You are on page 1of 17

Topics in Linguistics - Issue 16 – December 2015

DOI: 10.2478/topling-2015-0010

Je ne suis pas Charlie. Metadiscourses of


impoliteness following “France’s 9/11” in
selected print media
Milan Ferenčík
University of Prešov, Slovakia

Abstract
Almost immediately after the Charlie Hebdo shootings of 7 January 2015, some print media
made room for alternative opinions of what had happened. The articles and the discussions
they inspired are replete with evaluations which lend themselves to analysis using methods
and procedures of Politeness Theory. The paper examines an example of a metadiscourse of
(im)politeness which questions the “moral orders” underlying the cartoonists’ as well as
other participants’ social practices vis-à-vis their ideological foundations, esp. freedom of
speech as one of the principal liberties of our society. To that end, the approach to
politeness as “social practice” is employed which, while insisting on multiple understandings
of politeness, places participants’ evaluations at the centre of politeness research.

Keywords
Charlie Hebdo shooting, impoliteness, metacomment, politeness as discursive struggle,
politeness as social practice

Introduction aggression which was extensively covered in


The quote from my example of a European mainstream mass media and
metadiscourse, i.e. a discourse about ultimately invited audiences to take
discourse(s), succinctly formulates the positions. The “Charlie Hebdo discourses”
position in which many people seemed to almost immediately polarized the European
become “trapped” following the deadly populace along two opposing memes: Je suis
attacks on Charlie Hebdo’s staff on 7 January Charlie and Je ne suis pas Charlie. While the
2015 and who, while decrying the murders, former sprang out as an immediate and
did not approve of Charlie Hebdo’s satirical spontaneous negative evaluation of the
journalistic practices which preceded them. infamous violent act and sought to become
By drawing our attention to the tension primarily an expression of solidarity with the
between the illocutionary force of the victims and identification with the values
cartoons depicting the prophet and the which they professed, esp. freedom of
social goals which they were perceived to speech, the latter began to express a critical
meet, viz. that of a face-attack, the quote position towards this identification by
invokes the role of evaluations of others’ pinpointing the fact that freedom is not
behaviour, as well as our own, which are without limits. The “Charlie Hebdo
made against the background of the norms discourses” which appeared on the pages of
that have been established in the print media and in the discussion fora
sociocultural groups to which the evaluators underneath the articles are rich in
claim to belong. The killings, and the evaluations addressing the
ensuing developments over the following (in)appropriateness of this violent act, as
months, further aggravated an already tense well as of the Charlie Hebdo practices
atmosphere in Europe and added another regarded as having engendered it, and thus
layer of discourse about violence and offer possibilities of insight into how societal

42
Unauthenticated
Download Date | 4/4/17 9:45 PM
Topics in Linguistics - Issue 16 – December 2015

norms are “struggled over” vis-à-vis the expanded the “Be polite” rule by further
identities taken up by the actors of these specifying the three sub-rules, viz. “Don’t
disputes. The lexical-semantic layer of these impose”, “Give options” and “Make [alter] feel
discourses testifies to the actors’ good – be friendly”. Through her ground-
metapragmatic awareness and offers breaking study Lakoff delineated many of
analysts a wealth of pragmatic data for the future developments in politeness theory
scrutiny. My goal in the paper is to use the and practice, especially in its “classic”
methods and procedures resulting from period. A similar task of developing Grice’s
current approaches within Politeness Theory ingenious remark was tackled by Leech
(PT) and to demonstrate their feasibility in (1983), who devised the “Politeness
accounting for how debates following a Principle” as a finer system of six politeness
major societal disruption lead to a maxims based on several pragmatic scales,
reassessment of the underlying system of and placed it alongside Grice’s Co-operative
values upon which sociocultural groups are Principle within his more general framework
founded. of “Interpersonal Rhetoric”. Both Lakoff and
Leech represent the core pragmatic
1. Politeness Theory – an overview approaches to politeness by assuming that
In the course of just over forty years the area interlocutors behave rationally, i.e. use
within pragmatics known as PT has not only means-ends reasoning to calculate why their
gone through an emergence, rapid rise and partners depart from co-operation. For both
extensive growth of empirical research but authors, politeness is a constraint on human
also through a rethinking of its major tenets behaviour which is motivated by the need to
and approaches, until it has stabilized into a minimize conflict and/or confrontation
fully-fledged multidisciplinary domain of (Lakoff) and avoid discord/maintain concord
social research. It grew in the latter half of (Leech).
the past century as a reaction to the The bias towards the “polite” dimension of
“pragmatic turn” which brought about a interpersonal relationships also marks the
reorientation of research focus from langue third approach to politeness in the triad of
to parole and from linguistic to politeness classics, viz. Brown and
communicative competence. Ever since, Levinson’s (1978/87) model, which became
politeness thinking and practice has been and has remained the most influential, best
seen as evolving in three “waves” of known and most widely used ever since it
approaches (Grainger 2011). was conceived (1978) and reworked (1987).
The concepts they proposed form the
1.1 The first-wave approaches – the conceptual basis of PT and have become
classic/pragmatic period widely known outside the discipline. Among
Lakoff (1973), the pioneer of politeness them, the social-psychological concept of
research, found pragmatic rules of well- “face” (which they took over from Goffman
formedness on a par with those of a (1955)) occupies a central place, along with
syntactic nature which controlled syntactic other terms such as “positive face”, “negative
well-formedness and which, ultimately, face”, “face-threatening act” and several
determined the grammatical competence of others. Like Lakoff and Leech, Brown and
an ideal speaker/hearer, who was the Levinson also view politeness as the
primary focus of interest of Chomskyan strategically planned, rational behaviour of a
linguistics. Lakoff used the insight of the “model person”1 aimed at countering a
advances in ordinary language philosophy,
viz. Austin’s Speech Act Theory and Grice’s 1
In Politeness Theory, the notion of a Model
Co-operative Principle, and incorporated Person represents a construct of an ideal
them into her model of pragmatic interlocutor who is assigned the capacity to
competence. While Grice himself made only rationalize from communicative goals to
a passing note that, besides the maxims of expressive means and, when trying to be
quality, quantity, manner and relevance “polite”, to use those strategies which
there are possibly other maxims in consider the hearer’s face wants. Thus, the
operation, such as the politeness maxim, it five politeness strategies as suggested by
was Lakoff who was the first to explicitly Brown and Levinson (1987) are the result of
formulate the “Be polite” rule as the second the Model Person’s rational means-ends
of the two pragmatic rules (the first being reasoning through which he departs from
Grice’s Co-operative Principle in the guise of the maximum efficiency, and “sacrifices”
the formulation “Be clear”). Lakoff later cooperation (as captured in Grice’s

43
Unauthenticated
Download Date | 4/4/17 9:45 PM
Topics in Linguistics - Issue 16 – December 2015

potentially adverse impact upon one’s face. (which betrayed a strong Speech Act Theory
The face-threat inherent, as they claim, in influence) produced by the speaker and their
virtually any type of behaviour is to be emphasis on the production pole of a
averted or at least minimized by a strategy communication event, and ultimately, a
chosen from an array of choices which possible lack of correspondence between
rational users have at their disposal. These theoretical and lay understanding of what
unprecedentedly detailed strategies led to an polite behaviour is. Efforts to rectify the
upsurge of research into politeness issues problems inherent in the “classic” period of
worldwide. politeness research were made in the
The criticism levelled at the pragmatic subsequent decades.
foundations of the models was principally
directed at their Western bias, which was 1.2 The second-wave approaches – the
claimed to be present in the rationality- post-pragmatic period
based behaviour of an individual and also in In the early 1990s the first seeds of a
the conception of individual face2 which substantial shift in politeness theorizing
promoted Western values. Brown and were sown and new trends in its scope and
Levinson’s claims for universality were methodology were forecast. Watts et al.
contested and challenged especially by non- (1992) were among the first to suggest that
Western researchers. Other criticism was politeness is a “marked surplus”
made about the focus on isolated utterances phenomenon that is identifiable against a
background of unmarked, expected (or, as it
Cooperative Principle), but whose ultimate was called, “politic”) behaviour. The
aim is to maintain “social equilibrium”. suggestion was further developed by Watts
(2003) and by Locher and Watts (2005) and
2
Face is generally seen as a “relational elaborated as an approach that came to be
construct” which becomes meaningful only known as “politeness as a discursive
through the dis/approval of others and is struggle”. The focus on situated evaluations
constantly attended to in interaction since it of politeness made by the interlocutors
is in the best interests of all interactants to themselves in the course of negotiating their
maintain each other’s face: “everyone’s face interpersonal relationship, or “relational
depends on everyone else’s being work”, became the major theoretical-
maintained” (Brown and Levinson, 1987, methodological shift marking the emergence
p.61). O’Driscoll (2011) demonstrates this of the post-pragmatic politeness modelling.
reciprocal nature of face through the Its proponents claim that the evaluative
presence of “fellow-feeling” among nature of politeness causes it to be a
participants who assume a certain share of contestable phenomenon, which engenders
responsibility in the situation in which a its variability and relativity, even to a
face-threat is performed. As he claims, this (somewhat extreme) degree: “Politeness is
fellow-feeling is “built into us as like beauty, it’s in the eye of the beholder”
interactants”, and “[i]t is in this reciprocal (Locher and Watts, 2005, p.29). It is to be
nature – whereby damage to one person’s noted that the notion of the contestedness
face leads to the damage of everybody’s face of politeness evaluations was antedated by
– and the repair of that face simultaneously Lakoff herself in her remark that “what is
involves the repair of all faces – that the polite for me may be rude for you”; Lakoff,
phenomenon of face may be described as 1973, p. 303). Further, (im)politeness
ʽrealʼ” (O’Driscoll, 2011, p.19). Hence, a face- evaluations are claimed to be made within
threatening act potentially threatens all smaller sociocultural groups called
participants’ faces, despite the fact that they “communities of practice” (the concept was
may have a different degree of commitment adopted from Wenger, 1998) and are relative
to and/or presence in the act (cf. Figure 2). to the value systems these communities
This applies both to face-to-face as well as to have negotiated and agreed upon.
“dislocated”, i.e. mediated communication, Ultimately, the “classic” dichotomy of
since “it is quite possible that we habitually politeness vs. impoliteness is abandoned in
behave with an eye to our faces in all modes, favour of a much finer range of evaluations
that we project them onto the page, or which members of sociocultural groups have
screen or into the mouthpiece.” (O’Driscoll, at their disposal in rich inventories of
2011, p.27) evaluative concepts to judge each other’s
behaviour, with “politeness” being only one
of such labels. Finally, the notion of

44
Unauthenticated
Download Date | 4/4/17 9:45 PM
Topics in Linguistics - Issue 16 – December 2015

“facework”, which was seen as too closely Politeness is a social practice […] because it
tied with Brown-and-Levinsonian face-threat involves evaluations occasioned by social
mitigation, was replaced by “relational actions and meanings that are recognisable
work”, which was conceptualized as to participants. [S]social actions and
encompassing “all aspects of the work meanings necessarily draw on normative
invested by individuals in the construction, practices, ways of formulating talk and
maintenance, reproduction and conduct that are understood by participants
transformation of interpersonal relationships as doing and meaning certain things. (Kádár
among those engaged in social practice” and Haugh, 2013, p.66; original emphasis)
(Locher and Watts, 2008, p.96). It is possible to draw attention here to only
The radical changes that took place in some of their many interesting observations.
politeness research in the 1990s and 2000s First of all, they extend the notion of the
brought about a reassessment of nearly variability of politeness to the fact that there
every aspect of the previous approaches and are multiple different understandings of
can be briefly summarized here: politeness depending on the participation
 extending the scope of interest from statuses of those involved in politeness
politeness seen as face- evaluations. They offer a much more
maintaining/enhancing (harmonious, nuanced array of categories of persons, or
conflict-free behaviour) to face- participation footings, which goes beyond
aggravating, face-damaging the mere “speaker” and “hearer”. As they see
(aggressive, conflicting behaviour), or it, politeness goes beyond the use of
impoliteness/rudeness, which grew linguistic forms (usage); it is pervasive and
into a strand of “impoliteness permeates all human interactions. Finally,
research” in its own right; politeness evaluations are made with regard
 studying politeness-related to the underlying set of norms, or “moral
phenomena within larger spectrums orders” (MO) which have been negotiated
of negotiating interpersonal within specific sociocultural groups. Kádár
relationships, such as “relational and Haugh’s (2013) approach, which forms
work” (Locher and Watts, 2005; the backbone of my analysis, also draws our
2008), “rapport management” attention to other aspects of politeness,
(Spencer-Oatey, 2005), “face- such as the metapragmatics of politeness as
constituting theory” (Arundale, an important key to evaluations, layers of
2010); MO as a backdrop of evaluations, cognitive
 extending researchers’ interest from and emotional underpinnings of politeness,
the theoretical (2nd order) to lay (1st and many others.
order) conceptualization of
politeness, and from isolated acts to 1.4 A return to the pragmalinguistic roots
extended exchanges of turns; of politeness – Leech (2014)
 crossing over to related fields of While the major thread of sociopragmatic
social science, such as social politeness research over the past two
psychology, sociolinguistics and decades has greatly increased our awareness
cognitive science, and bridging of the multifarious aspects that need to be
politeness research with identity taken into account when studying this
construction, emotions and cognition phenomenon, it has in fact not progressed
(Locher, 2011). very much in our understanding of what
politeness actually is. As a result, the
1.3 The third-wave approaches – the approaches often border on relativism and
interactionist period are of limited generalizability and
These trends culminated in the 2010s with a predictability. There is little agreement on
book-length publication by Kádár and Haugh the “content” of politeness other than it is a
(2013) which seems to be the most thorough phenomenon which is contested, variable
synthesis and systematization yet of what is and open to evaluation with regard to
known about politeness phenomena and the specific norms; politeness thus still remains
processes of their emergence and a “slippery” and elusive concept (Watts,
evaluation. While offering no original 2003). In order to rectify the situation and
politeness model of its own, its merit lies in find firm ground upon which to base our
drawing our attention to politeness being a thinking about politeness anew, Geoffrey
social practice in its own right: Leech (2014) undertook to rethink his classic
(1983) approach and proposed a reworked

45
Unauthenticated
Download Date | 4/4/17 9:45 PM
Topics in Linguistics - Issue 16 – December 2015

politeness model in which he returns to the and “sociopragmatic” politeness, whereby he


language as a starting point in thinking makes a distinction between politeness
about politeness as a “constraint observed in attributed to an utterance out of context and
human communicative behaviour, in context respectively. While both
influencing us to avoid communicative attributions are scalar, pragmalinguistic
discord or offence, and maintain or enhance politeness is assessed on a unidirectional
communicative concord or comity” (Leech, scale (with a possibility of gradual
2014, p.87). His return to the intensification from non-politeness towards
pragmalinguistic roots of politeness has more politeness), and the sociopragmatic
brought about a critical reassessment of his politeness scale is bi-directional in that it
earlier model vis-à-vis the developments enables context-dependent evaluations of an
within politeness research and within utterance as polite or impolite (or even
pragmatic thinking in general over the three underpolite, overpolite, rude etc.). Although
decades. His understanding of politeness as the degrees of politeness assessed on the
“communicative altruism” is both general two scales tend to correlate, i.e. a
enough to enable cross-cultural comparison pragmalinguistically im/polite utterance is
and flexible enough to accommodate typically also evaluated as a
situated evaluations (O = other sociopragmatically im/polite one, in
person/people): particular contexts the correlation need not
General Strategy of Politeness: In order to be always pertain – people may evaluate a
polite, S expresses or implies the meanings certain social action as (sociopragmatically)
that associate a favourable value with what “impolite” despite the (pragmalinguistically)
pertains to O or associates an unfavourable “polite” form of an utterance. This distinction
value with what pertains to S (S= self, between the two sources of politeness
speaker). (Leech, 2014, p.90) evaluations is a crucial claim that Leech
His General Strategy of Politeness (GSP), raises against the relativist positions of post-
which is “directed toward concord and face- pragmatic politeness theorists by his
maintenance” (Leech, 2014, p.221), is an maintaining that there is a “default”
extension of his original six-maxim politeness value of an utterance which
Politeness Principle to a ten-maxim model participants rely on when there is no reason
and, relevant to my research, is to think otherwise.
complemented by the General Strategy of
Impoliteness (GSI) which, contrary to GSP, is 2. Objectives, methodology and data
“directed towards discord and face-attack”3 In the paper I attempt to examine a
(Leech, 2014, p.221). Another important particular instance of metadiscourse of
change which Leech made was replacing his impoliteness which took place in the
earlier (admittedly misleading) notions of selected papers dealing with the Charlie
“absolute” politeness and “relative” Hebdo attack where the aspects of the
politeness with “pragmalinguistic” politeness “moral orders” underlying the social actors’
(satirists’, attackers’, the general public’s)
3
When it comes to participants’ facework in worldviews are raised and whose
Charlie Hebdo discourse, I differentiate (ideological) foundations are thus challenged
between participants’ intentions and the and/or contested. My main objectives are:
outcomes of their acts, between the  to examine the metapragmatic awareness
perspective of the producer, whose acts of the participants present in the
(cartoons) carry a significant load of face- metadiscourse commentaries and to search
threat (as an illocutionary force), and that of for their own (emic) understandings of
the receiver’s, who may actually interpret im/politeness by closely scrutinizing their
that potential as a face-attack (a im/politeness evaluations;
perlocutionary effect); note that for  to demonstrate that the impoliteness
O’Driscoll (2011) face-attack can be both an discourses in the examined media are the
attempt and an achievement. The two sites of struggles over the values, and
perspectives mirror the differing focus on ideological foundations, of the respective
the speaker’s intentions and hearer’s moral orders upon which the given
interpretations as they emerged in the two sociocultural groups are built; it is through
waves of politeness research discussed in the participants’ recourse and/or appeals to
1.1 and 1.2. various layers of moral orders that their
value systems are negotiated and reified

46
Unauthenticated
Download Date | 4/4/17 9:45 PM
Topics in Linguistics - Issue 16 – December 2015

(including their understandings of the value status”, i.e. positions which people adopt in
of freedom of expression); relation to talk or conduct which are
 to apply Leech’s (2014) model of associated with respective, albeit mutually
impoliteness to account for the participants’ related, evaluations of politeness and which
evaluations while viewing them from the are subsumed under the broader categories
perspective of “politeness as social practice”, of “producers” and “recipients” (which are
which upholds the existence of a multiplicity extensions of Goffman’s original folk
of perspectives and understandings of categories of “speaker” and “hearer”). Each
politeness. category is seen to entail certain
participation footings (Goffman, 1979,
2.1 Methodology 1981), viz. roles and responsibilities in
In my analysis of the Charlie Hebdo interaction which form mutually aligned sets
(meta)discourse (CHHD), Kádár and Haugh’s of “production footings” and “reception
(2013) “politeness as social practice” (PSP) footings” and which are encompassed within
approach is adopted and complemented by a participation framework of those involved
Leech’s (2014) “neo-pragmatic” model to in an interaction.
account for (im)politeness evaluations made Given this, it is suggested that in the
by the social actors. From PSP the notion of analysed CHHD the following rather complex
the multiplicity of understandings of array of participation statuses and
(im)politeness is employed as arising from participation footings may be identified (cf.
the four perspectives which people may Kádár and Haugh, 2013; Culpeper and
adopt to view a particular social action, such Haugh, 2014) (see Figure 2). If we adopt
as CHH satirical practices; the four here the perspective4 that the CHH shooting
perspectives, or “loci” of politeness which triggered the Je (ne) suis (pas) Charlie
evaluations, are summarized in Figure 1 movements, was initiated by the CHH
where the centre of the converging satirical practices whose purpose was to
perspectives is occupied by CHH practices further intimidate “extremists”, we may
(the centre can be replaced by the other two consider, on the production side of
evaluative moments analysed in the paper, participation, the CHH staff as occupying the
i.e. the Je suis Charlie stance and the attack following footings: an utterer (animator) by
on CHH staff). These four understandings producing the cartoons, an author by
can be seen as jointly contributing to a more designing them, and a principal by
nuanced and holistic understanding of representing their beliefs in the cartoons
politeness arising in CHHD. What is more, and assuming responsibility for their
they are not equally salient in every account content. On the reception side of
of the evaluative moment; none of them is participation, the complementary footings
seen as privileged and they are not mutually
exclusive as more than one may be present 4
The viewpoint is attested to not only in
in one person at the same time. some of the journalists’ opinions in the
articles analysed but also in the introductory
post in the discussion forum underneath the
article (my emphasis): Charlie and co should
have known that terrorism is a threat to
Europe and civilisation altogether and to
fight terrorism you shouldn’t add fuel to
the fire and generally insult the faith of
millions of Europe who are peaceful and
demand respect for their faith like any true
adherent of their faith would. This means if
the paper wanted to challenge Islamic
ideas that are hard to understand, then a
rational approach and consistent arguments
Figure 1: PSP perspectives in CHH would be far more effective in penetrating
discourse (based on Kádár and Haugh, the thick skulls of the people that join such
2013) extreme movements and not polarise them
further with hate speech and racist mockery.
Next, drawing on and extending Goffman’s http://www.theweek.co.uk/world-
notion of “participation framework” (1979, news/charlie-hebdo/62060/seven-reasons-
1981), PSP offers a typology of “participation why-people-are-saying-je-ne-suis-pas-charlie

47
Unauthenticated
Download Date | 4/4/17 9:45 PM
Topics in Linguistics - Issue 16 – December 2015

occupied by the “Islamic terrorists” are a satirical journalism or, as overhearers, to


recipient who receives the message of the follow some parts of it (the remaining
cartoons, an interpreter who develops their categories of listeners-in and eavesdroppers
understanding of the authors’ message, and are too uncertain as to their membership to
an accounter who holds the principal be further detailed in this discussion). The
responsible for the content of the cartoons. reception role of an audience can be used as
As to the production footing of figure and a uniform category for ratified and non-
the reception footing of target, they are in ratified recipients with a differing
both cases represented by “Muhammad”, entitlement and/or responsibility to respond
who is a character portrayed in the cartoons. or react to the message and who may be
Even more complex is the participation seen as (meta)participants who “vicariously”
status, or the participants’ reception roles take part in interaction in which
participants that arise in this situation, and it “impoliteness” can become a “form of
may well be the case that they are not always entertainment” (cf. Kádár and Haugh, 2013,
clear and straightforward. What is more, in p.90, 93). Due to the gradual blurring of the
the case of mediated forms of distinction between “traditional” and “digital”
communication, they may become blurred. forms of communication, the line between
In the perspective outlined above, the participation and meta-participation also
“extremists” can be seen as ratified becomes increasingly blurred.
recipients who are directly addressed by the A simplified version of Kádár and Haugh’s
cartoons, hence they are the addressees to (2013) types of participation status and
whom the obnoxious and offensive message production and reception footings is
is (ostensibly) directed. However, when we presented in Figure 2. It is to be noted that
think of CHH as a magazine, it is the readers each of these footings and statuses are
(we may see them as assuming the role of sources of particular understandings and
ratified side-participants) who are also evaluations of (im)politeness5.
expected to receive the message of the
cartoons and hold their producers morally
accountable for their meaning, and who may 5
Leech (2014) comes close to PSP at least in
thus become a source of (im)politeness two ways: first, he makes room for other
evaluations (it is noteworthy that the number than the hearer status by using the category
of readers grew enormously worldwide as of Other, in which he includes the hearer
the circulation of the magazine rose and other third-persons who are recipients
immediately following the attack and during of politeness (hence “third-person
the weeks that followed). politeness”); and, second, that politeness
The rest of the public (in France, Europe, the evaluations are made by both the “speaker”
Western world, etc.) could be categorized as and the “hearer”, with both of them
unratified recipients with a differing degree following their own paths of problem
of involvement and interest in the solving.
communication and who, as bystanders, may
be expected to be able to follow CHH

Figure 2: Types of participation status and participation footings in CHH satirical journalism
(based on Kádár and Haugh, 2013, p.128)

48
Unauthenticated
Download Date | 4/4/17 9:45 PM
Topics in Linguistics - Issue 16 – December 2015

Besides the (meta)participants’ whose multiplicity engenders a multiplicity


understandings of politeness there are three of evaluations.
other loci of understandings of
(im)politeness evaluations represented by 2.2 Data
other social actors involved, or even by the The CHH discourse chosen as the data
same actors assuming other perspectives serves the purpose of accessing the
from which to evaluate the given social participants’ awareness of the relational
actions (cf. Figure 1). First, the analysed aspect of language use, i.e. of how social
newspaper article exemplifies a second- goals are met (the “how” aspect of the quote
order discourse, viz. “Charlie Hebdo above) along with illocutionary goals (the
metadiscourse” in which the journalist “what” aspect of the quote) by looking at the
discourses on seven other discourses, i.e. metapragmatic comments which they use to
news articles on the attack. From their make (implicit or explicit) appeals to the
observer perspective, the journalists can be underlying MO(s) which are occasioned by
seen as adopting a “lay-observer” perspective the social actions. These meta-commentaries
of (im)politeness and as conceptualizing the of social actions are, by representing both
incident in “folk-theoretic” terms. conceptualizations AND understandings
Next, as the author of a paper on the and/or evaluations of what had happened,
(im)politeness evaluations in CHHD who is are a form of social practice themselves, and
attempting to apply the most recent my goal as an analyst is to “tap into the
theoretical and methodological findings of reflexive awareness of such evaluative
politeness theoreticians, I can see myself as moments on the part of participants (and
assuming the “analyst” and the “theoretical” observers) themselves” (Kádár and Haugh,
perspective of the social action(s) under 2013, p. 186). The major methodological
scrutiny. Using the terminological apparatus problem is that this awareness need not
of the approach to politeness seen as social always be clearly articulated, often simply
practice, my goal is to search for because participants are not able to do it,
(meta)participants’ (emic and etic) and if they are, then the articulateness may
understandings of (im)politeness manifested be a matter of degree on a scale between
in their use of (im)politeness evaluators. saliency and subtlety6. Using the PSP
Finally, as private persons (whether
systematically or haphazardly) following the 6
The notion of salience is used here to
incident and its aftermath, both the address the fact that in communication, the
journalists and myself develop our “lay- making of choices always takes place with
observer” interpretations of what happened some degree of participants’ reflexive
which are based on our own “folk-theoretic” awareness: while some choices are made on
conceptualizations. As members of our a subliminal level, others are more or less
respective lingua-cultures (nation states or consciously controlled. Salience is “a
larger entities such as the European Union, function of the operation of the reflexive (or,
globalized World, etc.), we are all as we call it, ʽmeta-pragmaticʼ) awareness
(meta)participants of the events who import involved in language use” (Verschueren,
our own emic and/or etic evaluations 1999, p.67). The degree of salience is
informed by the respective moral orders to impossible to measure in any precise terms,
which we orient into the (meta)discourses we yet its relevance is in some instances of
(help) construct on the daily basis. Thus, in language use made more noticeable than in
the globalized world interconnected via others. Whenever politeness-related
mass-/social media networks it is difficult to evaluations are made, the social acts under
disassociate “observer” from “user” evaluation are “socially salient”, i.e. they are
perspectives of the same phenomena, since more marked because they are seen as
the global audiences are dispersed and less departing in some ways from established
clearly demarcated. In fact, we oscillate social norms, or moral orders, within
between these two perspectives which may respective social groupings. The
be co-present in the same persons, and at metalinguistic evaluators, the “emic” terms
any given moment of evaluation neither can and the expressions from the semantic field
be completely ruled out, although one may of politeness which form the
be more salient than the other. As “metapragmatics of politeness”, are the
individuals we are involved, or at least manifestations of this salience, since as
implicated, in evaluations through our indicators of participants’ reflexive
affiliations with respective moral orders awareness they index their reflexive

49
Unauthenticated
Download Date | 4/4/17 9:45 PM
Topics in Linguistics - Issue 16 – December 2015

approach, I focus on the four types of valenced in the sense that they are
metapragmatic awareness which give a (emotively) charged on the scale of
“window into the reflexive layers of the (in)appropriateness; for example, “polite” is
moral order” (Kádár and Haugh, 2013, positively valenced. It must be added that
p.187): metalinguistic awareness, i.e. not only are evaluators not valenced
expressions used to talk about politeness, consistently (besides their occupying
meta-communicative awareness, i.e. explicit similar/overlapping conceptual spaces) but
commentaries by participants which that in locally situated interactions their
represent their interpretations/evaluations valence can be judged differently, or even
of social actions, metadiscursive awareness, contrarily to their inherent valence (cf.
i.e. social discourses on politeness which Leech’s sociopragmatic politeness). An
offer “a persistent frame of interpretation important thing is that the valences of these
and evaluation that has become objectified (sets of) mutually related evaluators are not
in ongoing metapragmatic talk about made idiosyncratically but are negotiated
politeness (Kádár and Haugh, 2013, p.187)”, (i.e. struggled over) over time and space by
and metacognitive awareness, i.e. members of social groups who use them as
presentations of cognitively grounded states a normative frame of reference, i.e. the
(attitudes, expectations, etc.). assumption that other members would
As to the structure of MO itself, it is a evaluate the social actions similarly (cf.
layered construct consisting of expectations Leech’s pragmalinguistic politeness). It
which are grounded in three sets of norms should be mentioned that metapragmatic
representing three layers of MO: localized awareness is also manifested through other
norms (formed by individuals), group-based linguistic expressions which, rather than
norms (shared among sociocultural groups) being inherently polite, “lend themselves to
and societal/cultural norms. All three layers individual interpretation as ʽpoliteʼ” (Watts,
draw on (im)politeness evaluators 2003, p.168). These “formulaic and semi-
(metalanguage) which are conceptualized by formulaic expressions of linguistic
members and which we need to investigate politeness” (Watts, 2003) are a frequent
in order to access their own (emic, insider) object of attention in analyses of political
perspective on a social action. This should discourse, such as hedges in political
be, however, complemented by the non- speeches by Miššíková (2007), along with
members’ (etic, outsider) perspective(s) as communicative strategies stretching over
these are also formulated in the media entire sequences of political discourses, (cf.
discourses. It is through the latter Dontcheva-Navratilova, 2007; Rázusová,
perspective that we can systematically 2008).
investigate the ways the “same” action is The CHHD data for the present analysis is
conceptualized across cultures, which is represented by the news article Seven
essential in interactions which involve reasons why people are saying ‘Je ne suis
members of different cultures with possibly pas Charlie’ which is available on the
differing perspectives/evaluations of the internet version of the periodical The Week7
“same” social action. and which has for several months been
At the core of metapragmatic awareness are freely accessible as the first English article
politeness-related evaluators, i.e. listed when a crude Google search for the
metalinguistic expressions used by results of the Je ne suis pas Charlie slogan is
participants to conceptualize their politeness carried out. In terms of Google hits (in April
evaluations and which belong to the 2015), the Je ne suis pas Charlie discourse
semantic field of “politeness”. They are comes second after the Je suis Charlie
discourse and before other discourses
understandings of “(im)politeness”. In the appended to the related slogans in English,
analysis these indicators are discussed with such as I am Charlie; I am not Charlie. As an
the point being accentuated that they are the example of a metadiscourse on CHH attack,
clues to access the participants’ own the article references seven other articles
conceptualizations of what is “(im)polite” reporting on the attack (see Figure 3).
since “there is no way of understanding
forms of social behaviour without gaining 7
http://www.theweek.co.uk/world-
insight into the way in which the social news/charlie-hebdo/62060/seven-reasons-
actors themselves habitually conceptualize why-people-are-saying-je-ne-suis-pas-charlie
what it is they are doing” (Verschueren,
1999, p.196).

50
Unauthenticated
Download Date | 4/4/17 9:45 PM
Topics in Linguistics - Issue 16 – December 2015

journalist published article title newspaper


N/A 14/1/2015 Seven reasons why people are The Week
saying ‘Je ne suis pas Charlie’
A1 Roxane Gay 12/1/2015 If je ne suis pas Charlie, am I a The Guardian
bad person? Nuance gets lost in
groupthink
A2 Michael 12/1/2015 The Right and Wrong Reasons Daily Beast
Tomasky for Outrage
A3 David Brooks 8/1/2015 I Am Not Charlie Hebdo New York Times
A4 Brendan 9/1/2015 ‘I AM NOT CHARLIE’: Leaked National Review
Bordelon Newsroom E-mails Reveal Al
(Salah-Aldeen Jazeera Fury over Global
Khadr Support for Charlie Hebdo
Mohamed Vall
Salem)
A5 Robert 8/1/2015
Be glad someone had the Financial Times
Shrimsley courage to be Charlie
A6 Simon Kelner 13/1/2015 I am no more Charlie than The Independent
George Clooney or Helen Mirren
is
A7 Sam Leith 12/1/2015 Sam Leith: We are not Charlie, London Evening
and none of us has totally free Standard
speech
Figure 3: A survey of the analysed CHH metadiscourse

As to the social semiotics of the cartoons, viewer; or it may present an “offer”, in which
two particularly useful approaches are other interacting characters are “objects of
available: the grammar of visual design contemplation, impersonally, as though they
(Kress and Van Leeuwen, 1996) and the were specimens in a display case” (Kress and
Hallidayan framework of language Leeuwen, 1996, p.124).
metafunctions (Halliday, 1978). Being If we adopt the familiar Hallidayan
multimodal communicative acts, satirical framework (Halliday, 1978) of
cartoons can be seen as combining visual communicative metafunctions to trace the
and verbal codes which draw on mode- simultaneous presence of the three levels of
specific resources and “grammars” and meaning in the cartoons, i.e. ideational,
whose particular constellations are employed interpersonal and textual, we can observe
to complement and/or reinforce one another that the overall visual design of the cartoon
in order to convey a composite (satirical) can be seen as a realization of the textual
meaning. Visually, a CHH cartoon represents metafunction by combining visual resources
a “picture”, i.e. an “image or text or into intertwined wholes which are
combination of image and text that forms a recognisable as instances of the genre of
coherent single-framed sign” (Scollon and political satire. The capacity of the textual
Scollon, 2003, p.214) whose construction metafunction is also to integrate the other
elements, or participants, are arranged to two functions which find their way into the
form conceptual or narrative structures, by texts by means of their function-specific
representing participants and/or by means: the ideational metafunction
presenting unfolding actions. Thus, a CHH constructs particular representation of the
cartoon8 may portray the Prophet world through the choice of participants and
Muhammad alone uttering a message and, the propositional content of their utterances
through eye contact, addressing the (the latter provides the discourse with the its
viewers/readers, in which case the image lexical-semantic layer, or “field”), and the
realizes a “demand” of something from the interpersonal metafunction constructs the
relationships between the cartoon authors
8
http://www.huffingtonpost.com/2015/01/0 and their recipients, as well as between both
7/charlie-hebdo-cartoons-paris-french- of them and that which the cartoons
newspaper-shooting_n_6429552.html represent. The immediate means of
addressee involvement is the performance of
speech acts, whether linguistic or non-

51
Unauthenticated
Download Date | 4/4/17 9:45 PM
Topics in Linguistics - Issue 16 – December 2015

linguistic, with their respective illocutionary as perlocutionary effects. Although they are
forces and the expected perlocutionary best viewed as mutually overlapping, in the
effects conventionally associated with the following analysis the three social actions
genre of political satire. In summary, a CHH involved in the metadiscourse and the
cartoon can be considered a “single, multi- respective frames (moral orders) of their
layered, multimodal communicative act, interpretation and evaluation invoked by
whose illocutionary force comes about participants are examined separately.
through the fusion of all the component
semiotic modes” (Van Leeuwen, 2005, 3.1 The Je suis Charlie stance vis-à-vis
p.121). understandings of (im)politeness
The first evaluative moment through which
3. Analysis and discussion9 politeness arises challenges the Je suis
The analysed CHHD offers an aperture to Charlie stance. At the beginning of the
how, through societal-level debates about article, the author underscores the evaluative
(in)appropriateness of social actions, social nature of the social action of the CHH attack
metadiscourses on (im)politeness emerge. by pinpointing that it elicited two
People’s evaluations of social actions index contradictory evaluations on the part of the
their multiple understandings of politeness (meta)recipients: while “millions of people”
vis-à-vis the normative frames of reference declared Je suis Charlie, “some people”
established within the respective social claimed Je ne suis pas Charlie. The body of
groups. I suggest there are three such social the article consists of a survey of these latter
actions/evaluative moments which are evaluations which come from seven different
objects of participants’ evaluation in the journalistic sources and which are presented
analysed metadiscourse: (1) the Je suis as “seven reasons” for the disagreement
Charlie stance, (2) the CHH journalistic with, and disengagement from, the Je suis
practices and (3) the attack on the CHH staff. Charlie stance. The “reasons” are extracted
Using the PSP framework, from my from the individual articles and presented by
observer’s viewpoint of an the journalist in the form of seven sub-
analyst/theoretician, I attempt to analyse the headlines. It is noticeable that all the sub-
metadiscourse using Leech’s model of headlines which articulate the journalist’s
impoliteness (GSI). The analysed evaluations of the inappropriateness of the
metadiscourse is one such example of Je suis Charlie stance invoke particular
situated evaluations in which judgements of layers of the MO:
(in)appropriateness are made in particular (1) Groupthink makes it difficult to express
contexts; this means that a degree of nuance; (2) Intolerance provoked this violent
variability reflecting the contested nature of reaction; (3) The hypocrisy of “hate speech”;
politeness is expected. (4) “Baiting extremists isn’t bravely defiant”;
In the PSP perspective, the evaluative (5) I am not brave enough; (6) Tricky issue
moment is a locus of several interrelated cannot be reduced to a slogan; (7) Free
understandings of politeness on the part of speech is not a simple good.
the journalist who can be seen as the Looked at from Leech’s (2014)
producer of the metadiscourse evaluating pragmalinguistic, i.e. decontextualized
the evaluations of other journalists and politeness perspective, the proponents of
displaying emic, lay-observer and folk- the Je ne suis pas Charlie stance can be seen
theoretic understandings of politeness. His as acting “impolitely” by blatantly violating
production footing involves the roles and the Agreement Maxim of his GSI, viz. acting
responsibilities of the utterer, of the author in accordance with the impoliteness maxim
of his own evaluations and of the principal “give(s) an unfavourable/low value to
who can be held responsible for these O[ther]’s opinion” (Leech, 2014, p.221).
evaluations. The recipients (readers) are not However, viewing it from the
directly involved in the metadiscourse (contextualized) PSP perspective we are not
although their evaluations can be anticipated in a position to make such a straightforward
claim since no immediate feedback from the
9
To distinguish between scientific/technical receivers is available. All we can do is to
(2nd order, etic) terms and actually used search for evaluations in the articles
layperson’s (1st order, emic) evaluations I use reported on and look for the descriptive
double quotation marks (“ ”) and italics, metalanguage which participants use to
respectively. conceptualize their social worlds. More
specifically, we can focus on those

52
Unauthenticated
Download Date | 4/4/17 9:45 PM
Topics in Linguistics - Issue 16 – December 2015

expressions through which participants “inappropriate”, or as “impolite” (Leech) is


index their evaluation of the social action. In difficult to ascertain without using proper
the case of adopting the counter-Je suis methods. One of them is examining the
Charlie stance, we look at which “expected discussion forum which accompanies the
background features of everyday scenes that article and which is a rich source of data
members of a sociocultural group or about sociopragmatic (in-context) politeness
relational network ʽtake for grantedʼ” (Kádár evaluations, since it can be assumed that the
and Haugh 2013, p.269) are used as commenters joined the forum in order to
normative frames of reference to which position themselves with regard to the Je
participants are seen to orient themselves suis Charlie stance. Obviously, through their
when making their evaluations. These use of linguistic forms and expressions,
“features” are certain important aspects of including (im)politeness evaluators, these
the MO which they see as being commenters display their evaluations of the
compromised by the proponents of the Je other two social actions as well.
suis Charlie stance and which they
(implicitly) evaluate as “inappropriate”. This 3.2 Charlie Hebdo journalism vis-à-vis
evaluation is grounded in all three layers of understandings of (im)politeness
the MO. The multiple perspectives of the social
First, the Je suis Charlie stance is seen as action assumed by the journalists whose
taking some important societal/cultural individual articles are reported on in the
norms (3rd layer of MO/; or MO3) to extremes metadiscourse certainly yield multiple
or as misusing them: understandings of politeness. As
 thinking alike in order to express (meta)recipients, these people may be either
solidarity (i.e. “groupthink”) ratified as side-participants by being CHH
diminishes room for other opinions readers, or unratified as, for example,
(sub-headline/article 1), members of the (global) public at large (cf.
 unrestrained exercise of freedom of Figure 2).
speech is a form of intolerance and When making their evaluations of CHH
can become a source of provocation journalistic practices, the journalists place
(sub-headline/article 2), CHH and their addressees into the focus of
 as far as public criticism is their evaluations and hold them accountable
concerned, double standards exist in with regard to the the layers of the MO
(US) society: while offending “Islamic which they invoke. Through this, the
terrorists” is tolerated, some home discourses that they engender become
critics are “snubbed” (sub- ideologically charged since they address the
headline/article 3), principal values upon which the societies are
 while the slogan is an exercise of based. More often than not, these
freedom, it is an “empty expression” evaluations are to be inferred since they are
which simplifies a complex matter implied rather than explicitly stated.
(sub-headline/article 6), In her evaluation of the CHH journalism,
 free speech is not unconstrained, it is Roxane Gay (A1) invokes all three layers of
“de jure unfree” (sub-headline/article the MO: while she personally (MO1) evaluates
7). (some) CHH work (MO2) as distasteful, i.e.
 Next, the group-based norms (2nd negatively marked as “inappropriate”, she
layer of MO; or MO2) are disputed believes in the authors’ right to be so, even
with the claim that CHH journalists, at the expense of expressing an offense,
rather than defending the freedom of since she recognizes freedom of expression
expression, insisted on their right to as a privileged societal convention (MO3). By
be obnoxious and offensive, which implication, on the societal level, CHH
offended “millions of moderate satirical journalism as a way of exercising
people” (sub-headline/article 4). freedom of speech may be deemed as an
Finally, the localized/individualized norms “appropriate” type of behaviour whose
(1st layer of MO; or MO1) are invoked when negative, and potentially offensive, portrayal
personal hypocrisy and a lack of courage are of the target of satire is an expected, and
seen as the motivation for one’s unmarked, form of social practice10.
identification with CHH (sub-headline/article
5). 10
Watts (2003, p.260) notes that in certain
Whether or not the recipients (readers) types of interaction, such as close-knit family
actually evaluate this counter positioning as encounters, competitive political debates,

53
Unauthenticated
Download Date | 4/4/17 9:45 PM
Topics in Linguistics - Issue 16 – December 2015

Although the three layers of MO are manifestations of intolerance, and a


generally understood as reflexively ordered, violation of the MO3 norm. On the other
i.e. MO3 expectancies take precedence over hand, by his positioning as I am in total
both MO2 and MO1 expectancies, Roxane Gay agreement with them with regard to the
reverses them by formulating an ad hoc vulgar portrayals, Bill Donohue’s position
norm of a “freedom ... to express offence” may be seen as a demonstration of
which is to be applied when certain “politeness” towards “Muslims”, by explicitly
(individual or group-based) norms are adhering to the Agreement maxim of
breached. However, while she may be Leech’s GSP, viz. “Give a high value to O’s
considered to be empathizing with the opinions”; Leech, 2014, p.91).
addressees, she evaluates their behaviour as Like Roxane Gay, David Brooks (A3), as a US
“inappropriate” by holding them accountable cultural insider, finds the contradiction
for violating a supra-local (MO3) moral between people’s orientation to the
principle which she formulates as “murder is localized/individualized (MO1) norms and
not an acceptable consequence of anything“. CHH’s group-based (MO2) norms as the
In a similar vein, Bill Donohue (A2) evaluates reason why they evaluate the latter
CHH practices as negatively marked, hence negatively as “impolite” or even “rude”12:
“inappropriate/impolite”, by using the most of us don’t actually engage in the sort
metalinguistic terms and expressions with of deliberately offensive humour that that
negative connotations to conceptualize the newspaper specialises in. In addition to that,
precursor of the particular incident (the he makes his non-European outsider/etic
vulgar manner in which Muhammad has identity salient and invokes the multiplicity
been portrayed) as well as their journalism of the society-level (MO3) norms within the
over a longer period of time ([CHH had a] (Western) world which, among other values,
long and disgusting record of going way professes freedom of speech: he finds a flaw
beyond the mere lampooning of public within the US society’s MO, which is seen as
figures). Identified as president of the selective with regard to the implementation
Catholic League, i.e. a member of a of this freedom: A lot of people are quick to
community marked by conservative opinions “lionise” those who offend Islamist terrorists
(which are derived from particular MO2 but are a lot less tolerant toward those who
norms), he dismisses CHH’s MO2 norms offend their own views at home. The implied
which caused Muslims to be intentionally evaluator of this practice as hypocritical is
insulted over the course of many years. By yet another example of the negative
raising the issue of the recognition of evaluation of the existing societal ethos.
intentionality11 on the part of the Muslims, Another outsider/etic (non-European/non-
Bill Donohue underscores the severity of the Western) locus of impoliteness evaluation is
face-attack which is built into CHH represented in A4 by Al Jazeera English
journalism as its (planned) perlocutionary editor Salah-Aldeen Khadr and reporter
effect. From the perspective of his Mohamed Vall Salem. The target of their
understanding of politeness, Bill Donohue negative (sarcastic, and thus potentially
evaluates the behaviour of the two parties in “impolite”) evaluation is the abuse of free
the conflict as “inappropriate”, as speech by CHH, who interpreted the right of
free speech as the right to be obnoxious and
communities marked by rigid hierarchies offensive. They also draw attention to the
etc. face-threatening/damaging acts may be side-participants’ evaluative perspective, i.e.
sanctioned or neutralized; as so-called that of the millions of moderate people who
“sanctioned aggressive facework”, they may they claim have been offended by CHH
be considered expected, and “appropriate”, journalism. Finally, while admitting the
forms of social practice. Political satire can legitimacy of the content of the cartoons
be included among such types of interaction (the what), they argue against its
in which “face-attacking … plays a central interpersonally damaging effects (the how),
role, and thus might be said to be ʽnormalʼ”
(Culpeper, 2008, p.29). 12
Sometimes a distinction, although not
unequivocal, is made between impoliteness
11
Some politeness researchers suggest that and rudeness, based on the presence of
the perception of the presence of intention intention in the former (Culpeper, 2008) or
is decisive in evaluating certain behaviour as the latter (cf. “marked rudeness”, or
face-attacking (cf. Culpeper, 2008). “rudeness proper”; Terkourafi, 2008).

54
Unauthenticated
Download Date | 4/4/17 9:45 PM
Topics in Linguistics - Issue 16 – December 2015

which is the object of their negative tends to be regarded as the ultimate MO3
“impolite” evaluation: It’s not about what the norm, is only illusionary: The law may not
drawing said, it was about how they said it. stop me calling you a n*****, but that
One other thing that the article does is to doesn’t mean I take an important stand for
point out the “scale-shift” whereby CHH´s liberty by doing so. Also, he pinpoints the
MO2 practices are transferred to the societal meta-participatory status of “us” - the
(MO3) level, and which they deem as an audience of CHH attack, by underlining the
abuse of free speech. vicarious nature of our taking part in it, by
Robert Shrimsley’s article (A5) stands out enjoying a nice, self-affirming, essentially
from among other articles in that it infantile holiday from difficulty; the implied
accumulates positive metalanguage of CHH criticism is in itself an evaluative moment
journalism: [they were] maddeningly, which may be interpreted as “inappropriate”,
preposterously and – in the light of their or “impolite”.
barbarous end – recklessly brave, ready to
defy real death threats and firebomb 3.3 The attack on the CHH staff vis-à-vis
attacks. This face-enhancing strategy, which understandings of (im)politeness
is potentially interpretable as “polite”, can be In contrast with the other two social actions,
seen as upholding Leech’s GSP, although the the grave attack on CHH staff may at first
motivation is somewhat less altruistic than glance resist any analysis using politeness
expected; the author admits the fault in his theory; aggressive physical behaviour
individual MO1 when he emotionally and resulting in death may be seen as
morally approves of CHH, but what prevents indescribable using the technical vocabulary
him from declaring his support overtly is his of “politeness” theorization. Thus the
lack of courage to take this kind of risk. question arises whether or not we are
What is more, he “scale-shifts” this self- stretching the concept and theorization of
assigned negative moral trait to a larger “politeness” to its limits since “it is
collectivity of those who sit safely in an problematic to call somebody ʽimpoliteʼ who
office in western Europe [...]who would never has harmed a person physically” (Limberg
contemplate taking the kind of risks. The 2008, p. 167). Yet as a maximum degree of
extension of an individual (MO1) moral trait face aggravation involving physical rather
and its attribution to the other layers of the than verbal violence, death as a result of
moral order (MO2/3) is in itself an evaluative physical harm may be seen as an extreme
moment which may result in a potentially case of the application of GSI: “Give an
negative “impolite” evaluation from readers unfavourable value to O’s wants”; Leech,
of the article. 2014, p.221). As (im)politeness always
Simon Kelner’s (A6) evaluation of CHH involves scales, some extreme types of
journalism as “inappropriate” can possibly be conflictual verbal behaviour, which Leech
arrived at by drawing an inference from his (2014, p.223) classifies as “naked affront” or
saying that it is a tricky and as “rudeness” rather than “impoliteness”,
complicatedsituation to which there are no border on physical violence and may lead to
easy answers. Also, he takes issue with the an assault.
moral integrity of a society (and invokes the Regarding the attack on CHH staff, a
MO3 norms) which maintains double noticeable thing is that only three of the
standards regarding the application of seven articles are quoted to evaluate the
freedom of speech: while implying that it is murders explicitly negatively as “impolite”,
tolerant of CHH’s anti-Muslim practices, he with the metalanguage used varying between
casts serious doubt on whether it would mild and heavy criticism to: not acceptable
equally tolerate a display of extreme right- (A1), violent (A2), heinous (A4). In addition to
wing beliefs. Similar to Roxane Gay (A1), the use of evaluative language, these
Simon Kelner endorses the exercise of the journalists are seen as trying to rationalize
freedom of speech as the ultimate liberty the action by calling to attention the fact
within the society’s moral order. that the victims could have anticipated the
Finally, Sam Leith’s (A7) negative evaluation attack on them, as in Baiting extremists isn’t
of CHH practices as “inappropriate” is bravely defiant (A4), and neither should we
implied by his maintaining that free speech tolerate the kind of intolerance that
is both de jure and de facto unfree on the provoked this violent reaction (A2). A special
societal, group and individual levels. He case of evaluation is Roxane Gay’s (A1),
further implies that the CHH satire as an which, in addition to condemning the
exercise of freedom, the value of which killings by suggesting that Murder is not an

55
Unauthenticated
Download Date | 4/4/17 9:45 PM
Topics in Linguistics - Issue 16 – December 2015

acceptable consequence for anything among those who positioned themselves


invokes the existence of a trans- “against” this interpretation and who
societal/cultural layer of moral order, or suggested that Je suis Charlie is too
MO4, which she construes as one in which simplistic, and as a shorthand for a
life is seen as an absolute value. Another mutilayered identity, conceals more than it
thing which underscores the multiplicity of reveals. Hence, the emerging Je ne suis pas
understandings of politeness is when she Charlie platform offered a voice to identify
expresses empathy (and “politeness”) with for those who found it reasonable to
towards the murderers by defending their disassociate themselves from the
right to express offense, which she sees as official/mainstream identity. The analysed
falling within the scope of the same moral metadiscourse offers seven such sources of
order which guarantees freedom of this disassociation which are all based on
expression: Yet it is also an exercise of the journalists’ positioning themselves
freedom of expression to express offense at against particular layers of moral order. In
the way satire like Charlie Hebdo’s my analysis I have tried to explain how
characterises something you hold dear – like authors as participants in the (im)politeness
your faith, your personhood, your gender, considerations evaluate the appropriateness
your sexuality, your race or ethnicity. of three social actions by orienting to the
Here she draws attention to the value expectancies relative to the respective moral
structure of a group-based moral MO2 in orders which they explicitly or implicitly
which faith, personhood, gender, sexuality, invoke and through which they hold others
race, ethnicity are revered, and how their accountable for their actions. My basic claim
interference by an exercise of broader is that the methodology of “politeness as
societal (MO3) norms such as freedom of social practice” is capable of elucidating the
expression – a “scale shift” – may engender processes of evaluation and the means
negative evaluations, which, in this case, is which people use in making such evaluations
offense. by focusing on their own, i.e. emic
understandings of politeness demonstrated
Conclusion by their metapragmatic awareness and
Je suis Charlie was a stance which was manifested by the use of (implicit and
spontaneously created by an individual explicit) evaluative resources. Ultimately, my
person13 through which he displayed his aim is to demonstrate that evaluation of
evaluation of the fatal attack on CHH staff social actions is an omnipresent activity of
and demonstrated his solidarity with the social actors and represents a social practice
victims; in politeness terms, by orienting to in its own right through which the moral and
Leech’s GSP rule, he acted in a “polite” way. ideological foundations of sociocultural
This momentary expression of individual groups are permanently reified.
identification with CHH values and group-
based norms was subsequently taken up by Note: This publication is supported by the
other individuals and groups and became a KEGA 030PU-4/2014 grant scheme.
collective and societal declaration of
adherence to CHH practices (MO2) which Abbreviations:
were endorsed by the society-based norms CHH Charlie Hebdo CHHD Charlie
(MO3) in which freedom to act (and speak) Hebdo (meta)discourse
independently is an ultimate value. This GSP Grand Strategy of Politeness GSI
“scale shift”, whereby group-based norms Grand Strategy of Impoliteness
became transferred to wider debates about MO moral order MO1 first layer of the
the (in)appropriateness of behaviour at a moral order
societal level, can be seen as a reason why MO2 second layer of the moral order MO3
CHH staff were also considered to be victims third layer of the moral order
of the exercise of this freedom of speech, PSP politeness as a social practice PT
rather than of their own group-specific Politeness Theory
practices. However, an alternative position
began to form itself simultaneously from

13

http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Je_suis_Charlie

56
Unauthenticated
Download Date | 4/4/17 9:45 PM
Topics in Linguistics - Issue 16 – December 2015

References
ARUNDALE, R.B., 2010. Constituting face in conversation: Face, facework and interactional
achievement. Journal of Pragmatics, vol. 42, pp. 2078-105.
BROWN, P. and LEVINSON, S., 1978. Universals in language usage: Politeness
phenomena. In: E. N. Goody, ed. Questions and politeness. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, pp.56-289.
BROWN, P. and LEVINSON, S., 1987. Politeness, some universals in language usage.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
CULPEPER, J., 2005. Impoliteness and entertainment in the television quiz show:
The Weakest Link. Journal of Politeness Research, vol. 1, no. 1, pp. 35-72.
CULPEPER, J., 2008. Reflections on impoliteness, relational work and power. In: D.
Bousfield and M. A. Locher, eds. Impoliteness in language. Studies on its interplay with
power in theory and Practice. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter, pp. 17-44.
CULPEPER, J. and HAUGH, M., 2014. Pragmatics and the English language. Basingstoke:
Palgrave Macmillan.
DONTCHEVA-NAVRATILOVA, O., 2007. Some aspects of politeness in public speaking. Topics
in Linguistics, no.1, pp. 30-35.
GOFFMAN, E., 1955. On face-work: An analysis of ritual elements in social interaction.
Psychiatry: Journal of Interpersonal Relations, vol. 18, no. 3, pp. 213-231.
GOFFMAN, E., 1979. Footing. Semiotica, vol. 25, no. 1, pp. 1-29.
GOFFMAN, E., 1981. Forms of talk. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.
GRAINGER, K., 2011. ʽFirst orderʼ and ʽsecond orderʼ politeness: Institutional and
intercultural contexts. In: Linguistic Politeness Research Group (eds.) Discursive
approaches to politeness. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter, pp.167-88.
HALLIDAY, M. A. K., 1978. Language as social semiotic. London: Edward Arnold.
KÁDÁR, D. and HAUGH, M., 2013. Understanding politeness. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
KRESS, G. and VAN LEEUWEN, T., 1996. Reading images: The grammar of visual design.
London: Routledge.
LAKOFF, R., 1973. The logic of politeness; or minding your p’s and q’s. Papers from the
Ninth Regional Meeting of the Chicago Linguistic Society. Chicago: Chicago Linguistic Society.
pp. 292-305.
LEECH, G., 1983. Principles of pragmatics. London: Longman.
LEECH, G., 2014. The pragmatics of politeness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
LIMBERG, H. 2008. Threats in conflict talk: Impoliteness and manipulation. In: D. Bousfield
and M. A. Locher, eds. Impoliteness in language. Studies on its interplay with power in theory
and practice. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter, pp.155-179.
LOCHER, M., 2011. Situated impoliteness: The interface between relational work and
identity construction. In: B.L. Davies, M. Haugh and A. J. Merrison, eds. Situated politeness,
New York: London: Continuum International Publishing Group. pp. 187-208.
LOCHER, M. A. and WATTS, R. J., 2005. Politeness theory and relational work. Journal of
Politeness Research: Language, Behaviour, Culture, vol. 1, no. 1, pp. 9-33.
LOCHER, M. A. and WATTS, R. J., 2008. Relational work and impoliteness: Negotiating
norms of linguistic behaviour. In: D. Bousfield and M. A. Locher, eds. Impoliteness in
language. Studies on its interplay with power in theory and practice. Berlin: Mouton de
Gruyter, pp. 77-99.
MIŠŠÍKOVÁ, G., 2007. Maxim hedges in political discourse: A contrastive perspective.Topics
in Linguistics, no.1, pp. 76-79.
O´DRISCOLL, J. 2011. Some issue with the concept of face, In: F. Bargiela-Chiappini and D.
Z. Kádár, eds. Politeness across cultures. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan. pp. 17-41.
RÁZUSOVÁ, M., 2008. Specific nature of question-answer exchanges of television
political interview in English. Topics in Linguistics, no. 2, pp. 63-66.
SPENCER-OATEY, H. 2005. (Im)politeness, face and perceptions of rapport: Unpackaging
their bases and interrelationships. Journal of Politeness Research, vol.1, pp. 95-119.
TERKOURAFI, M. 2008. Toward a unified theory of politeness, impoliteness and rudeness.
In: D. Bousfield and M. A. Locher, eds. Impoliteness in language. Studies on its interplay with
power in theory and practice. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter, pp. 45-74.
VERSCHUEREN, J. 1999. Understanding pragmatics. London: Arnold.
WATTS, R. J., IDE, S. and EHLICH, K., (eds.), 1992. Politeness in language: Studies in its

57
Unauthenticated
Download Date | 4/4/17 9:45 PM
Topics in Linguistics - Issue 16 – December 2015

history, theory and practice. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.


WATTS, R. J., 2003. Politeness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
WENGER, E., 1998. Communities of practice. Learning, meaning, and identity. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.

Author’s address and contact details


Milan Ferenčík, doc., PhDr., PhD.
Inštitút anglistiky a amerikanistiky
Filozofická fakulta Prešovskej univerzity
Ul.17. novembra 1
080 01 Prešov
Slovak Republic
Phone: +421 51 75 70 801
E-mail: milan.ferencik@unipo.sk

58
Unauthenticated
Download Date | 4/4/17 9:45 PM

You might also like