT
Synapses rebalance
100 80
During sleep, all synapses are
100 scaled down, in proportion to 120
their strength, so that the day's
100 memories are not lost…

150

MORNING EVENING MORNING


80
Cycle starts New memories formed Ready to start again
Two hypothetical synapses each Later, one synapse becomes 120 …while the total strength of all synapses
have a strength of 100 units stronger due to a new memory throughout the brain is returned to what
it was at the start of the day

mothers stay awake for the entire month following birth. over the maintenance angle for over a century. It was
All this variation is vexing to those hoping to once a fashionable idea that some kind of toxin built
discover a single, universal function of sleep. “Bodily up in the brain during our waking hours, which, when
changes in sleep vary tremendously across species,” it reached a certain level, made sleep irresistible.
says Marcos Frank at the University of Pennsylvania Such a substance has never been found, but a
in Philadelphia. “But in all animals studied so far, the modern version of the maintenance hypothesis
[brain] is always affected by sleep.” says that during the day, we deplete supplies of large
So most sleep researchers now focus on the brain. molecules essential for the operation of the brain,
The most obvious feature of sleep, after all, is that including proteins, RNA and cholesterol, and that
consciousness is either lost or, at least in some animals, these are replenished during sleep. It has been found
reduced. And lack of sleep leads to cognitive decline, in animals that production of such macromolecules
not only in humans, but also rats, fruit flies and pretty increases during slow-wave sleep, although critics
much every other species studied. point out that the figures show a mere correlation,
Much of our slumber is spent in slow-wave sleep, also not that levels of these molecules control sleep.
known as stage 3 or deep sleep, during which there are The unique function school of thought also has a long
easily detectable waves of electrical activity across the pedigree. Sigmund Freud proposed that the purpose of
whole brain, caused by neurons firing in synchrony sleep was wish fulfilment during dreaming, although
about once a second. This is interspersed with other scientific support for this notion failed to materialise.
phases, including rapid-eye-movement sleep, where There is good evidence, however, for sleep mediating
brain activity resembles that seen during wakefulness, a different kind of brain function: memory
and transitional stages between the two states. consolidation. Memories aren’t written in stone
It is slow-wave sleep that is generally thought the instant an event is experienced. Instead, initially
to do whatever it is that sleep actually does. As well labile traces are held as short-term memories, before
as appearing to be the most different to the brain’s the most relevant aspects of the experience are
waking activity, the waves are larger at the beginning transferred to long-term storage.
of sleep, when sleep need is presumably greatest, and Several kinds of experiment, in animals and people,
then gradually reduce. And if you go without sleep show that stronger memories form when sleep takes
for longer than usual, these slow waves are larger place between learning and recall. Some of the most
when you do eventually nod off. compelling support for this idea came when electrodes
Explanations for sleep fall into two broad groups: placed into rats’ brains showed small clusters of
those related to brain repair or maintenance, and those neurons “replaying” patterns of activity during sleep
in which the sleeping brain is thought to perform some that had first been generated while the rats had been
unique, active function. There has been speculation awake and exploring. “Memory representations are >

54 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


YOUR BRAIN
WHILE SLEEPING
Some people swear that if they want alarm to jump-start the waking It is an ability that makes good
to wake up at 6 am, they just bang process. The pillow ritual might evolutionary sense, says Kouider.
their head on the pillow six times help set that alarm. “If you stop monitoring your
before going to sleep. Nonsense? The sleeping brain can also environment, you become very
Maybe not. A study from 1999 process language. In a 2014 study, vulnerable during sleep… It makes
shows that it all comes down to Sid Kouider at the École Normale sense that you don’t simply shut
some nifty unconscious processing. Supérieure in Paris and his down, but continue tracking in a kind
For three nights, researchers at colleagues trained volunteers to of standby mode.” This might explain
the University of Lübeck in Germany push a button with their left or right why some sounds, like our names,
put 15 volunteers to bed at midnight. hand to indicate whether they heard wake us more easily than others.
They either told the participants the name of an animal or object as This protective monitoring may
they would wake them at 9 am and they fell asleep. They monitored not last all night, however. A study
did; told them they would wake the brain’s electrical activity during published in 2016 found that while
them at 9 am, but actually woke training and when the people heard language processing continues in
them at 6 am; or said they would the same words when asleep. REM sleep for words heard just
wake them at 6 am and did. Even when asleep, activity before bed, once in deep sleep, all
This last group had a measurable continued in the brain’s motor responses disappear as the brain
rise in the stress hormone regions, indicating that the sleepers goes “offline” to allow the day’s
adrenocorticotropin from 4:30 am, were preparing to push the correct memories to be processed.
peaking around 6 am. People woken button. The people could also “Your cognition about things in the
unexpectedly at 6 am had no such correctly categorise new words environment declines progressively
spike. The unconscious mind, the they first heard after they had towards deep sleep,” says Kouider.
researchers concluded, can not dropped off, showing that they “Sleep is not all-or-none in terms
only keep track of time while we were genuinely analysing the of cognition; it’s all-or-none in
BASHTA/ISTOCK

sleep, but also set a biological meaning of the words while asleep. terms of consciousness.”

Chapter 4 | Sleep and dreaming | 55


“There is good evidence for
sleep mediating memory
consolidation”
reactivated during sleep,” says Jan Born at the The pair have also shown that when people learn
University of Tübingen in Germany. a task that uses a specific part of the brain, that area
Many labs remain focused on how memory generates more intense slow waves during subsequent
systems are updated during sleep, but since 2003, a sleep. This kind of downscaling is best done “offline”,
new idea has been gaining traction. It straddles both says Tononi. “You can activate your brain in all kinds of
categories of theory, concerned as it is with neuronal ways, because you don’t need to behave or learn.”
maintenance and memory processing. Synaptic homeostasis hasn’t won over everyone, but
The hypothesis concerns synapses, the junctions it is certainly getting a great deal of attention. It is, says
between neurons through which they communicate. Born, “currently the most influential [theory] among
We know that when we form new memories, the sleep researchers”. Frank, however, would like Tononi
synapses of the neurons involved become stronger. and Cirelli to provide more detail about mechanisms.
The idea is that while awake, we are constantly forming Jerry Siegel isn’t convinced either. A neuroscientist
new memories and therefore strengthening synapses. at the University of California, Los Angeles, Siegel is
But this strengthening cannot go on indefinitely: sticking with his provocative theory that sleep is
it would be too expensive in terms of energy, and simply an adaptive way of saving energy when not
eventually there would be no way of forming new doing essential things, such as foraging or breeding,
memories as our synapses would become “maxed out”. which are in fact more dangerous than napping
The proposed solution is slow-wave sleep. In someplace safe. For Siegel, sleep habits reflect the
the absence of any appreciable external input, variety of animal lifestyles, with different species
the slow cycles of neuronal firing gradually sleeping for different purposes.
lower synaptic strength across the board, while It is certainly possible that a phenomenon as
maintaining the relative differences in strength complex as sleep performs a multitude of functions,
between synapses, so that new memories are says Jim Horne, who studies the impact of sleep loss
retained (see diagram, page 54). on health at Loughborough University, UK. What’s
There is now much evidence to support what is more, given the complexity of the human brain, our
known as the “synaptic homeostasis hypothesis“. sleep may well be among the most complicated of all.
In humans, brain scans show that our grey matter Perhaps, then, it should be no surprise that theories
uses more energy at the end of the waking day than of sleep function are so diverse. Fathoming whether the
at the start. Giulio Tononi and Chiara Cirelli at the big “why” of sleep will yield a single, succinct solution
University of Wisconsin-Madison, who proposed or require myriad answers will probably keep biologists
the hypothesis, have shown that synaptic strength up at night for a little while yet. In that sense, perhaps
increases in rodents and fruit flies during wakefulness appropriately, it is a mirror of the situation with
and falls during sleep. consciousness generally.  ❚

56 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


HYPNAGOGIA
It is the brain’s natural twilight zone – a halfway
stage between wakefulness and sleep that we all
experience as we drop off. Known as hypnagogia
or “N1”, it is often characterised by vivid dreams –
although usually people progress into deep sleep
and forget the dreams when they wake. It repays
closer attention. “If you are a good observer, you

THE MEANING
will notice that those spots have a hallucinoid quality
to them,” says Tore Nielsen, a sleep researcher
at the Montreal Sacred Heart Hospital in Canada.
We don’t know what causes hypnagogia, but one
idea is that some parts of the brain are falling asleep
ahead of the rest. “It’s known that different parts of
the brain tune out at different times,” says Nielsen.
It has long been thought that hypnagogia can
inspire creativity. Chemist Friedrich August Kekulé
OF DREAMING
had his insight about the ring structure of benzene
Dreams are a signature feature of the altered
while half asleep. The surrealist artist Salvador Dalí
tuned in to his creativity by letting himself drop off state of consciousness we call sleep. We are
while suspending a spoon over a metal plate. As he
beginning to understand how our brains shape
fell asleep, the spoon would crash down, jerking him
awake while the dream images were still fresh in his our dreams, and why they contain such an
mind. Inventor Thomas Edison did something similar
eerie mixture of the familiar and the bizarre.
by holding a steel ball in each hand as he drifted off
while trying to grapple with a difficult problem.
In 2021, Delphine Oudiette at the National Institute
of Health and Medical Research in Paris and her team
tested the link with creativity objectively by getting ARY SHELLEY’S involved a pale
people to tackle a tricky maths problem using a student kneeling beside a corpse
particular method – without telling them there was that was jerking back to life.
a simple shortcut. While grappling with the problem, Paul McCartney’s contained
they were encouraged to take a short nap while the melody of Yesterday, while
holding a bottle in their hand, during which they James Cameron’s feverish visions
were wired up to an electroencephalogram (EEG). inspired the Terminator films.
On returning to the maths problem, 83 per cent of With their eerie mixture of
those who had only reached the N1 stage of sleep as the familiar and the bizarre, it
revealed by the EEG worked out the hidden shortcut, is easy to look for meaning the
compared with 31 per cent of those who remained nightly wanderings of our dreams. Why do our brains
awake and 14 per cent of those who had progressed take these journeys and why do they contain such
to deeper N2 sleep. outlandish twists and turns?
Hypnagogia has a darker side, however. It can Anyone who has ever awoken feeling amazed by
sometimes trigger one terrifying kind of sleep their night’s dream only to forget its contents by
paralysis, when the nerve inhibition that normally the time they reach the shower will understand the
accompanies our dreams kicks in before someone difficulties of studying such an ephemeral state of
is fully asleep. “Hypnagogia is largely an uncharted mind. Some of the best attempts to catalogue dream
domain,” says Nielsen. “We are still developing features either asked participants to jot them down
tools for navigating it.” as soon as they woke up every morning or, better still,
invited volunteers to sleep in a lab, where they were
awoken and immediately questioned at intervals in >

Chapter 4 | Sleep and dreaming | 57


the night. Such experiments have shown that our
dreams tend to be silent movies, with just half
containing traces of sounds. It is even more unusual WHEN
to enjoy a meal or feel damp grass beneath your feet:
taste, smell and touch appear only very rarely. DREAMS
Similar studies have tried to pin down some of the
factors that might influence what we dream about,
HAPPEN
though they have struggled to find anything reliable.
You might expect your dreams to reveal something Sleep occurs in repeating cycles, each about 
about your personality, but traits such as extroversion 90 minutes long. In a cycle, there are three
or creativity don’t seem to predict features of stages of non-REM sleep, where brain activity
someone’s journeys through the land of nod. Shelley becomes gentle and rhythmic, eventually
and McCartney’s dreams aren’t that unlike ours. heading into slow-wave, deep sleep.
“People’s dreams seem to be more similar than After slow-wave sleep, the brainwaves
different,” says Mark Blagrove at Swansea University change pattern again, the eyes start roiling
in the UK. This suggests common symbols in dreams under their lids and most of the muscles in the
might represent shared anxieties and desires, but body become paralysed to stop us acting out
attempts to find these have also been disappointing. our dreams. This is REM sleep, and the
A more fruitful approach has been to look at the proportion of time spent in this stage increases
brain’s activity during sleep for clues to the making in each successive sleep cycle throughout the
of our dreams. Of particular interest is the idea that night, so that by early morning, much of those
sleep helps to cement our memories for future recall. 90 minutes can be spent in REM.
After first recording an event in the hippocampus – We do dream in other stages of sleep,
which can be thought of as the human memory’s but these dreams tend to be unemotional,
printing press – the brain then transfers its contents concerned with simple things and hard to
to the cortex, where it files the recollection for remember. In short, they are boring. REM sleep
long-term storage. is where classic dreams occur, those with
This has led some psychologists, including Blagrove, bizarre juxtapositions, physically impossible
to suspect that certain elements of the memory feats and emotional, puzzling events.
may surface in our dreams as the different pieces
of information are passed across the brain. By studying
participants’ diaries of real-life events and comparing
them with their dream records, his team has found

58 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


A good night’s sleep of about 8 hours is comprised of five or six cycles.
We get a higher proportion of REM sleep after about 5.5 hours

Cycle First Second Third Fourth Fifth

DREAMING AWAKE
AW
Can occur at any stage but
REM
more common during REM

STA
T GE 1

TRANSITIONAL STAGES
STA
T GE 2

SLOW-WAVE SLEEP
Brain repair and STA
T GE 3
maintenance

Time (hours) 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8

Key period for REM sleep

that memories enter our dreams in two separate elements,” says McNamara.


stages. They first float into our consciousness on the Our dreams are more than a collection of characters
night after the event itself, which might reflect the and objects, of course. Like films or novels, they tell
initial recording of the memory, and then they their stories in many different styles – from a trivial
reappear between five and seven days later, which may and disordered sequence to an intense poetic vision.
be a sign of consolidation. Our emotional undercurrents seem to be the guiding
Even so, it is quite rare for a single event to appear force here.
in a dream in its entirety – instead, our memories Ernest Hartmann, a psychiatrist at Tufts University
emerge piecemeal. “What usually happens is that small in Massachusetts, has studied the dream diaries of
fragments are recombined into the ongoing story of people who have recently suffered a painful personal
the dream,” says Patrick McNamara at Northcentral experience or grief. He found that they are more likely
University in Arizona. And the order in which the to have particularly vivid dreams that focus on a single
different elements appear might reflect the way a central image, rather than a meandering narrative.
memory is broken down and then repackaged These dreams are also more memorable than those
during consolidation. from other, more placid times.
One of McNamara’s studies, which compared one Why would our emotions drive the form of our
individual’s dream and real-life diaries over a two-month dreams in this way? Hartmann suspects this might also
period, found that a sense of place – a recognisable reflect underlying memory processes – our emotions
room, for instance – was the first fragment of a memory are known to guide which memories we store and later
to burst onto the subject’s dreamscape, followed by recall. Perhaps the intense images are an indication
characters, actions and finally physical objects. of what a difficult process it is integrating a traumatic
While it may cement a memory into our synapses event with the rest of our autobiography. The result
during consolidation, the sleeping brain also forges may help us to come to terms with that event.
links to other parts of your mental autobiography, “I think it makes a new trauma less traumatic,”
allowing you to see associations between different says Hartmann, though he readily admits that
events. This might dredge up old memories and plant his hypothesis is difficult to prove.
them in our dreams, which in turn might explain why Despite these advances, many, many mysteries
we often dream of people and places that we haven’t remain. Top of the list is the question of the purpose of
seen or visited for months or even years. It could also our dreams: are they essential for the preservation of
lie behind those bizarre cases of mistaken identity our memories, for instance, or could we manage to store
while dreaming, when objects or people can appear to our life’s events without them? “There’s no consensus,”
be one thing, but assume another shape or character. says McNamara. But if we understood their origins, we
“It’s a by-product of the way the brain blends different would get a better grasp on consciousness in general.  ❚

Chapter 4 | Sleep and dreaming | 59


CHAPTER 5

Consciousness isn’t an on-off state, but more like a dimmer switch.


Or perhaps you might view it as a ladder of states, with zero consciousness
at the bottom and maximum consciousness at the top.

Many altered states of consciousness exist, from induced unconsciousness


in the form of anaesthesia to hallucinatory states that, besides being
induced by drugs, occur naturally in many of us. And even with states
regarded as minimally conscious, from comas to a persistent vegetative
state, it seems things aren’t as clear-cut as we once thought.

60 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


Chapter 5 | Altered consciousness | 61
THE MYSTERY OF
ANAESTHESIA
Many of us have put our faith in the ability of T WAS a Japanese surgeon who performed the
first known surgery under anaesthetic, in 1804,
doctors to use general anaesthesia to remove using a mixture of potent herbs. In the West,
our consciousness safely, even if we don’t the first operation under general anaesthetic
took place at Massachusetts General Hospital
really understand how it works. The truth in 1846. A flask of sulphuric ether was held close
is, given that no one knows what they are to the patient’s face until he fell unconscious.
Since then, a slew of chemicals have been
removing, no one does. co-opted to serve as anaesthetics, some inhaled,
like ether, and some injected. The people
who gained expertise in administering these agents
developed into their own medical speciality. Although
long overshadowed by the surgeons who patch you up,
the humble “gas man” does just as important a job,
holding you in the twilight between life and death.
The development of general anaesthesia has
transformed surgery from a horrific ordeal into
a gentle slumber. It is one of the most common
medical procedures in the world. Perhaps it isn’t that
surprising that we don’t know how it works: we still
don’t understand consciousness, after all, so how
can we comprehend its disappearance?
Altered consciousness doesn’t only happen under
a general anaesthetic, of course – it occurs whenever
we drop off to sleep, or if we are unlucky enough to
be whacked on the head. But anaesthetics do allow
neuroscientists to manipulate our consciousness
safely, reversibly and with exquisite precision.
We have long known that there are different
PABLO HURTADO DE MENDOZA
PREVIOUS PAGE: LUMEZIA/ISTOCK levels of anaesthesia (see diagram, overleaf) – just >

62 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


Chapter 5 | Altered consciousness | 63
Losing consciousness under anaesthesia is
not so much flipping a light switch as turning
down a dimmer switch

STAGES OF ANAESTHESIA
as consciousness exists on a scale, so we slide along
that scale. “The process of going into and out of general LIGHT-
anaesthesia isn’t like flipping a light switch,” says George HEADEDNESS
Mashour, an anaesthetist at the University of Michigan
in Ann Arbor. “It’s more akin to a dimmer switch.” AMNESIA
A typical subject first experiences a state similar to
drunkenness, which they may or may not be able to
recall later, before falling unconscious, which is usually UNCONSCIOUSNESS
defined as failing to move in response to commands. As Failure to respond
they progress deeper into the twilight zone, they now to commands
fail to respond to even the penetration of a scalpel –
which is the point of the exercise, after all – and at the
deepest levels may need artificial help with breathing.
These days, anaesthesia is usually started off with
injection of a drug called propofol, which gives a rapid FAILURE TO RESPOND TO PAIN
and smooth transition to unconsciousness. Unless the May need mechanical ventilation
to maintain breathing
operation is only meant to take a few minutes, an
inhaled anaesthetic, such as isoflurane, is then usually
added to give better minute-by-minute control of the
depth of anaesthesia.
Since they were first discovered, one of the big
mysteries has been how the members of such a
diverse group of chemicals can all result in the loss
of consciousness. Other drugs work by binding to
receptor molecules in the body, usually proteins,
in a way that relies on the drug and receptor fitting
snugly together like a key in a lock. Yet the long list
of anaesthetic agents ranges from large, complex
molecules, such as barbiturates or steroids, to the receptors have been found for many anaesthetics.
inert gas xenon, which exists as mere atoms. How Propofol, for instance, binds to receptors on nerve cells
could they all fit the same lock? that normally respond to a chemical messenger called
For a long time, there was great interest in the GABA. Presumably, the solubility of anaesthetics in oil
fact that the potency of anaesthetics correlates affects how easily they reach the receptors bound in the
strikingly with how well they dissolve in olive fatty membrane.
oil. The popular “lipid theory” said that instead of But that solves only a small part of the mystery.
binding to specific protein receptors, the anaesthetic We still don’t know how this binding affects nerve
physically disrupted the fatty membranes of nerve cells, and which neural networks they feed into. “If
cells, causing them to malfunction. you look at the brain under both xenon and propofol
In the 1980s, though, experiments in test tubes anaesthesia, there are striking similarities,” says
showed that anaesthetics could bind to proteins in Nick Franks at Imperial College London, who
the absence of cell membranes. Since then, protein overturned the lipid theory in the 1980s. “They

64 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


BROADLY EQUIVALENT TO
if any, are the root cause of the loss of consciousness.
BEING But is it even realistic to expect to find a discrete
DRUNK site or sites acting as the mind’s “light switch”? It isn’t
if you adhere to theories of consciousness such as the
global workspace theory that see consciousness as a
widely distributed phenomenon, in which we only
become conscious of an experience if incoming signals
SLEEP are broadcast to a network of neurons spread through
the brain.

←-
Page 14 has the low-down on-
global workspace theory-
UNCONSCIOUSNESS The idea has gained support from recordings of the
due to brain damage – includes brain’s electrical activity using electroencephalograph
persistent vegetative state and coma
(EEG) sensors on the scalp as people are given
anaesthesia. This has shown that, as consciousness
fades, there is a loss of synchrony between areas of
the cortex – the outermost layer of the brain important
in attention, awareness, thought and memory.
This process has also been visualised using
functional magnetic resonance imaging scans. One
study of what happens during propofol anaesthesia
when patients descend from wakefulness, through
mild sedation to the point at which they fail to respond
to commands, found that while small “islands”
of the cortex lit up in response to external stimuli
must be triggering some common neuronal change, when people were unconscious, there was no spread
and that’s the big mystery.” of activity to other areas, as there was during
Many anaesthetics are thought to work by making wakefulness or mild sedation.
it harder for neurons to fire, but this can have different Another study, which slowed down this process to
effects on brain function, depending on which neurons look at it in more detail, gave volunteers a mild electric
are being blocked. So brain-imaging techniques such shock at different points as they went under, and took
as functional MRI scanning, which tracks changes in EEG readings of the response. At the deepest levels of
blood flow to different areas of the brain, are being anaesthesia, the primary sensory cortex was the only
used to see which regions of the brain are affected region to respond to the electric shock, supporting
by anaesthetics. Such studies have been successful the idea that loss of consciousness is associated with
in revealing several areas that are deactivated by a blockage of long-distance communication in the
most anaesthetics. Unfortunately, so many regions brain – as if the message is somehow reaching the
have been implicated that it is hard to know which, mailbox, but no one is picking it up.  ❚

Chapter 5 | Altered consciousness | 65


THE POWER OF
HALLUCINATION
In recent years, it has become clear that hallucinations are much more than a rare symptom of
mental illness or the result of mind-altering drugs. Their appearance elsewhere has led to a better
understanding of how the brain can create a world that doesn’t really exist.

ALLUCINATIONS are sensations of experiencing them increases in your 60s; 5 per


that appear real but aren’t elicited cent of us will experience one or more hallucinations
by anything in our external in our life.
environment. They aren’t only visual – Many people hallucinate sounds or shapes before
they can be sounds, smells, even they drift off to sleep, or just on waking. People
experiences of touch. It is difficult experiencing extreme grief have also been known to
to imagine just how real they seem hallucinate in the weeks after their loss – often visions
unless you have experienced one. As of their loved one. But the hallucinations that may
Sylvia, a woman who has had musical reveal the most about how our brain works are those
hallucinations for years, explains, it that crop up in people who have recently lost a sense.
isn’t like imagining a tune in your head – more like This is known as Charles Bonnet syndrome. Bonnet,
“listening to the radio”, she says. a Swiss scientist who lived in the early 1700s, first
There is evidence to support the idea that these described the condition in his grandfather, who had
experiences are authentic. In 1998, researchers at King’s begun to lose his vision. One day, the older man was
College London scanned the brains of people having sitting talking to his granddaughters when two men
visual hallucinations. They found that brain areas that appeared, wearing majestic cloaks of red and grey.
were active are also active while viewing a real version When he asked why no one had told him they would
of the hallucinated image. Those who hallucinated be coming, he discovered that only he could see them.
faces, for example, activated areas of the fusiform It is a similar story with Sylvia. After an ear infection
gyrus, known to contain specialised cells that are active caused severe hearing loss, she began to hallucinate a
when we look at real faces. The same was true with sound that was like a cross between a wooden flute and
hallucinations of colour and written words. It was a bell. At first, it was a couple of notes that repeated
the first objective evidence that hallucinations are over and over. Later, there were whole tunes. “You’d
less like imagination and more like real perception. expect to hear a sound that you recognise, maybe a
Their convincing nature helps explain why piano or a trumpet, but it’s not like anything I know
hallucinations have been given such meaning – in real life,” she says.
even considered messages from gods. But as it became Max Livesey was in his 70s when Parkinson’s disease
clear that they can be symptoms of mental health destroyed the nerves that send information from the
conditions such as schizophrenia, they were viewed nose to the brain. Despite his olfactory loss, one day
with increasing suspicion. he suddenly noticed the smell of burning leaves. The
We now know that hallucinations occur in odours intensified over time, ranging from burnt wood
people without a mental illness. The likelihood to a horrible onion-like stench. “When they’re at their

66 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


ULZA/ISTOCK PHOTO

Sensory deprivation
is one way to stimulate
hallucination

most intense, they can smell like excrement,” he says. which processes the rawest elements, such as patterns
They were so powerful that they made his eyes water. and pitch. From here, signals get passed on to higher
Sensory loss doesn’t have to be permanent to bring brain regions that process more complex features,
on such hallucinations. When our senses are such as melody and key changes.
diminished, all of us have the potential to hallucinate. It Instead of relaying every detail up the chain, the
can take just 30 to 45 minutes for people to experience brain combines the noisy signals coming in with
hallucinations if they try a simple visual deprivation prior experiences to generate a prediction of what is
technique, such as the Ganzfeld procedure. This happening. If you hear the opening notes of a familiar
involves seating yourself in a room that is evenly lit, tune, you expect the rest of the song to follow. That
cutting a table-tennis ball in half, taping each segment prediction passes back to lower regions, where it is
over your eyes and then listening to some white noise compared with the actual input, and to the frontal
over headphones. In one study run by Jiří Wackermann lobes, which perform a kind of reality check, before
at the Institute for Frontier Areas of Psychology and it pops up into our consciousness. Only if a prediction
Mental Health in Freiburg, Germany, one volunteer is wrong does a signal get passed back to higher areas,
saw a jumping horse. Another saw an eerily detailed which adjust subsequent predictions.
mannequin. “It was all in black… had a long narrow You can test this for yourself. Anil Seth at the
head, fairly broad shoulders, very long arms,” they said. University of Sussex, UK, suggests listening to sine-
These hallucinations seem to come about because wave speech, basically a degraded version of a speech
the brain can’t tolerate inactivity in areas where recording. The first time, all you will hear is a jumble
it is usually constantly stimulated. These unreal of beeps and whistles. But if you listen to the original
experiences could thus provide a glimpse into the recording and then switch back to the degraded
way our brains stitch together our perception of reality. version, you will suddenly be able to make out what
Although bombarded by thousands of sensations is being said. All that has changed is your brain’s
every second, the brain rarely stops providing you expectations of the input. It means it now has better
with a steady stream of consciousness. When you blink, information on which to base its prediction. “Our
your world doesn’t disappear. Nor do you notice the reality,” says Seth, “is merely a controlled hallucination,
hum of traffic outside or the tightness of your socks reined in by our senses.”
(until they are mentioned, at least). Processing all of This idea is consistent with what was happening
those things all the time would be a very inefficient to Sylvia. Although she was mostly deaf, she could
way to run a brain. Instead, it takes a few shortcuts. still make out some sound – and she discovered
Sound waves, for example, enter the ear and are that listening to familiar Bach concertos suppressed
transmitted to the brain’s primary auditory cortex, her hallucinations. Timothy Griffiths, a cognitive >

Chapter 5 | Altered consciousness | 67


neurologist at Newcastle University, UK, scanned
Sylvia’s brain before, after and while listening to Bach,
and had her rate the intensity of her hallucinations PSYCHEDELIA:
throughout. They were at their quietest just after
the real music was played, gradually increasing A HIGHER STATE?
in volume until the next excerpt.
The brain scans showed that during her From magic mushrooms and ayahuasca –
hallucinations, the higher regions that process a potion used in South America during
melodies and sequences of tones were talking certain religious rites – to LSD and ketamine,
to one another. Yet, because Sylvia is profoundly using chemical means to achieve altered,
deaf, they weren’t constrained by the real sounds hallucinogenic states of consciousness has
entering her ears. Her hallucinations are her been part of human culture for millennia. In
brain’s best guess at what is out there. recent years, such mind-altering drugs have
Understanding why people react differently to been an increasing focus of medical attention
a diminished sensory environment could reveal as a treatment for conditions such as
why some are more prone to the delusions and depression and post-traumatic stress disorder.
hallucinations associated with certain mental health Only recently have we discovered how these
conditions. People with schizophrenia often have experiences are produced, however. In 2016,
overactivity in their sensory cortices, but poor researchers at Imperial College London
connectivity from these areas to their frontal lobes. monitored brain activity in 19 volunteers who
So the brain makes lots of predictions that aren’t had taken ketamine, 15 who had consumed
given a reality check before they pass into conscious LSD and 14 who were under the influence
awareness, says Flavie Waters, a clinical neuroscientist of psilocybin, a hallucinogenic compound in
at the University of Western Australia in Perth. magic mushrooms. The scans showed that
In conditions like Charles Bonnet syndrome, it is the volunteers’ hallucinations arose from the
underactivity in the sensory cortices that triggers the combined activity of brain regions that don’t
brain to start filling in the gaps, and there is no actual normally communicate with each other.
sensory input to help it correct course. In both cases, Regions responsible for vision, attention,
says Waters, the brain starts listening in on itself, movement and hearing became far more
instead of tuning in to the outside world. Something connected, while networks thought to give
similar seems to be true of hallucinations associated us an appreciation of the self became less so.
with some recreational drug use (see “Psychedelia: That may be why people who take LSD often
A higher state?”, right). say they feel “ego dissolution” – their sense
The knowledge that hallucinations can be a of self disintegrating – instead becoming more
by-product of how we construct reality might change at one with the world around them.
how we experience them. In his later years, the late A reanalysis of this research by Anil Seth
psychologist Oliver Sacks experienced hallucinations at the University of Sussex, UK, suggests
after his eyesight began to fail. When he played the that the brain on psychedelics might even,
piano, he would occasionally see showers of flat on some measures, be in a “higher” state
symbols when he was looking carefully at musical of consciousness than the waking brain.
scores. “I have long since learned to ignore my “We see an increase in the diversity of signals
hallucinations, and occasionally enjoy them,” from the brain,” he says. “The brain is more
said Sacks. “I like seeing what my brain is up complex in its activity.”
to when it is at play.”  ❚

68 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


CURIOSITIES OF
CONSCIOUSNESS
In some rare brain conditions, people calendar synaesthesia and many other conditions,
suspects this hints at the way our brains cope with the
noticeably experience the world very non-intuitive concept of months. “The brain didn’t
differently from the average individual. have time in evolution for creating the representation
of time – it’s too abstract,” he says. “What evolution
This provides another angle of attack often does is take pre-existing hardware and re-tool
on the problem of consciousness. it.” We did develop tools for conceptualising our
surroundings. “So you take a spatial map, map
time onto space, and you get a calendar,” he says. For
synaesthetes, that calendar seems to be visible in space.
Studies of such conditions can help illuminate
some of the mysteries of consciousness by revealing
the blurry boundary between the self and the outside
world. One of Ramachandran’s most unusual cases is
a man called David, who has Capgras syndrome. This
is usually characterised by the belief that a loved one
HERE is no lack of rare conditions has been replaced by an impostor. David, though,
that seem to suggest altered states believes himself to be the impostor.
of consciousness. Take phantom “He looks at his reflection and says: ‘Mom, that’s
limb syndrome – the sensation some the real David. If he comes back, are you going to
people have that their missing limb is disown me?’,” says Ramachandran. When pressed
still present – or Cotard syndrome, in for an explanation, David said the only logical one was
which people believe they are dead. that he had a long-lost twin and they were separated
Or calendar synaesthesia, perhaps at birth. “It’s an ingenious solution to the dilemma
one of the most striking examples of that he’s in, and it sends a chill down your spine. It
how the body and brain interact to shape takes you into questions about what the self is.”
our minds. When most people think about what they Our sense of self is also affected by those around
plan to do in November, say, they have a hazy concept us. For instance, when people with mirror-touch
of the months ahead. But people with calendar synaesthesia see someone else being touched, it feels
synaesthesia can actually see a calendar in front of as though they are being touched in the same way.
them, often in a strange formation – a hula hoop that People who experience such dramatic differences
touches them in the centre of their chest, for instance. in perception may be rare, but we are all capable of
Neuroscientist V. S. Ramachandran, who has studied distorting our sense of self. A simple experiment can >

Chapter 5 | Altered consciousness | 69


FREE
WON’T
In the 1964 film Dr Strangelove, the lead
character had an unusual affliction: his
right arm seemingly had a mind of its own.
Such a condition really does exist, although
it is vanishingly rare.
People with so-called alien hand syndrome
find that their affected limb reaches out and
grabs things they have no wish to pick up. They
might try restraining it with their other hand,
and if that doesn’t work, “they sometimes come
to the surgery with their hand tied up”, says
show how. Try looking at yourself in a double-reflecting Sergio Della Sala, a neuroscientist at
mirror – two mirrors facing each other such that the the University of Edinburgh, UK, who studies
second reflects the image in the first. Then, raise your the condition.
right arm. The first reflection is a normal mirror image, The cause is injury to the brain, usually in
but the second is inversed, which we aren’t used to a region known as the supplementary motor
seeing – it is a doppelganger, raising its right arm area (SMA). Work on monkeys has shown that
when you do and miming your behaviour. Keep another part of the brain, the premotor cortex,
looking and something odd can happen to your generates some of our actions unconsciously
sense of self – you start feeling you are out there. in response to things we see around us. The
What’s more, if you watch your arm moving in the SMA then kicks in to allow the movement or
second mirror, you may see a slight delay. Exactly why stop it, but damage to the SMA can wreck this
this happens is something Ramachandran and his team control – hence the anarchic hand, acting on
are working on, but we know that neurons in your brain every visual cue. A few people are unfortunate
telling your hand to move fire milliseconds before you enough to have damage to the SMA on both
consciously decide to move it. sides of the brain, and experience both
To avoid the sensation of being a puppet, your brain hands acting outside their control. They
smoothes things out so that everything feels are at the mercy of environmental triggers,
simultaneous. Ramachandran suspects that when you says Della Sala.
see this doppelganger in the mirror, your brain doesn’t The system sounds like the very opposite
compute it as you – so the correction isn’t applied. In of free will – Della Sala calls it “free won’t”.
essence, you are seeing the unconscious machinery of The findings suggest that, while it feels like
the brain laid bare. our actions are always under our conscious
These insights build a picture of our consciousness control, in reality, there is a lot of unconscious
as something very flimsy – but there is a limit to what decision-making going on too.
it can tell us about the hard problem of consciousness. If that sounds implausible, have you
“You can figure out the circuitry and all that, but it ever been driving somewhere on a day
still leaves the qualia, or experiences – whether it’s an off and found yourself heading towards
orgasm or the colour of red or the flavour of Marmite the office the moment you hit part of your
or curry or whatever,” says Ramachandran “That normal route to work? That is your premotor
problem will remain with us until we find a new way cortex responding to an environmental cue.
to do science. Maybe it’ll be a permanent dual view
of the world. The inside view and the outside view.”  ❚

70 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


COVERT
CONSCIOUSNESS
It has been one of the most eye-opening insights into consciousness
in recent decades – that people believed to be in an unconsciousness state
after traumatic brain injury might be more aware than we thought.

S RECENTLY as the late 1990s, Nevertheless, Owen and his team began to test
it was assumed that people in a the idea. Their first patient was Kate, a woman left in
vegetative state, by definition, had a vegetative state by a virus. In 1997, they scanned
no conscious awareness. They would Kate’s brain using positron emission tomography,
show signs of sleep and wake cycles, which can measure brain activity, while showing her
and occasionally open their eyes or pictures of her family or playing familiar speech. To
make involuntary movements, but their surprise, her brain responded just as you might
weren’t aware of themselves or the expect a conscious person’s brain to respond. But
people around them. However, Owen’s team faced a problem: a lot of neural activity
Adrian Owen, then at the MRC happens automatically, so the result didn’t necessarily
Cognition and Brain Sciences Unit in Cambridge, UK, prove she was conscious. It took another decade to
had a worrying thought: what if we were wrong? work out a solution.
Neurologists have long been aware of locked-in In 2006, Owen and his colleagues showed that a
syndrome, in which people are awake and aware but 23-year-old woman in a vegetative state could respond
unable to move almost all of their body. It was first to instructions, by asking her to imagine walking
defined in medical textbooks in 1966, but must have around her house or playing tennis. These two mental
been known about much earlier; it was described in tasks require different brain activity, which can be
Alexandre Dumas’s 1844 tale, The Count of Monte Cristo. identified from brain scans. It confirmed, beyond
People who are locked in need help breathing and any doubt, that she was consciously aware of herself
many can communicate only using eye movements. and the researchers, and that she had the ability to
But they aren’t classed as having a condition of respond to their requests.
consciousness because, unlike people in a coma, Disorders of consciousness are notoriously difficult
vegetative state or minimally conscious state, to diagnose. Most doctors use variations of the Glasgow
they are fully conscious (see “Six reduced states of Coma Scale to assess someone’s ability to open their
consciousness”, page 73). Still, a diagnosis can take eyes in reaction to various stimuli, and their verbal
months, or even years if eye movement is limited. responses and motor movements. They can also use
Owen wondered whether people in a vegetative brain scans to identify physical damage.
state could also have a hidden awareness. At the However, to identify covert consciousness, you need
time, this was dismissed as a “bonkers idea”, he says, to use functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI)
not least because it made people feel uncomfortable or several electroencephalograph (EEG) tests over time
that someone might be trapped inside their body to verify brain activity that reflects comprehension and
without anyone knowing. the capacity to follow commands. “But we’re just not >

Chapter 5 | Altered consciousness | 71


“Some people in a vegetative
state can be awoken with the
right intervention”
screening patients for this level of higher function,” There is no data on the exact number of people
says Nicholas Schiff at Weill Cornell Medical College with conditions of consciousness across the world,
in New York. “And it’s not that hard to find them but Schiff has been involved in an international
when we do.” investigation into rates of misdiagnosis. A conservative
The real canary in the coal mine, says Schiff, estimate is that 1 in 10 people who appear to be in a
was a study carried out in 2017 by Brian Edlow at coma, vegetative state or minimally conscious state
Massachusetts General Hospital. Edlow knew that actually has covert consciousness. “It’s a big problem,”
covert consciousness had been discovered in people says Schiff. “And now we know it’s not a rare problem.”
who’d had months or years to recover from their These new insights have been accompanied by other
injuries, but he wondered whether it might exist advances in medical science. Twenty years ago, there
in people with more recent brain injuries. wasn’t a lot you could do for people in a vegetative state
He and his colleagues scanned the brains of other than hope that they would slowly recover, or have
16 seemingly unconscious people with severe head a rare, spontaneous awakening. Now, we know that
injuries. During the scans, he asked them to do mental some people in a vegetative state have the capacity
tasks, such as “imagine squeezing your right hand”. to be awoken with the right intervention. There is
Of eight people who had no behavioural evidence no golden bullet, but some drugs seem to assist the
of awareness, four could follow his instructions. It process, in certain cases. Schiff’s team implanted
was a small study, but it had massive ramifications. electrodes in the thalamus of a man who had been in
“These people were in intensive care,” says Schiff. a minimally conscious state for six years following an
“What if you’d withdrawn their care?” Even for those assault. Improvements were seen straight away. By the
who are provided with life-sustaining treatment, a end of the six-month trial, the man could eat, speak
misdiagnosis might result in limited rehabilitation and watch a movie. In 2016, Martin Monti at the
that thwarts an opportunity for recovery. University of California, Los Angeles, and his colleagues
A diagnosis of covert consciousness can be life- showed that something similar might be possible
changing. For instance, one man, thought to be in a by stimulating the thalamus using low-intensity
vegetative state, made sporadic head movements that ultrasound. Others are focusing on different areas of
had been dismissed as random. Once Schiff’s team the brain and on the vagus nerve, which runs between
became aware of his covert consciousness, these the brain, the thalamus and several areas of the body.
movements were given more attention. A researcher These advances raise new ethical questions. Some
developed a head-mounted computer mouse for him, people may see surviving a brain injury with some
which he used to control a keyboard. Eventually, he was degree of consciousness as worse than being in a
able to write Schiff an email to give his own consent to vegetative state, because you can experience pain
join Schiff’s next study. and have some awareness of your predicament.

72 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


SIX REDUCED
STATES OF
CONSCIOUSNESS
BRAIN DEAD
A person is brain dead when they no longer have
any brain activity. They won’t regain consciousness
or be able to breathe without artificial life support.

COMA
Someone in a coma is unconscious and has low
levels of brain activity. They will be unresponsive
to sound and pain and will have greatly reduced
reflexes, such as swallowing or coughing. They
may be able to breathe on their own.
Some improvements using drugs have proved to be
VEGETATIVE STATE only temporary and to produce diminishing returns,
A state in which a person may have some reflexes, with people lapsing back into unconsciousness. And
including yawning and eye movements, but shows then there is the pain of discovering a loved one has
no awareness of themselves or their environment. covert consciousness, but that you can’t offer any
means of continuing the conversation.
M I N I M A LLY C O N S C I O U S Another question is whether it is possible for
As a person begins to show intermittent people with conditions of consciousness to have a
awareness of themselves or their environment, more meaningful conversation about their welfare.
they are said to be in a minimally conscious state. “Once a person shows signs of awareness, can they
As they develop the ability to communicate, they decide whether to live or die?” asks medical ethicist
are said to have emerging consciousness. Joseph Fins, also at Weill Cornell Medical College.
Historically, we have thought about such decisions as
COVERT CONSCIOUSNESS all or nothing – people are either capable of consenting
Some people who are diagnosed as being in a to treatment or not, he says. But now, we have this
coma, vegetative state or minimally conscious third scenario, he says, a person who may be aware
state may have periods of awareness that they enough to answer difficult questions some of the
are unable to reveal because they can’t make time. “Now that people with brain injuries are
any purposeful movements. This differs from emerging and communicating, we have to listen
locked-in syndrome because the person still to what they say,” says Fins.
has cognitive troubles, such as memory loss, One thing we do know is that a locked-in life isn’t
or inconsistent consciousness. necessarily a miserable one. A small survey of people
who could only communicate using eye movements
LOCKED-IN SYNDROME found that the majority were happy, and the longer
A person who is locked in is fully conscious, they had been locked in, the happier they were. But that
so isn’t classed as having a condition of stems from their ability to engage with those around
consciousness, but is unable to move most of them regularly. Without that, Schiff fears people with
their body. Sometimes, they can communicate conditions of consciousness face extreme isolation.
through eye and facial movements. Their “There hasn’t been a formal study of well-being in
condition is normally associated with an people with disorders of consciousness,” says Ralf
injury to the brain stem. Clauss at the Royal Surrey County Hospital, UK. “But
anecdotally, from what people have told me during
periods of awareness, they are happy.”  ❚

Chapter 5 | Altered consciousness | 73


WHAT HAPPENS
TO CONSCIOUSNESS
WHEN WE DIE?
The short answer comes as no surprise: we don’t know.

N 15 April 1987, Michelle Francl- you die, blood stops flowing, the muscles cool,
Donnay’s husband Tom was due to pick consciousness slips away – and your physical
her up from an evening meeting, but body begins to return to the atoms that made it.
decided to take a swim first. He had But as to whether this is really the last word on you –
an undiagnosed heart condition, and well, no one truly knows. The integrated information
while in the pool had a catastrophic theory of consciousness, for example, suggests it
aneurysm. Michelle rode with him emerges because of the way particular physical systems
in the ambulance. That was the last organise information. Some researchers think life itself
time she spoke to him. is a similar emergent property embodied in a simple
“When I saw Tom’s body the next equation: life = matter + information.
morning, he clearly wasn’t there anymore,” says It is a cast-iron rule of physics that information
Francl-Donnay, a chemist at Bryn Mawr College in cannot be destroyed. So might physics provide a back
Pennsylvania and an adjunct scholar at the Vatican door for some form of afterlife in which information
Observatory who writes extensively on both science associated with you can live on? Francl-Donnay
and spirituality. Over the years, she found herself reckons quantum physics provides teasing hints, in
mulling a question humans have asked for a long the way that the quantum wave functions defining
time: where had he gone? our individual atoms and particles don’t have a well-
Even those of us who rationally reject the idea of an defined boundary in space or time. “At some long
afterlife have trouble letting go of the idea. That might distance, there is still some incredibly tiny chance of
be down to our theory of mind. Because we habitually finding an electron there,” says Francl-Donnay. “It’s not
put ourselves in other people’s shoes and imagine their measurable. But that doesn’t mean it’s not important.”
thoughts and feelings, it can be hard to believe that The suggestion that some form of consciousness
those thoughts and feelings can just cease to be when survives death goes way beyond what science can
ours still feel so real. currently tell us. But we continue to exist in the minds
of those who outlive us, of course. “Even today there’s
←- a sense in which Tom persists – in my memory,” says
Turn back to page 42 for more on metacognition- Francl-Donnay. “And I can hear his voice if I shut my
eyes.” The last resting place of our self that we can be
Yet we have no evidence for anything different. When sure of is in the minds of those we leave behind.  ❚

74 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


PERSPECTIVE DANIEL BOR

“CONSCIOUSNESS
IS ABOUT COMBINING
INFORMATION”
Different lines of evidence point to the HE first time I saw my father in hospital
after his stroke, I was disturbed to find
origins of consciousness lying in how that my strong and confident dad had
the brain deals with the data it receives, been replaced by someone confused and
childlike. Besides being concerned about
giving hope for cracking its mysteries. whether or not he would recover, I was
struck by the profound metaphysical
implications of what had just happened.
At the time, I was a few weeks away
from my final university exams in
philosophy and neuroscience, both of which addressed
consciousness. In my philosophy lectures, I had heard
PROFILE elegant arguments that consciousness isn’t a physical
DANIEL phenomenon and must be somehow independent
BOR of our material, corporeal brains. This idea, most
famously articulated by René Descartes as dualism
nearly 400 years ago, seemed in stark contrast to the
Daniel Bor is a neuroscientific evidence in front of me: my father’s
neuroscientist and consciousness had been maimed by a small blood
psychologist at the clot in his brain.
University of Soon after, I abandoned plans for a PhD in the
Cambridge, UK philosophy of the mind, opting for one on the
neuroscience of consciousness instead. There are
certainly questions about our minds that seem more
in the realms of philosophy. What is it like to be a bat?
Is your experience of seeing the colour red the same
as mine? In fact, how do we know for certain that other
people are conscious at all? But I would argue that it is
neuroscience, not philosophy, that has the best chance >

Chapter 5 | Altered consciousness | 75


PERSPECTIVE DANIEL BOR

of answering even these most difficult questions. words or sounds, other areas kick into action. These
One area in which we have made great progress are the lateral prefrontal cortex and the posterior
is in discovering the physical or neural correlates parietal cortex, another region heavily involved in
of consciousness – what consciousness in the brain complex, high-level thought, this time at the top of
“looks like”, you might say. One way to investigate this the brain, to the rear.
question is to see what changes when consciousness Satisfyingly, while many animals have a
is reduced or absent, as happens when people are in thalamus, the two cortical brain areas implicated
a vegetative state, with no sign of awareness. in consciousness are nothing like as large and well
Brain scans show that such people usually developed in other species as they are in humans.
have damage to the thalamus, a relay centre located This fits with the common intuition that, while
smack bang in the middle of the brain (see diagram, there may be a spectrum of consciousness across
right). Another common finding is damage to the the animal kingdom, there is something very
connections between the thalamus and the prefrontal special about our own form of it.
cortex, a region at the front of the brain, generally In humans, the three brain areas implicated
responsible for high-level complex thought. in consciousness  the thalamus, lateral prefrontal
The prefrontal cortex has also been implicated cortex and posterior parietal cortex – share a distinctive
using another technique – scanning the brain while feature: they have more connections to each other and
people lose consciousness under general anaesthesia. to elsewhere in the brain than any other region. With
As awareness fades, a discrete set of regions are such dense connections, these three areas are best
deactivated, with the lateral prefrontal cortex the placed to receive, combine and analyse information
most notable absentee. from the rest of the brain. Many neuroscientists
Those kinds of investigations have been invaluable suspect that it is this drawing together of information
for narrowing down the search for the parts of the that is a hallmark of consciousness. When I talk to a
brain involved in us being awake and aware, but they friend in the pub, for instance, I don’t experience him
still don’t tell us what happens in the brain when we as a series of disjointed features, but as a unified whole,
see the colour red, for example. combining his appearance with the sound of his voice
Simply getting someone to lie in a brain scanner and my knowledge of his name, favourite beer and
while they stare at something red won’t work, because so on – all amalgamated into a single person-object.
we know that there is lots of unconscious brain activity How does the brain knit together all these
caused by visual stimuli – indeed, any sensory stimuli. disparate strands of information from a variety of
How can we get round this problem? brain locations? The leading hypothesis is that the
One solution is to use stimuli that are just at the relevant neurons start firing in synchrony many
threshold of awareness, so they are only sometimes times a second, a phenomenon we can see as
perceived – playing a faint burst of noise, for instance, brainwaves on an electroencephalogram (EEG),
or flashing a word on a screen almost too briefly to be whereby electrodes are placed on the scalp. The
noticed. If the person doesn’t consciously notice the signature of consciousness seems to be an ultra-fast
word flashing up, the only part of the brain that is form of these brainwaves originating in the thalamus
activated is that which is directly connected to the and spreading across the cortex.
sense organs concerned – in this case, the visual One of the most prominent attempts to turn this
cortex. But if the subject becomes aware of the experimental data into a theory of consciousness is the

76 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


Brain scanning reveals that certain areas of the brain in the pub, with all senses and knowledge about him
have a pivotal role in generating conscious experience wrapped together, feels so much more than the raw
sensory information that makes it up.
LATERAL POSTERIOR
PARIETAL But the model could be applied equally well to the
PREFRONTAL
CORTEX CORTEX internet as to a human: its creators make the audacious
claim that we should be able to calculate how conscious
any particular information-processing network is,
be it in the brain of a human, rat or computer. All we
need to know is the network’s structure, in particular
how many nodes it contains and how they are
connected together.
Unfortunately, the maths involves so many
THALAMUS fiendish calculations, which grow exponentially as the
(internal)
number of nodes increases, that our most advanced
supercomputers couldn’t perform them in a realistic
time frame for even a simple nematode worm with
about 300 neurons. The sums may well be simplified
in future, however, to make them more practical.
This mathematical theory may seem very different
from the global neuronal workspace – it ignores the
brain’s anatomy, for a start – yet encouragingly, both
global neuronal workspace model. This suggests that models say consciousness is about combining
input from our eyes, ears and so on is first processed information, and both focus on the most densely
unconsciously, primarily in sensory brain regions. It connected parts of the information-processing
emerges into our conscious awareness only if it ignites network. I feel this common ground reflects the
activity in the prefrontal and parietal cortices, with significant progress the field is making.
these regions connecting through ultra-fast brainwaves. We may not yet have solved the so-called hard
This model links consciousness with difficult tasks, problem of consciousness – how a bunch of neurons
which often require a drawing together of multiple can generate the experience of seeing the colour red.
strands of knowledge. This view fits nicely with the fact Yet to me, worrying about the hard problem is just
that there is high activity in our lateral prefrontal and another version of dualism, seeing consciousness as
posterior parietal cortices when we carry out new something that is so mysterious it can’t be explained
or complex tasks, while activity in these areas dips by studying the brain scientifically.
when we do repetitive tasks on autopilot, like driving Every time in history we thought there had
a familiar route. to be some supernatural cause for a mysterious
The main rival to the global workspace as a theory of phenomenon, such as mental illness or even the
consciousness is integrated information theory, which rising of bread dough, we eventually found the
says consciousness is simply combining data together scientific explanation. It seems plausible to me that
so that it is more than the sum of its parts. This idea is if we continue to chip away at the “easy problems”, we
said to explain why my experience of meeting a friend will eventually find there is no hard problem left at all.  ❚

Chapter 5 | Altered consciousness | 77


CHAPTER 6

78 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


Consciousness is all we have, but what is its place in the world? The
relationship between our internal world and the external one is another
of the great mysteries of consciousness with as yet few answers.

It is a conundrum with two sides. The first, already touched on, is how
the physical processes that we understand to underlie the workings of
reality contrive to make conscious experience. The second is the role
consciousness itself plays in constructing reality – which is where
matters become very murky indeed.

Chapter 6 | Consciousness and reality | 79


THE PHYSICS OF
CONSCIOUSNESS
HIMS, memories, hopes,
To what extent can physical laws explain
judgements, morals,
the workings of consciousness? Attempts qualms – all coming together
to influence decisions. It is
to answer that question come to a head
sometimes hard for us to
in one of the most mysterious abilities understand how we reach
the decisions we do. For
of conscious minds – to apparently use
fundamental physicists, it
our subjective experience to change the is a complete mystery. Our
decision-making ability,
world around us.
rooted in our conscious experience of the world, is a
not-so-secret superpower to alter the physical world,
changing its evolution apparently at will.
That is something no physical law yet devised
can explain, and it leads to a question at the sharp
end of considerations of the relationship between
consciousness and the external world. “We act, we
decide, we initiate actions,” says Carlo Rovelli at Aix-
Marseille University in France. “How can we insert
this agency into the general picture of nature?”
Agency seems to exist on a similar sort of spectrum
as consciousness. We wouldn’t be inclined to ascribe
conscious experience to an apple, say, and an apple
doesn’t decide when it falls from a tree. If we climb
a tree, however, we can make a conscious decision to
jump down. Things get messy in the middle, though –
is a slime mould using chemotaxis to move towards
a food source displaying agency, for example?
PABLO HURTADO DE MENDOZA
PREVIOUS PAGE: LUMEZIA/ISTOCK Most people think not. “Agency is not just reflexes,” >

80 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


Chapter 6 | Consciousness and reality | 81
says Larissa Albantakis at the Center for Sleep and hard because it does look like, for instance, when I put
Consciousness at the University of Wisconsin- lots of serotonin in your brain, your mental states
Madison. “If you’re only reacting to the environment, change,” says Knox. “The question is how you think
you’re not an agent, you’re just a system going through that could work if you think there’s two kinds of
the motions.” The apparently deliberative quality separate stuff.”
of our agency sets it apart from bacteria responding “If there’s evidence we should carve out a different
to chemical stimuli, or even frogs reflexively snapping realm for organic things or people or whatever, then
at passing flies. “We collect influences from our past, by all means,” says physicist Sean Carroll at the
we subject those influences to reflective process, we California Institute of Technology. “But I’m made of
somehow extract things like hope and dreams and atoms, my laws of physics purport to explain atoms,
bring them to bear on behaviour, to mediate between and it would seem by far the most likely hypothesis
the influences impinging on us,” says philosopher that the laws of physics explain me.” The central
Jenann Ismael at Columbia University in New York. conundrum becomes what sort of physical laws can
Our current physical laws don’t try to explain unify two very different, conflicting views. “We see
how this can come about. “We think of ourselves as agents that make choices and exert a causal influence
coming from outside the causal order and somehow on what happens in the world, and then science comes
intervening in it, making things happen,” says Ismael. along and says, ‘you’re actually a bunch of particles or
The godlike status we accord ourselves as conscious atoms and you’re just obeying differential equations’,”
beings is highly suspicious to many physicists. “If says Carroll. “What we want to figure out is how those
I’m saying that something doesn’t boil down to the things can both be true at the same time.”
laws of physics, then I’m basically positing something For Carroll and many others, the answer lies not
supernatural, that’s outside natural laws,” says physicist in mysticism, but in emergence. This is the idea that
Matt Leifer at Chapman University in California. behaviours and properties that are inscrutable when
This has been a popular way out for natural you look at single components of a complex system
philosophers over the years, in various forms of mind- pop into existence when you view things as a whole.
body dualism: the idea that the mental and physical There are plenty of precedents. The temperature or
realms are separate, and the rules of one don’t apply density of a gas, for example, doesn’t mean much at
to the other. But that hardly seems a tenable position the level of single molecules. Look at all the molecules
within modern science. “Being a full-on dualist is quite of the gas together, however, and they are measurable

82 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


“One question is why we
should expect physics to
explain consciousness”

quantities that explain physical change: how Some doubt whether physics-based theories have
temperature differences cause heat flows, for example, the chops at all, however. “I don’t believe that physics
or how a gas pushes a piston when compressed. is necessarily as fundamental as most of us have
The catch remains the phenomenal complexity been led to believe,” says Leifer. Physics has been so
of our brains. “It’s one thing to say I can explain the successful, he thinks, precisely because it has extracted
temperature and density of the air by hypothesising the easy stuff – the bits of the world amenable to
that it is made of molecules bumping into one characterisation by regular, mathematical laws –
another,” says Carroll. “It seems quite a more dramatic and put it in a box marked “physics”. But that doesn’t
project to say I can explain mind and choices and mean everything fits in there.
consciousness as emerging out of atoms and Take an old chestnut that often comes up in
molecules bumping into one another.” discussions of conscious perceptions: colour.
But just as we don’t need to know how every “Physicists have a definition of red: light of such and
molecule in a gas is moving to know its temperature, such a wavelength,” says Leifer. But they miss out the
so agency might be understood by skating over its most essential aspect of a thing’s redness – how red
interior details and finding global quantities that we perceive it to be – purely because we have no
correspond to measurable outcomes. There is still a way of coming up with a common standard. The
lot of groundwork to be laid if we are to achieve that. question is what reason we have to think that
“How do you even translate concepts like ‘make a physics has an answer.
decision’ or ‘choice’ or ’cause something to happen’ That might represent a return to new, more subtle
into the language of statistical mechanics where you dualist ways of thinking. Others think answers
have things bumping into each other and probability might lie in some new understanding of how
distributions and stuff like that?” asks Carroll. quantum effects play out in our brains, or even more
Such progress that has been made so far revolves speculatively in the interplay of quantum theory and
around the still-nebulous concept of “information” gravity, or other physics we haven’t even invented yet.
as a physical thing, with the way conscious brains “Is it just a matter of building the bridges
manipulate it being seen as a key. That is the between different layers of scientific description,
starting point, for example, of mathematical or understanding an entirely new phenomenon?”
theories of consciousness, such as integrated asks Carroll. “I think it’s the first answer, but I’m
information theory (IIT). admitting there’s a question there.”  ❚

Chapter 6 | Consciousness and reality | 83


DOES CONSCIOUSNESS
CREATE REALITY?
Because our conscious experience seems related to and part of an external
physical world, our natural take is that our consciousness is a product of it.
We might have got things precisely the wrong way round.

OES reality exist without us? Albert decay. Those who subscribe to the many-worlds
Einstein appeared to be in no doubt: interpretation think it is an illusion conjured by
surely the moon doesn’t vanish when a splitting of the universe into each of the possible
we aren’t looking, he once asked outcomes. Others still say that there is no point in
incredulously. He had been provoked trying to explain it – and besides, who cares? The
by the proposition that things only maths works, so just shut up and calculate.
become real when we observe them. Whatever the case, wave function collapse seems
That suggestion emerges from the to hinge on intervention or observation, throwing
best-tested theory of material reality up some huge problems, not least about the role
that we have ever had: quantum theory. of consciousness in the whole process. This is the
When it comes to forecasting how the world will measurement problem, arguably the biggest headache
behave, quantum theory is unsurpassed. Its every in quantum theory. “It is very hard,” says Kelvin
prediction, no matter how counter-intuitive, is McQueen, a philosopher at Chapman University
borne out by experiment. Electrons, for instance, in California. “More interpretations are being
can sometimes display behaviour characteristic of thrown up every day, but all of them have problems.”
waves, even though they seem in other circumstances The most popular is known as the Copenhagen
to behave like particles. interpretation after the home city of one of quantum
Before observation, such quantum objects are theory’s pioneers, Niels Bohr. He argued that quantum
said to be in a superposition of all possible observable mechanics tells us only what we should expect when
outcomes. This doesn’t mean they exist in many states we make a measurement, not what causes that
at once, rather that we can only say that all the allowed outcome. The theory can’t tell us what a quantum
outcomes of measurement remain possible. This system is like before we observe it; all we can ever ask
potential is represented in the quantum wave function, of it is the probabilities of different possible outcomes.
a mathematical expression that encodes all outcomes Such a perspective seems to back you into an
and their relative probabilities. uncomfortable corner: that the act of our observation
But it isn’t at all obvious what, if anything, the wave calls the outcome into being. Can that be true? It seems
function can tell you about the nature of a quantum the antithesis of what science normally assumes, as
system before we make a measurement. That act Einstein intimated. Yet the idea has some pedigree.
reduces all those possible outcomes to one, dubbed Hungarian physicist John von Neumann was the first
the collapse of the wave function – but no one really to entertain it in the early 1930s, and his compatriot
knows what that means either. Some researchers Eugene Wigner went deepest with a thought experiment
think it might be a real physical process, like radioactive in the 1950s now known as Wigner’s friend.

84 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


Suppose that Wigner is standing outside a
windowless room where his friend is about to
make some measurement on a particle. Once
that is done, she knows what the observed property
of the particle is, but Wigner doesn’t. He can’t
meaningfully say that the particle’s wave function
has collapsed until his friend tells him the result.
Worse still, until she does, quantum theory
offers no way for Wigner to think about all the
unseen events inside the lab as having fixed
outcomes. His friend, her measuring apparatus and
the particle remain one big composite superposition.
It is as if we live in a solipsistic world where
WEERACHONOAT/ISTOCK

collapse only occurs when knowledge of the result


impinges on a conscious mind. “It follows that the
quantum description of objects is influenced by
impressions entering my consciousness,” Wigner
wrote. “Solipsism may be logically consistent with
present quantum mechanics.”
Albert Einstein queried whether John Wheeler at Princeton University put it
the moon really ceases to exist differently: it isn’t solipsism, but a kind of interactive
when we aren’t looking at it collaboration that brings things into being. We live,
said Wheeler, in a “participatory universe” – one that
can’t be meaningfully described without invoking
our active involvement. “Nothing is more astonishing
about quantum mechanics,” he wrote, “than its
allowing one to consider seriously… that the universe
would be nothing without observership.”
But Wheeler couldn’t escape the thicket of
irresolvable questions that the participatory universe
raises. For one, Wigner and his friend seem locked in an
infinite regress. Is Wigner himself in a superposition >

Chapter 6 | Consciousness and reality | 85


“Quantum theory could imply
that nothing would happen
without our involvement”
of states until he passes on the result to his other ‘facts’ of one of them are more fundamental than those
friends in the next building? Which observer of the other,” says Brukner – and so we are forced to
“decides” when wave function collapse occurs? And conclude that “there are no ‘facts of the world per se’ ”.
what constitutes a conscious observation anyway? Rather, there are only facts for each observer.
Despite the persistence of such questions, One interpretation of quantum mechanics takes
some theorists have recently returned to a form such a conclusion in its stride. Devised in the 2000s
of Wheeler’s vision, what Chris Fuchs at the by Fuchs and others, quantum Bayesianism (also
University of Massachusetts in Boston has called known as QBism) is rooted in the view that quantum
“participatory reality”. That shift is partly for want mechanics supplies only recommendations about
of a better alternative, but primarily it is because what a rational observer should believe they will see on
if you take quantum mechanics seriously, some making a measurement – and that these beliefs can be
element of observer-dependent subjectivity updated as the observer takes fresh experiences into
seems impossible to avoid. account. That is where the “Bayesianism” comes in: it
A couple of years ago, theoretical physicist Caslav refers to the classical theory of probability, initiated in
Brukner at the University of Vienna revisited the the 18th century, that assigns probabilities on the basis
Wigner’s friend scenario in a slightly altered form of what the observer already knows to be the case.
proposed by David Deutsch at the University of Oxford. QBism point-blank denies that there is any objective
Here, the friend makes the measurement – she has notion of a quantum state at all. This doesn’t mean
collapsed the particle’s wave function, producing either there can be nothing “real” beyond personal belief,
outcome A or B – but tells Wigner only that she sees only that quantum mechanics doesn’t speak directly
a definite result, not what it is. In Deutsch’s scenario, to that issue. The existence of Brukner’s “alternative
Wigner is forced to conclude that his friend, her facts” causes no pain in such a picture, because it has
measuring apparatus and the particle are in a joint assumed them all along. Nor, indeed, does wave
superposition, even though he knows a measurement function collapse, which is then just a way of talking
has happened. about how measurement updates our knowledge.
To Wigner’s friend, she is definitely in, say, the state But few physicists are prepared to accept such
“I see A”, but to Wigner, she is in a superposition of “I stringent limits on their efforts to describe reality,
see A” and “I see B”. So who is right? They both are, says which is why QBism remains a minority sport.
Brukner, depending on whose point of view you adopt. The response of Markus Müller, a theorist at the
He has shown that if quantum mechanics is correct, Institute for Quantum Optics and Quantum
there is no privileged perspective from which a third Information in Vienna, is to take things up a notch.
observer can reconcile both Wigner’s and his friend’s “QBism is not extreme enough,” he says. “It assumes
statements. “There is no reason to assume that the that there is this one external world out there which is

86 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


ultimately responsible for our experiences.” His to be simple and different observers can generally
approach involves imagining that there are no agree on some aspects of the plot,” says Chiribella.
fundamental laws of nature – no general relativity, The surprises don’t stop there. This emergent reality
Maxwell’s equations or Heisenberg’s uncertainty should have just the qualities we see in quantum
principle – and asking what the world would then physics, where objects can show wave-like properties
look like. and behave in “non-local” ways, when a measurement
Müller stripped away the physics and used a field of on one particle can seem instantaneously to influence
maths called algorithmic information theory, which the state of another separated in space.
uses inductive logic to ask, given that you experience The upshot is that from the most minimal
X – you make an observation of the world and see assumptions about the probabilities of what our
the outcome X – what are the chances you will then personal experiences will contain, you can recover a
experience another outcome, Y? The idea, says theorist world like the one we know. “The world could still look
Giulio Chiribella at the University of Hong Kong, “is something like how we experience it, even though in
to think of our experience as a movie made of many truth it would be mind-bogglingly different,” says Müller.
frames and to ask the question, given the frames I It isn’t easy to see how Müller’s ideas can be tested.
have seen so far, what frame will I see next?” But circumstantial evidence that he could be on the
The remarkable answer is that, even without any right track comes with the way they solve a long-
underlying laws, as random experiences stack up, standing metaphysical conundrum. In the late 19th
the conditional probability of the next experience, century, Austrian physicist Ludwig Boltzmann
as described by a string of bits, tends to be higher described the world as space filled with particles in
for simpler bit sequences than for complex ones. random motion, adopting all manner of different
This makes it look as if there is a fairly simple algorithm configurations. Experiments have long confirmed that
generating the bit strings. So the observer deduces our reality matches this vision, but there is a problem.
a simple “model” of reality, characterised by regular If you examine the probabilities of each configuration,
and comprehensible laws that smoothly connect it turns out we are much less likely to be sentient
one experience to the next. beings who evolved on a planet over billions of
This seems deeply odd: how can randomness years than ephemeral lone “brains”, condensed
give rise to this apparently law-bound behaviour? It out of chaos by sheer chance and floating freely,
is a little like the way we understand a gas. Although, complete with imagined memories and experiences.
in principle, all possible configurations of its molecules How can we know we aren’t these “Boltzmann
are allowed, the probability distribution of particle brains”, apt to dissolve back into the fluctuating
speeds we see has a simple bell-shaped curve, and cosmos at any moment?
the particles are distributed in space with bland If objective reality emerges from the mathematically
uniformity. Out of that come simple laws relating to predictable way our past experiences determine
things we can easily measure: pressure, temperature future observations, then sudden discontinuities
and volume. Those laws aren’t written into the gas in experience of the sort Boltzmann brains
particles themselves; they are an emergent property would encounter will be vanishingly improbable.
of the probabilities of different configurations. Experience should be smooth, connected and,
“The remarkable thing is that a notion of an objective at our scale, rather predictable.
external world emerges automatically in the long run,” All the same, this image of the universe built directly
says Müller. What’s more, “different observers will from conscious experiences is so “out there” that other
tend to agree on properties of that external world”, researchers barely know what to make of it. Yet few
he says. That is because, according to algorithmic would dismiss it out of hand. Even Einstein kept an
information theory, the probabilities of bit strings open mind. “It is basic for physics that one assumes
for different observers will tend to converge on the a real world existing independently from any act of
same distribution – so they will agree on what the perception,” he wrote in a letter shortly before he
“laws of the world” are. “Overall, the ‘movie’ is likely died in 1955. “But this we do not know.”  ❚

Chapter 6 | Consciousness and reality | 87


IS THE UNIVERSE
CONSCIOUS?
Attempts to encapsulate the problem of consciousness
mathematically lead down some very strange alleyways –
most controversially, suggesting that some form of
consciousness might be a universal property of matter.
HE unique difficulty of the hard theory (IIT) holds that a system’s consciousness
problem of consciousness stems arises from the way information moves between
from the inherently subjective nature its subsystems.
of felt experience. Whatever it is, you
might think, it isn’t something you ←-
can prod and measure – not a natural Turn back to page 14 for the basis of IIT-
fit for our mathematically based
models of physical phenomena. One way to think of these subsystems is as islands,
Then again, mathematics has each with their own population of neurons. The islands
a track record with hard problems. are connected by traffic flows of information. For
Physicist Eugene Wigner coined the phrase the consciousness to appear, so the idea goes, this
“unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics” in the information flow must be complex enough to make
1960s to encapsulate the curious fact that merely by the islands interdependent. Changing the flow of
manipulating numbers, we can describe and predict information from one island should affect the state and
all manner of natural phenomena with astonishing output of another. In principle, this lets you put a
clarity, from the movements of planets and the number on the degree of consciousness: you could
strange behaviour of fundamental particles to quantify it by measuring how much an island’s output
the consequences of a collision between two relies on information flowing from other islands. This
black holes billions of light years away. gives a sense of how well a system integrates
That success is down to the ability of mathematics information, a value called “phi”.
to translate concepts into formal, logical statements If there is no dependence on a traffic flow between
that can draw out insights that wouldn’t be exposed the islands, phi is zero and there is no consciousness.
from just talking about things in messy human But if strangling or cutting off the connection makes
language. “This might help us to quantify experiences a difference to the amount of information it integrates
like the smell of coffee in ways that we can’t if we and outputs, then the phi of that group is above zero.
rely on plain English,” says Johannes Kleiner, a The higher the phi, the more consciousness a system
mathematician at the Munich Centre for will display.
Mathematical Philosophy in Germany. Another key feature of IIT, known as the exclusion
This is why Kleiner and Sean Tull, a mathematician postulate, says that a group will explicitly display
AGSANDREW/ISTOCK

at the University of Oxford, have begun formalising consciousness only when its phi is “maximal”. That is
the mathematics behind arguably the only theory to say, its own degree of consciousness has to be bigger
of consciousness with a halfway-thought-through than the degree of consciousness you can ascribe to
mathematical underpinning. Integrated information any of its individual parts, and simultaneously bigger >

Chapter 6 | Consciousness and reality | 89


than the degree of consciousness of any system of are sedated via a general anaesthetic, for instance,
which it is a part. Any and all parts of the human brain but Pedro Mediano, now part of Bor’s lab at the
might have a micro-consciousness, for example. But University of Cambridge, and his colleagues have
when one part has an increase in consciousness, such shown that it doesn’t. “It either goes up or stays the
as when a person is brought out of anaesthesia, the same,” says Bor. And explaining why information
micro-consciousnesses are lost. In IIT, only the system flow gives rise to an experience, such as the smell
with the largest phi displays the consciousness we of coffee, is problematic. IIT frames conscious
register as experience. experience as the result of “conceptual structures”
The idea has won adherents since Giulio Tononi, that are shaped by the arrangement of parts of the
a neuroscientist at the University of Wisconsin, first relevant network, but many find the explanation
came up with it. “Theoretically, it’s quite appealing,” convoluted and unsatisfying.
says Daniel Bor at the University of Cambridge. “We Philosopher John Searle is one of IIT’s detractors.
have this association between consciousness and He has argued that it ignores the question of why
intelligence: creatures able to recognise themselves and how consciousness arises in favour of making
in the mirror also seem to be the most intelligent. the questionable assumption that it is simply a by-
So some connection between consciousness and product of the existence of information. For that
intelligence seems reasonable.” And intelligence has reason, he says, IIT “does not seem to be a serious
a link to gathering and processing information. “That scientific proposal”.
means you may as well make the related connection Perhaps the most troubling critiques of IIT as a
that, in some way, consciousness is related to mathematical theory concern a lack of clarity about
information processing and integration,” says Bor. the underlying numbers. When it comes to actually
It also makes sense given what we know about calculating a value for phi for the entirety of a system
consciousness in the human brain. It is compromised, as complex as a brain, IIT gives a recipe that is almost
for example, if there is damage to the cerebral cortex. impossible to follow – something even Tononi admits.
This region has a relatively small number of highly “As it’s currently given, phi is very difficult to
interconnected neurons, and would have a large phi calculate for a whole brain,” says Tull. That is an
in IIT. The cerebellum, on the other hand, has a much understatement. Using the current method, calculating
higher number of neurons, but they are relatively phi for the 86 billion neurons of the human brain
unconnected. IIT would predict that damage to the would take longer than the age of the universe. Bor has
cerebellum might have little effect on conscious worked out that just calculating it for the 302-neuron
experience, which is exactly what studies show. brain of a nematode worm would take 5 × 1079 years
IIT is less convincing when it comes to some details, on a standard PC.
though. Phi should decrease when you go to sleep or And when you calculate phi for things you wouldn’t

90 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


BET_NOIRE/ISTOCK

Attempts to quantify consciousness


suggest even some electrical circuits
could have it

expect to be conscious, you get all sorts of strange thinks we need to clarify and simplify the mathematics
results. Scott Aaronson, a theoretical physicist at the underlying it. That is why he and Tull set about trying
University of Texas at Austin, for example, was initially to identify the necessary mathematical ingredients
excited by the theory, which he describes as “a serious, of IIT, splitting them into three parts. First is the set
honourable attempt” to figure out how to get common of physical systems that encode the information. Next
sense answers to the question of which physical is the various manifestations or “spaces” of conscious
systems are conscious. But then he set to testing it. experience. Finally, there are basic building blocks that
Aaronson took the principles of IIT and used them relate these two: the “repertoires” of cause and effect.
to compute phi for a mathematical object called a In 2020, they demonstrated how these ingredients
Vandermonde matrix. This is a grid of numbers whose can be joined in a way that provides a logically
values are interrelated, and can be used to build a grid- consistent way of applying the IIT algorithm for finding
like circuit, known as a Reed-Solomon decoding circuit, phi. “Now the fundamental idea is well-defined enough
to correct errors in the information that is read off CDs to make the technical problems go away,” says Kleiner.
and DVDs. What he found was that a sufficiently large Their aspiration is that mathematicians will now be
Reed-Solomon circuit would have an enormous phi. able to create improved models of consciousness based
Scaled to a large enough size, one of these circuits on the premises of IIT – or, even better, competitor
would end up being far more conscious than a human. theories. “We would be glad to contribute to the further
The same problem exists in other arrangements of development of IIT, but we also hope to help improve
information processing routines, Aaronson pointed and unite various existing models,” says Kleiner.
out: you can have integrated information, with a high “Eventually, we may come to propose new ones.”
phi value, that doesn’t lead to anything we would One consequence of this stimulus might be a
recognise as consciousness. He concluded that IIT reckoning for the notion, raised by IIT’s application
unavoidably predicts vast amounts of consciousness to grid-shaped circuits, that inanimate matter can
in physical systems that no sensible person would be conscious. Such a claim is typically dismissed
regard as particularly ‘conscious’ at all. out of hand, because it appears to be tantamount
Aaronson walked away, but not everyone sees to “panpsychism”, the idea that consciousness is
highly conscious grid-shaped circuits as a deal-breaker. a fundamental property of all matter.
For Kleiner, it is simply a consequence of the nature This isn’t to say that fundamental particles have
of the beast: we lack information because any analysis feelings. But panpsychists do argue that they may
of consciousness relies on self-reporting and intuition. have some semblance of consciousness, however
“We can’t get reports from grids,” he says. “This is fragmentary, that could combine to generate the various
the problem.” levels of consciousness experienced by birds or chimps
Rather than abandoning a promising model, he or us. “Particles or other basic physical entities might >

Chapter 6 | Consciousness and reality | 91


have simple forms of consciousness that are Roger Penrose’s suggestion that our consciousness is
fundamental, but complex human and animal actually “the reason the universe is here”. It is based on
consciousness would be constituted by or emergent a hunch about quantum theory’s shortcomings. But
from this,” says Hedda Hassel Mørch at Inland Norway if there is any substance to this idea, the framework of
University of Applied Sciences in Lillehammer. IIT – and its exclusion postulate in particular – suggests
The idea that electrons could have some form that information flow between the various scales of
of consciousness might be hard to swallow, but the universe’s contents could create different kinds
panpsychists argue that it provides the only plausible of consciousness that ebb and flow depending on
approach to solving the hard problem. They reason what exists at any particular time. The evolution
that, rather than trying to account for consciousness of our consciousness might have, in IIT’s terms,
in terms of non-conscious elements, we should “excluded” the consciousness of the universe.
instead ask how rudimentary forms of consciousness Or perhaps not. There are good reasons to
might come together to give rise to the complex remain sceptical about the power of maths to
experiences we have. explain consciousness, never mind the knock-on
With that in mind, Mørch thinks IIT is at least a effects for our understanding of physics. We seem
good place to start. Its general approach, analysing to be dealing with something so involved that
our first-person perspective in terms of what we calculations may not even be possible, according
perceive when certain brain regions become active and to Phil Maguire, a computer scientist at Maynooth
using that to develop constraints on what its physical University in Ireland. “Breaking down cognitive
correlate could be, is “probably correct”, she says. And processes is so complex that it is not feasible,” he says.
although IIT as currently formulated doesn’t strictly Others express related doubts as to whether maths is
say everything is conscious – because consciousness up to the job, even in principle. “I think mathematics can
arises in networks rather than individual components – help us understand the neural basis of consciousness in
it is entirely possible that a refined version could. the brain, and perhaps even machine consciousness,
“I think that the core ideas underlying IIT are fully but it will inevitably leave something out: the felt
compatible with panpsychism,” says Kleiner. inner quality of experience,” says Susan Schneider,
That might also fit in with indications from a philosopher and cognitive scientist at the University
elsewhere that the relationship between our of Connecticut.
consciousness and the universe might not be as Philip Goff, a philosopher at Durham University, UK,
straightforward as we imagine. Take the quantum and a vocal advocate for panpsychism, has a similar
measurement problem. Quantum theory, our view. Consciousness deals with physical phenomena
description of the basic interactions of matter, says in terms of their perceived qualities, he points out – the
that before we measure a quantum object, it can have smell of coffee or the taste of mint, for example – which
many different values, encapsulated in a mathematical aren’t conveyable in a purely quantitative objective
entity called the wave function. So what collapses the framework. “In dealing with consciousness, we need
many possibilities into something definite and “real”? more than the standard scientific tools of public
One viewpoint is that our consciousness does it, observation and mathematics,” says Goff.
which would mean we live in what physicist But Kleiner isn’t put off. He is developing a
John Wheeler called a “participatory universe”. mathematical model that can incorporate ineffable,
There are many problems with this idea, not least the private experiences. It is currently undergoing peer
question of what did the collapsing before conscious review. And even if it doesn’t work, he says, something
minds evolved. A viable mathematical model of else will: “I’m fully convinced that in combination
consciousness that allows for it to be a property of with experiments and philosophy, maths can help
matter would at least provide a solution for that. us proceed much further in uncovering the mystery
Then there is University of Oxford mathematician of consciousness.”  ❚

92 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


PERSPECTIVE ANIL SETH

“WE NEED TO SOLVE


THE REAL PROBLEM
OF CONSCIOUSNESS”
The best way to make progress on the HE subjective nature of consciousness
makes it difficult even to define. The
nature of consciousness might be to break closest we have to a consensus is that
it down into its constituent parts. there is “something it is like to be
conscious”. There is something it is like
to be me or you, and probably something
it is like to be a dolphin or a mouse. But
there is – presumably – nothing it is like
to be a bacterium or a toy robot. The
challenge is to understand how and why
this can be true. How do conscious experiences relate
to the cells and molecules and atoms inside brains and
PROFILE bodies? Why should physical matter give rise to an
ANIL inner life at all?
SETH Some people fear science may not be up to the
task. They point out that you can’t precisely control
or observe felt experiences. Some even question
Anil Seth is professor the idea that physical mechanisms can ever
of cognitive and explain consciousness.
computational I disagree. I believe that science is capable of
neuroscience at the explaining consciousness, but only if we stop treating it
University of Sussex, as a single big mystery requiring a humdinger solution.
Instead, we must break it down into its various
UK, and author of Being
related properties and address each in turn. As we
You: A new science of progressively explain why particular patterns of
consciousness brain activity map to particular kinds of conscious
experience, we will find that the deeper mystery
of consciousness itself begins to fade away.
The easy problem is really a series of problems. >

Chapter 6 | Consciousness and reality | 93


PERSPECTIVE ANIL SETH

These involve understanding how the brain, in concert the experience of redness is the way it is. Why isn’t
with the rest of the body, gives rise to functions like it like blueness, or toothache, or jealousy?
perception, cognition, learning and behaviour. These This approach has something of a pedigree. Not
problems aren’t actually easy at all; the point is that so long ago, biologists and chemists doubted that
there is no conceptual mystery, that these problems the property of “being alive” could ever be explained
can be solved in terms of physical mechanisms, mechanistically. Nowadays, although there are still
however complex and hard to discern these many things about life that remain unknown, the idea
mechanisms may be. The hard problem, on the other that being alive requires some special sauce has long
hand, is the enigma of why and how any of this should been retired. The hard problem of life wasn’t so much
be accompanied by conscious experience at all: why solved as dissolved.
aren’t we just meaty robots, without an inner universe? Now, it is true that life isn’t the same thing as
The temptation is to think that solving the easy consciousness. Most conspicuously, the properties
problems would get us nowhere at all in solving the of life are objectively describable, whereas the
hard problem, leaving the brain basis of consciousness properties of consciousness exist only in the first
a total mystery. person. But this isn’t an insurmountable barrier;
Fortunately, there is an alternative, which I have it mostly means the relevant information, because
come to call the “real problem” of consciousness: how it is subjective, is harder to collect.
to explain, predict and control the various properties Part of the strategy in dissolving the hard problem
of consciousness in terms of physical processes in of life was to stop treating it as one big scary mystery
the brain and body. The real problem is distinct from in need of a eureka solution and instead as a collection
the hard problem, because it isn’t – at least not in of related properties, each addressable somewhat
the first instance – about explaining why and how separately. For consciousness, there are many ways
consciousness is part of our universe. It is also distinct to cut the cake. One way I advocate is to distinguish
from the easy problems, because it doesn’t sweep the between conscious level (how conscious you are, as
subjective, experiential properties under the carpet. in the difference between general anaesthesia and
The real problem isn’t a completely new way of normal wakeful awareness), conscious content
thinking, but, for me, putting things in terms of (what you are conscious of) and conscious self
explanation, prediction and control has helped to (the experience of “being you” or “being me”).
crystallise what a successful science of consciousness By developing accounts that explain, predict and
should look like, since these are the criteria that are control these different aspects of consciousness,
applied in most other fields of science. my belief is that a fulfilling picture of all conscious
Take, for example, the visual experience of redness. experience will come to light.
The hard problem asks why there is such an experience Let’s focus on content and self. My strategy
at all, while the easy problems encompass all the for explaining these properties of consciousness
processes and outcomes associated with light of a is based on an increasingly popular theory in
particular wavelength entering the eye. From the cognitive neuroscience called predictive processing.
perspective of the real problem, we want to know The bedrock idea is simple. Imagine that you are your
what it is about specific patterns of activity in the brain, locked inside the bony vault of the skull, trying to
brain that explains (and predicts and controls) why figure out what is out there in the world – a world that,

94 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


from the perspective of the brain, also includes the bridges between neural mechanisms and aspects
body. All you have to go on are noisy and ambiguous of what conscious experiences are like, from the
sensory signals, which are only indirectly related to perspective of the person experiencing them.
what is out there, and which certainly don’t come with This is what my colleagues and I have been doing in
labels attached (“I’m from a cup of coffee! I’m from my laboratory at the University of Sussex, UK. Some of
a tree!”). Perception, in this view, has to be a process our experiments are very simple – for example, finding
of inference, of neurally implemented probabilistic that people consciously perceive expected images
guesswork. When I see a red coffee cup on the table more quickly, and more accurately, than unexpected
in front of me, this is because “red coffee cup” is the images. But the really exciting work is taking us deeper
brain’s best guess of the hidden, and ultimately into the phenomenology – the “what-it-is-like”-ness –
unknowable, causes of the corresponding sensory of conscious experiences. In one example, we are
signals. When I experience the glow of a sunset, or investigating the phenomenology of different varieties
the sharp taste of an adventurous cheese, that, too, of visual hallucination in terms of their dependence
is a perceptual best guess. on different kinds of perceptual prediction.
How are these perceptual best guesses arrived Some hallucinations, such as those due to psychosis
at? According to predictive processing, the brain is or neurodegenerative disease, can be complex,
constantly calibrating its perceptual predictions using featuring rich perceptual scenes experienced as being
data from the senses. The predictive processing theory real. Others, such as those arising from progressive
has it that perception involves two counterflowing visual loss, can be relatively simple and aren’t
streams of signals. There is an “inside-out” stream, experienced as being continuous with the real world.
cascading downwards through the brain’s perceptual These differences can be simulated by novel neural
hierarchies, that conveys predictions about the causes network architectures that deploy perceptual
of sensory inputs. Then there are “outside-in” predictions in different ways. These neural networks
prediction errors – the sensory signals – that report serve as computational models of the brain basis of
the differences between what the brain expects and visual experiences, and we can check their output by
what it gets. By continually updating its predictions to asking people who experience hallucinations to rate
minimise sensory prediction errors, the brain will settle what they come up with. We are now extending
and resettle on an evolving best guess of its sensory this approach – which we call “computational
causes, and this is what we consciously perceive. phenomenology” – to other, more fundamental
Perception, in this view, isn’t a passive registration aspects of perceptual experience, like the sensation
of an external reality. It is an active construction, a kind of time passing and the three-dimensional structure
of “controlled hallucination”, in which the brain’s best of visual space.
guesses are tied to the world – and the body – through By progressively accounting for the deep structure of
a continuous process of prediction error minimisation. perceptual experiences – not only the specific contents
Predictive processing isn’t a theory of consciousness, they present, like a cat or a coffee cup, but how they
in the sense that solving the hard problem would unfold over time and space – my belief is that the
require. Instead, at least at first, it is best thought of as apparent mystery of the hard problem is already
a theory for consciousness science, in the real problem beginning to dissolve. And this process gathers
sense. It provides a method for building explanatory momentum when we ask who, or what, is doing >

Chapter 6 | Consciousness and reality | 95


PERSPECTIVE ANIL SETH

all this perceiving – and consider the experience internal state of the body – blood pressure, say, or
of being a conscious self from the same “real how the heart is doing – and therefore enable the
problem” perspective. brain to perform its most important task: keeping
Contrary to how things might seem, selves aren’t the body alive.
essences-of-you that peer out through the windows Like all sensory signals, interoceptive signals
of the senses from somewhere inside the skull. Instead, are only indirectly related to their causes, and so
the self is a perception too. Experiences of “being you” interoception must also involve a process of best-
are collections of brain-based best guesses, and guessing. And just as inference about the causes
understanding this further erodes the dualistic of visual signals underpins visual experience, my
intuitions on which the hard problem rests. proposal is that interoceptive inferences underpin
Just as consciousness has many aspects, there are other kinds of experiences: in this case, bodily
also many ways we experience being a self. These can experiences, like emotions and moods.
be arranged in a loose hierarchy, beginning with low- This proposal might seem nothing more than a
level experiences of being a physical body, through to modern gloss on some old ideas that emotion involves
experiences of seeing the world from a particular first- perception of changes in the physiological condition
person perspective, conscious intentions to do things of the body. But there is more to it than that. Following
(what we might call experiences of free will), all the way the real problem strategy, the differences between
up to experiences of being a continuous person over emotional experiences and visual experiences can
time within a rich social and cultural environment – now be understood in terms of the different kinds of
a self with a name, an identity and a set of memories. I perceptual prediction at play. Visual experiences of
argue that each of these aspects of selfhood can be objects are generally concerned with figuring out
understood as a distinctive form of controlled what is there, so it makes sense for the corresponding
hallucination. perceptual experiences to have the character of things
For now, let’s drill down to the most basic aspect with specific locations and physical extents. Emotional
of conscious selfhood: the experience of being a body. experiences, by contrast, are generally concerned with
I think of this as a rudimentary feeling of simply being the organism’s physiological condition and prospects
a living organism – partly expressed through emotions of staying alive. These experiences, and experiences
and moods, but at its deepest layers without any of being a body more generally, don’t have shapes and
describable content at all. locations in space. They instead have valence, which,
It is here that the perception of the body from in psychology, means things are good or bad now, or
within, known as interoception, comes to the fore. likely to be good or bad in the future – which is what
Interoceptive sensations tell the brain about the it is like to feel an emotion.  ❚

96 | New Scientist Essential Guide | Consciousness


ESSENTIAL
GUIDE №13

THE SOLAR SYSTEM


A JOURNEY THROUGH OUR COSMIC
NEIGHBOURHOOD – AND BEYOND

THE SUN /
EARTH AND THE MOON /
THE INNER PLANETS /
THE GAS GIANTS AND THEIR MOONS /
THE UNKNOWN EDGE /
EXOPLANETS AND LIFE /
AND MORE

ON SALE 21 JULY
ESSENTIAL
GUIDE№12

CONSCIOUSNESS
WHY DO WE HAVE CONSCIOUS EXPERIENCES AND
HOW DO OUR BRAINS MAKE THEM? WHAT IS THE SELF,
AND HOW DOES CONSCIOUSNESS FIT INTO THE COSMOS?
CONSCIOUSNESS IS EVERYTHING WE HAVE – OUR FEELING OF BEING,
AND OUR RELATIONSHIP WITH THE WORLD. BUT WHAT IT IS AND WHY
IT EXISTS REMAIN FUNDAMENTAL MYSTERIES, THE SUBJECTS OF THIS
12TH NEW SCIENTIST ESSENTIAL GUIDE. TOPICS INCLUDE:
❶ Theories of consciousness
❷ Animal and human minds
❸ The self and free will
❹ Sleep, dreaming and altered consciousness
❺ Consciousness and the universe

£9.99

1 2

9 772634 015019

You might also like