You are on page 1of 9

Tragedy without Character: Poetics VI.

1450$^{a}$ 24
Author(s): Catherine Lord
Source: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 28, No. 1 (Autumn, 1969), pp. 55-62
Published by: Wiley on behalf of The American Society for Aesthetics
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/428909 .
Accessed: 01/02/2015 11:16

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Wiley and The American Society for Aesthetics are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend
access to The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 128.235.251.160 on Sun, 1 Feb 2015 11:16:54 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
CATHERINE LORD

Tragedy Without Character:


Poetics VI. 1450so 24

I one point. This point has been felt to be


the most vulnerable of all his assertions
IT IS COMMONLY BELIEVED that of the primacy of plot. Aristotle is not
there are two kinds of readers or spectators. content to say merely that plot is the pri-
There are those who read primarily for plot, mary part of tragedy. He goes further.
story, action, narrative, and who espe- He says, "Without action there cannot be
cially enjoy spectacle-the vulgar. Then a tragedy; there may be without charac-
there are those, the connoisseurs of letters, ter" (1450a 24).1 I shall understand this
the cognoscenti-ourselves-who place a statement in its most uncompromising
greater premium on character, thought, form; by taking it quite literally I hope
and diction. When we find Aristotle ex- to show what tragedy without character
pressly giving the pride of place to plot entails.
among the six parts of Tragedy-Plot, More important still, there is a general
Character, Thought, Diction, Spectacle, principle at work here which lies at the
and Music-we are instantly perplexed, if foundation of aesthetic inquiry. I have
not outraged. Even those of us who may argued that to understand a work of art
be sympathetic to Aristotle on some fairly is to understand the kind of unity it
general ground are strongly tempted to possesses.2 Here, then, is a program that
suppose that what Aristotle means by plot, requires us to show in detail how the parts
mythos in some places, logos in others, of a certain type of work, in the present
cannot possibly be that crude thing, case a tragedy, function together to pro-
namely, story and action. He must mean duce a unity. To discover what kind of
something more subtle than that. Those of unity a tragedy possesses one must try to
us who are not prepared to give Aristotle separate in thought what may or may not
the benefit of the doubt will insist that he be separable in reality in an effort to de-
does, indeed, mean the crude thing and termine whether or not it is indeed actually
that he is insensitive to the finer features separable in reality. If the theory of or-
of the literary art. ganic unity is correct, it may be supposed
In this essay I shall assume that Aris- that such an effort at separation will prove
totle does mean that plot, story, action, a failure. But having questioned the doc-
the crude thing, is primary and I shall trine of organic unity, we are prepared to
undertake to defend his thesis in regard to
accept in certain cases quite a different
verdict. It is surprising that the philoso-
CATHERINELORD is a member of the philosophy de-
partment of Syracuse University. Her latest article pher who is especially associated with the
in this journal is "Unity with Impunity" (Fall theory of organic unity should be willing
1967). to allow for a tragedy without character.

This content downloaded from 128.235.251.160 on Sun, 1 Feb 2015 11:16:54 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
56 CATHERINE LORD

Presumably, then, Aristotle does not re- plot and character correlative. The fact of
gard character as being, in the strict sense, the matter is that Aristotle explicitly
organically entailed by tragedy, even states: ". . Tragedy is an imitation, not of
though he assigns it a role second only to men, but of an action...." 8 More fully,
plot. Dramatic action... is not with a view to the
If we look at what Aristotle actually does representation of character; character comes in
in the Poetics, we find that his remark in as subsidiary to actions. Hence the incidents and
VI, 1450a 24 is by no means an isolated the plot are the end of a tragedy; and the end is
the chief thing of all.9
apercu. He is engaged in the ambitious
enterprise of understanding tragedy For House, plot becomes subservient to
through what can only be called a total character because it supplies the material
dismantling or disassembling of tragedy conditions which individuate character.10
into its component parts. What is being To make plot and character correlative
dismantled is a system (not an organism) is to ignore the individual nature of these
which, in the process of being reassembled, two parts of tragedy and to misconstrue
is seen to exhibit a fairly complex kind of their actual relationship to each other.
unity. The present essay is designed as a There is no justification for the view that
specific application of a more general all six parts of a tragedy, taken together,
method of aesthetic inquiry (call it sys- should exhibit organic unity: Aristotle de-
tems-analysis, if you will) which can be fines organic unity in specific connection
employed in the examination of any work with his discussion of plot. He tells us
of art. that the plot should exhibit a unity such
My discussion remains entirely within that if any one of the parts of the plot is
the Aristotelian framework; it does not "displaced or removed the whole will be
depend on a redefinition of Tragedy, "an disjointed and disturbed." 11 We must not
imitation of an action that is serious, com- identify the parts of the plot with the six
plete, and of a certain magnitude: in lan- parts of tragedy: the plot is one of those
guage embellished with each kind of six parts.
artistic ornament, the several kinds being Three considerations argue for the in-
found in separate parts of the play;... "3 dependence and the separability of at least
on a redefinition of Character, "that in some of the parts of a tragedy. First,
virtue of which we ascribe certain qualities Aristotle grades them in importance. Char-
to agents4... that which reveals moral acter is given second place.'2 Spectacle is
purpose, showing what kind of things a said to be least important because a work
man chooses or avoids," 5 nor on a redefini- can achieve the proper effect just in the
tion of Plot, "the arrangement" or "com- hearing.'3 This means that the parts have
bination of the incidents" (Aristotle uses "grades of relevance," as I have called it.14
the word synthesis).6 In particular, then, there is at least one
Those commentators who seem to re- part, spectacle, which is both separable in
spect Aristotle's emphasis on the primacy thought and separable in reality.
of plot usually undermine this emphasis by The second consideration derives from
their modifications of it. Drawing upon the fact that most of the parts are said to
Aristotle's work in ethics, they argue that possess each its own intrinsic power.
since character is formed by action, tragedy Thought can arouse "pity, fear, anger and
is to be viewed as character-in-action. This the like." 15 Spectacle can also arouse pity
is essentially the position of S. H. Butcher and fear16 and it has an emotional attrac-
and Humphry House. House goes even tion of its own.l7 Music, though termed
further to insist that Aristotle's emphasis an embellishment,l8 gives especially in-
on the primacy of plot "is best under- tense pleasure (as does spectacle) and we
stood as an attempt to guarantee the in- know from the Politicsl9 that music has the
dividuality of character." Such modifica- power to induce catharsis. Notice that we
tions of Aristotle's thesis tend to make now have two parts, spectacle and music,

This content downloaded from 128.235.251.160 on Sun, 1 Feb 2015 11:16:54 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Tragedy Without Character: Poetics VI. 1450a 24 57

which, even though they contribute to the we can now see the advantages of the
tragic effect, cannot be taken as essential functional approach which an organic
or indispensable. theory invites. I only inveigh against what
Finally, Aristotle expressly maintains might be termed the indispensability-inter-
that there can be tragedy without char- dependence view of organic unity.
acter. No longer need we regard this
statement as some oddity or stumbling II
block which must be excused in some way
or dismissed as an extravagance. His state- Interestingly enough, it is Humphry
ment is all of a piece with his general House, with all his concern for the im-
approach. Aristotle even entertains (for portance of character, who gives the key
him) the more radical possibility of a to tragedy without character. House main-
plotless tragedy, or quasi-tragedy, when he tains that the famous "flaw," the hamartia,
says, has nothing to do with a moral state at all.
.. if you string together a set of speeches expres-
He argues that the hamartia should not be
sive of character, and well finished in point of viewed as a flaw or a moral frailty. Rather,
diction and thought, you will not produce the it should be taken to mean a mistake due
essential tragic effect nearly so well as with a to ignorance of circumstance.22 Nearly all
play which, however deficient in these respects, scholars now accept the interpretation of
yet has a plot....20
the hamartia as simple mistake. Gerald F.
To sum up these results: we see that Else summarizes the scholarship and elab-
Aristotle, in his very investigation of trag- orates on the implications of this inter-
edy, overhauls and dismantles it part by pretation.23 His conclusions (commended
part. Accordingly, we find that we can have by Richmond Lattimore)24 accord with
tragedy without spectacle. We can have House's thesis. Accordingly, I shall main-
tragedy without music. We can have trag- tain without argument that hamartia
edy without character. We may perhaps means simple mistake. This mistake should
have tragedy without thought, for the not be construed as an error of judgment
incidents should speak for themselves.21 as Bywater does in his translation. An
And we can even have tragedy without error of judgment implies a failure of
plot. Let us not, however, commit the practical wisdom and this, for Aristotle
fallacy of composition and conclude that certainly, is a flaw in character. But any-
we can have tragedy without all of these one, anyone at all, can make a simple mis-
parts taken collectively! take. When Oedipus married Jocasta he
Aristotle sees tragedy as a goal-directed made a mistake; there was no error in
system. The goal is catharsis. He disassem- judgment. It may be difficult for us to
bles tragedy in order to see how each part accept the possibility that the tragic rever-
functions to promote that goal. Precisely sal can be brought about by an elementary
because each part does individually con- error. Perhaps this is due to our traditional
tribute to the whole, no one part is ab- preoccupation with hubris as well as to a
solutely necessary. The system is over- general fascination with flaws, preferably
determined and redundant. In this respect tragic, in ourselves and others.
tragedy is indeed like a living organism. It Despite his interpretation of the hamar-
is what W. R. Ashby calls ultrastable. tia as a simple mistake, House insists that
Damage to a part of a living organism Aristotle "assumes as a matter of course
often receives compensation from another that the hamartia is accompanied by moral
part. For instance, one part of the brain imperfections...." 25 Does Aristotle make
will take over for an injured part. Leonard any such assumption? Here House is as-
Meyer has pointed out that this kind of suming, as a matter of course, the second
analysis in particular brings to clear sight part, Character, which seems likely to be
overdetermination and redundancy, fea- flawed because the hero must not be
tures of a living organism. Furthermore, "eminently" good. But to discover what

This content downloaded from 128.235.251.160 on Sun, 1 Feb 2015 11:16:54 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
58 CATHERINE LORD

tragedy without character is like we must character? After all Aristotle tells us that
respect Aristotle's dissociation of the ... the action involves agents, who must of neces-
hamartia from moral imperfection, be it sity have distinctive qualities both of character
vice, in the full-blown sense, or faulty and thought, since it is by these that we ascribe
judgment, a failure of practical wisdom. certain qualities to their actions.. .8a
Once we take the hamartia as a simple All agents, in so far as they are capable of
mistake without modification, explicit or deliberation and choice, possess character,
implied, then we see that it is a function of the disposition to choose or avoid certain
the plot. House argues along these lines things. However, an action need not reveal
and Else urges further that the hamartia is the character of the agent. We should note
complemented by the discovery.26 The that Aristotle says, "character in a play...
mistake is made in ignorance; the dis- reveals moral purpose... where this is not
covery involves the recognition of the obvious." All actions require agents, but an
mistake and is followed by or coincides action need not reveal the character of the
with the reversal. When we see that the agent, for instance, Oedipus's action in
hamartia is a part of the plot together with marrying Iocasta.
the discovery and the reversal, then we At this point protest may be raised that
realize that tragedy need not involve char- Aristotle is concerned with serious action
acter at all. and serious action is bound to reveal
Let us look at what Aristotle regards as character. Here let me make another dis-
the best kind of plot. tinction, the distinction between the seri-
The last case is the best, as when in the ous and the moral. The moral is not always
Cresphontes Merope is about to slay her son, but, introduced through deliberation and
recognising who he is, spares his life. So in the choice. A choice may bring about tragic
Iphigenia, the sister recognises the brother just
in time. Again in the Helle, the son recognises consequences through a simple mistake.
the mother when on the point of giving her up.27 Then it is morally neutral. Furthermore,
tragedies may evolve from sheer suffering;
These plots turn on a simple mistake in- it is obvious that Aristotle's conception of
volving ignorance of identity. Of course an action includes suffering as well as
the mistake is serious, but there is no vice, doing. However, the action of most
sin, moral frailty, or error of judgment in tragedies is a moral matter because it in-
them. Again, as a function of the plot, the volves killing, incest, adultery, as well as
hamartia takes its place among those ele- conflicts within and between the domestic,
ments which Aristotle deems the most religious, and political domains. And,
powerful in tragedy, the discovery and the Aristotle is in fact primarily concerned
reversal.28 The hamartia, then, is the mis- with moral action. Must not moral action
take which leads to the reversal. The dis- surely reveal character? In Oedipus the
covery is the discovery of the mistake. action is such that one might say, "If I had
We are told that the best discovery in- known so and so (of which I was ignorant
volves persons closely related29 and entails at the time) I would have acted differ-
the shift from hate to love or love to hate.30 ently." Had Oedipus known that he was
Do these specifications of a good discovery marrying his mother he would have acted
introduce character, it could well be differently. The remorse, which coincides
asked? To reply we must draw an impor- with his discovery of the identity of
tant distinction. We must observe the dif-
Iocasta, testifies to this. Is not Oedipus's
ference between character and agent. character thereby defined? No. I think we
Aristotle himself makes the distinction can say without any hesitation that if Al
when he says, Capone were to discover that he had
Character in a play is that which reveals moral married his mother, he would be in a state
purpose of the agents, i.e. the sort of thing they of the greatest remorse, if remorse is not
seek or avoid, where that is not obvious.8l too weak a word. But knowing this about
But surely the actions of the agents imply him is to know nothing. We have reached

This content downloaded from 128.235.251.160 on Sun, 1 Feb 2015 11:16:54 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Tragedy Without Character: Poetics VI. 1450a 24 59

such a fundamental level that we can take discovery is the discovery of the mistake,
certain responses for granted. This is also and this is followed by or coincides with
true of the shift from hate to love or love the reversal of the entire action. The ac-
to hate which attends discovery, as when tions or events, which the plot orders into
Merope recognizes her son, Iphigenia her a total action, require agents or doers, but
brother, and the son in Helle recognizes the character of the agents is not revealed.
his mother. I am not suggesting that Aristotle demonstrates this when he gives
Oedipus Rex is a play without character; I the plot of Iphigenia:
am exploring what tragedy without char- A young girl is sacrificed; she disappears mysteri-
acter is like and what it means to say that ously from the eyes of those who sacrificed her;
plot is primary. she is transported to another country, where the
It must be stressed that tragic actions in- custom is to offer up all strangers to the goddess.
To this ministry she is appointed. Some time
volving members of the same family are so later her own brother chances to arrive. The fact
serious in themselves that they do not call that the oracle for some reason ordered him to go
for considerations of character. The fact of there, is outside the general plan of the play.
being an agent in a given relationship does However, he comes, he is seized, and when on
the point of being sacrificed, reveals who he is
not, in itself, reveal character. To be a .. he exclaims very naturally: "So it was not my
mother, son, brother, or a sister does not sister only, but I too, who was doomed to be
commit the agent to a definite character. sacrificed," and by that remark he is saved.34
Nor does the discovery of the identity of the
agent, in itself, entail character. When the Merely to read this account, knowing
nothing else about the play, does indeed
discovery involves members of the same make us thrill with horror and melt with
family it is sure to give rise to extreme
pity at what takes place. There is no defini-
emotions and these do not in themselves
tion of character here. There are agents
reveal character. We expect certain emo-
certainly. There are actions. And there is
tions to be aroused in members of the
same family in certain situations. We have suffering narrowly averted, but there is no
character. In fact such an intimate ex-
a minimal expectation, that, as a matter of
change between brother and sister would
course, a son will not be pleased to dis-
cover that he has married his mother. We seem to make the addition of character
superfluous.
assume Oedipus's remorse. Finally, the
events are so terrible and the suffering so Again let us look at Aristotle's summary
great in tragedy that it is meaningless to of the Odyssey.
ask what the agents involved are like. A certain man is absent from home for many
Both in literature and in life tragedy is years; he is jealously watched by Poseidon, and
a great leveler of character. When we hear left desolate. Meanwhile his home is in a
wretched plight-suitors are wasting his sub-
of a widow who has lost her only two sons stance and plotting against his son. At length,
in a war, we do not ask (outside the semi- tempest-tossed, he himself arrives; he makes cer-
nar room, that is) whether she is a good tain persons acquainted with him; he attacks the
woman or what her sons were like. Thus suitors with his own hand, and is himself pre-
since tragedy, by its very nature, does not served while he destroys them.86
call for considerations of character, we can "This is the essence of the plot," Aristotle
readily understand why, on simply hearing concludes, "the rest is episode." The likely
the plot, we "thrill with horror and melt to exclamation, "The rest is episode, indeed!"
pity at what takes place." 33 invokes the distinction between story and
In the foregoing, I have tried to show plot. Such summaries, it may be countered,
how the hamartia, the discovery, and the correspond to the general form or outline
reversal function together as parts of the which Aristotle advises the poet to work
plot in a way that enables the plot to do its out first. The "tempest tossed" corresponds
work without the presence of character. to the episodes with which the poet fills
The entire action of the play turns on out the general plan. But Aristotle, him-
these three parts. A mistake is made, the self, makes no distinction between plot and

This content downloaded from 128.235.251.160 on Sun, 1 Feb 2015 11:16:54 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
60 CATHERINE LORD

story. He uses the terms, mythos and logos, play arousing pity and fear and achieving
interchangeably. For the Iphigenia he uses catharsis.
mythos, for the Odyssey, logos. Else accepts In the Rhetoric Aristotle defines pity as
the identification of the two.36 These sum-
a feeling of pain caused by the sight of some evil,
maries give the main events and give them destructive or painful, which befalls one who
in their proper order. Character has does not deserve it, and which we might expect
dropped out entirely; the wily Odysseus to befall ourselves or some friend of ours...88
is simply "a certain man." He concludes later,
Here another point may be pressed:
These summaries set forth the action so Most piteous of all is it when, in such times of
that the character of the agent is bound to trial, the victims are persons of noble character;
whenever they are so our pity is especially ex-
drop out. To put this criticism in another cited, because their innocence, as well as the
way, it could be urged that one can define setting of their misfortune before our eyes makes
an action so generically as to render the their misfortunes seem close to ourselves.89
delineation of character unnecessary. This The Poetics tells us
simply that "... pity is
is a very serious criticism. It correlates aroused
by unmerited misfortune, fear
with the view that when the episodes are
by the misfortune of a man like our-
filled in, character emerges. Thus the de- selves." 40
tails of Odysseus's journey will show him Learning that a sister has acci-
dentally killed her brother inspires us with
to be wily. This is House's thesis when he
pity over her undeserved misfortune. Now
argues that the plot guarantees the indi- it is indeed possible that if the sister were
viduality of character. known to be Lucretia Borgia we might
How shall we answer this objection? We well feel that her misfortune was a case of
can only say, "Look!" Look at the plots
"poetic justice." This is a negative con-
without prejudging the issue one way or sideration that must be
the other. Above all let us look at the plots acknowledged.
some one then press that this ac-
which Aristotle especially recommends. Might
knowledgment concedes the case for charac-
Take the Iphigenia. Without doubt, as in ter?
almost any extensive narration, the very Aristotle gives two very different specifi-
scope of the terrain to be covered will cations of the character of the hero,
make it very difficult to avoid some mini-
namely, that he should be good or noble
mal sketching in of character if only to fill and that he should be like
ourselves.
out the play. But it is by no means true These two
approaches are reflected in the
that all plots require character to the same Poetics itself where we find that
Aristotle
extent and the plots which Aristotle favors sometimes
requires that the hero be good
scarcely seem to require it at all. The and at other times requires that he be like
tragic effect of the Iphigenia cannot occur ourselves. What is it to be like ourselves?
unless we know something very important It is not to be
good. We are told in the
about the agents, namely, that they are Rhetoric that
brother and sister. To know this is to
know nothing of their character and any- most men tend to be bad, slaves to greed, and
cowards in danger... [and] as a rule men do
thing we might actually say as to their
wrong to others whenever they have the power
character could only contribute to the to do it.<
arousal and purging of pity and fear in
some auxiliary way. Else argues that although to be like
To these considerations it might be ourselves and to be good are irreconcilable,
countered that although we can describe he maintains that the homoios should not
a play in which character has no part, a be taken as a separate category intro-
play that turns on plot, there cannot be ducing another object of imitation.42 His
tragedy in the fullest sense where there is argument, interesting as it is, does not
no delineation of character. This is respect Aristotle's observation that the poet
Butcher's contention.37 We can have must of necessity represent men as better,
drama, but not a tragedy, presumably a worse, or as they are.43The examples given

This content downloaded from 128.235.251.160 on Sun, 1 Feb 2015 11:16:54 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Tragedy Without Character: Poetics VI. 1450" 24 61
are Homer who makes man better, a good play. "Do not stake your all on
Cleophon who makes them as they are, and character," Aristotle seems to be saying.
Nicochares who makes men worse than This is especially useful instruction for a
they are.44 Furthermore, Sophocles is working poet, for, according to Aristotle,
quoted as saying that he drew men as they "Beginners succeed earlier with the Dic-
ought to be; Euripides as they are.45 And tion and Characters than with the con-
we might note here that Aristotle points struction of the story (Plot)." 50 Thus he
to Euripides as the one who is felt to be advises the poet not to stake his all on
"the most tragic of the poets." 46 When character because there may be tragedy
Aristotle says that the hero must be good without character; there cannot be tragedy
he explains summarily that the charac- without plot.
ter of the hero is good if his intention is
good.47 But to arouse pity the disaster does
not have to occur to a good man. It must
only be undeserved. This necessary inno- 1 Aristotle Poetics VI. 1450a, trans. S. H. Butcher.
cence is established by the fact that a mis- Bywater reads: "Besides this, a tragedy is impossible
take was made in ignorance as well as on without action, but there may be one without Char-
the basis of the most general assumption as acter." I draw on both translations throughout.
2 Catherine Lord, "Organic Unity Reconsidered,"
to the character of the hero. Only a mon- JAAC (Spring 1964) and "Unity with Impunity,"
ster, a Nero, deserves to kill his father and JAAC (Fall, 1967).
marry his mother unwittingly. In this re- sPoetics VI. 1449b 24-26.
4Poetics VI. 1450' 12.
gard, it is striking that Aristotle allows a 5Poetics VI. 1450b 8.
quasi-pity for a bad man who is punished. 6Poetics VI. 1450a 5.
He tells us that, although this would in- 7Humphry House, Aristotle's Poetics (London.
spire neither pity nor fear (hence a plot 1961), Ch. V, p. 80.
concerning the downfall of an utter villain 8VPoetics V. 1450' 15.
9 Poetics VI. 1450' 19.
is inappropriate for tragedy), the fall of a 10House, Ch. V, p. 79.
bad man does arouse philanthropia,48 uPoetics Ch. VIII, 1451' 33-34.
"human feeling," or, more precisely, sym- 1 Poetics VI. 1450' 39.

pathy. Because the tragedies with which "Poetics XIV. 1453b 5.


Aristotle is concerned occur within the "Unity with Impunity (especially).
context of the family, because, concom- sPoetics XIX, 1456b 1.
1"Poetics XIV. 1452a 39.
mitantly, the reversal is so terrible, charac- 17Poetics VI. 1450b 18.
ter is not indispensable. The tragic effect 18Poetics VI. 1449b 29.
will occur without it. 19Aristotle, Politics, trans. B. Jowett (Oxford), Bk.
VIII, Ch. 6.
Obviously a tragedy with character is 20Poetics VI. 1450' 29-31.
better than one without character. Nobody 21Poetics XIX. 1456b 5.
would contest this. The best tragedy has 22House, VI, 5, p. 94.
all six parts. And character is, after all, 23Gerald F. Else, The Argument of Aristotle's
second in importance among the parts. Poetics (Harvard Univ. Press, 1963), Ch. 13, pp.
376-399.
But, as I have pointed out before, to judge "Richmond Lattimore, Story Patterns in Greek
that something makes a thing better is not Tragedy (Univ. of London, 1964), Ch. I, p. 10: "Pro-
to hold that it is necessary.49This point is fessor Else has demonstrated with I think complete
crucial and it is connected with the sepa- and sensational success that the famous Aristotelian
hamartia can mean neither fault, or flaw, in charac-
rability of the parts of tragedy. Plot does ter, nor yet an error in judgment, but simply a
not, ipso facto, involve character. Further- mistake about the identity of a person."
more, character is not rendered necessary 25House, Lecture VI, 5, p. 95.
because it makes tragedy better. This is 26Else, Ch. 13, p. 379.
27Poetics XIV. 1454' 5.
fundamentally Aristotle's view. The good 28Poetics VI. 1450' 13.
and the necessary should not be confused.
29poetics XIV.1453b 15-20.
The fact that character makes a work 30Poetics XI. 1452a 31.
better, but is not necessary, becomes a "Poetics VI. 1450b 10-11.
normative principle for the construction of "2Poetics VI. 1450" 1.

This content downloaded from 128.235.251.160 on Sun, 1 Feb 2015 11:16:54 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
62 CATHERINE LORD
8SPoetics XIV. 1453b 5-6. 41Rhetoric, Bk. II, Ch. 5, 1382b 10.
3 Poetics XVII. 1455b 3-12. 4aElse, Ch. 15, pp. 475-483.
36 Poetics XVII. 1455b 16-24. 4 Poetics II. 1448a 1-2 and XXV, 1460b 9-10.
8 Else, Ch. 6, pp. 243-244. 4 Poetics II. 1448a 11-13.
87S. H. Butcher, Aristotle's Theory of Poetry and 4 Poetics XXV. 1460" 35-36.
Fine Arts, Ch. 9, p. 344. 46 Poetics XIII. 1453a 29-30.
38Aristotle Rhetoric, trans. W. Rhys Roberts (Ox- 7 Poetics XV. 1454a 19.
ford), Bk. II, 8, 1385b 13-15. 4S Poetics XIII. 1453a 2.
39 Rhetoric, Bk. II, 8, 1386b 5-10. 49 Unity with Impunity, pp. 105-106.
40 Poetics XII. 1453a 5-6.
60 Poetics VI. 1450" 35-38.

This content downloaded from 128.235.251.160 on Sun, 1 Feb 2015 11:16:54 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

You might also like