You are on page 1of 10

857093

research-article2019
QIXXXX10.1177/1077800419857093Qualitative InquiryMaxwell

Research Article
Qualitative Inquiry

The Value of Qualitative Inquiry


2020, Vol. 26(2) 177­–186
© The Author(s) 2019
Article reuse guidelines:
for Public Policy sagepub.com/journals-permissions
DOI: 10.1177/1077800419857093
https://doi.org/10.1177/1077800419857093
journals.sagepub.com/home/qix

Joseph A. Maxwell1

Abstract
This article focuses on public policies and programs as a major component of the “public sphere,” and argues that
qualitative inquiry can make uniquely valuable contributions to their development and evaluation. These contributions
include understanding (a) how people interpret and respond to such policies, (b) contextual variability and its effects on the
implementation and consequences of these policies, and (c) the processes through which policies achieve their results. The
movement for “evidence-based” policy and practice has largely ignored these issues, but they are critical for developing
policies that actually achieve their goals and avoid unintended and damaging consequences.

Keywords
public policy, qualitative inquiry, public sphere, implementation

In this article, I address the development and evaluation of Such conflicts were temporarily lessened by the merger
public policies and programs as a major part of the “public of the Evaluation Research Society (largely quantitative)
sphere,” and the roles that qualitative research can play in and the Evaluation Network (largely qualitative) as the
this endeavor. To do this, however, I want to begin by con- American Evaluation Association in 1986, but were not
sidering why the value of qualitative research for these eliminated even within that organization, and reemerged
tasks has even been questioned, or seen as problematic. In more broadly with the movement for “evidence-based
my doctoral training in anthropology, in the 1970s and policy” in the 1990s, which promoted a hierarchy of meth-
1980s, I never encountered this prejudice; “applied anthro- ods for establishing evidence, with randomized controlled
pology” (which was basically applied qualitative research) trials (RCTs) as the “gold standard” and qualitative meth-
was assumed to be practice- and policy-relevant. Michael ods relegated to the bottom (e.g., National Research
Quinn Patton’s (1980) Qualitative evaluation and research Council, 2002).
methods and David Fetterman’s (1984) Ethnography in
educational evaluation were widely used in qualitative
The Origins of Quantitative
methods courses, and qualitative researchers were a signifi-
cant part of the evaluation community, as recognized in Dominance in the Social Sciences
Cook and Reichardt’s (1979) important work Qualitative What was the basis (aside from competition for jobs) for
and quantitative methods in evaluation research. this dismissal of qualitative research? To understand this, I
This is not to say that there was no controversy about believe that it’s necessary to go back several centuries, to
qualitative methods. Mary Anne Pitman reported an inci- the spectacular successes of Newton’s laws in explaining
dent from her own experience, with two applied anthropol- the physical universe. Thomas Kuhn (1957) stated, in The
ogist colleagues, at the annual meeting of the Evaluation Copernican revolution “These mathematical derivations
Research Society in 1977: were without precedent in the history of science. They
transcend all the other achievements that stem from the
We were in a standing-room-only crowd listening to an new perspective introduced by Copernicus” (p. 256). They
evaluator, an organizational psychologist by training, were unprecedented in two ways that have been profoundly
presenting his case for the state licensing of evaluators . . . The
important for the relationship between quantitative and
speaker’s proposed licensing criteria would have mandated a
gate-keeping structure that would “keep the charlatans out of
1
the field.” It soon became clear to the three of us, however, that George Mason University, Fairfax, VA, USA
we were the charlatans. Qualitative researchers, according to Corresponding Author:
the speaker, were threatening the integrity of evaluation, Joseph A. Maxwell, College of Education and Human Development,
particularly the rigor of its procedures and the validity of its George Mason University, 44 Endicott Road, Stoneham, MA 02180, USA.
findings. (Pitman & Maxwell, 1992, p. 730) Email: jmaxwell@gmu.edu
178 Qualitative Inquiry 26(2)

qualitative research. First, Newton’s laws were entirely for qualitative researchers to understand the assumptions,
mathematical; there were no underlying theories, pro- explicit and implicit, that lie behind these arguments, and
cesses, or mechanisms on which they depended. (The latter how to effectively challenge these assumptions. A full
feature was later incorporated in David Hume’s “constant account of the origins and impacts of these assumptions is
conjunction” theory of causation, which held that causa- beyond the scope of this article, and an overview, with a few
tion simply is the regular association of phenomena, with examples, will have to suffice.
nothing “behind” these that explains this conjunction. This The two fundamental concepts discussed above, of gen-
later came to be known as the “regularity” theory of causa- eral laws and their mathematical formulation, were central
tion, which has been influential in quantitative research up to prominent philosophies of science that emerged during
to the present.) Second, they were universal, applying the next two centuries, which assumed that the goal of sci-
without exception to all physical phenomena. ence was to establish such laws, not just for physics, but for
The influence of these two ideas was profound and long- the social sciences as well. Friedrich Hayek (1952), in The
lasting, and strongly shaped the conceptions of what “sci- Counterrevolution of Science, described in detail how this
ence” appropriately meant for the sciences generally. Giere happened. In doing so, Hayek (1952) introduced into
(1999) argued that English the term “scientism” to refer to

The theories about science prominent in Europe and North an attitude which is decidedly unscientific, in the true sense
America until around 1960 derived ultimately from the of the word, since it involves a mechanical and uncritical
Enlightenment of the eighteenth century, a period in which the application of habits of thought to different fields from those
achievements of the seventeenth century scientific revolution in which they have been formed . . . The scientistic as opposed
became incorporated into a more general cultural worldview. A to the scientific view is not an unprejudiced but a very
number of concepts came into prominence in particular ways prejudiced approach which, before it has considered its
during that time, including those of laws of nature, scientific subject, claims to know what is the most appropriate way of
truth, and scientific rationality. (pp. 3-4) investigating it. (p. 24).

As a consequence, The influence of these ideas on the philosophy of science


eventually led to the positivism of Auguste Comte (1798-
Many people on both sides [of the ‘science wars”] seem so to 1857), who stated that “the fundamental character of all
have internalized the Enlightenment view of science that, for positive philosophy is to regard all phenomena as subject to
them, to challenge aspects of that view is to challenge science invariable natural laws, whose precise discovery and reduc-
itself, and, conversely, to defend science is to defend it in its tion to the smallest number possible is the aim of all our
Enlightenment form. (Giere, 1999, p. 5) efforts” (Comte, quoted by Hayek, 1952, p. 328).
Although Comte was a major force in establishing the
Giere noted elsewhere that, ironically, view of science as inherently dependent on “natural laws,”
the mathematicization of these laws, and the incorporation
The notion of a law of nature did not arise out of the practice of this into later positivist thinking, was influenced more by
of science itself. Sometime in the seventeenth century it was his contemporary, the astronomer and statistician Adolphe
imported into discourse about science from Christian Quetelet (1796-1874). For Quetelet,
theology, both directly and indirectly through mathematics.
Originally, laws of nature were understood as God’s laws for the more advanced the sciences have become, the more they
nature. Thus, behind the laws of nature was a lawgiver, from have tended to enter the domain of mathematics . . . We can
whence came the universality and necessity of such laws . . . judge of the perfection to which a science has come by the
It also seems pretty clear that this theological notion of laws facility, more or less great, with which it may be approached by
of nature became prominent through the writings of Descartes. calculation. (Hayek, 1952, p. 357)
Newton then picked up the idea from Descartes, though he
hardly needed Descartes to encourage his theological
A key aspect of Quetelet’s impact on statistics was his
inclinations. How the notion got stripped of its theological
implications throughout the eighteenth and nineteenth
expanded use of the concept of “average.” Astronomers had
centuries seems a story yet to be told. Twentieth century realized that when multiple measurements of a single phe-
philosophers struggled to understand the nature of natural nomenon (e.g., the observed time that it took for a planet to
laws, especially features such as universality and necessity, in move a given distance) varied, the best estimate of the
completely secular terms. (Giere, 2006, p. 70, referencing “true” value was the arithmetic mean (average) of these
Weinert, 1995) measurements; variations from this mean were treated as
“error.” This technique, which is quite legitimate for this
In this article, I argue that, to counter arguments for the purpose, was then transferred by Quetelet to single mea-
inherent superiority of quantitative research, it is essential surements of multiple individuals or events, treating
Maxwell 179

individual variation as “error” (Mayr, 1982, p. 47; Rose, astronomy, that rely substantially on physics (although
2015, pp. 23-28). This was key to Quetelet’s and others’ Cartwright [1983, 1999] has argued that they are problem-
dream of “‘automating’ the human sciences by substituting atic even for physics). In genetics, the discovery of the
calculation for intuition” (Weisberg, 2014, p. 4). structure of DNA in 1953 led many researchers to believe
Quetelet’s emphasis on averages as the true measure of that they were on the verge of a Newtonian transformation
some phenomenon was far-reaching. “scholars and thinkers of their field. These researchers, some trained in physics,
in every field hailed Quetelet as a genius for uncovering the sought the simplest possible organisms for study, aiming to
hidden laws of society” (Rose, 2015, p. 31). The father of establish general laws analogous to those of physics (Keller,
experimental psychology, Wilhelm Wundt, invoked 1983, pp. 4-6, 159-165). This goal was eventually undercut
Quetelet in claiming that “more psychology can be learned by (among other things) the work of Barbara McClintock
from averages than from all philosophers, except Aristotle” on the genetics of maize, for which she belatedly received a
(Rose, 2015, p. 31). Weisberg (2014) argued that these Nobel Prize. McClintock’s approach was essentially quali-
influences led to “willful ignorance” of the actual variabil- tative, grounded in the naturalist tradition of field biology,
ity of phenomena and a profound misunderstanding and and relying on detailed microscopic study of the cytology of
mismeasure of uncertainty, and have distorted the use of her maize plants. This was guided by what she called “a
statistics for understanding variability. feeling for the organism,” an intimate understanding of the
Logical positivism, which was the dominant philoso- entire plant and of the diversity of genetic features that her
phy of science during the first half of the 20th century, maize plants exhibited (Keller, 1983, pp. 8-9, 197-201).
differed in important respects from Comte’s positivism, For evolutionary biology, Stephen Jay Gould (1989)
but it retained these two elements: the focus on mathe- similarly argued that
maticization and the goal of general laws. The most
influential presentation of the latter was Carl Hempel’s The stereotype of the “scientific method” has no place for
“deductive-nomological” or “covering law” model of irreducible history. Nature’s laws are defined by their invariance
science. For Hempel, there was “no difference in princi- in space and time . . . [and] presuppose that all times can be
ple between human sciences like history and natural sci- treated alike . . . But the restricted techniques of the “scientific
method” cannot get to the heart of [a] singular event involving
ences like physics. To the extent that both offer
creatures long dead on an earth with climates and continental
explanations, both appeal to general, predictive laws” positions markedly different from today’s. The resolution of
(Bohman, 1991, p. 19). history must be rooted in the reconstruction of past events
However, logical positivism was shown in the 1950s to themselves—in their own terms—based on narrative evidence
be largely unworkable, and many of its tenets were aban- of their own unique phenomena . . .
doned by philosophers. A. J. Ayer (1936), whose book
Language, Truth, and Logic basically introduced logical Historical science is not worse, more restricted, or less capable
positivism to the English-speaking world, famously said of achieving firm conclusions because experiment, prediction,
much later, when asked what the problems were with logi- and subsumption under invariant laws of nature do not
cal positivism, “I suppose the greatest defect is that nearly represent its usual working methods. The sciences of history
all of it was false” (Ayer, 1978). use a different mode of explanation, rooted in the comparative
Despite this, positivist ideas have continued to influence and observational richness of our data. (pp. 277-279)
the thinking of many social researchers. Steinmetz (2005)
wryly noted that “Despite repeated attempts by social theo- The eminent biologist Ernst Mayr (1976, pp. 408-415;
rists and researchers to drive a stake through the heart of the 1982, 1988, pp. 9-19) has provided a detailed critique of
vampire, the [social science] disciplines continue to experi- what he termed “essentalist” approaches that ignored indi-
ence a positivistic haunting” (p. 3). Contemporary versions vidual variability and sought to establish general laws for
of positivism have typically held biology. He argued that biology in general does not seek or
rely on such laws, but develops theories that have limited
that there is a unity of method between the natural and the applicability. He stated that “every student in biology is
social sciences; the notion that the social sciences ought to impressed by the fact that there is hardly a theory in biology
search for eternal, lawlike generalizations; . . . a rejection of for which some exceptions are not known” (Mayr, 1988, p.
explanations which refer to subjective states of individuals 19), and that “as is characteristic for so much of the biologi-
such as motives or purposes; [and] a predilection toward cal sciences, the answers to many of these questions are of
quantification. (Baert, 1998, p. 140) a qualitative, rather than a quantitative, nature” (Mayr,
1976, p. 410).
In the social sciences, efforts to establish causal laws, in
Problems With the Positivist Agenda anything like the sense of Newton’s laws, have been a strik-
These goals have proved elusive even in many of the natu- ing failure. Donmoyer (2008) stated that “For a variety of
ral sciences, aside from physics and those fields, such as reasons, including the complexity of social phenomena and
180 Qualitative Inquiry 26(2)

the ever-changing cultural dimension of social life, quanti- 1983, p. 133, cited by Schofield, 1990, p. 202). The philoso-
tative researchers have had difficulty producing even prob- pher Susan Haack (2003) has trenchantly observed that
abilistic findings that can be generalized to even delimited
populations” (p. 372). Mohr (1996), in a work on the causes In the agenda inherited from logical positivism it was often
of human behavior, similarly argued that “few practitioners assumed that we must choose either methodological monism,
in the social and behavioral disciplines would claim today according to which the social sciences seek explanatory, causal
that there are universal laws governing human behavior” (p. theories and use the scientific method just as physics and
chemistry do, or methodological dualism, according to which
1), and that such laws are unnecessary for the causal expla-
the social sciences seek understanding rather than causal
nation of such behavior (an issue discussed in detail below). explanation, and use a method of empathy rather than objective
Some of the problems with attempts to develop causal observation. This makes me feel like the legendary Irishman
laws in the social sciences are illustrated by the work of the who asked for directions to a distant village: “sure and
anthropologist George Peter Murdock (1949), who com- begorrah, I wouldn’t start from here.” (pp. 165-166)
piled in the 1940s a massive inventory of data, which he
later called the Human Relations Area Files, on all human However, although qualitative researchers largely
societies for which such data were available, and quantita- rejected the relevance of mathematicization and natural
tively analyzed these data to discover correlations among laws for their own approach, they have often accepted
features of social structure. In his book Social Structure, he these, at least implicitly, as valid for quantitative research
presented a unified general theory of how changes in social in the social sciences. A recent example, from the
structure occur, supported by voluminous correlations, American Psychological Association Publications and
many with highly significant chi-square values, among fea- Communications Board Task Force (2018), is found in
tures of social structure in 250 societies. On this basis, he their statement on Reporting Standards for Qualitative
asserted that “cultural forms in the field of social organiza- Primary, Qualitative Meta-Analytic, and Mixed Methods
tion reveal a degree of regularity and of conformity to sci- Research in Psychology (Levitt et al. 2018):
entific law not significantly inferior to that found in the
so-called natural sciences” (p. 259). Because their work tends to focus on human experiences,
However, many of the actual correlations that Murdock actions, and social processes, which fluctuate, qualitative
reported were quite modest. In addition, for at least one of researchers do not aim to seek natural laws that extend across
Murdock’s culture areas (the indigenous tribes of the North time, place, and culture, but to develop findings that are bound
American Plains), one that was studied specifically to test to their contexts. (p. 29)
Murdock’s (and others’) theories, the data that he used were
often incorrect. This investigation showed that, although This statement appears to accept (or at least fails to chal-
there were some commonalities across these tribes, there lenge) the claim that discovering such laws is a legitimate
were also substantial differences, and that neither the com- goal of quantitative research in the social sciences. However,
monalities nor the differences could be understood without this claim, if valid, inherently justifies quantitative research-
a detailed grasp of the specific natural and social environ- ers’ arguments for their methods’ superiority in generalizing
ments that each tribe had encountered, its history of adapta- their findings across times and settings, a key issue for pro-
tions to these environments, and an adequate theory grams and policies. Even works that ostensibly seek a broad
(including an understanding of the meanings and uses of consensus across qualitative and quantitative research, such
kinship terms) of how the changes in their kinship systems as the U.S. National Research Council’s (2002) report
and social structures occurred (Eggan & Maxwell, 2001; Scientific Research in Education, often uncritically incor-
Maxwell, 1978). The methods for establishing this were porate these arguments, leading to the dismissal or subordi-
fundamentally qualitative rather than quantitative (Maxwell, nation of qualitative research. (For a detailed critique of this
2013, Chapter 9), and cast serious doubt on any claims report, see Maxwell, 2004.)
about “scientific laws” of social organization.
The failure of the positivist agenda to adequately repre- The Strengths of Qualitative Research
sent or guide the social sciences, in combination with the
for Developing and Evaluating Public
increasing dominance of quantitative methods in many
social science fields, was one factor leading to what have Policies and Programs
been called the “paradigm wars.” Many qualitative research- Having criticized some influential beliefs that have often
ers, following the mandate of Egon Guba and Yvonna marginalized qualitative researchers in addressing public
Lincoln (1989; Lincoln & Guba, 1985), adopted a radical policies and programs, I want to now turn to the particular
constructivism that rejected not only the goals of mathema- strengths of qualitative research and how these are relevant
ticization and general laws, but also the concepts of “real- to public policy. I will discuss three main strengths that I see
ity,” validity, causation, and even of generalization (Denzin, in qualitative research, strengths that are widely recognized
Maxwell 181

in the qualitative methods literature, but that are often perceptions, and that a researcher might be mistaken about
ignored in defending the value of qualitative research. I’ve these meanings. Thomas Schwandt (2007), in his Dictionary
dealt with these strengths in more detail elsewhere of Qualitative Research, argued that
(Maxwell, 2004, 2012).
The message of this article can be summarized in three On a daily basis, most of us probably behave as garden-variety
statements about what matters in planning and evaluating empirical realists—that is, we act as if the objects in the world
such policies and programs: that meaning matters, context (things, events, structures, people, meanings, etc.) exist as
matters, and process matters. Meaning, context, and pro- independent in some way from our experience with them. We
also regard society, institutions, feelings, intelligence, poverty,
cess are three key issues for, and strengths of, qualitative
disability, and so on as being just as real as the toes on our feet
research. What I hope to do here is to show how these are and the sun in the sky. (p. 256)
critically relevant for developing and evaluating public
policies and programs, and to challenge quantitative
This is implicitly assumed by much of the actual practice
researchers’ claims for the greater value of their methods
of qualitative research, which is concerned with how to
in this task.
avoid misunderstanding these meanings or imposing the
researcher’s own theories and biases. This practice implic-
Meaning Matters itly (and sometimes explicitly) combines an ontological
realism about meanings (these meanings exist indepen-
Qualitative research is essential for understanding the dently of the researcher’s constructions) with an epistemo-
meanings that a particular policy or program has, both for logical constructivism that recognizes that our interpretation
those creating or implementing this and for those affected of these meanings is our own construction, and that reality
by it. By “meaning,” I refer broadly to people’s beliefs, val- is more complex than any single construction can ade-
ues, theories, understandings, and other “mental” phenom- quately capture. Our understanding of people’s meanings,
ena, what is often encompassed by the phrase “participants’ as with our understanding of things in general, is necessar-
perspectives”; understanding these is the primary goal of ily partial, incomplete, and fallible; we are inherently inca-
what is often termed “interpretive inquiry.” The importance pable of “objectively” capturing these. A particularly clear
of such beliefs, values, and understandings in creating and statement of this position is by the anthropologist Fredrik
evaluating policies and programs is basically just common Barth (1987):
sense; it should be obvious that people’s understanding of
and attitudes toward a policy or program impact its effec- Like most of us, I assume that there is a real world out there—
tiveness and can create unintended consequences. but that our representations of that world are constructions.
However, “evidence-based” approaches typically People create and apply these constructions in a struggle to
ignore these issues, or address them only through “thin” grasp the world, relate to it, and to manipulate it through
surveys of people’s “attitudes,” which fail to provide an concepts, knowledge, and acts. In the process, reality impinges,
in-depth understanding of these issues and are almost and the events that occur subsequently are not predicated on
always analyzed to discover “average” values rather than the cultural system of representations employed by the people,
although they may be largely interpretable within it. A people’s
to explore individual differences and how these interact
way of life is thus not a closed system, contained within their
with contextual influences. An understanding of the com- own cultural constructions. That part of the real world on
plexity and diversity of people’s views of a policy or pro- which we as anthropologists need to focus is comprised of this
gram, how these influence their responses to this policy widest compass: a natural world, a human population with all
or program, and how these might be addressed in devel- its collective and statistical social features, and a set of cultural
oping and explaining the policy or program are essential ideas in terms of which these people try to understand and cope
to its effective development and implementation. with themselves and their habitat. (p. 87)
Problems with the development and rollout of the
Affordable Care Act in the United States were due in part For a more detailed account of a realist understanding of
to a failure to adequately understand how the policy was meaning and culture, see Maxwell (2013, Chapter 2).
perceived by a large portion of the electorate—how they This argument implies that reasons can legitimately be
understood the policy, the assumptions and values that seen as causes of people’s behavior, a view that has been
shaped these perceptions, and the actions to which these advanced by numerous philosophers, including Bhaskar
perceptions and beliefs led. (1989), Davidson (1980, 1993), McGinn (1991/1999), and
This emphasis on meaning does not imply or require a Putnam (1999), as well as by psychologists and social sci-
constructivist or relativist ontology; any philosophical posi- entists (Bandura, 1986; House, 1991; Huberman & Miles,
tion other than extreme positivism or radical relativism 1985, p. 354; Menzel, 1978; Mohr, 1996; Pawson, 2006, pp.
assumes that meanings are ontologically real—that a per- 27-29; Sayer, 1992, pp. 110-112). Thus, Mohr (1996) con-
son’s meanings exist independently of the researcher’s cluded that
182 Qualitative Inquiry 26(2)

people’s motives or reasons for undertaking certain behaviors policy to shape its outcomes. Although they never use the
could not form part of general laws governing those behaviors, term “qualitative” in presenting these issues, their book is to
but . . . those same motives or reasons could, in the individual a substantial extent a detailed argument for the importance
case, cause the behaviors to be carried out (p. vi). of qualitative understandings in implementing any policy in
a specific context.
The psychologist Albert Bandura (1986) similarly argued The “external validity” of experimental research is usu-
that ally assumed to be primarily a matter of the similarity of
the intended context to that in which the research was
What people think, believe, and feel affects how they behave.
done. For example, Shadish, Cook, and Campbell (2002)
The natural and extrinsic effects of their actions, in turn, partly
stated, as their first “principle of generalized causal infer-
determine their thought patterns and affective reactions. (p. 25)
ence,” that “scientists generalize by judging the apparent
similarities between the things they studied and the targets
This position is generally accepted in both our everyday
of generalization” (p. 353). Cartwright and Hardie (2012)
explanations of people’s behavior and in psychology as a
countered that
science. However, the sharp distinction between “meaning”
and “cause” explanations by Dilthey, Weber, Winch, and
others has been far more influential in qualitative research. For us, the key question is how good a job this advice does in
getting you from “it worked there” to “it will work here.” The
The view of meanings as causes becomes less problematic
answer: you are lucky if it gets you anywhere. (p. 46)
when the dependence of causality on laws is abandoned
(Putnam, 1999, pp. 73-91, p. 200, fn. 11, 14; Sayer, 1992,
“Similarity” is both too vague (what features must be simi-
pp. 126-127). The issue of causality is discussed in more
lar?) and too demanding (almost no two contexts are similar
detail below, under “process.”
in all important respects), and provides no guidance in
understanding how your specific context will affect the out-
Context Matters come of the policy (Cartwright & Hardie, 2012, pp. 46-49).
Although internal (causal) validity in a given experimental
The importance of context is a key feature of qualitative
study is clearly relevant to the generalizability of the result,
research; qualitative researchers inherently incorporate the
the latter is an entirely different issue from the former, and
local context of the phenomena they study in their analyses
conceptualizing the two as both being forms of “validity” (a
and findings, and reject the idea of “context-independent”
view that seems inherently dependent on the idea of “gen-
conclusions about the effects of a policy or program.
eral laws”) can lead to lack of attention to what is critical for
Unfortunately, most approaches to “evidence-based policy”
the transferability of the results to other contexts. Shadish
fail to incorporate this context-dependence, assuming that
et al. (2002) acknowledged that “the embeddedness of
the results of “rigorous” evaluations will be inherently gen-
experimental results in a particular local context seems to
eralizable. Thus, RCTs, which are seen as the “gold stan-
provide little basis for generalizing results beyond that con-
dard” for understanding the effect of some intervention, are
text” (p. 341). However, in their extensive discussion of
treated as the “best evidence” for generalizing the effects of
external validity/generalization (pp. 83-93, 341-455), they
a given policy.
paid little attention to a key issue for generalizability: how
Nancy Cartwright and Jeremy Hardie, in their important
will the process that resulted in the experimental outcome
book “Evidence-based Policy: A Practical Guide to Doing it
in that specific context operate in different contexts?
Better,” stated at the very outset that
The qualitative concept of “transferability” is a far more
useful tool, for both qualitative and quantitative research,
You are told: use policies that work. And you are told: RCTs–
randomized controlled trials–will show you what these are. than is “external validity” in understanding how a given
That’s not so. RCTs are great, but they do not do that for you. policy or program may work in a new context. The transfer-
They cannot alone support the expectation that a policy will ability of either quantitative or qualitative results is not a
work for you . . . For that, you need to know a lot more. straightforward extension of the findings to “similar” con-
(Cartwright & Hardie, 2012, p. ix) texts, but involves developing a theory of the processes that
led to a particular outcome, and of how these processes
The “lot more” that their book explains is primarily an might operate in a different context (Donmoyer, 2008;
understanding of context: why context is important, and Maxwell & Chmiel, 2014, pp. 240-241). Becker (1992)
how to assess its implications for implementing a particular showed that, in a qualitative study of social organization in
policy in your own setting. This includes identifying the rel- men’s and women’s prisons, a similar process (that prison-
evant features of the setting in which the policy is imple- ers developed a social organization that provided things that
mented, which can support or impede the goals of the they felt deprived of in prison) resulted in very different
policy, and how these interact with each other and with the organizational structures in the two prisons, both because
Maxwell 183

the administrative policies in the two prisons (context) were social science has been singularly unsuccessful in discovering
different, and because the deprivations the women felt law-like regularities. One of the main achievements of recent
(meanings) were very different from those of the men. realist philosophy has been to show that this is an inevitable
consequence of an erroneous view of causation. Realism
replaces the regularity model with one in which objects and
Process Matters social relations have causal powers which may or may not
produce regularities, and which can be explained independently
This last point leads to the third issue: process. of them. In view of this, less weight is put on quantitative
Anticipating the likely consequences of implementing a methods for discovering and assessing regularities and more on
particular policy or program in a specific setting depends methods of establishing the qualitative nature of social objects
fundamentally on understanding the actual processes by and relations on which causal mechanisms depend (pp. 2-3).
which the policy or program could achieve its results,
which may result in unintended as well as intended out- In particular, causal processes are not well addressed by
comes. These processes incorporate the meanings that experimental research. Shadish et al. (2002) stated that
stakeholders and recipients have toward the policy and
how these influence their actions, as well as the many the unique strength of experimentation is in describing the
features of the particular setting that influence the imple- consequences attributable to deliberately varying a treatment.
mentation and outcomes of the policy. We call this causal description. In contrast, experiments do
By “processes,” I’m explicitly referring to causal pro- less well in clarifying the mechanisms through which and the
cesses. Causality has been a deeply contested concept in conditions under which that causal relationship holds—what
qualitative research, largely due to the prevalence of the we call causal explanation. (p. 9; emphasis in original)
positivist understanding of causality as simply the regular
association of events or variables (Maxwell, 2012). As Qualitative research, with its unique ability to identify
described above, both sides in this debate have largely the actual processes operating in a specific event or case,
assumed the positivist view of causation, and differed pri- and the contextual influences on these, is thus particularly
marily on whether it applied to qualitative research. relevant to understanding how policies and programs lead
Quantitative researchers generally argued that it did apply, to particular (sometimes unexpected) outcomes. This was
and that qualitative research was therefore inherently infe- well understood by many qualitative sociologists prior to
rior to quantitative research in establishing the regularities the 1950s, who argued against the positivist emphasis on
that this conception required. Some qualitative researchers quantitative associations between variables and for a pro-
accepted (explicitly or implicitly) this understanding of cess understanding of causality (Abbott, 2001, pp. 107-
causation; Patton (1990) warned that 108). Even Shadish et al. (2002) acknowledged that
“qualitative methods provide an important avenue for dis-
One of the biggest dangers for qualitative researchers is that, covering and exploring causal explanations” (p. 389), and
when they begin to make interpretations about causes, described how, in one experiment, the actual cause of the
consequences, and relationships, they fall back on the linear result was “revealed only by the qualitative examination of
assumptions of quantitative analysis and begin to specify the actual operation of groups” (p. 391).
isolated variables that are mechanically linked together out of
Miles and Huberman (1994), in their influential book
context. (p. 423)
Qualitative Data Analysis, coined the phrase “local causal-
ity” to refer to process-oriented, context-specific interpreta-
Other qualitative researchers either argued that this concep-
tions of causation, stating that
tion of causation didn’t apply to qualitative research because
its assumptions and goals were different from those of
Qualitative analysis, with its close-up look, can identify
quantitative research, or that the entire idea of causation mechanisms, going beyond sheer association. It is unrelentingly
was so seriously flawed that it needed to be completely local, and deals well with the complex network of events and
rejected (e.g., Guba & Lincoln, 1989, pp. 44, 86; Lincoln & processes in a situation. It can sort out the temporal dimension,
Guba, 1985, p. 141). showing clearly what preceded what, either through direct
All of these positions ignored the development of an observation or retrospection. (p. 147)
alternative, realist, process-oriented conception of causa-
tion, both by philosophers (e.g., Salmon, 1984, 1998) and Ray Pawson and Nick Tilley (1997; Pawson, 2006,
by researchers (e.g., Huberman & Miles, 1985; Pawson, 2013) have provided a detailed critique of quantitative/
2006; Pawson & Tilley, 1997; Sayer, 1992, 2000; for a experimental strategies for program and policy evaluation,
detailed discussion of how this conception is relevant for and present a realist strategy for evaluation that signifi-
qualitative research, see Maxwell, 2012, 2013, chapter 3). cantly incorporates qualitative methods. They use the acro-
Sayer (1992) argued that nym “CMOs” to refer to the complex system of contexts,
184 Qualitative Inquiry 26(2)

mechanisms, and outcomes that they see as central to under- argued persuasively for the value of integrating different
standing how programs and policies achieve their results. “mental models” for research; the compatibility and com-
Cartwright and Hardie (2012) similarly use the concept of plementarity of qualitative and quantitative approaches is
“causal cakes,” diagrams showing the “ingredients” that clearly recognized, both within the mixed methods com-
must be present for the policy to achieve its intended out- munity and in other disciplines that have developed such
comes in your situation (pp. 62-63). integration independently of the “mixed methods” move-
The value of qualitative methods for evaluating pro- ment (Maxwell, 2016). Maxwell (1993) presented some
grams and policies was eventually recognized by the major ideas on how qualitative researchers can effectively inter-
figure in the experimental evaluation of social programs, act with quantitative researchers to gain acceptance for
Donald Campbell, who stated that their methods and ideas.

without competence at the qualitative level, one’s computer


printout is misleading or meaningless. We failed in our thinking Conclusion
about programme evaluation to emphasize the need for a The development and evaluation of public policies and pro-
qualitative context that could be depended on . . . The lack of grams has mostly been dominated by quantitative research-
this knowledge . . . makes us incompetent estimators of
ers, aided by a long history of quantitatively oriented views
programme impacts, turning out conclusions that are not only
wrong, but often wrong in socially destructive ways. (Campbell,
in the philosophy of science. However, these views have
1984, p. 36, quoted by Pawson, 2006, p. 50) been strikingly unsuccessful in guiding the social sciences
(and even some of the natural sciences), and have been
The key issue for qualitative researchers who accept challenged by more recent developments in the philosophy
these arguments is, how do I do this? The development of science. These developments have led to increased rec-
and evaluation of public programs and policies is cur- ognition of the strengths of qualitative research for develop-
rently dominated by quantitative researchers. However, ing and evaluating policies and programs, and of the
there is an extensive body of literature, by qualitative complementarity and compatibility of qualitative and quan-
evaluators and others, on how to understand the pro- titative approaches. I encourage qualitative researchers to
cesses involved in developing, implementing, and engage with these efforts.
assessing programs and policies (e.g., Bennett &
Chekel, 2015; Cartwright & Hardie, 2012; Donaldson, Declaration of Conflicting Interests
Christie, & Mark, 2009; Pawson & Tilley, 1997; Weller The author(s) declared no potential conflicts of interest with respect
& Barnes, 2014.) to the research, authorship, and/or publication of this article.
In addition, many quantitative researchers have now
recognized the value of integrating qualitative and quanti- Funding
tative approaches—a practice that has become known as
The author(s) received no financial support for the research,
“mixed methods” research, although its use long predated authorship, and/or publication of this article.
the invention of the term (LeVine, 2016; Maxwell, 2016).
Case reports of such “mixed methods” evaluations go References
back at least to a study by Trend (1979), and more recent
Abbott, A. (2001). Chaos of disciplines. Chicago, IL: University
examples can be found in books edited by Thomas Weisner
of Chicago Press.
(2005) and M. Cameron Hay (2016). (See the index in the Ayer, A. J. (1936). Language, truth, and logic. London, England:
Hay volume for policy-relevant examples.) The U.S. Victor Gollancz Ltd.
Department of Education, the Spencer Foundation, and Ayer, A. J. (1978). Interview (this contains a link to a video of the
the W. T. Grant Foundation have provided significant television interview in which Ayer said this). Retrieved from
funding for such integrative efforts, and the fifth edition of https://www.basicincome.com/bp/ratherlike.htm
the Handbook of Research on Teaching contains a major Bandura, A. (1986). Social foundations of thought and action: A
paper by Pamela Moss and Edward Haertel (2016) on social cognitive theory. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
“Engaging Methodological Pluralism.” Barth, F. (1987). Cosmologies in the making: A generative
This integration of qualitative and quantitative approach to cultural variation in New Guinea. Cambridge,
approaches is clearly not just “positivism in drag” UK: Cambridge University Press.
Becker, H. S. (1992). Generalizing from case studies. In E. Eisner
(Giddings, 2006). In many of these studies, qualitative
& A. Peshkin (Eds.), Qualitative inquiry in education: The
methods were essential to revising the initial research continuing debate (pp. 233-242). New York, NY: Teachers
questions as a result of unexpected findings, and made College Press.
major contributions to the conclusions; see, for example, Bennett, A., & Chekel, J. T. (2015). Process tracing: From meta-
the studies discussed by Maxwell and Loomis (2003) and phor to analytic tool. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University
Maxwell, Chmiel, and Rogers (2015). Greene (2007) has Press.
Maxwell 185

Bhaskar, R. (1989). Reclaiming reality: A critical introduction to Keller, E. F. (1983). A feeling for the organism: The life and work
contemporary philosophy. London, England: Verso. of Barbara McClintock. New York, NY: W. H. Freeman.
Bohman, J. (1991). New philosophy of social science. Cambridge, Kuhn, T. S. (1957). The Copernican revolution: Planetary astron-
MA: MIT Press. omy in the development of Western thought. Cambridge, MA:
Campbell, D. C. (1984). Can we be scientific in applied science? In Harvard University Press.
R. F. Connor, D. G. Altman, & C. Jackson (Eds.), Evaluation LeVine, R. A. (2016). Repairing the fractured social sciences: An
studies review annual (pp. 24-48). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. introduction from a historical point of view. In M. C. Hay
Cartwright, N. (1983). How the laws of physics lie. Oxford, UK: (Ed.), Methods that matter: Integrating mixed methods for
Oxford University Press. more effective social science research (pp. 3-12). Chicago,
Cartwright, N. (1999). The dappled world: A study of the boundar- IL: University of Chicago Press.
ies of science. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Levitt, H. M., Bamberg, M., Creswell, J. W., Frost, D. M.,
Cartwright, N., & Hardie, J. (2012). Evidence-based policy: Josselson, R., & Suárez-Orozco, C. (2018), Journal Article
A practical guide to doing it better. Oxford, UK: Oxford Reporting Standards for Qualitative Primary, Qualitative
University Press. Meta-Analytic, and Mixed Methods Research in Psychology:
Cook, T. D., & Reichardt, C. S. (1979). Qualitative and quantita- The APA Publications and Communications Board Task
tive methods in evaluation research. Beverly Hills, CA: Sage. Force Report. American Psychologist, 73(1), 26-46.
Davidson, D. (1980). Essays on actions and events. Oxford, UK: Lincoln, Y. S., & Guba, E. G. (1985). Naturalistic evaluation.
Oxford University Press. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Davidson, D. (1993). Thinking causes. In J. Heil & A. Mele Maxwell, J. A. (1978). The evolution of Plains Indian kin termi-
(Eds.), Mental causation (pp. 3-17). Oxford, UK: Clarendon nologies: A non-reflectionist account. Plains Anthropologist,
Press. 23, 13-29.
Denzin, N. K. (1983). Interpretive interactionism. In G. Morgan Maxwell, J. A. (1993). Gaining acceptance for qualitative meth-
(Ed.), Beyond method: Strategies for social research (pp. ods from clients, policy-makers, and participants. In D. M.
129-144). Beverly Hills, CA: Sage. Fetterman (Ed.), Speaking the language of power (pp. 105-115).
Donaldson, S. I., Christie, C. A., & Mark, M. M. (2009). What Washington, DC: Falmer Press.
counts as credible evidence in applied research and evalua- Maxwell, J. A. (2004). Causal explanation, qualitative research,
tion practice? Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. and scientific inquiry in education. Educational Researcher,
Donmoyer, R. (2008). Generalizability. In L. Given (Ed.), The 33(2), 3-11.
Sage encyclopedia of qualitative research methods (pp. 171- Maxwell, J. A. (2012). The importance of qualitative research for
117). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. causal explanation in education. Qualitative Inquiry, 18, 649-
Eggan, F., & Maxwell, J. A. (2001). Kinship and social organi- 655.
zation. In R. DeMallie (Ed.), Handbook of North American Maxwell, J. A. (2013). A realist approach for qualitative research.
Indians, volume 13: Plains (pp. 974-982). Washington, DC: Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Smithsonian Institution. Maxwell, J. A. (2016). Expanding the history and range of mixed
Fetterman, D. (1984). Ethnography in educational evaluation. methods research. Journal of Mixed Methods Research,
Beverly Hills, CA: Sage. 10(1), 12-27.
Giddings, L. S. (2006). Mixed-methods research: Positivism Maxwell, J. A., & Chmiel, M. (2014). Generalization in and from
dressed in drag? Journal of Research in Nursing, 11, 195-203. qualitative analysis (with Margaret Chmiel). In U. Flick (Ed.),
Giere, R. N. (1999). Science without laws. Chicago, IL: University The Sage handbook of qualitative data analysis (pp. 540-
of Chicago Press. 553). London, England: Sage.
Giere, R. N. (2006). Scientific perspectivism. Chicago, IL: Maxwell, J. A., Chmiel, M., & Rogers, S. (2015). Designing
University of Chicago Press. integration in mixed method and multi-method research. In
Gould, S. J. (1989). Wonderful life: The Burgess Shale and the S. Hesse-Biber & R. B. Johnson (Eds.), Oxford handbook of
nature of history. New York, NY: W.W. Norton. multimethod and mixed methods research inquiry (pp. 223-239).
Greene, J. C. (2007). Mixed methods in social inquiry. San Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass. Maxwell, J. A., & Loomis, D. (2003). Mixed methods design:
Guba, E. G., & Lincoln, Y. S. (1989). Fourth generation evalua- An alternative approach. In A. Tashakkori & C. Teddlie
tion. Newbury Park, CA: Sage. (Eds.), Handbook of mixed methods in social and behavioral
Haack, S. (2003). Defending science within reason: Between sci- research (pp. 241-271). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
entism and cynicism. New York, NY: Prometheus Books. Mayr, E. (1976). Evolution and the diversity of life. Cambridge,
Hay, M. C. (Ed.). (2016). Methods that matter. Chicago, IL: MA: Harvard University Press.
University of Chicago Press. Mayr, E. (1982). The growth of biological thought: Diversity, evo-
Hayek, F. A. (1952). The counterrevolution of science: Studies on lution, and inheritance. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
the abuse of reason. Glencoe, IL: The Free Press. Press.
House, E. (1991). Realism in research. Educational Researcher, Mayr, E. (1988). Toward a new philosophy of biology. Cambridge,
20(6), 2-9+25. MA: Harvard University Press.
Huberman, A. M., & Miles, M. B. (1985). Assessing local causal- McGinn, C. (1991). Conceptual causation: Some elementary
ity in qualitative research. In D. N. Berg & K. K. Smith (Eds.), reflections. Mind, 100, 573-586. (Reprinted in C. McGinn,
Exploring clinical methods for social research (pp. 351-382). Knowledge and reality: Selected essays, pp. 152-167, by C.
Beverly Hills, CA: Sage. McGinn, Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press, 1999)
186 Qualitative Inquiry 26(2)

Menzel, H. (1978). Meaning: Who needs it? In M. Brenner, P. Schofield, J. W. (1990). Increasing the generalizability of qualita-
Marsh, & M. Brenner (Eds.), The social contexts of method tive research. In E. W. Eisner & A. Peshkin (Eds.), Qualitative
(pp. 140-171). New York, NY: St. Martin’s Press. inquiry in education: The continuing debate (pp. 201-232).
Miles, M. B., & Huberman, A. M. (1994). Qualitative data New York, NY: Teachers College Press.
analysis: An expanded sourcebook. Thousand Oaks, CA: Schwandt, T. A. (2007). The Sage dictionary of qualitative inquiry
Sage. (3rd ed.). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Mohr, L. B. (1996). The causes of human behavior: Implications Shadish, W. R., Cook, T. D., & Campbell, D. T. (2002).
for theory and method in the social sciences. Ann Arbor: Experimental and quasi-experimental designs for generalized
University of Michigan Press. causal inference. Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin.
Moss, P. A., & Haertel, E. H. (2016). Engaging methodologi- Steinmetz, G. (2005). Introduction: Positivism and its others in
cal pluralism. In D. Gitomer & C. Bell (Eds.), Handbook of the social sciences. In G. Steinmetz (Ed.), The politics of
research on teaching (5th ed., pp. 127-247). Washington, DC: method in the human sciences (pp. 1-58). Durham, NC: Duke
American Educational Research Association. University Press.
Murdock, G. P. (1949). Social structure. New York, NY: The Free Trend, M. (1979). On the reconciliation of qualitative and quanti-
Press. tative analyses: A case study. In T. D. Cook & C. S. Reichardt
National Research Council. (2002). Scientific research in educa- (Eds.), Qualitative & quantitative methods in program evalu-
tion. Washington, DC: National Academy Press. ation (pp. 68-86). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Patrick, B. (1998). Social Theory in the Twentieth Century. Weinert, F. (Ed.). (1995). Laws of nature: Essays on the philo-
Washington Square, NY: New York University Press. sophical, scientific, and historical dimensions. New York,
Patton, M. Q. (1980). Qualitative evaluation and research meth- NY: Walter de Gruyter.
ods. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. Weisberg, H. I. (2014). Willful ignorance: The mismeasure of
Patton, M. Q. (1990). Qualitative evaluation and research meth- uncertainty. Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley.
ods (2nd ed.). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. Weisner, T. S. (Ed.). (2005). Discovering successful pathways in
Pawson, R. (2006). Evidence-based policy: A realist perspective. children’s development: Mixed methods in the study of child-
London, England: Sage. hood and family life. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Pawson, R. (2013). The science of evaluation: A realist manifesto. Weller, N., & Barnes, J. (2014). Finding pathways: Mixed meth-
London, England: Sage. ods research for studying causal mechanisms. Cambridge,
Pawson, R., & Tilley, N. (1997). Realistic evaluation. London, UK: Cambridge University Press.
England: Sage.
Pitman, M. A., & Maxwell, J. A. (1992). Qualitative approaches to
Author Biography
evaluation. In M. D. LeCompte, W. L. Millroy, & J. Preissle
(Eds.), The handbook of qualitative research in education Joseph A. Maxwell is a professor (Emeritus) in the Research
(pp. 729-770). San Diego, CA: Academic Press. Methods program in the College of Education and Human
Putnam, H. (1999). The threefold cord: Mind, body, and world. Development at George Mason University. His doctoral degree is
New York, NY: Columbia University Press. in anthropology, but his research and teaching have mainly been in
Rose, T. (2015). The end of average. New York, NY: education, with a focus on methodology. He is the author of
HarperCollins. Qualitative Research Design: An Interactive Approach, 3rd edi-
Salmon, W. C. (1984). Scientific explanation and the causal struc- tion (Thousand Oaks, Sage: 2013) and A Realist Approach for
ture of the world. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Qualitative Research (Thousand Oaks, Sage: 2012), as well as
Salmon, W. C. (1998). Causality and explanation. New York, many papers on qualitative and mixed methods research. His cur-
NY: Oxford University Press. rent research deals with using qualitative methods for causal
Sayer, A. (1992). Method in social science: A realist approach explanation, validity in qualitative and quantitative research, the
(2nd ed.). London, England: Routledge. history and breadth of mixed methods research, the value of philo-
Sayer, A. (2000). Realism and social science. London, England: sophic realism for research, and the importance of diversity and
Sage. dialogue across research paradigms and methods.

You might also like