You are on page 1of 37

The International Journal of Organizational Analysis

THE FUTURE OF CORPORATE SOCIAL RESPONSIBILITY


Duane Windsor
Article information:
To cite this document:
Duane Windsor, (2001),"THE FUTURE OF CORPORATE SOCIAL RESPONSIBILITY", The
International Journal of Organizational Analysis, Vol. 9 Iss 3 pp. 225 - 256
Permanent link to this document:
http://dx.doi.org/10.1108/eb028934
Downloaded on: 06 December 2014, At: 07:49 (PT)
References: this document contains references to 0 other documents.
To copy this document: permissions@emeraldinsight.com
Downloaded by Monash University At 07:49 06 December 2014 (PT)

The fulltext of this document has been downloaded 3646 times since 2006*
Users who downloaded this article also downloaded:
Geoffrey P. Lantos, (2001),"The boundaries of strategic corporate social responsibility", Journal of
Consumer Marketing, Vol. 18 Iss 7 pp. 595-632 http://dx.doi.org/10.1108/07363760110410281
Lance Moir, (2001),"What do we mean by corporate social responsibility?", Corporate Governance:
The international journal of business in society, Vol. 1 Iss 2 pp. 16-22 http://dx.doi.org/10.1108/
EUM0000000005486
Rosamaria C. Moura#Leite, Robert C. Padgett, (2011),"Historical background of corporate
social responsibility", Social Responsibility Journal, Vol. 7 Iss 4 pp. 528-539 http://
dx.doi.org/10.1108/1747111111117511

Access to this document was granted through an Emerald subscription provided by 451335 []
For Authors
If you would like to write for this, or any other Emerald publication, then please use our Emerald
for Authors service information about how to choose which publication to write for and submission
guidelines are available for all. Please visit www.emeraldinsight.com/authors for more information.
About Emerald www.emeraldinsight.com
Emerald is a global publisher linking research and practice to the benefit of society. The company
manages a portfolio of more than 290 journals and over 2,350 books and book series volumes, as well
as providing an extensive range of online products and additional customer resources and services.
Emerald is both COUNTER 4 and TRANSFER compliant. The organization is a partner of the
Committee on Publication Ethics (COPE) and also works with Portico and the LOCKSS initiative for
digital archive preservation.
*Related content and download information correct at time of
download.
Downloaded by Monash University At 07:49 06 December 2014 (PT)
The International Journal of Organizational Analysis
2001, Vol. 9, No. 3, pp. 225-256

THE FUTURE OF CORPORATE


SOCIAL RESPONSIBILITY

Duane Windsor
Rice University

Corporate social responsibility is one of the earliest and key concep-


Downloaded by Monash University At 07:49 06 December 2014 (PT)

tions in the academic study of business and society relations. This arti-
cle examines the future of corporate social responsibility. Bowen's
(1953) key question concerned whether the interests of business and
society merge in the long ran. That question is assessed in the present
and future contexts. There seem to be distinctly anti-responsibility
trends in recent academic literature and managerial views concerning
best practices. These trends raise significant doubts about the future
status of corporate social responsibility theory and practice. The vital
change is that a leitmotif of wealth creation progressively dominates the
managerial conception of responsibility. The article provides a devel-
opmental history of the corporate social responsibility notion from the
Progressive Era forward to the corporate social performance frame-
work and Carroll's pyramid of corporate social responsibilities. There
are three emerging alternatives or competitors to responsibility: (1) an
economic conception of responsibility; (2) global corporate citizenship;
and (3) stakeholder management practices. The article examines and
assesses each alternative. The article then assesses the prospects for
business responsibility in a global context. Two fundamentals of social
responsibility remain: (1) the prevailing psychology of the manager;
and (2) the normative framework for addressing how that psychology
should be shaped. Implications for practice and scholarship are consid-
ered.
Bowen (1953), in the seminal work establishing academic study of corporate
social responsibility, posed the following vital question: "To what extent do the
interests of business in the long run merge with the interests of society?" (p. 5).
(For a businessperson's view, see Wright, 1967). The form of Bowen's question
admits the likelihood of short run deviations between business and social interests.
This paper addresses Bowen's question in today's context. The paper assesses
future directions and prospects for corporate social responsibility in both scholar­
ship (i.e., academic theory and evidence) and management (i.e., business practice
226 FUTURE OF CORPORATE SOCIAL RESPONSIBILITY-DRAFT

and application). The paper is a reflection and prediction piece rather than a formal
literature review. (Carroll, 1999, provides an excellent developmental history and
bibliography of the core academic literature; see also Preston, 1975.)
The author detects distinctly anti-responsibility trends in recent academic lit­
erature and managerial views concerning best practices. These trends raise signifi­
cant doubts about the future status of corporate social responsibility theory and
practice. A leitmotif of wealth creation progressively dominates the managerial
conception of responsibility. This leitmotif is entering into academic scholarship.
The leitmotif of wealth creation has a veneer of respectability, in that it is not sim­
ply a resurgence of the philosophy of unrestrained greed that preceded the Progres­
sive Era. Rather, the modern approach treats wealth creation as the best path to
social welfare improvement. Such a case is not unreasonable. But this leitmotif is
highly congenial to management practices, since it eliminates Bowen's long-
accepted conceptual duality separating wealth and responsibility. And the leitmotif
fails to examine whether there may be unavoidable managerial choices between
Downloaded by Monash University At 07:49 06 December 2014 (PT)

wealth seeking wrapped within a responsibility rhetoric and moral conduct at the
expense of wealth creation.
The author thus emphasizes two points—one conceptual, the other empirical.
Conceptually, there are significant difficulties in distinguishing whether business
behavior is truly moral conduct or instrumental adoption of an appearance of moral
conduct as useful reputational strategy. Voluntary acceptance of material loss may
serve to identify moral conduct, but material gain cannot serve to isolate reputa­
tional strategy. Empirically, despite considerable effort in the academic literature to
discover a reliable relationship between responsible conduct and financial perform­
ance, the evidence remains mixed at best. Where responsibility and wealth readily
associate, responsibility is simply a calculation. Where responsibility and wealth
conflict, theory and practice may prove difficult to reconcile unless one dominates
the other. The concern here is that wealth-oriented practice is dominating theory
development.
The author's concern is admittedly at variance with the mainstream view. Car­
roll (1999) sees a "bright future" for corporate social responsibility in both scholar­
ship and management. Carroll views the developmental history examined in the
next section as the steady embedding of the responsibility concept in both broader
theory and more enlightened practice. As one of the key leaders in the development
of the modern corporate social responsibility and performance literatures, Carroll's
views properly command considerable deference.
And viewed superficially, widespread academic and managerial use (see
Walker, 1994; World Business Council, 1999, 2000) of the language of corporate
social responsibility continues. It remains a "core construct" (Carroll, 1999). But
this use is partly a matter of academic belief and tradition, and partly an unavoid­
able managerial rhetoric. No manager today can openly advocate greed or non-
responsibility. Rather, the terms of socially admissible debate concern various
opinions for defining corporate social responsibilities and the best path to social
welfare improvement. Embedded within these opinions is thus an important defini-

The International Journal of Organizational Analysis, Vol. 9, No. 3, 2001


D. WINDSOR 227

tional controversy concerning the proper meaning of corporate social responsibil­


ity. The absence of specific definition leaves responsibility open to conflicting
interpretations.
Bowen (1953) intentionally avoided making a specific definition, preferring to
leave the matter to managers in light of concrete conditions. He approached respon­
sibility as follows: "It refers to the obligations of businessmen to pursue those poli­
cies, to make those decisions, or to follow those lines of action which are desirable
in terms of the objectives and values of our society" (p. 6). (Technically inter­
preted, this definition leaves open the possibility that society cares only about
short-run profit maximization or suffers totalitarian absorption of business.) The
working assumption is one of a broad and morally acceptable set of social objec­
tives and values in a democratic context. Bowen viewed a (voluntary) sense of
responsibility as operating in addition to controls on business due to competition,
custom, and law. Bowen perhaps conflated responsibility and responsiveness: "My
reluctance to attempt definitive formulations of the social responsibilities of busi­
Downloaded by Monash University At 07:49 06 December 2014 (PT)

nessmen has been based on a belief that the way to greater responsiveness of busi­
nessmen toward their social obligations lies in the processes of broadly based dis­
cussion and individual soul-searching on the part of actual participants—not in the
spelling out of 'answers' by outside observers" (p. xi).
In evidence of his concern, the author points to several specific developments
in literature and practice.
Conceptually, the responsibility construct is now part of and subordinate to a
broader framework of corporate social performance. (This performance framework
traces at least to Kreps, 1940; see U.S. Department of Commerce, 1980). In signifi­
cant measure, the growth of alternative, or arguably parallel, academic disciplines
of business ethics and environmentalist» supplants (other scholars may prefer "rein­
forces") the responsibility construct. The high water mark of corporate social
responsibility may be today's socially responsible investment funds and screens.
These funds and screens reveal the key issue. They must show equal or greater
financial returns, or show the true opportunity cost of responsibility in lower finan­
cial returns. While the corporate social performance framework conceptually aligns
corporate social responsibility with corporate social responsiveness, some literature
argues that the latter ought more simply to supersede the former in management
theory and practice (see Frederick, 1994). The difficulty of differentiating moral
responsibility from calculated responsiveness (i.e., reputational strategy) lies buried
deeply in the literature.
Managerially, the responsibility notion has tended to yield to newer rhetorics
of global corporate citizenship and management stewardship directed in significant
measure at stakeholder management practices. (Other scholars may prefer to view
these newer rhetorics as supplementing responsibility.) Globalization is a key
recent theme or mantra of justification. Stakeholder literature is beginning to
explore responsibilities of stakeholders to each other and to the firm (see Andriof,
Waddock, Rahman, & Husted, in press). This interest suggests a broadening of
what was traditionally corporate social responsibility to stakeholders' responsibili­
ties. Corporate responsibility is but one dimension within the latter notion, which

The International Journal of Organizational Analysis, Vol. 9, No. 3, 2001


228 FUTURE OF CORPORATE SOCIAL RESPONSIBILITY-DRAFT

includes stakeholders' responsibilities to the firm. The author argues that these
newer rhetorics reflect an increasing domination of academic conceptualization by
wealth-oriented practitioner views. The term rhetoric conveys that detailed con­
structs are not available in the literature.
What amounts to a counter-reformation in academic theories of responsibility
and performance adopts a narrowly economic conception of responsibility readily
aligned with the marked success recently of shareholder value or economic value
creation strategies (see Jensen, 2000; McWilliams & Siegel, 2001a; cf. Husted &
Salazar, 2001, for a broader conception). The economists' long-standing criticism
of corporate social responsibility (Friedman, 1962, 1970) has returned with a
vengeance in the form of new models explicating a purely economic or private
cost-benefit conception of responsibility. This approach argues that firms are in
business for private wealth creation; and that every component of business
(including philanthropy and stakeholder management) should be directed to that
goal. Responsibility, like responsiveness, is in this view purely penultimate or
Downloaded by Monash University At 07:49 06 December 2014 (PT)

instrumental to wealth creation. If so, responsibility becomes indistinguishable from


responsiveness. The latter may be purely instrumental. But responsibility must have
a normative basis. The modern economic conception recognizes public policy (i.e.,
business-government relations) as a constraint. But thereby in this author's view the
conception discards business ethics as a decision consideration (whether serving as
goal or constraint). Part of the justification for an economic responsibility is prop­
erty rights doctrine; part of the justification is the expected social welfare benefits
of wealth creation. The revived economic conception aligns to the dramatic success
stories associated with shareholder value and economic value creation strategies.
These stories date from Jack Welch's appointment as head of General Electric in
April 1981 (see "The revolutionary spirit," 1999; McTaggart, Kontes, & Mankins,
1994; Tully, 1993).
The remainder of this paper undertakes an assessment and prediction in the
following manner. The second section explains the origins, developmental history,
and key criticisms of the corporate social responsibility construct. The third section
examines three principal alternatives that have emerged: economic responsibility
theory, global corporate citizenship philosophy, and stakeholder management prac­
tices. The concluding section makes some observations on the likely future of cor­
porate social responsibility and the implications for scholarship and practice.

Corporate Social Responsibility: Developmental History


This section examines the developmental history of the corporate social
responsibility construct and its managerial application. The proposed developmen­
tal history comprises three phases: (1) rise and extension; (2) decline and absorp­
tion; (3) and as proposed here a revival of the concept. Although responsibility
rhetoric remains, the responsibility construct has tended to evaporate under criti­
cism of its alleged vagueness and internal inconsistency (Levitt, 1958; Friedman,
1962, 1970). What Carroll (1999, p. 268) calls "alternative themes" have suc­
ceeded that construct: in academic circles, corporate social performance, stake-

The International Journal of Organizational Analysis, Vol. 9, No. 3, 2001


D. WINDSOR 229

holder theory, and business ethics approaches; in managerial circles, global corpo­
rate citizenship and stakeholder stewardship rhetorics focused in practice on an
emerging economic theory of profitable "responsibility."
The academic context of this developmental history is conceptually and
empirically disparate. Business and society studies comprise a very loose affiliation
of several research and teaching streams. While partly overlapping, these streams
do not organize around any widely accepted core paradigm (cf. Preston, 1975).
These streams include (at a minimum): business ethics, corporate social perform­
ance, environmental protection, global corporate citizenship, international policy
regimes, public policy (i.e., business-government relations), and stakeholder man­
agement theory. Loose alignment reflects the wide variety of scholarly associations
and journals. Chief candidate for a core paradigm would be an overarching integra­
tion of corporate social performance (embedding responsibility and responsiveness
Downloaded by Monash University At 07:49 06 December 2014 (PT)

constructs) and stakeholder theory—extended by full incorporation of business


ethics and environmentalism (cf. Swanson, 1995). But even this assertion competes
with a more nature-oriented approach (Frederick, 1998).

The Progressive Era


Adam Smith (1776, Book 4, Ch. 2) pronounced explicitly that economic self-
interest is typically a more reliable path to social welfare improvement than affect­
ing to act for the public interest. Laissez-faire market philosophy in the 19th cen­
tury (enshrined in Spencer, 1851) was triumphant at law in private contract doc­
trine. Reinforced by Social Darwinism (see Tindall, 1988, pp. 836-837), the phi­
losophy emphasized unfettered pursuit of personal opportunity.
Responsibility and responsiveness emerged out of Progressivism. The Pro­
gressive reform movement emerged in the U.S. at the turn of the century. The
movement was a broadly diffused and diversified set of reactions to the post-1865
Gilded Age. Progressivism was more "the common spirit of an age rather than . . .
an organized group or party" (Tindall, 1988, p. 941).
While the modern terminology did not develop until after World War II, busi­
ness leaders have since the 1920s widely adhered to some conception of responsi­
bility and responsiveness practices. But they did so as both business apologetics
and business methods for defusing conflict with potentially influential interest
groups. The Michigan Supreme Court in Dodge v. Ford Motor Co. (204 Mich. 459,
170 N.W. 668, 1919) supported the primary importance of profit maximization on
behalf of owners. It also supported the business judgment rule granting reasonable
discretion to managers (American Law Institute, 1994, pp. 70-71, summarizes the
legal history). Yet Drucker (1999, p. 59) states that managerial balancing of stake­
holder interests dates to the 1920s. Freeman (1984), in his seminal book founding
stakeholder theorizing, conceded that, despite strictly product-market theories of
efficiency and effectiveness (p. 4), "Business has always dealt with non-market­
place stakeholders" (p. 28). Mitchell (1989) "traced the emergence of corporate
social responsibility in the 1920s as an ideological movement intended to legitimize
the power of large corporations" (Oberman, 2000, p. 239).

The International Journal of Organizational Analysis, Vol. 9, No. 3, 2001


230 FUTURE OF CORPORATE SOCIAL RESPONSIBILITY-DRAFT

Viewed in retrospect, the Progressive Era revealed three postures concerning


business responsibilities: (1) post-game philanthropy; (2) pre-game legal constraint;
and (3) in-game moral conduct. Carnegie (1900) preached essentially "richesse
oblige" (labeled here in imitation of "noblesse oblige"). But this philanthropy
occurred after retirement from the competitive race for personal opportunities
played without legal or moral restraints (see Chernow, 1999). Regulation sets pre-
game constraints on conduct (see Jenks, 1917). The modern "mixed economy" is a
blend of more and less regulated industries, leaving a large role for government
(Bowen, 1953, pp. 21, 25). Clark (1916) argued the in-game merits of broader
responsibilities of business relative to profit seeking. Bowen's notion of responsi­
bility reflects this in-game approach.

Formalization of the Responsibility Construct


Downloaded by Monash University At 07:49 06 December 2014 (PT)

Bowen (1953, 1948) is the modern "Father of Corporate Social Responsibil­


ity." He took a broad-gauged approach to business responsibilities. His construct
was a general rubric embracing responsiveness (1953, p. xi), stewardship (pp. 36,
39-40, 44, 243 ff.), social audit (pp. 155-156, 255), corporate citizenship (p. 5),
and a rudimentary version of stakeholder theory (pp. 41-42). There was, as Carroll
(1999) notes, a subsequent shift in terminology from social responsibilities (SR) of
business to corporate social responsibilities (CSR).
Levitt (1958), a distinguished Harvard Business School marketing professor,
early criticized the responsibility theme. He emphasized the dangers of social
responsibility. He subsequently advocated a "third sector" (i.e., voluntary philan­
thropy) for creating "a responsive society" (Levitt, 1973). Preston (1975) viewed
that proposal as "simply a highly generalized version of the 'social responsibility'
thesis" (p. 445). The present author inclines to stronger distinctions between
responsibility and responsiveness and between business responsibilities and the
development of a "third sector" more independent of business.
Friedman (1962, 1970), a Nobel laureate in Economics and member of the so-
called Chicago School of economics, argued against discretionary social responsi­
bilities by managers. They are fiduciary agents in public companies. Hence, discre­
tionary action on their part is little more than "theft" from consumers, employees,
and owners. (Friedman, 1970, p. 124, exempted privately owned businesses. Their
owners could exercise moral sentiment directly; cf. Bowen, 1953, pp. 6-7.) Part of
this criticism is ideological. Friedman (1962) argued that "few trends could so
thoroughly undermine the very foundations of our free society as the acceptance by
corporate officials of a social responsibility other than to make as much money for
their stockholders as possible" (p. 133). Friedman also criticized the ambiguity and
poor logic of social responsibility reasoning. (Davis, 1967, viewed corporate social
responsibility as a puzzle.)
Friedman admitted the desirability of both legal and moral "rules of the
game." He saw a role for both public policy and business ethics. He also admitted
the strategic acceptability of prudential altruism, as distinct from discretionary
altruism. The latter can be a form of responsibility. But prudential altruism is a type

The International Journal of Organizational Analysis, Vol. 9, No. 3, 2001


D.WINDSOR 231

of responsiveness. Another Nobel laureate in Economics, Samuelson (1971),


argued that "a large corporation these days not only may engage in social responsi­
bility, it had damn well better try to do so" (p. 24). The argument substitutes the
term responsibility for responsiveness, but the latter is the more appropriate notion.
Carroll (1999) divides what the present paper treats as the rise of responsibil­
ity into phases by decade: the 1950s (origin of notion), the 1960s (expansion of
literature), and the 1970s (proliferation of responsibility definitions). The 1970s
witnessed the rise of themes of corporate social performance and public responsi­
bility. Preston and Post (1975) redirected attention from corporate to public
responsibility. They argued alignment of corporate responsibility to the limited
scope of the public policy process in distinction to the unlimited scope of individual
opinion and conscience. That defining responsibility should be the province of
public policy is a key theme picked up in modern economic conceptions. Carroll
Downloaded by Monash University At 07:49 06 December 2014 (PT)

views the 1980s as a shift to more empirical research applying his proposed four-
dimensional pyramid model of responsibility (discussed later) and also "a splinter­
ing of writings into alternative concepts and themes" (p. 284). He argues that
responsibility did not die out but rather was "recast." For example, one can view
responsiveness as tempered by combination with responsibility in the corporate
social performance framework. The present author argues that responsibility, as
embedded in that broader framework, has declined in favor of more wealth-friendly
rhetorics. Responsibility requires a moral philosophy or normative basis of some
kind.
Figure 1 gives a reasonable picture of the current state of corporate social
responsibility theory and its role within the corporate social performance frame­
work. The key components of the modern theoretical approach to responsibility are
the corporate social performance (CSP) framework reformulated by Wood (1991)
to combine responsibility (CSR1) and responsiveness (CSR2) with outcomes, Car­
roll's (1991) pyramid of corporate social responsibilities (CSR1), and the stake­
holder theory of the firm stemming from Freeman (1984). Figure 1 locates the
Wood CSP framework, the Carroll (1979) CSR1 responsibility pyramid, and the
stakeholder theory of the firm in relationship to one another. (The note to Figure 1
explains the CSP, CSR1, and CSR2 acronyms now commonly used in the business
and society literature.)
The Corporate Social Performance Framework
The CSP framework emerged through a long evolutionary process summa­
rized and evaluated by Wood (1991). Wood's reformulation or reconstruction of
the CSP template argued a tripartite linking of three elements (each comprised in
turn of three subelements): (1) responsibility (CSR1) principles and motivators of
action and choice; (2) intraorganizational responsiveness (CSR2) processes for
determining action and choice; and (3) resulting outcomes of action and choice.
The present author separates Wood's outcomes logically into outputs of intraor­
ganizational CSR2 processes—social policies and social programs, and the result­
ing social impacts. Wood states explicitly that managers should use any discretion

The International Journal of Organizational Analysis, Vol. 9, No. 3, 2001


232 FUTURE OF CORPORATE SOCIAL RESPONSIBILITY-DRAFT

morally. Managerial morality reflects social expectations of firm conduct and per­
formance, and hence is difficult of separation from responsiveness.

Figure 1
Relationship Among the CSP Framework, CSR1 Pyramid,
and Stakeholder Theory

Social Outcomes

CSP = CSR1 + CSR2 + CSR2 + Social


Principles Processes Outputs Impacts

Institutional Level: Environmental Social Policies


Downloaded by Monash University At 07:49 06 December 2014 (PT)

Legitimacy Assessment
+ + +

Organizational Level: Stakeholder Social Programs


Public Responsibility Management
+ +

Individual Level: Issues


Managerial Discretion Management

CSR1 = Economic + Legal + Ethical + Charitable


Source: Carroll (1991, 1995), Epstein (1987), Wood (1991). Frederick (1994) provided a
shorthand or acronym distinction between corporate social responsibility (CSR1) and
responsiveness (CSR2) that he later extended to rectitude (CSR3) (1986) and CSR4 (cos­
mos-science-religion) (1998).

The CSP framework appears at the top of the figure in the format of a logical
"equation" (derived from Epstein, 1987, and Carroll, 1995). The logical expression

The InternationalJournalofOrganizational Analysis, Vol. 9, No. 3, 2001


D. WINDSOR 233

proposed here is admittedly awkward but designed to definite purpose. Two logical
"operators" for connecting elements and subelements are shown simultaneously: (1)
"+" denotes that the elements and subelements of the framework are additive; and
(2) " " denotes a temporal ordering (logically conceived). Additivity may permit
variation or tradeoff among subelements (some possibly negative) still aggregating
to positive CSP overall. (Carnegie behaved "as i f post-game charity expiated in-
game misconduct.) Missing from the CSP template is a specific set of weights for
combining the subelements; and any explicit statement of minimum standards pre­
scribed for each subelement. Such weights would define responsibilities concretely.
Temporal ordering means that, for example, impacts "flow" only from (i.e., occur
after) policies and programs. Temporal ordering is a necessary condition for cau­
sality.
Downloaded by Monash University At 07:49 06 December 2014 (PT)

Carroll's Pyramid of Responsibilities


Wood (1991) retained Carroll's four CSR1 categories but effectively subordi­
nated them to the notion of CSR1 principles or motivators. Figure 1 positions Car­
roll's four-dimensional pyramid of responsibilities beneath the CSR1 principles.
The figure also positions stakeholder relationships as a crosswalking matrix from
responsibilities to outcomes (following Carroll, 1995) beneath social outcomes
(i.e., outputs and impacts).
Carroll (1991) organized the crude notion of multiple corporate social respon­
sibilities into a pyramid construct. In this pyramid, economic responsibilities are the
foundation and philanthropy is the apex. The construction is such that the other
responsibilities cannot be achieved in the absence of economic performance (i.e.,
goods and services, jobs, profitability)—a bankrupt firm will cease to operate. Eco­
nomic and legal responsibilities are socially required (i.e., mandatory); ethical
responsibilities are socially expected; philanthropy is socially desired. These com­
ponents may be aggregative (Carroll, 1995, p. 49), as shown in Figure 1 below the
pyramid construction in another logical equation format (connected by "+" only
and not by "=>").
Carroll (1995) was explicit that all dimensions of responsibility are "infused
or embedded with ethical issues or overtones" (p. 49). Carroll means that economic
obligations "should coexist" (Kang & Wood, 1995, p. 408) with other obligations;
and that "social responsibility can only become reality if more managers become
moral instead of amoral or immoral" (Carroll, 1991, p. 39; also cited by Kang &
Wood, 1995, p. 415). The four components are simultaneously binding and specifi­
cally not sequential although additive (Carroll, 1999, p. 289).
Carroll (1995) in effect places minimum moral conditions on each dimension.
These minimum conditions lack specification, and hence operate more as a spirit of
the times. Figure 1 suggests these minimum conditions by indeterminate dashed
lines within the pyramid.
Figure 1 suggests a modification to the pyramid construct. To the left of the
pyramid, the figure sketches a vertical axis. Along this axis the four responsibilities
aggregate to maximum wealth. Each responsibility beyond profitability is then a
subtraction from maximum wealth. Managers are likely to view matters in this

The International Journal of Organizational Analysis. Vol. 9. No. 3. 2001


234 FUTURE OF CORPORATE SOCIAL RESPONSIBILITY-DRAFT

fashion, or alternately to view responsibility dimensions as a strategy for wealth


maximization.
Kang and Wood's Attempted Reformulation
Kang and Wood (1995) undertook to reformulate (or reconstruct) the Carroll
pyramid. Their specific solution appears unsatisfactory overall and complex in
explication. Their difficulties suggest robustness of Carroll's construct. But vitally
they distinguish between after-profit responsiveness (cf. post-game philanthropy)
and before-profit responsibility (cf. pre-game morality). They argue that the litera­
ture, and hence the Carroll model, had proceeded from a flawed assumption that
social responsibility occurs after (some minimum) profit, whereas responsibility (or
some part of it) must occur before profit. In their view, businesspeople tend to
articulate a profit-plus path to responsibility and expect market value added (or at
Downloaded by Monash University At 07:49 06 December 2014 (PT)

least low-cost duty fulfillment) in socially responsible management. The authors'


expressed concern was that this profit-oriented path had created a muddle in the
CSP literature and overlapped too much with neoclassical economics asserted as a
primacy of values. This concern accords with that of the present author.
Kang and Wood (1995) introduce a moral dimension (which is, however,
certainly not missing in Carroll's 1995 treatment), and then suppress Carroll's eth­
ics-law distinction into an overarching social responsibility dimension. The term
"social" removes "the artificial and simplistic distinction between legal and ethical
responsibility in older models" (p. 414). As an intermediate step, abandoned as
unsatisfactory, Kang and Wood initially simply inverted the Carroll pyramid—so
that the hierarchy of responsibilities (or values) is turned upside down. This
approach was unsatisfactory. Since a simple inversion did not suffice, they under­
took to reformulate or reconstruct the pyramid's design. They retain four steps to
the pyramid. Their proposed solution is a moral base (or foundation) to the pyra­
mid, succeeded in declining relative importance by social responsibility and then
economic responsibility. Kang and Wood convert benevolence into a dotted tip of
the pyramid. Their purpose is to make a distinction between involuntary philan­
thropy (representing a "moral or social obligation to stakeholders) and "purely vol­
untary" philanthropy or benevolence. The distinction resembles Friedman's (1970)
notions of prudential and discretionary altruism. (There is also an effort to link the
reformulated pyramid to the three levels of CSR1 principles in Wood's, 1991,
reconstruction of the CSP template. The individual level links to moral responsi­
bilities; the organizational level to social responsibilities; the institutional level to
economic responsibilities.)
While the Kang and Wood (1995) modifications are complex and ultimately
unsatisfactory, the present author does not read Carroll's seminal construction as
strictly simple in comparison. Complexity arises with the infusion of all dimensions
with morality, and with the broadening of economic responsibilities beyond profit­
ability. There are in effect five dimensions, one invisibly (in Carroll's depiction)
permeating all of the other four. There is in effect both a normative (ideal or pre­
scriptive) and a behavioral (realistic or descriptive) version of the pyramid. Argu­
ment works back and forth between how people ought to behave (i.e., morally) and

The International Journal of Organizational Analysis, Vol. 9, No. 3, 2001


D. WINDSOR 235

how people are likely to behave (i.e., amorally). Behavior (i.e., practice) may come
to dominate theory (i.e., ethics) by appeal to the desirability of material outcomes.

Three Emerging Alternatives to Responsibility


Three competitors to responsibility have emerged: (1) a revived and extended
economic conception of responsibility; (2) a global corporate citizenship philoso­
phy; and (3) stakeholder management practices. This section assesses each alterna­
tive in a separate subsection below.
The Economics of Responsibility
The American Enterprise Institute organized a debate between two economists
(Manne & Wallich, 1972). Their definition of responsibility involved: (1) reduced
Downloaded by Monash University At 07:49 06 December 2014 (PT)

marginal returns; (2) purely voluntary activity; and (3) actual corporate expenditure
rather than a conduit for individual philanthropy. The implication is that responsi­
bility is costly. They similarly distinguished voluntary responsibility from legal
duty, but favored stockholder instructions on the matter. Drucker (1984) attempted
reconciliation through converting social responsibilities into profitable business
opportunities. (McWilliams & Siegel, 2001a, take up the theme that responsibility
is costly and should involve profitable opportunities.)
This last theme has become pronounced in a recent literature that revives and
extends the Friedman view that the sole (or primary) responsibility of business is
profitability seeking. The framework for this revival is broader than the Friedman
criticism of discretionary responsibility. Wealth creation (the modern conception) is
a goal and a motive. Business operates within parameters established by public
policy. (The social performance approach argues that managerial motives should
reflect moral and social determinants.) As Jensen (2000) makes clear, the perform­
ance measure is not immediate profit maximization but long run wealth creation.
This revival reflects: (1) the perceived logical weaknesses of social responsibility
and performance theories (Sternberg, 1996; Jensen, 2000); (2) the reassertion of
traditional property rights doctrine (Sternberg, 1996); and (3) the evident success in
recent years of shareholder value and economic value maximization practices.
Superficially, an economic conception would appear reasonable. It links
wealth and social welfare. It admits of a social control context for the pursuit of
private economic interest. And this conception comes in the context of a significant
shift away from 19th century laissez-faire and Social Darwinism views. Therefore,
a detailed examination of this apparently reasonable conception follows.
Sternberg's Property Rights Conception. Sternberg (1994, 1996, 1999)
stresses owners' property rights. This argument holds that owners organized (or
alternately purchased) the firm (a presumption posited in financial-economics the­
ory) and are ("constitutionally") entitled to the (residual) fruits of their financial
investment. Otherwise the organization is definitionally not-for-profit. The argu­
ment in effect portrays stakeholder theorizing as theft of extant (and morally justifi­
able) property rights of owners (cf. Friedman, 1970). For Sternberg, stakeholder

The International Journal of Organizational Analysis, Vol. 9, No. 3, 2001


236 FUTURE OF CORPORATE SOCIAL RESPONSIBILITY-DRAFT

rights (if any) are strictly secondary (i.e., subordinated) to the property rights of
owners.
Sternberg's argument is doctrinaire in the following sense. What property law
concerns is not who has ownership—i.e., actual possession; but rather who pos­
sesses the best right—i.e., claim to such ownership. Otherwise progressive taxation
of income and wealth is not defensible.
Sternberg's corporate-governance argument conflicts with two different
views. Donaldson and Preston (1995) formulated a broader theory of property
rights, taking into account the investment "equities" of stakeholders other than
financial claimants. Blair (1995) formulated an argument for extending (on both
motivational and equity grounds) ownership shares (not necessarily with voting
rights) to knowledge workers.
Jensen's Wealth Creation Conception. Compared to 19th century laissez-
Downloaded by Monash University At 07:49 06 December 2014 (PT)

faire reasoning, today's more sophisticated argument holds that total long-run mar­
ket value (i.e., financial-claim) creation by management is the best path to social
wealth creation ultimately benefiting all stakeholders. (Financial claimants include
equity, debt, preferred stock, and warrants—Jensen, 2000, p. 38.) Jensen argues
that the "value maximization proposition . . . has its roots in 200 years of research
in economics and finance" in contrast to stakeholder theory's "roots in sociology,
organizational behavior, the politics of special interests, and managerial self inter­
est." Supporting the social welfare argument is the apparent success recently of
shareholder value and economic value creation strategies.
Jensen (2000) does add an intriguing wrinkle to the financial-economics
approach. He argues first that managers and employees require (logically and
behaviorally) a single-valued objective function (i.e., bottom-line value creation).
(For the competing viewpoint, see Bowden, Lane, & Martin, 2001; Elkington,
1998; Fombrun, 1997). He argues second that attention to stakeholder interests is
necessary for full motivation of managers and employees to pursue long-term value
creation. The wrinkle admits to an important psychological dimension to manage­
rial and employee conduct (see Donaldson, 1999). Even so, his view basically is
that "enlightened stakeholder theory" (using his words) is a handmaiden of an
"enlightened value maximization" theory. The market game plays out from existing
conditions. Jensen holds that stakeholder practices amount to nothing more than
what managers must do in any case for long-run strategic performance of the firm.
They must deal with important stakeholders to their satisfaction (Jensen, 2000, pp.
42,44, 50), as must occur in any truly voluntary contracting.
Jensen's (2000) arguments hold within state-conditions determined by public
policy concerning externalities and monopolies. Public policy, a political game also
played from existing conditions, operates simultaneously to grapple with external­
ities and monopolies. But business may instrumentally seek to influence public
policy. A growing economy (generating higher market values for firms) in associa­
tion with reductions in externalities and monopolies is (more or less) moving in the
direction of greater social welfare. (Public policy is not here perfect. Rather with
respect to externalities and monopolies, market activities and change in public pol­
icy are moving in parallel over time from whatever starting point historically.)

The International Journal of Organizational Analysis, Vol. 9, No. 3, 2001


D. WINDSOR 237

The general approach in Jensen (2000) is to emphasize financial-economics


and strategic management of stakeholders, with problems of context (i.e., state-
conditions) addressed in public policy. This approach effectively sidesteps business
ethics. The general stance in economics has been to assume self-interested actors,
but that stance does not address whether such actors are moral or amoral (cf. Car­
roll, 1995) in conduct. Self-interest can be duty abiding and benevolent. If all eco­
nomic actors are purely self-interested, managers could not be trustworthy stew­
ards.
McWilliams and Siegel's Economic Model. McWilliams and Siegel (2001a)
formalize the economic approach. They usefully outline "a supply and demand
model of corporate social responsibility (CSR)" treated as product or process
changes that "directly support social responsibility" or "signal the firm's commit­
ment to CSR" (p. 117). The approach asks only whether a stakeholder claim's cost
and price effects yield a profit equal to ignoring the claim. (The reader should con­
Downloaded by Monash University At 07:49 06 December 2014 (PT)

sult the exchange between McWilliams & Siegel, 2001b, and Windsor, 2001b, in
which the authors respond to this view.) The model's usefulness is that it highlights,
but does not resolve, some key issues delineated in Friedman and Carroll (2001a),
whom these authors cite. The authors model public firms' strictly wealth-maximiz­
ing investment in responsibility (CSR) attributes as differentiated from legal com­
pliance (not further addressed by the authors): "Here we define CSR as actions that
appear to further some social good, beyond the interests of the firm and that which
is required by law. . . . CSR means going beyond the law" (p. 117, underlining
added). The American Law Institute (1994) document explicitly criticizes legal
compliance based on a purely cost-benefit calculus (p. 60), because such compli­
ance is a duty and not a calculation. Moreover, the authors' approach does not
address business ethics independently of law.
McWilliams and Siegel (2001a) differentiate CSR "demands from multiple
stakeholder groups" into "(1) [ultimate] consumer demand and (2) [penultimate]
demand from other stakeholders" (p. 119). The latter must translate into the former:
CSR-oriented supply occurs at higher cost (cf. Manne & Wallich, 1972). A purely
instrumental cost-benefit calculus invests in advertised CSR attributes-signals, sold
to consumers at higher prices, to the point at which additional revenue (reflecting
downward-sloping demand) equals additional cost (reflecting upward-sloping sup­
ply). Absent barriers to resource mobility (suggestive of perfect competition), rates
of return equalize, and thus there is no prescriptive CSR investment level.
McWilliams and Siegel (2001a) conclude on variability of reported empirical
relationships between CSR and financial performance "there will generally be a
neutral relationship between CSR activity and firm financial performance" (p. 125).
While arguably balancing market-priced "demands" of multiple stakeholder groups,
the proposed model yields only a quite limited model οf profit-maximizing behavior
labeled as responsibility while explaining and reflecting the authors' empirical
findings of neutrality (see McWilliams & Siegel, 2000).
Neither Jensen (2000) nor McWilliams and Siegel (2000) address the well-
known difference beUveen corporate social responsibility (CSR1) and responsive­
ness (CSR2). In fairness to these authors, Frederick (1994), not cited by them,

The International Journal of Organizational Analysis, Vol. 9, No. 3, 2001


238 FUTURE OF CORPORATE SOCIAL RESPONSIBILITY-DRAFT

judges responsibility to be philosophical-ethical vagueness, and makes responsive­


ness action-oriented realism. But Banfield (1985, p. 337) argued that pure respon­
siveness to external conditions, undertaken on a cost-benefit calculus, is not moral
choice but simply pricing behavior. Responsibility may result in a situation that
imposes economic loss on the firm justified by some higher consideration. The
economic approach leaves moral choices and unprofitable demands to the uncertain
legal or public policy arenas.
Global Corporate Citizenship
The term "corporate citizenship" appears in Bowen (1953). Carroll (1999)
comments that, by 1991, he was suggesting that the philanthropy dimension
included corporate citizenship. But corporate citizenship has become an important
and practitioner-based movement only in recent years. Various recognition awards
are now given. Davenport (2000) states that "corporate citizenship became a com­
monly used term by practitioners" in the 1990s and is a more accurate descriptor of
Downloaded by Monash University At 07:49 06 December 2014 (PT)

corporate behaviors than corporate social performance, which "is a theoretical con­
struct from the academic community" (p. 211).
The key argument (Vidal, 1999) holds that citizenship activities enhance cor­
porate reputation and hence long-term financial performance; or at least that a bad
reputation will damage long-term financial performance. The rhetoric is thus of
practical appeal to managers pursuing shareholder wealth or economic value crea­
tion goals. Two terms are closely intertwined: citizenship conveys the sense of
responsibility for social impacts, good neighborliness the sense of local community
impacts. Carroll (1998) addressed corporate citizenship in terms of four faces (eco­
nomic, legal, ethical, and philanthropic) adapted directly from the four-step pyra­
mid of responsibility. The idea has global reach. A multinational enterprise operat­
ing in an integrating world economy should practice global corporate citizenship: it
should be a good citizen (and good neighbor) in every host country in which it
operates.
A Criticism of Corporate Citizenship. The present author views corporate
citizenship adversely (see Windsor, 2001a). Corporate citizenship is a managerial
and philanthropic ideology; it is a strategic doctrine and movement evolved by
practitioners. The strategic doctrine amounts to investment in market development
and social stability viewed as global state-conditions for corporate wealth creation.
Corporate citizenship is consistent with voluntarism advocated by government.
Both strict compliance with law and limited if purely strategic benevolence accom­
plish some social good. While corporate citizenship embeds older traditions of cor­
porate social responsibility and responsiveness, fundamentally it crafts an instru­
mental, self-serving view of the relationship between business and society.
Corporate citizenship is a marriage of two circumstances: (1) rising societal
expectations of corporate benefits in an age of governmental cutbacks; and (2)
strategic management aimed at value creation in all functions and activities of a
firm. It is a strategy for arguing that direct benefits (i.e., actual gains or reductions
in losses) are generated for all stakeholders of a firm through value creation orien­
tation. If negative impacts of corporate activities were in fact reduced and mini-

The International Journal of Organizational Analysis, Vol. 9, No. 3, 2001


D. WINDSOR 239

mized, and all affected parties received either such reduction or some gain, then
corporate citizenship would correspond to an increase in corporate social perform­
ance. But these very circumstances would then be a standard and a test for serious
corporate citizenship.
Corporate citizenship is a two-edged sword to be handled carefully. One edge
admits both the ultimate power of society to impose corporate responsibilities and
the strategic advantages of business alignment with societal expectations. The other
edge advances a novel theory (rejected by the U.S. Supreme Court in the 19th cen­
tury) that the corporation should be treated as a citizen in terms of legitimating the
political influence and activities of business executives. (The U.S. Supreme
Court—see Miller, 1968—explicitly rejected an early argument for treating corpo­
rations as if citizens in 1839, and then much later accepted the corporate artificial
person fiction in 1886.) Such treatment would restrict corporate social responsibili­
ties to be no more than the duties of ordinary individual citizens. This posture
refurbishes the 19th century legal doctrine of corporate personhood developed in
Downloaded by Monash University At 07:49 06 December 2014 (PT)

the U.S. Supreme Court as economic substantive due process. It serves to blunt any
possible development of progressive corporate responsibility. (It may be inaccurate
to argue that the posture was explicitly intended to do so. But the implicit opportu­
nity for abuse must be evident, at least in the narrow sense of promoting tort
"reform" and retarding anti-business legal developments in criminal and civil
cases.)
The author views corporate citizenship as a managerial movement that effec­
tively substitutes a different conception, as well as language, for responsibility. The
substitution is less a recognition of the vagueness of the responsibility construct
than an effort to transform obligation into rights conceptually while focusing
resource allocation on strategic reputation enhancement activities. A "citizen" has
rights as well as duties. The citizenship language places corporations on the same
constitutional plane as the individual citizen. At law, the corporation is an artificial
person and acquires certain privileges, including freedom of speech and political
activity in consequence; but a citizen has constitutional rights that only transfer to
the corporation through the circumstance that it is a collectivity of such citizens.
The Role of Corporate Philanthropy. A limited corporate philanthropy
meets the business judgment rule (American Law Institute, 1994). The American
Law Institute argues for allowing "corporate resources to be devoted to public wel­
fare, humanitarian, educational, and philanthropic purposes even without a showing
of expected profits or ethical norms" (p. 65). The rationale is consideration of a
firm's social impact, its stakeholder concerns, and "the cooperation of corporations"
with public policy, including desirable diversity of philanthropic participation.
"However, corporate activity that is justified solely by social considerations should
be subject to a limit of reasonableness" (p. 65).
Orts (1992, pp. 71-72) warns against short-term concessions intended to gain
long-term benefits. His argument is that, in each succeeding round of owner-stake­
holder interactions, stakeholder demands for more concessions may simply rise.
Friedman's (1970) critique of discretionary corporate social responsibility by
management explicitly conceded a plausible role for prudent altruism, as distinct

The International Journal of Organizational Analysis, Vol. 9, No. 3, 2001


240 FUTURE OF CORPORATE SOCIAL RESPONSIBILITY-DRAFT

from discretionary altruism. He defined the former as strategic concessions for the
protection (or promotion) of long-term profits. A prudent appearance of altruism
does not make strategic investment a moral activity. The notion of prudent conduct
at least suggests a broader, stakeholder-responsive (if not, strictly speaking, a moral
responsibility) conception of business strategy.
The Need for Moral Judgment. Business has abandoned the 19th century
tradition of overt contempt for the public interest that prevailed prior to the Pro­
gressive Era. The shift is a recognition of Davis's (1973) proposed "Iron Law of
Responsibility" holding that businesses misusing social power will lose social
legitimacy especially in the face of rising societal expectations. Davis defined
social responsibility as beginning where legal compliance ends: it must exceed
minimum legal obligations. But the "Iron Law" effectively makes such responsibil­
ity nothing more than calculated responsiveness.
Historically, the attempted cutback in growth of governmental domestic
Downloaded by Monash University At 07:49 06 December 2014 (PT)

activities during the Reagan and Thatcher era of the 1980s greatly propelled the
corporate citizenship movement. Ideologically, conservative governments preferred
deregulation, privatization, tax reduction, and voluntarism (i.e., civic virtue). A
decline in public sector responsibility, coupled with government and philanthropic
calls for voluntary action by individuals and businesses, led on to the corporate
citizenship movement filling but arguably not resolving an intellectual void left by
the debate over social responsibility. This change in business-government relations
accompanied recognition of the evolution of a more integrated and competitive
world economy (see Conference Board, 1999; Tichy, McGill, & St. Clair, 1997).
Corporate citizenship is far more a matter of strategic policy including legal
compliance than any application of moral principle. At a minimum, corporate citi­
zenship—understood explicitly as strategic investment in the firm's social and natu­
ral environments for sustainable corporate growth and profitability—arguably
aligns corporate and social interests to mutual benefits in win-win outcomes for all
stakeholders of the firm. The essential idea thus arguably both broadens and
enriches the older notion of corporate social responsibility. If so, even gross imper­
fection of motives should not be treated as the implacable enemy of at least some
good outcomes (to paraphrase and modify what has been said in another context).
True corporate citizenship requires moral leaders; but such ideal leaders may prove
relatively scarce.
The Fictional Nature of Corporate Citizenship. Corporate citizenship may
be an eminently practical rhetoric; but analogies, fictions, and metaphors alike
should receive careful scrutiny before one accepts the practical implications. Cor­
porate citizenship is literally a fiction in two senses.
Firstly, citizenship tacitly portrays the domestic enterprise as equivalent to the
ordinary individual citizen. Citizenship conveys the sense of "one person, one vote"
and equality of constitutional, legal, and political standing in a democratic polity.
The corporate citizenship notion conflates citizen (which a firm cannot be) and
person (which a firm can be but only as a legal fiction). While a corporation is at
law a fictional "person" with rights of private contracting, public expression, and
political activities, the corporation cannot vote or hold office—the key hallmarks of

The International Journal of Organizational Analysis, Vol. 9, No. 3, 2001


D.WINDSOR 241

citizenship defined as a share in sovereign power in a democratic polity. Any pre­


sumption that the corporation is an association of citizens who thus in some sense
vote collectively ignores the agency problems resulting from separation of owner­
ship and control. The corporation should arguably act if a non-voting citizen pre­
cisely because of its power to affect others greatly. Corporate citizenship practices
may serve to blunt or channel that power. But fictional "personhood" is not a sound
basis for artificial "citizenship."
The current corporate citizenship approach suggests equivalence of the corpo­
ration with ordinary individual citizens—an equivalence potentially of advantage in
criminal and civil cases against corporations. The American Law Institute (1994)
recommendations on corporate governance propose, in effect, that a corporate citi­
zen be subject to the same, but not any greater, duties relative to the individual citi­
zen. Citizenship thus both sounds more positive than corporate social responsibility
and yet is a more minimalist, voluntarist notion with natural liberty and freedom of
contract overtones that conceptually limits externally imposed responsibilities. Citi­
Downloaded by Monash University At 07:49 06 December 2014 (PT)

zenship involves privileges and immunities, as well as obligations (see "Constitu­


tional rights," 1982). The duties are mandatory; the key matter is whether the duties
ought to be higher for businesses than for ordinary individuals.
Secondly, global citizenship portrays the multinational enterprise as a citizen
of the world—a notion that constitutionally and legally does not exist. (There are as
yet no UN-chartered businesses.) Rather, the meaning of the terminology must
plainly be that the enterprise is a non-voting (if influential) force in each nation-
state in which it operates (i.e., direct effects) or which it otherwise affects (i.e., indi­
rect effects). While some countries recognize dual citizenship, the notion has never
extended to embrace multiple citizenships of the sort suggested by global corporate
citizenship.
The notion of a home country—i.e., a nation-state whose interests are superior
to those of other countries in which the enterprise operates—evaporates. And this
evaporation may not prove consistently popular with national governments. The
notion of global corporate citizenship releases corporations from traditional
national sovereignty. Globally "footloose" firms might be less responsive to stake­
holders' interests, precisely because the firm can more readily move activities to
less "costly" locations involving lower standards of conduct.
A Hitachi Foundation publication (Logan, Delwin, & Regelbrugge, 1997)
explicitly argues that the "home" of the multinational enterprise is "now much more
global and multicultural." The authors expand the scope of the term corporate citi­
zenship to include "corporate responsibility, corporate community involvement,
corporate community investment, and corporate community responsibility" (cited
by Preston & Mihalko, 1999, p. 46). Global corporate citizenship may arguably
serve to integrate corporate social responsibility and stakeholder management
within a corporate social performance framework. The Hitachi Foundation publica­
tion defines good corporate citizenship as "meeting, within reason, the expectations
of all its societal stakeholders to maximize the company's positive impact and
minimize the negative impact on its social and physical environment, while pro­
viding a competitive return to its financial stakeholders" (Preston & Mihalko, 1999,

The International Journal of Organizational Analysis, Vol. 9, No. 3, 2001


242 FUTURE OF CORPORATE SOCIAL RESPONSIBILITY-DRAFT

p. 46). The Hitachi Foundation publication explains global corporate citizenship in


terms of the business need to increase the consumption capacity of developing
countries as the essential basis for maintaining "profitability and growth rates" in
circumstances in which the "industrialized world has become saturated with pro­
ducers" (Preston & Mihalko, p. 47).
Two Examples of Bad Corporate Citizenship. A journalist criticized Cater­
pillar for flunking the corporate citizenship test in York County, Pennsylvania
(Hicks, 1996). Hicks lists historical evidence of the firm's previous good citizen­
ship: jobs, high compensation, community participation (especially philanthropy),
and job training. According to Hicks, however, Caterpillar allegedly "ceased being
a good corporate citizen in York County when it placed" profits ahead of employee
safety.
Philip Morris Cos. has long positioned itself as a good corporate citizen. One
could find on a company website a corporate citizenship report stating: "We have
Downloaded by Monash University At 07:49 06 December 2014 (PT)

had a prominent international corporate citizenship program for more than 30 years
in the many communities where we do business." The three main businesses of the
corporation are foods, beer, and tobacco. The Czech affiliate of Philip Morris inde­
pendently commissioned Arthur D. Little International, consultants, to conduct a
study into the social impacts of smoking. The report concluded that cigarette use
was not a financial drain on the Czech state, because government saves money on
"health care, pensions and housing when smokers die prematurely" (Reuters, 2001).
Philip Morris Cos. apologized for the study distributed in the Czech Republic, and
effectively repudiated the action.
A Progressive Responsibilities Conception. If one is to take corporate citi­
zenship seriously, then contrary to the current approach of equal responsibilities for
businesses and individuals, unequal distributions of wealth and power in society
imply a fundamentally different theory of progressive responsibilities for corpora­
tions. The more powerful and wealthy the firm, the greater that firm's responsibili­
ties to neighbors and the community must be. The argument is strongest for legal
and moral compliance. It is useless to construct a case for increasing corporate
altruism (which must come out of monies belonging to owners or consumers),
which must always be strategic calculation. Public policy may induce or compel
philanthropy as a direct substitute for government taxation. But then business
engages in responsiveness and not responsibility.
The U.S. has embraced in this century progressive income and wealth taxa­
tion. Progressive citizenship responsibility is, for individuals, built into the notion
of graduated income tax liabilities. Progressive taxation rests arguably on an uneasy
case (Blum & Kalven, 1970), but Adam Smith (1776) in The Wealth of Nations
made the case for ability-to-pay taxation.
A progressive responsibility case that applies to individual citizens must apply
most particularly to large and hence influential corporations (see Windsor, 2001a).
More is expected of Bill Gates, not the same or less, with respect to his conduct of
Microsoft's business precisely because of its success. Where an individual and a
large corporation's employee pour a single can of oil on the ground (neither should
do so, of course), the responsibility is greater for the corporation, not simply equal

TheInternationalJournalof Organizational Analysis, Vol. 9, No. 3, 2001


D. WINDSOR 243

to that of the individual. The current notion of corporate citizen promotes a mini­
mization of socially imposed responsibilities equivalent to those expected of an
individual ordinary citizen.
Stakeholder Management Practices
Blair (1995) and Clarkson (1995) conceded the conceptual vagueness of
responsibility, as argued by Friedman, and asserted the superiority of stakeholder
theory. Clarkson viewed stakeholder management practices as a superior path to
corporate social performance compared to any responsibility concept. Corporate
citizenship can readily translate into action in response to and/or on behalf of vari­
ous stakeholder groups. U.S. Secretary of Labor Reich (1996) stated the citizenship
argument with respect to employees, their families, and local communities as fol­
lows: "If the government is to do less, then the private sector will have to do more"
in terms of "responsibility for Americans' economic well-being."
Stakeholder theory is attractive in that it addresses concrete interests and
Downloaded by Monash University At 07:49 06 December 2014 (PT)

practices. In favor of stakeholder thinking is Carroll's (1995) argument that "Stake­


holder thinking is a powerful way of visualizing organizations and their social
responsibilities" (p. 71). Jensen (2000), however, argues that "stakeholder theory is
incomplete as a specification for the corporate purpose or objective function" (p.
38). Also critical of stakeholder thinking is Campbell and Alexander's (1997)
observation that the approach does not determine any specific business strategy.
Reich (1996) notes: In a 1951 address that was typical of the era, Frank
Abrams, chairman of Standard Oil of New Jersey, proclaimed, "The job of man­
agement is to maintain an equitable and working balance among the claims of the
variously directly interested groups . . . stockholders, employees, customers and the
public at large." The entire notion of balancing of partially conflicting interests,
however, requires more careful scrutiny than has occurred (see Windsor, 1999).
Developmental History of Stakeholder Theory. The stakeholder theory of
the firm, in recognizable modem form, originated at the Stanford Research Institute
(in a 1963 SRI internal memo; Freeman, 1984, pp. 31, 49). In retrospect, one can
identify some earlier stakeholder-like reasoning approaches (Dodd, 1932). The
post-1945 management-labor arrangements in Germany and Japan were stake­
holder-like (Donaldson & Preston, 1995, p. 76). Drucker (1999, p. 59) argues,
however, that the arrangements were simply to avoid industrial strife. There was a
parallel Scandinavian theory effort (Rhenman, 1964/1968; Rhenman & Stymne,
1965). Stakeholder theory received active academic interest following Freeman's
(1984) seminal book.
In origin, stakeholder theorizing was explicitly and intendedly a softening of
(if not implicitly a fundamental challenge to) strict stockholder doctrine (Freeman,
1984, p. 32) then prevailing in U.S. (i.e., state-level) corporate-governance law
since at least Dodge v. Ford (1919). Stockholder doctrine posits that shareholder
return is the primary purpose of a business corporation (other purposes, if any, are
then strictly secondary). Such return is certainly the primary purpose of financial
claimants. "The SRI researchers argued that unless executives understood the needs
and concerns of . . . stakeholder groups, they could not formulate corporate objec-

The International Journal of Organizational Analysis, Vol. 9, No. 3, 2001


244 FUTURE OF CORPORATE SOCIAL RESPONSIBILITY-DRAFT

tives which would receive the necessary support for the continued survival of a
firm" (Freeman, 1984, p. 32; cf. Clarkson, 1995).
A large and diverse stakeholder literature has blossomed since 1984, with a
marked surge of stakeholder publications in and after 1995, partly in connection
with the Sloan Foundation-supported Redefining the Corporation research project
operated through the University of Toronto's Clarkson Centre for Business Ethics.
The stakeholder viewpoint informs so-called constituency statutes adopted in some
29 U.S. states (Orts, 1992, pp. 72-73; Jensen, 2000, p. 55, citing Sternberg, 1994).
Orts argues, however, that such statutes merely increase the discretion of managers
while weakening the power of owners without increasing the power of other stake­
holders. Corporate-governance reform reports issued during the 1990s (American
Law Institute, 1994; Dey, 1994; Hampel, 1998; Peters, 1997) all included language
highlighting in some form stakeholder considerations as well as improved account­
ability of management to shareholders. Jensen (2000, p. 55) cites Sternberg (1996)
on the acceptance of stakeholder theory by the Business Roundtable and the Finan-
Downloaded by Monash University At 07:49 06 December 2014 (PT)

cial Times (of London). The Blair government (Labour Party) in the UK endorsed a
stakeholder theory of the economy (Jensen, 2000, 55; see also Blair, 1996).
The surge of stakeholder publications in 1995 marked not simply a triumph of
the approach, but deliberate efforts at explicit reformulation or extension.
Donaldson and Preston (1995) argue that much of stakeholder literature has
engaged in implicit theorizing through lack of separation of implicit descriptive,
instrumental, and normative arguments.
One key problem has concerned the proper definition or scope of stakeholder-
ship. The. definitional controversy is not a minor matter. Freeman emphasized
capacity to affect or be affected by a focal firm (i.e., a broad concept of influence).
Rhenman (1964/1968) defined "stakeholders" more narrowly in terms of mutual
dependence. Jensen (2000) uses a narrow definition focused, in effect, on power
(he does not use that term) to "affect the welfare the firm" (p. 38). The Sloan Foun­
dation project has emphasized a broadened theory of property rights (relative to
stockholder doctrine) treating various stakeholders as (or "as if morally) holding
investments-at-risk in the focal firm. These claims are equal morally and practically
in importance to the investments of financial claimants. (The argument is that all
"investments" are equally necessary to success of the firm—see Clarkson Centre for
Business Ethics, 1999, 2000.)
A second problem has concerned the status of nature: can, and if so, should
nature be defined as or treated as if enjoying stakeholder rights or status? Jensen
(2000) is dubious. The alternative view, grounded ultimately in Kant, is that only
humans can be stakeholders, so that the role of nature must be apprehended in
terms of stakeholders' interests.
The Relationship of Stakeholder Practices to Wealth Creation. There are
conflicting views concerning the connection between stakeholder practices and
wealth creation. Jensen (2000) argues that "enlightened stakeholder practices" can
support wealth creation. Mayer (1996) argues that stakeholder practices in Europe
have come at an economic cost, such that stakeholder management and wealth
creation are not coincidental. Preston and Donaldson (1999) report that stakeholder

The International Journal of Organizational Analysis, Vol. 9, No. 3, 2001


D. WINDSOR 245

management practices can enhance "organizational wealth" defined as "the aggre­


gate value of a going concern."
Donaldson and Preston (1995) assert a redistribution of property rights as the
normative core of stakeholder theory. In contrast, the recent empirical evidence
suggests that managers behave in such a purely instrumental manner with respect to
stakeholders (see Agle, Mitchell, & Sonnenfeld, 1999; Ogden & Watson, 1999).
Sutton, Harris, Kaysen, and Tobin (1956) argued that social responsibility is
only a voluntary activity within the managerial creed and is not a "right" of the
recipients (cited by Preston, 1975, p. 435). Extending this argument to stakeholder
theory would leave practice susceptible to a purely instrumental approach for dis­
arming and exploiting stakeholders to the benefit of management (and through
fiduciary responsibility, to the benefit of investors). The relationship is then simply
one of relative power and its exercise.
Downloaded by Monash University At 07:49 06 December 2014 (PT)

The Prospects for Business Responsibility


The present edifice of business and society studies is undoubtedly ramshackle.
Even so, its moral and intellectual location is extraordinarily valuable "real estate."
(The author adapts here an oral statement by McKenzie, 2001). Corporate social
responsibility was the earliest notion in business and society studies (as post-game
philanthropy was the earliest notion in managerial philosophy). It is still in common
usage as a widely accepted "core construct" (Carroll, 1999) for academics and
managers.
The central issue is where to go with responsibility in the face of the compet­
ing alternatives discussed earlier. This section considers the following matters.
First, global operations raise far more complex responsibility issues. Second, the
two fundamentals of responsibility concern managerial psychology and a well-
defined normative framework for educating that psychology. Third, what matters
most is the morality and accountability of managers. The existing responsibility
construct does not successfully address that combination of key considerations. The
competing alternatives examined here are even less successful. They all emphasize
the leitmotif of wealth creation. The section ends with a discussion of implications
for responsibility theory and practice.
Global Enterprises
The context for corporate social responsibility has shifted to a world economy
in which multinational enterprises are key actors. Scherer and Smid (2000) argue
the case for why multinational enterprises "should take responsibility for the
improvement of world-wide social and environmental conditions" (p. 351). The
authors' basic thesis is that conditions are beyond the capabilities of governments
and must therefore be addressed by the world's multinational corporations. This
thesis flatly contradicts Adam Smith's (1776) caution concerning affecting to trade
for the public interest. It was argued elsewhare that serving the poor in developing
areas can be highly profitable business, as well as good sustainable development

The International Journal of Organizational Analysis, Vol. 9, No. 3, 2001


246 FUTURE OF CORPORATE SOCIAL RESPONSIBILITY-DRAFT

strategy. The poor are underserved due to lack of entrepreneurial innovativeness in


providing goods and services (Hamto, 2001).
Talisman Energy (in Calgary) is a Canadian firm operating in the war-torn
Sudan (where the non-Muslim black southern region seeks independence from an
Arab-dominated fundamentalist Islamic government), where the government may
be harboring al-Qaida terrorists ("Firm responds," 2001). Talisman has a 25 per­
cent stake in the Greater Nile Petroleum Operating Co., which produces oil in south
central Sudan. According to the news report cited here, the CEO, James Buckee,
stated (before the Royal Institute of International Affairs in London) that "it is
socially responsible for a corporation to invest in certain places that some elements
of popular opinion find objectionable." The statement argues that (1) opinion and
hence public policy are sharply divided on the issue, and (2) oil is important for the
development of the Sudan, ultimately contributing to peace in the region, and oil is
Downloaded by Monash University At 07:49 06 December 2014 (PT)

important to the functioning of the global economy. Mr. Buckee does not assert
laissez-faire theory but rather a position on social responsibility.
The World Bank and International Monetary Fund (IMF) were recently
expected to fund "a controversial energy project" in the West African countries of
Chad and Cameroon (Ivanovich, 2000). Oil fields in landlocked Chad with a pipe­
line to the Atlantic coast through neighboring Cameroon would transform the two
countries. An oil company spokesman stated: "We believe that the citizens of Chad
deserve the right to benefit from responsible development of their resources." The
opposition comes chiefly from environmentalists and human rights advocates con­
cerned with "possible disruption of the lifestyle of local Pygmies" and "long-term
survival of the black rhinoceros." Cameroon ranked worst globally on the 1999
Corruption Perceptions Index published by Transparency International (of Berlin),
and Chad has been through a civil war. Ivanovich characterizes both countries as
corrupt and abusive of human rights. (There have also been criticisms that the two
countries are receiving an inadequate share of the projected oil revenues.)
There are fundamental differences of opinions and values in the global econ­
omy, well beyond those found in U.S. domestic politics. Gilpin (1987) argues that
"ideologies of liberalism, nationalism, and Marxism have divided humanity" (and
continue to do so) and that "The conflict among these three moral and intellectual
positions has revolved around the role and significance of the market in the organi­
zation of society and economic affairs" (p. 25). (One might add anarchism, reli­
gious fundamentalism, and totalitarianism—but these ideologies concern control of
state power rather than economic organization.) "These three ideologies are funda­
mentally different in their conceptions of the relationships among society, state, and
market" (p. 25).
The context for the thesis may now have to embrace the origins and effects of
global terrorism (see Fish, 2001). Phillips (2001) argues that the essential strategy
in combating terrorism is "to change the environment" so as to minimize the supply
of "desperate or frustrated" young men "drawn to terrorism." (Phillips' forecast is
that a small supply of hundreds of terrorists can develop into a large supply of mil­
lions of terrorists.) Phillips does not explain in any detail how environmental

The International Journal of Organizational Analysis, Vol. 9, No. 3, 2001


D. WINDSOR 247

change is to be obtained. But logically his path may converge with Scherer and
Smid's argument concerning business global responsibilities.
Two Fundamentals of Social Responsibility
Corporate social responsibility reasoning must grapple with two fundamen­
tals. One fundamental is the prevailing psychology of the manager (see Donaldson,
1999). The other fundamental is a normative framework for addressing how that
psychology should be shaped.
What managers believe presumably affects how they behave. Much of the
business and society literature has aimed at shaping managerial psychology and
hence influencing exercise of any managerial discretion. Today's managers are
different, at least with respect to rhetoric concerning wealth creation for social wel­
fare improvement and acceptance of public policy limits on freedom of action, from
Downloaded by Monash University At 07:49 06 December 2014 (PT)

their laissez-faire predecessors of the 19th century.


A Fortune ("Fortune management," 1946) survey of business executives con­
cerned their social responsibilities where 93.5% of respondents agreed with the
statement that "social consciousness" meant being responsible for wider conse­
quences of business actions not measured in financial statements; 29.2% reported
half of businessmen had "social consciousness," 26.7% three-quarters, and 3% all.
That psychology has, however, yielded to the modem leitmotif of wealth
creation. Reich (1996) asserted that there was an "implicit social compact between
corporations, their employees and communities" for benefit sharing during the
1950s through the 1970s. That "compact" subsequently disappeared due to
increased competition (resulting from information technologies, deregulation,
global competition, and decline of market entry barriers). In Reich's words, "this
'electronic capitalism' has replaced the gentlemanly investment system that had
given 'industrial statesmen' the discretion to balance the interests of shareholders
against those of employees and communities." So characterized, such "discretion"
(cf. Wood, 1991) must have rested on both management autonomy from investor
controls and corporate market power relative to customers. Whitman (1999) argues
that power has shifted toward investors and consumers. These assertions by Reich
and Whitman suggest that markets are functioning more efficiently (i.e., immedi­
ately) than formerly. (Whether greater market efficiency, so defined, is socially
desirable is a different matter.) If so, the shift in power has been away from other
stakeholders, such as employees and communities.
The specific content of corporate social responsibility was always ambiguous
once one moved beyond establishing a kind of firewall against 19th century capi­
talist apologetics (see Preston, 1975, p. 434). The notion has been subject to multi­
ple interpretations (Votaw & Sethi, 1973, pp. 11-12).
The Committee on Economic Development (1971) defined social responsibil­
ity in terms of three concentric (i.e., nested) circles. The circles work outward from
economic function (e.g., products, jobs, growth) through awareness of changing
social values and priorities (e.g., environmental conservation, employee relations,
customer expectations) to newly emerging and amorphous responsibilities to

The International Journal of Organizational Analysis, Vol. 9, No. 3, 2001


248 FUTURE OF CORPORATE SOCIAL RESPONSIBILITY-DRAFT

improve pro-actively the social environment (e.g., poverty, urban blight). This
approach emphasized economic performance, defined more broadly than wealth
creation. It then diffuses into amorphous considerations, left by Jensen (2000) and
McWilliams and Siegel (2001a) to public policy.
Accountability and Morality of Managers
Both Dodd (1932) and Jensen (2000) favor making managers more account­
able to something external and arguably more objective. Dodd (Weiner, 1964) was
critical of increasing the discretionary responsibility of managers for stakeholders'
interests. Dodd advocated increasing the legal rights of consumers and employees,
in particular. Where they differ is that Jensen absorbs much of stakeholder reason­
ing directly into managerial choice, guided by value creation, whereas Dodd pre­
ferred something more reliable.
Downloaded by Monash University At 07:49 06 December 2014 (PT)

Davis (1960) viewed responsibility as nebulous but tied to long-term eco­


nomic return and stated an "Iron Law of Responsibility" requiring conduct com­
mensurate with social power of business. Davis (1973) offered the definition that
responsibility "refers to the firm's consideration of, and response to, issues beyond
the narrow economic, technical, and legal requirements of the firm" (p. 312). The
present author has argued here that it is difficult to distinguish responsibility and
responsiveness on such bases.
Corporate social responsibility was intendedly normative or value-concerned
in orientation. (Bowen's 1953 work was part of a six-volume study sponsored by
the Federal Council of Churches.) In this long and steady tradition, Donaldson and
Preston (1995) characterized stakeholder theory in terms of three separate but
linked dimensions organized like an onion: (1) a normative theory at the core; (2)
an instrumental theory serving as linkage beUveen core and surface; and (3) a
descriptive (empirical or behavioral) theory at the surface.
It matters greatly whether managers are moral. If corporate social responsibil­
ity in fact evolved in the 1920s as a managerial ideology (as argued by Mitchell,
1989), then what vouchsafes today's corporate citizenship movement unless modern
managers are truly different in motive (see Jackall, 1988, who characterizes corpo­
rate life in terms of moral mazes)? Carroll (1991), cited previously, suggests that
the supply of moral managers (those who embrace responsibility) is thin relative to
the supply of amoral managers (those who practice responsiveness as calculated
reputational strategy) and the supply of immoral managers (those who practice irre­
sponsible laissez-faire opportunism).
The distinguishing characteristic of economic, citizenship, and stakeholder
management approaches is their shared emphasis on an instrumental interpretation
of "responsibility." This emphasis is a vital shift in conceptualization and rhetoric
as well as in language, in the direction of managerial practice. In McWilliams and
Siegel's (2001a) treatment, management evaluates "demands" by stakeholders in
terms of bottom-line result. Only if a "demand" can be met at equal or higher profit,
should management "respond." An economic calculus takes place, within the law
(or public policy), to which all other considerations are assigned. McWilliams and
Siegel propose simply to define requirements at law (public policy embedding eco-

The International Journal of Organizational Analysis, Vol. 9, No. 3, 2001


D. WINDSOR 249

nomic as well as legal performance) and then to treat expectations and desires as
demands arising from particular stakeholder interests and subject only to an inves­
tor cost-benefit evaluation. Jensen views stakeholder interests in a broader (i.e.,
"enlightened") context, but only to the extent that managers' and employees' moti­
vations for effort are affected.
A response to this line of criticism is that made by Keynes (1936, p. 378), that
it was not the logic of classical economics that was at fault but rather the failure of
its tacit assumptions to correspond to the real world. The key difficulty in strong
economic cases for market action is that they tend to shunt the problems over to
public policy, while leaving firms (their managers and owners) free to influence
that context through the use of wealth. The approach reduces everything to markets
and laws, on a tacit assumption that the combination will work in the long run. Self-
interested managers, imbued with the mental model that capitalism is the salvation
Downloaded by Monash University At 07:49 06 December 2014 (PT)

of the world (cf. Werhane, 2000), akin to an "economic theology" (Heilbroner,


1953, p. 314, citing J. K. Galbraith), will simply treat all stakeholders as abstrac­
tions (see Selekman, 1958). And they will treat moral issues as subsumed within the
public policy process, itself subject to intervention by managers.
The instrumental view relies on the long-term dynamics of capitalist market
development and growth. Adam Smith (1776) suggested that rising wealth,
obtained through freer market exchange, released people's natural sympathies for
the situation of others. He also advised moral education.
The need for moral education of managers is as follows. There is, in addition
to the difficulties of externalities, information asymmetries, and monopolies, a per­
sistent tradeoff problem: "It is the dynamic nature of capitalism—very tough on
specific individuals in the short run, highly beneficial for almost everyone in the
long run. In place of the jobs lost will be new jobs from upstart companies and
from large companies that are doing well" (Tobias, 2001, p. 5). As Wilson (1989,
p. 63) points out, capitalism is not moral; but it has a morally desirable outcome,
reduction of poverty for many (not creation of wealth for some), in the long run. A
difficulty in this line of reasoning is that the long run may be so far off as not to
matter (cf. Keynes, 1936). Corporate social responsibility addresses short run
deviations between the interests of business and society.
Some Implications for Practice and Scholarship
This paper offers caveats concerning the future directions and prospects for
corporate social responsibility theory and practice. The management-friendly leit­
motif of wealth creation is progressively dominating scholarly conceptions of
responsibility. Part of the difficulty is that the responsibility construct is now
embedded within the broader corporate social performance (CSP) framework. The
embedding occurred partly due to criticisms of the responsibility construct, and
partly due to the perceived need to link responsibility and responsiveness con­
structs. Part of the difficulty is that managers are adhering to corporate citizenship
and stakeholder management views as instruments for wealth creation. Part of the
difficulty is a counter-reformation aimed at promoting a more economic conception
of responsibility along those wealth creation lines. Judgments of this sort involve,

The International Journal of Organizational Analysis, Vol. 9, No. 3, 2001


250 FUTURE OF CORPORATE SOCIAL RESPONSIBILITY-DRAFT

of course, subtleties; and one can reasonably depict a much more positive picture of
the situation. But given the increasing importance of the wealth creation leitmotif,
the present author selects caution over optimism.
A key difficulty is overturning the presumption in favor of wealth creation. As
Jensen (2000) rightly observes, there is 200 years of evidence for the long-run
wealth creation effects of freer market economies. Whether this evidence points in
the direction of a single-value objective function for managers is more debatable.
The empirical evidence on the financial performance effects of responsible behav­
ior is highly mixed (see especially McWilliams & Siegel, 2000). Griffin and Mahon
(1997) note methodological deficiencies in the literature. Verschoor (1998) con­
cludes that, among the 500 largest U.S. public corporations, the 26.8 percent com­
mitting in annual reports to ethical behavior toward stakeholders or compliance
with corporate code of conduct have higher financial performance measures than
Downloaded by Monash University At 07:49 06 December 2014 (PT)

the other firms that do not. But as noted previously, both Agle et al. (1999) and
Ogden and Watson (1999) concluded that managers appear to behave instrumen-
tally with respect to stakeholder practices. The caveats raised here have important
implications for managerial practice and academic scholarship.
Managers should understand that there are serious deviations between short
run impacts of business activities and the long run alignment of business and social
interests in wealth creation. These deviations leave ample scope for abuse of mar­
ket power and irresponsible conduct. The recent collapse of Enron Corp., which
was politically and philanthropically active, is a good illustration. The leitmotif of
wealth creation can easily lead to both moral misconduct and financial manipula­
tions ultimately destructive of social purposes and stakeholders' welfare. There is a
subtle attractiveness to substitute rhetorics of corporate citizenship and stakeholder
management. This attractiveness is due to the promise that such practices will align
reputation and wealth creation. A reasonable guide for the prudent manager may
well be that moral conduct is costly. Such a test is crystal clear.
Academic scholarship needs to reexamine the responsibility construct and its
role. A marked tendency in the relevant literature has been the willingness to
examine alternatives—such as citizenship or stakeholder management—precisely
because of the difficulties inherent in the responsibility construct. This tendency is
both good and bad. It is good in that it promotes continuing inquiry and an open­
ness to new ideas. It is bad in that it tends to step around the very difficulties inher­
ent in asking managers to be socially responsible. Guidance to managers is easy
where responsibility and wealth readily associate. Academic scholarship, both con­
ceptual and empirical, needs to focus more attention on what to do where responsi­
bility and wealth do not readily associate. The Enron collapse is a reminder that
such deviation is never far away in the increasingly competitive landscape of global
business operations.

The International Journal of Organizational Analysis, Vol. 9, No. 3, 2001


D.WINDSOR 251

References
Agle, B. R., Mitchell, R. K., & Sonnenfeld, J. A. (1999). Who matters to CEOs: An investi­
gation of stakeholder attributes and salience, corporate performance, and CEO values.
Academy of Management Journal, 42, 507-525.
American Law Institute. (1994). Principles of corporate governance: Analysis and recom­
mendations (Vol. 1 of 2, Pt. II.). St. Paul, MN: Author.
Andriof, J., Waddock, S., Rahman, S., & Husted, B. (Eds.) (in press). Special issue on
"Stakeholder Responsibility." Journal of Corporate Citizenship.
Banfield, E. C. (1985). Here the people rule: Selected essays. New York: Plenum Press.
Blair, M. M. (1995). Ownership and control: Rethinking corporate governance for the
twenty-first century. Washington, DC: Brookings Institution.
Blair, T. [Prime Minister]. (1996, January 13). Blair raises the stakes. Economist, p. 57.
Downloaded by Monash University At 07:49 06 December 2014 (PT)

Blum, W. J., & Kalven, H. (1970). The uneasy case for progressive taxation. Chicago: Uni­
versity of Chicago Press.
Bowden, A. R., Lane, M. R., & Martin, J. H. (2001). Triple bottom line risk management:
Enhancing profit, environmental performance, and community benefits. New York:
Wiley.
Bowen, H. R. (1948). Toward social economy. New York: Rinehart.
Bowen, H. R. (1953). Social responsibilities of the businessman. New York: Harper & Row.
Campbell, Α., & Alexander, M. (1997). What's wrong with strategy? Harvard Business
Review, 75 ( 6), 42-44, 46, 48-51.
Carnegie, A. (1900). The gospel of wealth, and other timely essays. New York: Century.
Carroll, A. B. (1979). A three-dimensional conceptual map of corporate performance. Acad­
emy of Management Review, 4, 497-505.
Carroll, Α. Β. (199Ι). The pyramid of corporate social responsibility: Toward the moral
management of organizational stakeholders. Business Horizons, 34 (4), 39-48.
Carroll, A. B. (1995). Stakeholder thinking in three models of management morality: A
perspective with strategic implications. In J. Näsi (Ed.), Understanding stakeholder
thinking (pp. 47-74). Helsinki, Finland: LSR-Publications.
Carroll, A. B. (1998). The four faces of corporate citizenship. Business and Society Review,
100/101, 1-7.
Carroll, A. B. (1999). Corporate social responsibility: Evolution of a definitional construct.
Business & Society, 38, 268-295.
Chernow, R. (1999, October 10). Learning from robber barons. Houston Chronicle, pp. 3C,
5C.
Clark, J. M. (1916). The changing basis of economic responsibility. Journal of Political
Economy, 243, 209-229.
Clarkson, Μ. Β. Ε. (1995). A stakeholder framework for analyzing and evaluating corporate
social performance. Academy of Management Review, 20, 92-117.
Clarkson Centre for Business Ethics. (1999). Principles of stakeholder management.
Toronto: University of Toronto.
Clarkson Centre for Business Ethics. (2000). Research in stakeholder theory, 1997-1998.
Toronto: University of Toronto.
Committee for Economic Development (CED). (1971). Social responsibilities of business
corporations. New York: Author.
Conference Board. (1999). 77îe expanding parameters of global corporate citizenship
(Report No. 1246). New York: Author.

The International Journal of Organizational Analysis, Vol. 9, No. 3, 2001


252 FUTURE OF CORPORATE SOCIAL RESPONSIBILITY-DRAFT

Constitutional rights of the corporate person. (1982). Yale Law Journal, 91, 1641-1658.
Davenport, K. (2000). Corporate citizenship: A stakeholder approach for defining corporate
social performance and identifying measures for assessing it. Business & Society, 39,
210-219.
Davis, K. (1960). Can business afford to ignore social responsibilities? California Manage­
ment Review, 2 (3), 70-76.
Davis, K. (1967). Understanding the social responsibility puzzle: What does the business­
man owe to society? Business Horizons, 10 (4), 45-50.
Davis, K. (1973). The case for and against business assumption of social responsibilities.
Academy of Management Journal, 16, 312-322.
Dey Report. (1994). Where are the directors? Guidelines for improved corporate govern­
ance in Canada. Toronto: Toronto Stock Exchange Committee on Corporate Govern­
ance in Canada.
Dodd, Ε. Μ. (1932). For whom are corporate managers trustees? Harvard Law Review, 45,
Downloaded by Monash University At 07:49 06 December 2014 (PT)

1145-1163.
Donaldson, T. (1999). Making stakeholder theory whole. Academy of Management Review,
24, 237-241.
Donaldson, T., & Preston, L. E. (1995). The stakeholder theory of the corporation. Academy
of Management Review, 20, 65-91.
Drucker, P. F. (1984). The new meaning of corporate social responsibility. California Man­
agement Review, 26, 53-63.
Drucker, P. F. (1999). Management challenges for the 21st century. New York: Harper-
Business.
Elkington, J. (1998). Cannibals with forks: The triple bottom line of 21st century business.
Gabriola Creek, BC: New Society.
Epstein, Ε. Μ. (1987). The corporate social policy process: Beyond business ethics, corpo­
rate social responsibility, and corporate social responsiveness. California Management
Review. 29 (3), 99-114.
Firm responds to terrorist. (2001, October 21). Houston Chronicle, p. 3D.
Fish, S. (2001, October 21). Is terrorism relative? To serious thinkers, it is. Houston Chroni­
cle, p. 4C.
Fombrun, C. J. (1997). Three pillars of corporate citizenship: Ethics social benefit, profit­
ability. In N. M. Tichy, A. R. McGillis, & L. St. Clair (Eds.), Corporate global citizen­
ship: Doing business in the public eye (pp. 27—42). San Francisco: New Lexington
Press.
Fortune management poll. (1946, March). Fortune, pp. 197-198.
Frederick, W. C. (1986). Toward CSR3: Why ethical analysis is indispensable and unavoid­
able in corporate affairs. California Management Review, 28 (2), 126-141.
Frederick, W. C. (1994). From CSR1 to CSR2. Business & Society, 33, 150-164.
Frederick, W. C. (1998). Moving to CSR4: What to pack for the trip. Business & Society,
37, 40-59.
Freeman, R. E. (1984). Strategic management: A stakeholder approach. Boston: Pitman.
Friedman, M. (1962). Capitalism andfreedom. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Friedman, M. (1970, September 13). The social responsibility of business is to increase its
profits. New York Times Magazine, pp. 32-33, 122, 124, 126.
Gilpin, R. (1987). The political economy of international relations. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Griffin, J. J., & Mahon, J. F. (1997). The corporate social performance and corporate finan­
cial performance debate: Twenty-five years of incomparable research. Business & Soci­
ety, 36, 5-31.

The International Journal of Organizational Analysis, Vol. 9, No. 3, 2001


D. WINDSOR 253

Hampel Report. (1998). Committee on corporate governance: Final report. London:


Author.
Hamto, M. (2001, October 25). Serving the poor is good business, says strategy guru Pra-
halad. Rice News, p. 6.
Heilbroner, R. L. (1953). The worldly philosophers: The lives, times, and ideas of the great
economic thinkers. New York: Simon and Schuster.
Hicks, L. (1996, May 8). Caterpillar flunks corporate citizenship test. York Dispatch, p. A7.
Husted, B., & Salazer, J. de J. (2001). Taking Friedman seriously: Maximizing profits and
social performance. Proceedings of the International Association for Business and Soci­
ety, 12, 86-90.
Ivanovich, D. (2000, June 6). OK for African oil project expected, But its impact on two
impoverished nations debated. Houston Chronicle, pp. 1C, 5C.
Jackall, R. (1988). Moral mazes: The world of corporate managers. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Jenks, J. W. (1917). Business and the government. New York: Alexander Hamilton Institute.
Jensen, M. C. (2000). Value maximization and the corporate objective function. In M. Beer
Downloaded by Monash University At 07:49 06 December 2014 (PT)

& N. Nohria (Eds.), Breaking the code of change (pp. 37-57). Boston: Harvard Busi­
ness School Press.
Kang, Y. C., & Wood, D. J. (1995). Before-profit social responsibility: Turning the eco­
nomic paradigm upside down. Proceedings of the International Association for Busi­
ness and Society, 6, 408-418.
Keynes, J. M. (1936). The general theory of employment, interest and money. New York:
Harcourt, Brace.
Kreps, T. J. (1940). Measurement of the social performance of business. In An investigation
of concentration of economic power (Temporary National Economic Committee,
Monograph No. 7). Washington, DC: U.S. Government Printing Office.
Levitt, T. (1958). The dangers of social responsibility. Harvard Business Review, 36 (5),
10-19.
Levitt, T. (1973). The third sector. New York: AMACOM.
Logan, D., Delwin, R., & Regelbrugge, L. (1997). Global corporate citizenship—rationale
and strategies. Washington, DC: Hitachi Foundation.
McKenzie, Κ. D. (2001, July). War stories from the trenches. Paper presented at the 8th
annual International Conference on Advances in Management, Athens, Greece.
Manne, H. G., & Wallich, H. C. (1972). The modern corporation and social responsibility.
Washington, DC: American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research.
Mayer, C. (1996). Corporate governance, competition and performance. Paris: OECD Eco­
nomics Department, WP-164.
McTaggart, J. M., Kontes, P. W., & Mankins, M. C. (1994). The value imperative: Manag­
ing for superior shareholder returns. New York: Free Press.
McWilliams, Α., & Siegel, D. (2000). Corporate social responsibility and financial perform­
ance: Correlation or misspecification? Strategic Management Journal, 21, 603-609.
McWilliams, Α., & Siegel, D. (2001a). Corporate social responsibility: A theory of the firm
perspective. Academy of Management Review, 26, 117-127.
McWilliams, Α., & Siegel, D. (2001b). Profit-maximizing corporate social responsibility.
Academy of Management Review, 26, 504-505.
Miller, A. S. (1968). The Supreme Court and American capitalism. New York: Free Press.
Mitchell, N. J. (1989). The generous corporation: A political analysis of economic power.
New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

The International Journal of Organizational Analysis, Vol. 9, No. 3, 2001


254 FUTURE OF CORPORATE SOCIAL RESPONSIBILITY-DRAFT

Oberman, W. D. (2000). Review of Mitchell (1997). Business & Society, 39, 239-244.
Ogden, S., & Watson, R. (1999). Corporate performance and stakeholder management: Bal­
ancing shareholder and customer interests in the U.K. privatized water industry. Acad­
emy of Management Journal, 42, 526-538.
Orts, Ε. C. (1992). Beyond shareholders: Interpreting corporate constituency statutes.
George Washington Law Review, 61, 14-135.
Peters Report. (1997). Corporate governance in the Netherlands: Forty recommendations.
Amsterdam, Netherlands: Committee on Corporate Governance.
Phillips, C. V. (2001, October 26). Drain swamps that breed millions of new terrorists.
Houston Chronicle, pp. 1C, 5C.
Preston, I . E. (1975). Corporation and society: The search for a paradigm. Journal of Eco­
nomic Literature, 13, 434-453.
Preston, L. E., & Donaldson, T. (1999). Stakeholder management and organizational wealth.
Academy of Management Review, 24, 619-620.
Preston, L. E., & Mihalko, D. (1999). Corporate responsibility: Comparative analysis of
current documents. In Clarkson Centre for Business Ethics (Ed.), Principles of stake­
Downloaded by Monash University At 07:49 06 December 2014 (PT)

holder management (pp. 21-59). Toronto, University of Toronto.


Preston, L. E., & Post, J. E. (1975). Private management and public policy: The principle of
public responsibility. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Reich, R. B. (1996, February 6). Pink slips, profits, and paychecks: Corporate citizenship in
an era of smaller government. Address at School of Business and Public Management,
George Washington University.
Reuters News Service. (2001, July 27). Tobacco firm apologizes over Czech smoking study.
Houston Chronicle, p. 3C.
The revolutionary spirit: Jack Welch, GE and creative destruction. (1999, September 18-
24). Economist, pp. 17-18, 23-26.
Rhenman, E. (1968). Industrial democracy and industrial management (N. Adler, Trans.).
London: Tavistock. (Original work published 1964)
Rhenman, R., & B. Stymne. (1965). Corporate management in a changing world. Stock­
holm: Aldus/Bonniers. (Swedish only)
Samuelson, P. A. (1971, Spring). Love that corporation. Mountain Bell Magazine, p. 24.
Scherer, A. G., & Smid, M. (2000). The downward spiral and the US Model Business Prin­
ciples—why MNEs should take responsibility for the improvement of world-wide social
and environmental conditions. Management International Review, 40, 351-371.
Selekman, B. M. (1958). Is management creating a class society? Harvard Business Review,
36 (1), 37-46.
Smith, A. (1776). An inquiry into the nature and causes of the wealth of nations. New York:
Modern Library. (Edited by E. Cannan, 1937)
Spencer, H. (1851). Social statics or, the conditions essential to human happiness specified,
and the first of them developed. London: John Chapman.
Sternberg, E. (1994). Just business: Business ethics in action. Boston: Little, Brown.
Sternberg, E. (1996). Stakeholder theory exposed. Corporate Governance Quarterly (Hong
Kong), 2, 4-18.
Sternberg, E. (1999). The stakeholder concept: A mistaken doctrine. In Foundation for
Business Responsibilities (SSRN Electronic Paper Collection Retrieved March 27,
2001, from website: http://papers.ssrn.com/paper.taf?abstract_id=263144.
Sutton, F. X., Harris, S. E., Kaysen, C., & Tobin, J. (1956). The American business creed.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

The International Journal of Organizational Analysis, Vol. 9, No. 3, 2001


D. WINDSOR 255

Swanson, D. L. (1995). Addressing a theoretical problem by reorienting the corporate social


performance model. Academy of Management Review, 20, 43-64.
Tichy, N. M., McGill, A. R., & St. Clair, L. (Eds.). (1997). Corporate global citizenship:
Doing business in the public eye. San Francisco: New Lexington Press.
Tindall, G. B. (1988). America: A narrative history (2nd ed.). New York: W. W. Norton.
Tobias, A. (2001, August 12). What the economy means to you. Houston Chronicle Parade
Magazine, pp. 4-5.
Tully, S. (1993, September 20). The real key to creating wealth. Fortune, pp. 38-40, 44-45,
48, 50.
U.S. Department of Commerce, Task Force on Corporate Social Performance. (1980). Busi-
ness and society: Strategies for the 1980s—Report of the Task Force on Corporate
Social Performance. Washington, DC: U.S. Government Printing Office.
Verschoor, C. C. (1998). A study of the link between a corporation's financial performance
and its commitment of ethics. Journal of Business Ethics, 17, 1509-1516.
Vidal, D. J. (1999). The link between corporate citizenship and financial performance
(Report No. 1234). New York: Conference Board.
Downloaded by Monash University At 07:49 06 December 2014 (PT)

Votaw, D., & Sethi, S. P. (1973). The corporate dilemma. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-
Hall.
Weiner, J. L. (1964). The Berle-Dodd dialogue on the concept of the corporation. Columbia
Law Review, 64, 1458-1467.
Werhane, P. H. (2000). Exporting mental models: Global capitalism in the 21st century.
Business Ethics Quarterly, 10, 353-362.
Whitman, M. v. N. (1999). New world, new rules: The changing role of the American cor-
poration. Boston: Harvard Business School Press.
Wilson, J. Q. (1989). Adam Smith on business ethics. California Management Review, 32
(1), 59-71.
Windsor, D. (1999). Can stakeholder interests be balanced? Proceedings of the Interna-
tional Association for Business and Society, 10, 476-481.
Windsor, D. (2001a). Corporate citizenship: Evolution and interpretation. In J. Andriof &
M. Mcintosh (Eds.), Perspectives on corporate citizenship (pp. 39-52). Sheffield, UK:
Greenleaf.
Windsor, D. (2001b). Corporate social responsibility: A theory of the firm perspective:
Some comments. Academy of Management Review, 26, 502-504.
Wood, D. J. (1991). Corporate social performance revisited. Academy of Management
Review, 16, 691-718.
World Business Council for Sustainable Development. (1999). Meeting changing expecta-
tions: Corporate social responsibility. Retrieved October 10, 2001, from website:
http://www.wbcsd.ch.
World Business Council for Sustainable Development. (2000). Corporate social responsi-
bility: Good business sense. Retrieved October 10, 2001, from website
http://www.wbcsd.ch.
Wright, M. A. (1967). The business of business: Private enterprise and public affairs. New
York: McGraw-Hill.

The Internationaljournal of Organizational Analysis, Vol. 9, No. 3, 2001


256 FUTURE OF CORPORATE SOCIAL RESPONSIBILITY-DRAFT

Biographical Note
Duane Windsor
Jones Graduate School of Management
Rice University
Houston, TX 77251-1892
Phone/Fax: 713-348-5372/5251
Email: odw@rice.edu
Dr. Windsor (Ph.D., Harvard University) is Lynette S. Autrey Professor of Management.
He is an alumnus of Rice University (B.A.). He teaches business ethics and leadership in the
Executive MBA program, and organizational politics in the regular MBA program. His
research focuses on corruption, corporate citizenship, social responsibility, and stakeholder
theory.
Received: August 15, 2001
Downloaded by Monash University At 07:49 06 December 2014 (PT)

Accepted by M. A. Rahim after three revisions: February 1, 2002


TheInternationalJournalof Organizational Analysis, Vol. 9, No. 3, 2001


This article has been cited by:

1. Kenneth Amaeshi, Emmanuel Adegbite, Tazeeb Rajwani. 2014. Corporate Social Responsibility in
Challenging and Non-enabling Institutional Contexts: Do Institutional Voids matter?. Journal of
Business Ethics . [CrossRef]
2. Martin Brueckner, Angela Durey, Christof Pforr, Robyn Mayes. 2014. The civic virtue of
developmentalism: on the mining industry's political licence to develop Western Australia. Impact
Assessment and Project Appraisal 32, 315-326. [CrossRef]
3. Zahid A. Memon, Yi-Ming Wei, Mark Gregory Robson, Muhammad Aamir Obaid Khattak. 2014.
Keeping track of ‘corporate social responsibility’ as a business and management discipline: case of
Pakistan. Journal of Cleaner Production 74, 27-34. [CrossRef]
4. Russell Lacey, Pamela A. Kennett-Hensel, Chris Manolis. 2014. Is corporate social responsibility a
motivator or hygiene factor? Insights into its bivalent nature. Journal of the Academy of Marketing
Science . [CrossRef]
5. Yunhee Kim, Christian Brodhag, Desta Mebratu. 2014. Corporate social responsibility driven
Downloaded by Monash University At 07:49 06 December 2014 (PT)

innovation. Innovation: The European Journal of Social Science Research 27:2, 175-196. [CrossRef]
6. Chung Hee Kim, Kenneth Amaeshi, Simon Harris, Chang-Jin Suh. 2013. CSR and the national
institutional context: The case of South Korea. Journal of Business Research 66:12, 2581-2591.
[CrossRef]
7. Najah Attig, Sadok El Ghoul, Omrane Guedhami, Jungwon Suh. 2013. Corporate Social
Responsibility and Credit Ratings. Journal of Business Ethics 117:4, 679-694. [CrossRef]
8. Taru Vuontisjärvi. 2013. Argumentation and socially questionable business practices: The case of
employee downsizing in corporate annual reports. Scandinavian Journal of Management 29, 292-313.
[CrossRef]
9. Matthew Walker, Haylee Mercado. 2013. The Resource-worthiness of Environmental
Responsibility: A Resource-based Perspective. Corporate Social Responsibility and Environmental
Management n/a-n/a. [CrossRef]
10. Jon Burchell, Joanne Cook. 2013. CSR, Co-optation and Resistance: The Emergence of New
Agonistic Relations Between Business and Civil Society. Journal of Business Ethics 115:4, 741-754.
[CrossRef]
11. Pål StrandbakkenEmerging Technologies and Democracy 3-16. [CrossRef]
12. Vlasios SarantinosEthics, CSR and MNCs: Establishing the Link with HRM in Times of Economic
Crisis 205-222. [Abstract] [Full Text] [PDF]
13. Andromachi Athanasopoulou. 2012. Managers' Corporate Social Responsibility Perceptions and
Attitudes across Different Organizational Contexts within the Non-Profit–For-Profit Organizational
Continuum. Journal of Change Management 12:4, 467-494. [CrossRef]
14. Suthisak Kraisornsuthasinee. 2012. CSR through the heart of the Bodhi tree. Social Responsibility
Journal 8:2, 186-198. [Abstract] [Full Text] [PDF]
15. Les Tien‐Shang Lee. 2012. The pivotal roles of corporate environment responsibility. Industrial
Management & Data Systems 112:3, 466-483. [Abstract] [Full Text] [PDF]
16. Yongqiang Gao. 2011. Philanthropic disaster relief giving as a response to institutional pressure:
Evidence from China. Journal of Business Research 64:12, 1377-1382. [CrossRef]
17. Rosamaria C. Moura‐Leite, Robert C. Padgett. 2011. Historical background of corporate social
responsibility. Social Responsibility Journal 7:4, 528-539. [Abstract] [Full Text] [PDF]
18. Jacquie L'Etang, Jairo Lugo-Ocando, Zeti Azreen AhmadEthics 167-187. [CrossRef]
19. Chris Mason, John Simmons. 2011. Forward looking or looking unaffordable? Utilising academic
perspectives on corporate social responsibility to assess the factors influencing its adoption by
business. Business Ethics: A European Review 20:2, 159-176. [CrossRef]
20. Leslie E. Sekerka, Derek Stimel. 2011. How durable is sustainable enterprise? Ecological
sustainability meets the reality of tough economic times. Business Horizons 54:2, 115-124. [CrossRef]
21. Paul K. Shum, Sharon L. Yam. 2011. Ethics and Law: Guiding the Invisible Hand to Correct
Corporate Social Responsibility Externalities. Journal of Business Ethics 98:4, 549-571. [CrossRef]
22. Dr Jon Burchell, Dr Joanne Cook, André H.J. Nijhof, Ronald J.M. Jeurissen. 2010. The glass
ceiling of corporate social responsibility. International Journal of Sociology and Social Policy 30:11/12,
618-631. [Abstract] [Full Text] [PDF]
23. Faruk Merali. 2010. Does the explicit recognition of the commitment and contribution of staff
within an organisation's CSR strategy matter?. Social Responsibility Journal 6:4, 492-509. [Abstract]
[Full Text] [PDF]
Downloaded by Monash University At 07:49 06 December 2014 (PT)

24. Martin Brueckner, Mohammed Abdullah Mamun. 2010. Living downwind from corporate social
responsibility: a community perspective on corporate practice. Business Ethics: A European Review
19:4, 326-348. [CrossRef]
25. Marjo E. Siltaoja, Meri J. Vehkaperä. 2010. Constructing Illegitimacy? Cartels and Cartel
Agreements in Finnish Business Media from Critical Discursive Perspective. Journal of Business Ethics
92:4, 493-511. [CrossRef]
26. Mario Fernando. 2010. Corporate social responsibility in the wake of the Asian tsunami: Effect of
time on the genuineness of CSR initiatives. European Management Journal 28:1, 68-79. [CrossRef]
27. Tyler Earle Wry. 2009. Does Business and Society Scholarship Matter to Society? Pursuing a
Normative Agenda with Critical Realism and Neoinstitutional Theory. Journal of Business Ethics
89:2, 151-171. [CrossRef]
28. Belaid Rettab, Anis Ben Brik, Kamel Mellahi. 2009. A Study of Management Perceptions of the
Impact of Corporate Social Responsibility on Organisational Performance in Emerging Economies:
The Case of Dubai. Journal of Business Ethics 89:3, 371-390. [CrossRef]
29. Faruk Merali. 2009. Managing within the challenges and tensions facing the twenty‐first century UK
National Health Service (NHS): the dilemma of a managerial identity within the context of a socially
responsible organization. Social Responsibility Journal 5:2, 152-164. [Abstract] [Full Text] [PDF]
30. Maria Aluchna, Sudhir Chandra Das. 2009. Status and direction of corporate social responsibility
in Indian perspective: an exploratory study. Social Responsibility Journal 5:1, 34-47. [Abstract] [Full
Text] [PDF]
31. Jeremy Galbreath. 2009. Building corporate social responsibility into strategy. European Business
Review 21:2, 109-127. [Abstract] [Full Text] [PDF]
32. Andy Adcroft, Jon Teckman, Geoff Walters, Simon Chadwick. 2009. Corporate citizenship in
football: delivering strategic benefits through stakeholder engagement. Management Decision 47:1,
51-66. [Abstract] [Full Text] [PDF]
33. Ron Cacioppe, Nick Forster, Michael Fox. 2008. A Survey of Managers’ Perceptions of Corporate
Ethics and Social Responsibility and Actions that may Affect Companies’ Success. Journal of Business
Ethics 82:3, 681-700. [CrossRef]
34. Dima Jamali. 2008. A Stakeholder Approach to Corporate Social Responsibility: A Fresh Perspective
into Theory and Practice. Journal of Business Ethics 82:1, 213-231. [CrossRef]
35. George Z. Peng, Paul W. Beamish. 2008. The Effect of National Corporate Responsibility
Environment on Japanese Foreign Direct Investment. Journal of Business Ethics 80:4, 677-695.
[CrossRef]
36. Richard Marens. 2008. Recovering the past: reviving the legacy of the early scholars of corporate
social responsibility. Journal of Management History 14:1, 55-72. [Abstract] [Full Text] [PDF]
37. Michelle Greenwood. 2007. Stakeholder Engagement: Beyond the Myth of Corporate
Responsibility. Journal of Business Ethics 74:4, 315-327. [CrossRef]
38. Jan Lepoutre, Nikolay A. Dentchev, Aimé Heene. 2007. Dealing With Uncertainties When
Governing CSR Policies. Journal of Business Ethics 73:4, 391-408. [CrossRef]
39. Jennifer Oetzel, Kathleen A. Getz, Stephen Ladek. 2007. The Role of Multinational Enterprises
in Responding to Violent Conflict: A Conceptual Model and Framework for Research. American
Business Law Journal 44:2, 331-358. [CrossRef]
40. Mohd Rafi Yaacob, Loong Wong. 2007. Stakeholders' Activisms: Indigenous Peoples' of Sarawak
Resistance against the State Government and Corporations. Social Responsibility Journal 3:2, 39-51.
[Abstract] [PDF]
Downloaded by Monash University At 07:49 06 December 2014 (PT)

41. Dima Jamali, Ramez Mirshak. 2007. Corporate Social Responsibility (CSR): Theory and Practice
in a Developing Country Context. Journal of Business Ethics 72:3, 243-262. [CrossRef]
42. DIMA JAMALI. 2007. The Case for Strategic Corporate Social Responsibility in Developing
Countries. Business and Society Review 112:1, 1-27. [CrossRef]
43. Mario Fernando. 2007. Corporate Social Responsibility in the Wake of the Asian Tsunami:.
European Management Journal 25:1, 1-10. [CrossRef]
44. Kenneth M. Amaeshi, Bongo Adi. 2007. Reconstructing the corporate social responsibility construct
in Utlish. Business Ethics: A European Review 16:1, 3-18. [CrossRef]
45. Christopher Seow, Ruth Hillary, D. Jamali. 2006. Insights into triple bottom line integration from
a learning organization perspective. Business Process Management Journal 12:6, 809-821. [Abstract]
[Full Text] [PDF]
46. Marjo Elisa Siltaoja. 2006. Value Priorities as Combining Core Factors Between CSR and Reputation
– A Qualitative Study. Journal of Business Ethics 68:1, 91-111. [CrossRef]
47. Faruk Merali. 2006. Developing an explicit strategy towards social responsibility in the NHS. Journal
of Health Organization and Management 20:4, 309-324. [Abstract] [Full Text] [PDF]
48. Michaela Driver. 2006. Beyond the Stalemate of Economics versus Ethics: Corporate Social
Responsibility and the Discourse of the Organizational Self. Journal of Business Ethics 66:4, 337-356.
[CrossRef]
49. Rute Abreu, Fátima David, David Crowther. 2005. Corporate social responsibility in Portugal:
empirical evidence of corporate behaviour. Corporate Governance: The international journal of business
in society 5:5, 3-18. [Abstract] [Full Text] [PDF]
50. Professor Michael Jay Polonsky, Frédéric Jallat, Elliot Wood. 2005. Exploring “deep” and “wide”
stakeholder relations in service activity. European Journal of Marketing 39:9/10, 1013-1024.
[Abstract] [Full Text] [PDF]
51. Simon Knox, Stan Maklan, Paul French. 2005. Corporate Social Responsibility: Exploring
Stakeholder Relationships and Programme Reporting across Leading FTSE Companies. Journal of
Business Ethics 61:1, 7-28. [CrossRef]
52. Faruk Merali. 2005. NHS managers’ commitment to a socially responsible role: the NHS managers'
views of their core values and their public image. Social Responsibility Journal 1:1/2, 38-46. [Abstract]
[PDF]

You might also like