You are on page 1of 13

Recognition and resistance

Axel Honneth’s critical social theory

Roger Foster

Critical theory, by its very nature, opposes reduction beginning. Yet, as we shall see, the shortcomings of
to a corpus of historically frozen doctrine. None was his own project are also largely due to a continued
more acutely aware than the inner circle of the Institut adherence to the critical framework opened by the
für Sozialforschung that a theory which resists adapt- ʻKantian turnʼ, of which Habermas remains the chief
ation to the changing nature of society forsakes its expositor.
critical purpose, turning instead into another form of
theoretical dogmatism.1 Rather than being identified Culture and criticism
through commitment to a fixed body of ideas, critical In an early essay, entitled ʻCommunication and Recon-
theory might be defined by what Horkheimer, in his ciliation: Habermasʼs Critique of Adornoʼ, Honneth
well-known essay ʻTraditional and Critical Theoryʼ, affirmed the necessity of Habermasʼs efforts to ground
termed the ʻcritical attitudeʼ. This denotes a commit- a normative framework for critique, as a way out of
ment to social change which is conscious of itself as the allegedly intractable pessimism and negativism
an intervention whose claim to validity is inextricable which marked Adornoʼs philosophy, after the Frankfurt
from the demands of the historical juncture in which Schoolʼs original interdisciplinary research programme
it arises. To do ʻcritical theoryʼ, then, is always to be had been rendered obsolete. Essentially, this essay con-
engaged in a process of reconstruction and reformu- stituted a more or less faithful Habermasian reading of
lation. The work of Axel Honneth constitutes a power- the problems of Adornoʼs project, charging that, having
ful and ambitious attempt to extend this tradition, reduced rationality to instrumental rationality, Adorno
by developing a theoretical perspective capable of was forced to locate the potential for reconciliation
deciphering the changed logics of social struggle in in the ʻmimetic knowledgeʼ of the artwork.2 Because
late modern societies. Adorno does not distinguish between the normative
Honneth claims that the diverse and fragmentary terms of social interaction and the logic of the appro-
forms of struggle which occur along the multiple priation of nature, he is forced to deploy an ʻovertaxingʼ,
axes of gender, sexuality, race, ethnicity and class ʻtheologicalʼ model of reconciliation. Thus it is only
can be brought under the theoretical umbrella of a through endorsing Habermasʼs distinction between the
morally motivated struggle for recognition, in which praxis of intersubjective interaction and the poiesis of
social actors raise normative claims against social engagement with objects that one can recover the pos-
arrangements in which they feel ʻdisrespectedʼ. Before sibility of ʻtheoretically guided political practiceʼ.3 Yet
discussing this project in greater detail, I shall begin also, and importantly, Honneth locates a central failing
by looking at how Honneth has attempted to dis- of Adornoʼs later work in its inability to formulate any
tinguish the ʻcritical theory of recognitionʼ from ʻfirst- idea of, or theoretical basis for, collective struggle.
generationʼ Frankfurt School theorists (Horkheimer The immediate penetration into consciousness of the
and Adorno), as well as from Habermas. I believe ideological products of the culture industry, together
it can be shown that Honneth manages to overcome with the (alleged) absolute separation between the
a number of the most problematic features that have mimetic knowledge of the artwork and the instrumental
dogged Habermasʼs theoretical endeavours from the rationality prevalent in society, meant that ʻthe

6 Radical Philosophy 94 (March/April 1999)


experience of oppressionʼ, for Adorno, ʻcan be formu- psycheʼ.7 Consequently, Horkheimer is forced to fall
lated only on an individual basisʼ. Adorno no longer back on a determinist philosophy of history in which
expects ʻthe contradictions of capitalist accumulationʼ the potential for transformative praxis emerges from
to ʻgenerate class resistanceʼ.4 objective contradictions rooted within the economic
It is the combination of a commitment to a version structure.
of Habermasʼs distinction between the sphere of norm- A point worth raising here, to which Honneth does
ative interaction and the sphere of production, with not give due consideration, is whether this view of the
the perceived need to link the perspective of norma- cultural in Horkheimer is attributable to a theoretical
tive critique with forms of opposition and resistance decision, or whether it is a result of what Horkheimer
emerging within social reality itself, which has defined perceives to be the fate of culture within monopoly
the direction of Honnethʼs project. However, the com- capitalism. Honneth assumes it is the former, and thus
mitment to the first of these ideas means accepting attributes it to Horkheimerʼs adherence to a ʻMarxist
Habermasʼs break with historical materialism, which functionalismʼ.8 But there are passages in ʻTraditional
consequently renders problematic the second, since and Critical Theoryʼ that lend credence to the latter
the actors within social reality who might be charged interpretation. At one point, Horkheimer refers to the
with the task of transforming the established order changed nature of the ʻdependence of the cultural
can no longer be identified by their position within the on the economicʼ, suggesting that ʻeconomic factors
economic structure. Struggle was no longer reducible more directly and consciously determine menʼ, and
to class struggle. Rather than following Habermasʼs ʻthe solidity and relative capacity for resistance of the
tendency to bracket the question of critical theoryʼs cultural spheres are disappearingʼ.9 Granted that Hork-
location within social reality, Honneth has attempted heimer relates this capacity for resistance to a rather
to develop a response to this question in tune with crude psychology, stressing the role of the independent
a commitment to the pluralization of the political
bourgeois subject, the question of whether particular
Left, thereby breaking the exclusive identification of
structural arrangements incapacitate cultural resistance
domination with economic domination.
remains a plausible one which, I shall argue later,
The solution to this problem emerges from an
Honneth needs to address.
account of the cultural sphere as the location of
Honnethʼs reading of Horkheimer and Adornoʼs
ʻpractical-critical activityʼ, which Honneth begins to
ʻnegativismʼ as reaching its inevitable conclusion in
develop in Critique of Power.5 Arguing against Hork-
the abandonment of an emancipatory perspective in
heimerʼs early efforts to develop critical theory within
Dialectic of Enlightenment is clearly indebted to Hab-
the framework of a Marxist philosophy of history,
ermasʼs interpretation, according to which the failure
Honneth seeks to uncover a realm of quasi-autonomous
of Horkheimer and Adorno to ground an emancipatory
cultural activity which, he argues, is suppressed by the
perspective is ascribable to their failure to recognize
identification of the goals of critical activity with the
the autonomy of the sphere of communicative action.
ends of the production process. Such a conception of
Honneth praises Habermasʼs theorizing of the sphere
cultural activity, Honneth argues, would involve the
of communication for providing critical theory with
ʻcooperative testing and problematizing of interpre-
tations worked out within the groupʼ. Insight into the a normative standard, which allows for the construc-
injustice of the economic structure within the cultural tion of a critical perspective on social structures.10
horizon of oppressed groups may then be formulated However, Honnethʼs adherence to Habermasʼs theory
as an insight which forces group members to ʻcorrect is tempered by a rejection of Habermasʼs severance of
and expand the traditional horizon of interpretation communicative understanding from a relation to the
in the face of unmasked realityʼ. Social struggle forms of critical activity rooted within social praxis.
may be theorized as the attempt by social groups Honneth believes that Habermasʼs abstract reading of
ʻto realize within the normative structures of social communicative understanding produces a false oppo-
life the norms of action acquired in the repeated sition between norm-free power and power-free com-
experience of suffering injusticeʼ.6 This potentially munication: the sphere of conflict and struggle, and
critical force of cultural praxis, however, is ruled out the sphere of discourse.11 In Struggle for Recognition,
by Horkheimerʼs exclusive stress on the socializing Honneth attempts to integrate these elements through
function of the cultural sphere – its operation as a a theory of morally motivated struggle. Before looking
superstructure that reflects ʻthe behavioural constraints at this in greater detail, it is worthwhile briefly examin-
of the economic system back upon the individual ing the specifics of Honnethʼs critique of Habermas.

Radical Philosophy 94 (March/April 1999) 7


Honneth’s critique of Habermas Thompson and Barrington Moore on Honnethʼs ideas,
In an earlier essay, ʻDiskursethik und implizites each of whom, through the notion of ʻmoral economyʼ
Gerechtigkeitskonzeptʼ, which prefigures the attempt and the postulation of an implicit ʻsocial contractʼ,
in Struggle for Recognition to render concrete Hab- respectively, furnished the means for an understanding
ermasʼs idealized representation of communicative of the struggle between capital and labour as a form of
understanding in the form of formal structures of moral struggle.18 More recently, Honneth has argued
ethical life, Honneth argues that Habermasian dis- that the importance of rendering the labour process
course ethics must be extended to incorporate a con- accessible to moral categories stems from the funda-
ception of material justice. The basis of this critique mental connection between work and ʻself-esteemʼ.
is the fact that discourse ethics relies upon a ʻdialogue Since self-identity is integrally bound to the way the
which is to be actually carried outʼ, and as a result, significance of oneʼs labour is constituted socially, it is
it cannot be indifferent to the conditions which make necessary that the labour process be organized in such
that dialogue possible. What is at stake here, Honneth a way that it permits the generation and sustaining of
argues, is the impossibility of interpreting ethics as a a form of self-respect.19
procedure of discursive will-formation while, at the Perhaps the most important aspect of Honnethʼs
same time, failing to grant moral worth to the social- critique of Habermas has been the charge that Haber-
structural relations which represent the necessary masʼs discourse ethics fails to gain access to the moral
social conditions for the putting into effect of those claims of underprivileged groups. In his essay ʻMoral
forms of will-formation.12 Among these conditions Consciousness and Class Dominationʼ, Honneth argues
are social structures of intersubjective recognition, that Habermasʼs formulation of moral validity in terms
through which individuals gain a degree of autonomy of discursive agreement overlooks class-specific differ-
permitting them freely to take a position on morally ences in the expression of normative claims. The moral
disputed norms.13 Discourse ethics also presupposes ideals of oppressed groups, Honneth claims, take the
a freedom from all forms of institutional and cultural form of a ʻconsciousness of wrongʼ, as a ʻhighly sensi-
coercion, and an equal access to social information and tive sensorium for injuries of moral claims presumed
cultural traditions of education, such that individuals to be justʼ. Since the everyday experience of oppressed
would possess equal means to set forth their convic- groups does not require normative abstraction, the
tions in argument in a convincing manner.14 moral intuitions of these groups remain tied to their
Honneth has also been critical of Habermasʼs reduc- emotional engagement in particular situations, in a way
tion of the sphere of work to instrumental action, which resists the systematization of their moral experi-
with regard to the difficulty it generates for forming ences in formal/abstract norms of action.20 Habermasʼs
a critical perspective on the organization of the work discourse ethics, in seeking to provide a forum for
process itself.15 Since he distinguished the instrumental the new-found sensitivity of privileged social groups
action characteristic of productive activity from the towards material deprivation, unwittingly de-moralizes
communicative action of social praxis in his early the normative claims of the oppressed by identifying
essay on Hegelʼs Jena social philosophy,16 Habermas moral claims with universal validity claims raised in
has had very little to say about the potential of differ- public discourse – an arena and a form of expression
ent arrangements and structurings of the work process which are resisted by the moral intuitions of the
to promote or suffocate autonomy, or to render work oppressed. This gives rise to a subsequent difficulty:
meaningful or monotonous. In his essay ʻWork and through equating the normative potential of social
Instrumental Actionʼ, Honneth argues that cutting interaction with the ʻlinguistic conditions of reaching
the Marxian link between social emancipation and understanding free from dominationʼ, Honneth argues,
the consciousness-forming potential of social labour Habermasian critical theory becomes unable to locate
does not imply the necessity of doing away with a a standpoint within social reality which corresponds
ʻcritical concept of workʼ altogether. Rather, we can to the normative point of view of the theorist. For the
make an internal differentiation within instrumental restriction of intuitively mastered rules of language
action according to whether the work process enables is too far removed from how subjects understand and
independent activity, initiative, and a minimal degree experience injuries to their moral intuitions to be able
of external control.17 Such a distinction would allow to guide, theoretically, experiences of injustice felt by
for the theorizing of the potential for moral conflict lifeworld actors. Honneth suggests that the everyday
within the work process itself. This critique reflects experience of injustice should be reconstructed theo-
the extent of the influence of the researches of Edward retically, not as the violation of communicative rules,

8 Radical Philosophy 94 (March/April 1999)


but as the ʻviolation of identity claims acquired in ognition as a reworking of the Hobbesian struggle
socializationʼ.21 In this way, the normative content of for self-preservation such that, according to Siep, the
the idea of communicative action can be transferred struggle takes shape as part of the ethical formation
to the idea of social recognition, and in consequence (Bildung) of individuals, a reading which allows the
critical theory becomes capable of giving expression transition from the state of nature to ethical life to
to the everyday experience of injustice. Also worth be presented as an ethical development.23 This gives
noting here is that this theory seems capable of dealing Honneth the all-important bridge he needs to the
far more adequately with the ʻmotivational deficitʼ. A theoretical reconstruction of struggle as founded on
constitutive weakness of Habermasʼs critical theory moral claims.
has been the impossibility of communicative rules After filtering this conception through the social
linking up with the concrete motivations of lifeworld psychology of George Herbert Mead, which, Honneth
actors. Habermas has, instead, been forced to instru- claims, allows for the draining of the residue of ideal-
mentalize the relation between communicative rules ism from Hegelʼs conception, Honneth focuses on a
and empirical motivation by conceiving social and reconstruction of the idea of a struggle for recognition
institutional structures as a functional complement to through a critique of sociological theories of conflict,
normative validity, ensuring the compatibility between and philosophical conceptions of the moral point of
the moral point of view and structures of motivation view. The sociological critique concerns the reliance
by technocratic means.22 upon a utilitarian model of conflict (the ʻinterests
We can now see more clearly how Honneth has modelʼ), which, following Talcott Parsons, Honneth
endeavoured to maintain critical theoryʼs link with a traces back to Hobbes. It is also said to be apparent in
viewpoint within social reality, whilst accepting the Marxʼs transition to a ʻreductionistʼ, ʻquasi-utilitarianʼ
consequence of Habermasʼs distinction between the view in his systematic writings.24 Such theories are
independent logics of communicative and productive capable of conceiving emancipation solely in distribu-
activity: namely, that this critical viewpoint can no tive terms – that is, as a question of economic equality
longer be read off from the location of actors within and inequality alone.25 Social theoryʼs fixation on
the production process. The ʻpretheoretical resourceʼ
interests, Honneth claims, ʻhas so thoroughly obscured
of critical theory is now to be found in the socially
our view of the societal significance of moral feelings
transformative potential of experiences of disrespect
that today recognition-theoretic models of conflict
which arise when culturally sustained understandings
have the duty not only to extend but possibly to
and interpretations of justice are violated.
correctʼ.26
Indignation and disrespect What characterizes the ʻrecognition-theoreticʼ
In Struggle for Recognition, Honneth has sought to model is the claim that motives for social resistance
reconstruct critical theory in a way which renders are not reducible to physical needs, but are integrally
it more concrete and attuned to the moral claims of related to moral feelings of indignation and disrespect,
oppressed social groups, by turning to philosophical and are formed ʻin the context of moral experiences
anthropology, against Habermasʼs attempt to ground stemming from the violation of deeply rooted expec-
critical theory in a theory of language. By this means, tations regarding recognitionʼ. These expectations ʻare
Honneth hopes to render substantial the normative pre- internally linked to conditions for the formation of
suppositions of communicative action by reconfiguring personal identityʼ.27 Among those who have helped
those presuppositions as social conditions necessary to uncover this ʻmoral grammarʼ of social conflict,
for a positive relation to self. Like Habermas, but with Honneth claims, are Edward Thompson and Bar-
different results, Honneth turns to the social theory of rington Moore, who have shown that motivations for
the young Hegel to lay the foundations for this recon- engaging in resistance cannot be related solely to
struction. Whereas Habermas had focused on how questions concerning levels of economic provision, but
the young Hegel managed to capture the interrelation must be interpreted in terms of the ʻmoral expecta-
between the structures of labour and symbolic interac- tionsʼ which are implicit in a particular social situation.
tion without subordinating the developmental logic This recognition-theoretic model of struggle is clearly
of the one to the other, Honneth turns to Hegel for an extension of the notion of ʻpractical-criticalʼ activity
the social-philosophical basis of a theory of morally originally delineated in opposition to Horkheimerʼs
motivated struggle. Honneth draws substantially upon understanding of praxis. Feelings of moral disrespect,
Ludwig Siepʼs reading of Hegelʼs struggle for rec- Honneth argues, become the basis for collective resist-

Radical Philosophy 94 (March/April 1999) 9


ance when subjects articulate them within an ʻinter- of which individuals are valued for their particular
subjective framework of interpretationʼ.28 abilities and traits.29
In the final section of Struggle for Recognition, Honneth claims that it is the injuries to personal
Honneth offers a ʻtheoretical justificationʼ for the ʻnor- integrity which arise from violations of the socially
mative point of viewʼ which, he claims, is implicit in sustained forms of recognition encompassed by
the moral claims raised in forms of social struggle. rights and solidarity that drive the process of social
The goal is to render explicit the moral logic implicit struggle. These violations occur through a denial of
in forms of social conflict, which are to be understood rights or a devaluing of communally sustained forms
as part of a process of moral development. This, of self-realization. It is clear that Honnethʼs intention
the philosophical component of Honnethʼs analysis, is to fit the dynamics of struggle into the philo-
attempts (all too briefly) a synthesis of the Kantian sophical frame of the liberal-communitarian debate.
and Hegelian traditions of political thought through But this gives cause to question what, exactly, is
the delineation of what Honneth calls a ʻformalʼ con- justifying what here. Is the ʻformalʼ structure of
ception of ethical life. The key is the idea of social- ethical life being deduced from the logic of social
structural conditions of individual self-realization, conflict, or is the latter serving simply as empiri-
through which the universalism of Kantian ethics is cal support for a Hegelian liberalism? And if, as
rendered substantial in terms of the social and institu- Honneth claims,30 the ʻintersubjective prerequisitesʼ
tional conditions for self-worth, or self-respect, which of a ʻsuccessful lifeʼ are historically variable, might
constitute a prerequisite of individual self-realization. it not also be the case that normative claims emerge
Honneth grounds this analysis in the Hegelian idea through forms of struggle which a liberal-communi-
of the intersubjective structure of personal identity. tarian structuring of the conditions of self-realization
He takes this to imply the dependence of a positive proves unable to satisfy? Further, might there not be
relation to self on the ways in which one finds oneʼs occasions when the cultural understandings through
identity confirmed in different forms of recognition which an oppressed group works out an interpreta-
constituted through lifeworld structures. The three tion of the ground of the disrespect it endures are in
forms of recognition which, according to Honneth, systematic conflict with the necessary conditions of
serve as preconditions of self-realization are love, its emancipation? If so, the relation between critical
rights and solidarity, to which correspond three forms activity rooted in culture and emancipatory struggle
of positive self-relation: self-confidence, self-respect might not be as straightforward as Honneth implies.
and self-esteem. Whereas love concerns recognition Before addressing these questions, it is worthwhile
as a needy being, rights are secured through legally looking briefly at the notion of ʻsocial pathologyʼ,
guaranteed autonomy, and solidarity is sustained which Honneth has introduced more recently into
through an encompassing value horizon, in terms this project.

10 Radical Philosophy 94 (March/April 1999)


In his introduction to Pathologien des Sozialen: point that ideological messages propagated by the
Die Aufgaben der Sozialphilosophie, Honneth traces culture industry are always mediated through the sub-
the history of the tradition of ʻsocial philosophyʼ from cultural horizon of interpretation, which offsets any
Rousseau through Marx and the early sociologists. direct and automatic reproduction of ideological mes-
Social philosophy, he suggests, is defined by its concern sages in the personality structures of the individual.35
with historically specific forms of social pathology. By overlooking the cultural level, Adorno was led
The central idea is that particular organizations of to conceive the individual as a ʻpassive victimʼ of
social life are analysed in terms of internal, structural directed techniques of domination.
distortions that act as barriers to a successful human The worth of Honnethʼs analysis as a critique of
life. The idea of ʻpathologyʼ denotes a diagnosis of a the simplistic model of the stifling of resistance in the
social anomaly (sozialer Mißstand) that is rooted in work of ʻfirst-generationʼ theorists is unquestionable,
certain structural features of a particular process of and chimes with the insights of social reproduction
social development, which undermine the conditions of theorists into the autonomous logic of the cultural.
a successful life.31 Thus, for example, the sociological Exemplary among the latter works is Paul Willisʼs
theories of Durkheim, Tönnies, Simmel and Weber can landmark ethnographic study Learning to Labour,
be seen as addressing in different ways the problem which demonstrates convincingly that the structural
of the loss of ʻethical orientationʼ, related to certain forces bearing upon individuals at the lower end of
distorting effects on the social lifeworld of the gen- the class structure are always and necessarily mediated
eralized expansion of capitalist economic processes.32 through the meanings and attitudes sustained through
With Habermas, the determination of social pathology cultural practices, which are potentially capable of
takes the form of a process of ʻcolonizationʼ, through sustaining forms of contestation and resistance. Willis
which the strategic rationality of systems governed calls this process ʻcultural productionʼ.36 Thus the
by mechanisms of money and power displace the consent of individuals to live under conditions of
sphere of communicative consensus. Honneth argues structurally induced oppression can only be under-
that this rationalist understanding of pathology ought stood through an account of how and why they come
to be replaced with the determination of pathologies to accept their situation in terms of the meanings and
of recognition. This calls for ʻresearch that concerns interpretations sustained at the cultural level.
itself with the empirical state in which the institu- So far as it goes, then, Honnethʼs critique of earlier
tional embodiments of [recognition in the form of critical theorists would seem to be legitimate. The
love/friendship, rights, and self-esteem] are foundʼ.33 question I want to raise here is the following: is
This is a significant development in Honnethʼs work, Honnethʼs reading of the connection between the
since it signals the intention of retaining important production of cultural meaning and the capacity of
aspects of the substantive social critique found in the cultural level to serve as the focal point for resist-
earlier critical theory in the form of the investigation ance against dominant norms as unproblematic as his
of ʻsocial contradictionsʼ. It is clear that Honnethʼs own analysis seems to imply? For to claim that domination
critical project intends something different from and is always understood through the mediation of group-
more than the narrow focus of left-Rawlsianism on the specific interpretations leaves open the question of the
normative principles underlying political structures.34 conditions under which ʻcultural productionʼ would be
capable of constructing interpretations that might serve
Rethinking resistance as the basis for social resistance.37 All too often, in fact,
We have seen how, by arguing that cultural resistance the potential of cultural resistance gets stuck between
has a normative logic, Honneth attempts to mediate the ʻrockʼ of a neutralizing assimilation to dominant
Habermasʼs Kantianism with a reading of collective interpretations of liberal individualism and the ʻhard
struggle located at the cultural level, such that the placeʼ of an outright rejection of the dominant value
abstract ʻoughtʼ of Kantian critique can be reinscribed, system. In neither of these cases can culture form
in Hegelian fashion, as a form of inner-social trans- the basis for the constructive critique of dominant
cendence. This perspective allows Honneth to make norms, which Honnethʼs account of the moral logic of
a decisive break with the ʻtheory of manipulationʼ social resistance requires. A good example of outright
central to Adornoʼs reading of the effectiveness of rejection would be the complex cultural construct
the culture industry in generating the unreflective that Philippe Bourgois has termed ʻinner-city street
conformity of underprivileged groups. Adorno, as cultureʼ.38 Definitive of ʻstreet cultureʼ, which is char-
Honneth rightly points out, overlooks the significant acteristically a construct of racial/ethnic minorities

Radical Philosophy 94 (March/April 1999) 11


under conditions of intense economic exclusion and claims of gay and lesbian groups as identity politics
ubiquitous racism, is adherence to a set of rebellious prevents the question of ʻcultural affirmationʼ from
practices which often function by inverting the domin- functioning as a critique of the way in which social
ant, white middle-class value system in a way that and economic structures reproduce heterosexuality
permits the pain and humiliation of social exclusion as the norm.42
to be lived, at least in the short term, as a form of Honnethʼs account, I suggest, places too much faith
culturally defined superiority. Clearly, an effect of this in the ability of the ʻmoral doctrines and ideasʼ of
will be to prevent the experience of disrespect from the wider society to sustain a platform for effective
functioning as a spur to morally motivated resistance resistance.43 This causes him to miss the connec-
by redefining the parameters of personal respect.39 tion between these ʻmoral doctrines and ideasʼ and a
Honneth, in fact, is well aware of the specific form of liberal individualist ideology which separates
mechanisms of this process of the deflection of oppo- cultural affirmation from operations of oppression and
sition, in which cultural reinterpretations offset resist- exclusion rooted in social and economic structures.44
ance by redefining ʻrespectʼ. He suggests that we focus The very paradox of cultural opposition seems to be
on how ʻa moral culture could be so constituted as to that constructive engagement can only be engendered
give those affected, disrespected and ostracized the by forfeiting the possibility of effective resistance
individual strength to articulate their experiences in (assimilation through identity politics), whereas con-
the democratic public sphere, rather than living them certed resistance can only be maintained by forsak-
out in the countercultures of violenceʼ.40 However, ing the possibility of constructive engagement (the
presenting the problem in this way is indicative of value-inversions of excluded subcultures). To account
an untenable ʻHabermasianʼ faith in the capacity of for this, we would need to focus on the way that the
the ʻdemocratic public sphereʼ to sustain the expres- conditions – stated and unstated – of participation in
sion of genuine cultural resistance, which overlooks the ʻdemocratic public sphereʼ effectively offset and
the extent to which oppositional subcultures can be defuse the possibility of resistance by requiring of
understood as a reaction to patterns of social exclusion oppressed groups adherence to a liberal-individualist
whose very existence is denied within the demo- belief-system which is central to the reproduction of
cratic public sphere itself. This point connects with the structures that dominate them. It is this which,
the second way of deflecting opposition mentioned for example, leads to the defusing of claims to sexual
above: namely, the neutralizing assimilation of the liberation through transforming them into claims to
oppositional force of forms of culturally based resist- the freedom of a private sexual identity. Accounting
ance. It is this process which causes the most problems for the barriers to effective cultural resistance would
for Honnethʼs theory. also mean that we would need to recover a concept
What I have in mind here, broadly, is the claim which is entirely missing from Honnethʼs account
that the ʻculturalʼ is articulated, politicized and con- – namely, ideology. Honnethʼs portrayal of how ʻhurt
structed within the public sphere of late capitalism feelingsʼ become the basis for collective resistance,
in such a way that a genuine oppositional stance through being articulated in an ʻintersubjective frame-
is effectively excluded. Wendy Brown has argued work of interpretationʼ that shows them to be ʻtypical
that this takes place through the transformation of for an entire groupʼ,45 relies upon an idealized notion
cultural opposition into ʻidentity politicsʼ, a conver- of cultural autonomy, and consequently entirely over-
sion which ʻrecasts politicized identityʼs substantive looks how the pressure of liberal ideology, which
(and often deconstructive) cultural claims and cri- continually reinforces the tendency of individuals to
tiques as generic claims of particularism endemic view their situation in individualistic terms, is in many
to universalist political cultureʼ.59 By this means, cases precisely what prevents this type of oppositional
cultural resistance can be deflected from a critique group formation from taking place.46 This is likely
of capitalist economic structures and from a critique to be especially prevalent where the oppression in
of bourgeois cultural values. By converting cultural question concerns, or indirectly intersects with, class.
opposition into claims to the affirmation of cultural The autonomous, sovereign subject of liberalism is
particularity, the link is effectively broken between constructed precisely through diverting attention from
oppression and the reproduction of socio-economic domination rooted in the economic structure and por-
structures – that is to say, between ʻculturalʼ exclu- traying the distribution and positioning of individuals
sion and material exclusion. Thus, for example, the within this structure as the outcome of individual
construal within the public sphere of the political effort, thus reinforcing the notion that individuals as

12 Radical Philosophy 94 (March/April 1999)


individuals are responsible for a failure to achieve, and to condition and delimit the sphere of articulation left
blocking their awareness of the structures which domi- to cultural self-expression, Honnethʼs account prevents
nate them as a group.47 It is perhaps the predominance the transfiguration of identity in an expanded politics
of a liberal individualist ideology which, more than by naturalizing that identity as a form of private
anything, forces excluded groups towards an explicit interest.
rejection of the dominant value system by implicitly What this argument suggests is that the turn to
denying the existence of forms of structural oppression culture as the site of the critical potential of the
subordinating individuals as a (racial, ethnic, sexual, present does not provide for the sort of unproblematic
class or gender-based) group. link-up between the critique of current society and the
Honneth represents the autonomy of the liberal anticipation of an emancipated future which Honnethʼs
subject in terms of legal recognition, which provides account implies. The ease with which dominant norms
for the possibility of ʻsymmetrical esteem among appear able to subsume forms of opposition as partic-
legally autonomous citizensʼ.48 Thus within the mutu- ularistic identity claims – neutralizing their political
ality of law, through which subjects are constituted as force through naturalizing them – might in fact appear
autonomous, the claims of self-realization appear as as a vindication of Adornoʼs scepticism concerning the
claims for the recognition of particularity. But does openness and transformability of the modern social
this not simply rewrite in the terms of ʻcultureʼ the order. Adornoʼs argument, in his essay ʻSocietyʼ, that
representation of the political as a boundary point human beings are constituted by the exchange system
of private egoism? And consequently, by reading indicates precisely the relation between identity claims
culturally based claims as private assertion, might and structures of power that renders problematic any
not the result of this construction be simply to disguise
attempt to treat those claims as immediately con-
structural inequality by depoliticizing cultural claims?
stituting the basis for a transformative politics. Without
The way in which gender domination is reproduced in
a transfiguration of those identities, Adorno believes,
economic structures, for example, cannot be addressed
cultural resistance can only, on each occasion, reinforce
merely by reasserting the value of the feminine. We
the ʻtriumph of integrationʼ which reconciles human
should recall here Honnethʼs wavering on the relation
beings to the structures that dominate them.51 One
between recognition and interests. Honneth follows a
must ask whether a similar false integration is also
line of theorists who have sought to integrate cultural
produced through the granting of a legal autonomy that
claims into the notion of social justice.49 But what is
works through privatizing cultural difference, such that
lacking from his work thus far is an account of the
the structural basis of cultural opposition is obscured.
relation between the denial of recognition and struc-
I do not intend here, however, to affirm a picture of
turally reproduced forms of material exclusion. This
the individual as a ʻpassive victimʼ of techniques of
problem becomes doubly acute when we take account
domination. Honneth is surely right to criticize the
of the Foucauldian insight that subjects must be under-
thesis of the internalization of ideology of earlier criti-
stood as partial effects of their subjugation by particu-
cal theory, according to which the demands of system
lar structures of social power. In these circumstances,
reproduction are directly replicated in the personality
to seek emancipation through recognition of cultural
particularity, say (to give one overworked example) the structure of the individual. But in no sense does it
re-valorization of the role of women as private ʻcarersʼ, follow from this that individual or collective action
only serves to re-legitimize the structures of economic does not occur under conditions of severe structural
domination which forced women into the subordinate constraint and the ubiquitous (but in no sense all-
role of providing care to men.50 This process can only powerful and all-determining) operation of liberal ide-
obscure how cultural claims are always already marked ology.52 What is problematic in Honnethʼs recent work,
by structurally produced domination. Treating claims and particularly surprising given the central position
to recognition as identity claims seems to rest upon accorded to Foucault in the history of critical theory in
the untenable notion that oppression can be overcome Critique of Power, is the absence of anything like an
without political, social and economic transformation adequate theoretical account of the capacity of power
merely by writing class-blindness, gender-blindness, and ideology to block the transformative potential of
sex-blindness and colour-blindness into the state struggles for recognition. Accounting for the operation
– in the form of the autonomous legal subject. What of power and ideology requires a reformulation of the
happens, in fact, is that by allowing the abstract legal concept of recognition itself.
recognition which constitutes autonomous personhood

Radical Philosophy 94 (March/April 1999) 13


Rethinking recognition to participate in the social universal. The danger is,
The absence of an adequate account of power and then, that interpreting the claims to recognition of
ideology is reflected in the way that Honneth deploys excluded groups as identity claims may simply have
the concept of recognition as a normative principle. the effect of constituting a group or class as a victim
This is particularly apparent in his delineation of the class, which simultaneously takes away its power posi-
sphere of law as a harmonious sphere of mutuality with tively to rework and transform its injured identity.55
a universalistic dynamic, through which individuals Honneth fails to see this because he reduces the
gain recognition as autonomous subjects. What is struggle for recognition to its affirmative aspect and
altogether missing in this account is any consideration neglects its transformative dimension. Oppositional
of the productive power of recognition – that is, its groups engaged in resistance against their exclusion
necessarily performative character, which destabilizes do not demand merely recognition of who they are,
the attempt to portray social discourses and institu- as they have been constituted by exclusionary prac-
tions in terms of the ʻneutralʼ confirmation of claims tices. This turns political claims into claims for the
emanating from concrete subjects. The concept of rec- mere affirmation of a private identity. Rather, what
ognition implies a dependence on the other in the sense is demanded is a transformation of prevailing ideals,
of both self-confirmation and self-constitution. We in the process of which oppositional identities are
depend upon the other for confirmation, in the sense of themselves transfigured through the overcoming of
reflecting who we take ourselves to be, yet who we are the derogatory recognitions which constituted them
is always already co-determined by the performative as excluded. It is precisely this transformative demand
force of social discourse. Recognition is thus eternally that is expressed in queer politics, for example, where
suspended between confirmation and performance, the solidifying of a gay or lesbian identity is exactly
witnessing and constituting.53 Judith Butler has argued what is avoided in order to destabilize fixed sexual
that the constituting dimension of recognition can be identities, and the ʻhomo–heteroʼ dichotomy which
captured in terms of Althusserʼs notion of interpella- constitutes them.56 By conceiving legal discourse as
tion, outlined in his ʻIdeology and Ideological State the site where subjects are constituted as autonomous,
Apparatusesʼ. Recognitionʼs performative power can be Honnethʼs account seriously underrates the importance
understood in linguistic terms as the effect of the way of critical agency in transforming disfigured identities
it is regulated, allocated and refused as part of ʻlarger produced through derogatory recognitions. The appeal
social rituals of interpellationʼ, the ʻcall of recognition to the law to amend the injuries of subordination and
which solicits existenceʼ, and produces subjects as exclusion solidifies the identity of the injured as a
subjects of a certain kind.54 victim class in need of protection, and thus blocks
Attention to the performative or constituting dimen- the struggle for repositioning and transformation.57
sion of recognition allows us to theorize the operation The struggle for recognition, this argument suggests,
of ideology and power, which is absent in Honnethʼs would seem to be eternally beset by the ʻperformative
account. Honnethʼs neglect of the problems posed by contradictionʼ which, Drucilla Cornell argues, marks
the performative dimension of recognition is thus the the political struggle of feminism.58 What one wants
corollary of the failure adequately to theorize the to be recognized as in the struggle – in this case,
ever-present possibility of the struggle for recognition the recognition of the ʻfeminine within sexual differ-
being blocked by power, and its emancipatory potential enceʼ – is precisely what is not (yet) there, what is
undermined by dominant social interests. I want to refused by gender hierarchy. Thus the struggle must
look at two particular dimensions of the operation of embody the paradox of a claim for both affirmation
power that the notion of performance or constitution and transformation.
allows us to theorize, which suggest the need for an This brings us to the second dimension of the
alternative model of critical or oppositional activity operation of power. The emphasis here is not on the
within the frame of a struggle for recognition. way that power is already at work in constituting
The first dimension of power can be gleaned from identities prior to struggle, but rather on the way
the fact that oppressed groups, which raise claims to that power works within social institutions to subvert,
recognition in the process of struggle, cannot simply deflect or undermine emancipatory claims raised in
be said to have been denied access to social recog- social struggle. This can be expressed theoretically in
nition, but must rather be understood as groups that terms of the reciprocal operation of confirmation and
have been constituted as excluded by the ʻcall of constitution in the granting of recognition to previ-
recognitionʼ that constitutes them as other, as unfit ously excluded groups. It is because constitution (the

14 Radical Philosophy 94 (March/April 1999)


identity that is produced)
is never reducible to con-
firmation (the identity that
is demanded) that power
and domination are able to
get a foothold. To put this
more explicitly, the effects
of subject constitution are
always prone to manipula-
tion by dominant interests,
such that existing power
structures are effectively
untouched, even though a
particular demand for rec-
ognition appears to have
been met. A valuable illus-
tration of how the recipro-
cal workings of confirmation and constitution in social and thereby effectively subsumed class conflict under
recognition might undermine emancipatory struggle administration.60 If it is the case that dominant social
has recently been given by Mark Neocleous in his interests are potentially able to undermine emancipa-
account of the incorporation of the English tory claims at the point of subject constitution in this
working class by the state in the nineteenth century. way, then, I suggest, Honneth would have to give up
Neocleous persuasively argues that when the working the rather idealistic portrayal of social institutions,
class gained legal recognition (i.e. ʻconfirmationʼ) in in which they figure merely in the benign role of
the nineteenth century as a ʻsubject of rightsʼ, it was confirming and institutionalizing normative claims
simultaneously constituted by the state as an ʻobject raised by collective actors. It is the performative or
of administrationʼ.59 Consequently, the state constituting dimension of recognition – absent on
was able to develop a ʻlaw-and-administration con- Honnethʼs account – which allows us to theorize the
tinuumʼ, by means of which the emancipatory claims operations of power and domination within social
raised in working-class struggle were transformed into institutions, and consequently, brings into sharp relief
regulated and administered disputes through which the shortcomings of Honnethʼs idealistic portrayal of
class antagonism could, in effect, be domesticated social recognition as an identitarian relation between
and controlled. self and social structures.
An example of this was the growing use of industrial The operation of power and domination which
tribunals to administer disputes between legal subjects becomes apparent when social recognition is under-
concerning the labour contract. The same process stood as encompassing both performance and witness-
was at work, Neocleous argues, in the recognition of ing – constitution and confirmation – suggests the
trade unions as the ʻlegal subjectivity of the working need for a revised conception of critical agency. For
classʼ. Legal recognition of trade unions did not merely if dominant social interests can always potentially
represent the confirmation of certain freedoms of the deploy forms of subject constitution to defuse emanci-
working class, such as the freedom to strike, but actu- patory claims, what is necessary, in the first instance,
ally constituted the working class in a particular form is to locate a space outside subject constitution which
congenial to the stability of existing power structures. marks the failure of that constitution to be total and
Hence, a whole series of administrative mechanisms all-encompassing – that is, of fully incorporating the
were now put in place which established trade unions residue of ʻnonidentityʼ. I want to suggest that it is the
in a stabilizing and conciliatory role, and which were necessary tension between (emancipatory) claim and
implicitly premissed on discouraging the idea that the constitution, or between ʻrecognizerʼ and ʻrecognizedʼ,
purpose of unions was to strike. The constitution of that is presupposed by the transformative ambitions
trade unions through administrative mechanisms was of critical agency, since what that agency requires is
exemplified by the increasing prominence of proce- the nonidentity between the subject and the way it is
dures of collective bargaining, which set unions in socially constituted. Hence, although social recognition
a mediating role between the state and the worker precedes and conditions the formation of the subject,

Radical Philosophy 94 (March/April 1999) 15


the impossibility of full recognition, of a recognition ity to assimilate by inclusion.65 I want to suggest that
that is simply re-cognition, implies the instability we read this breach in Adornoʼs terms, as the ʻshock of
and incompleteness of subject formation.61 Further, the openʼ, the feeling of ʻdizzinessʼ which occurs when
only by understanding critical agency in this sense identity is confronted with what it tries to suppress.
does it become possible to overturn the ruse of power Within the ʻcoveredʼ, and the ʻnever-changingʼ, Adorno
implicit in ʻidentity politicsʼ, whereby the very oppres- claims, that shock will appear as the ʻnegativeʼ. It is
sive structure which produces exclusion is then called ʻuntruth only for the untrueʼ. The telos of philosophy
upon to protect identities thus formed by reifying itself, Adorno tells us, is to turn thinking towards ʻthe
them. If we read the nature of resistance in terms of open and uncoveredʼ, which destabilizes the totalizing
Adornoʼs dialectic of nonidentity, the remainder which claims of identity.66
oppressive forms of social constitution cannot exhaust The problems in Honnethʼs account are perhaps
appears as ʻpossibilityʼ – ʻthe possibility of which symptomatic of the tendencies towards idealization
their reality has cheated the objectsʼ. The dependence of the Kantian turn in critical theory, which have
of identity on nonidentity, which marks the failure of led to a turning away from the task of demonstrating
totalization, is the ground of resistance, of ʻthe resist- the ʻnegativity of the wholeʼ, which, of course, is
ance (Widerstand) of the other against identityʼ.62 how Adorno sought to keep the critical project alive.
This reading of resistance requires that we radical- The danger, when critical theory becomes idealizing
ize Honnethʼs notion of recognition. On Honnethʼs construction, as Honnethʼs work shows, is that the
view, the struggle for recognition is conceived in critical impulse becomes diluted through assimila-
terms of the development of self-relations, as social tion to existing norms and ideals. In spite of these
institutions are constructively modified such that the difficulties, however, it is clear that Honnethʼs efforts
subject acquires a positive relation-to-self through both to render critical theory more substantive and
the way that it is recognized within them.63 This to ground it more deeply in the concrete pathologies
reading evidently owes much to Ludwig Siepʼs deploy- of the lifeworld are a bold step in the right direction,
ment of the concept of recognition, in which political away from the stultifying formalism of Habermasʼs
and social institutions function as conditions for the communication theory. What is now required is a
formation of self-consciousness.64 It is their role in a more constructive engagement with ʻfirst-generationʼ
formative process through the development of patterns theorists. The degree of distance from Habermas,
of recognition that, according to Siep, provides a stand- which Honnethʼs work has now established, makes
ard of critical judgement vis-à-vis social institutions. this possible.
Although this account has undoubtedly proved invalu-
able in rejuvenating Hegelʼs concept of recognition as Notes
a critical concept in social philosophy, it risks under- I am grateful to Axel Honneth for the opportunity to discuss
these issues on numerous occasions, and to the reviewers of
estimating the subversive potential of recognition. The Radical Philosophy for their comments and criticisms.
Honneth–Siep account stresses the role of recognition 1. This is clearly stated in Horkheimerʼs preface to the
in the confirmation of identity, and neglects that this republished collection of his essays from the Zeitschrift
can only occur through the splitting of identity through für Sozialforschung, in Critical Theory, trans. M.J.
the priority of relation. That is to say, recognition is OʼConnell et al., Continuum, New York, 1972, especially
p. 5; as well as the 1969 preface, co-signed by Adorno,
not merely a mode of individual self-confirmation, to the republished edition of Dialectic of Enlightenment,
but also a mode of community formation which at the trans. J. Cumming, Verso, London, 1979, p. ix.
same time decentres, and thus destabilizes that com- 2. ʻCommunication and Reconciliationʼ, Telos 39, 1979, p.
50. Honneth repeats this charge in Critique of Power:
munity. Recognition therefore only secures identity by
Reflective Stages in a Critical Social Theory, MIT Press,
rendering it dependent on, in community with, what Cambridge MA, 1990, p. 68.
it is not, on what is nonidentical with it. This reading 3. Ibid., p. 58.
allows us to capture the transformative element of 4. Ibid., pp. 47, 56.
5. This term was used by Horkheimer in ʻTraditional and
a claim to recognition, which renders it irreducible Critical Theoryʼ, but it originates in Thesis One of
to self-confirmation. According to García Düttmanʼs Marxʼs ʻTheses on Feuerbachʼ, in Die Frühschriften,
account, the transformative element within the demand Alfred Kröner Verlag, Stuttgart, 1953, p. 339.
for recognition, which goes beyond a claim to inclu- 6. Critique of Power, p. 29.
7. Ibid., p. 27. This idea of culture is particularly prominent
sion, becomes apparent as a breach (Unterbrechung) of in Horkheimerʼs essay ʻAuthority and the Familyʼ, in
a dominant identity, which destabilizes that identity by Critical Theory, pp. 47–128.
rendering it relational, thereby undermining its capac- 8. ʻThe Social Dynamics of Disrespect: On the Location of

16 Radical Philosophy 94 (March/April 1999)


Critical Theory Todayʼ, Constellations 1, 1994, p. 257. Dispute with Hobbes in the Jena Writingsʼ, trans. C.
9. Critical Theory, p. 237. Dudas, in John OʼNeill, ed., Hegelʼs Dialectic of Desire
10. ʻThe Social Dynamics of Disrespectʼ, p. 259. and Recognition, State University of New York Press,
11. Béla Kerékgyártó, ʻAuf dem Weg zu einem formalen Albany NY, 1996. This essay was originally published
Konzept der Sittlichkeit? Die Reinterpretation der Hegel- in 1974.
schen Anerkennungstheorie bei Axel Honnethʼ, Hegel- 24. Struggle for Recognition, trans. J. Anderson, Polity
Jahrbuch, 1996, p. 203. In Critique of Power, Hon- Press, Cambridge, 1995, pp. 161, 147–9.
neth develops this idea through a comparison between 25. See the discussion in J. Alexander and M. Pia Lara,
Habermas and Foucault. ʻHonnethʼs New Critical Theory of Recognitionʼ, New
12. ʻDiskursethik und implizites Gerechtigkeitskonzeptʼ, Left Review 220, 1996, pp. 126–36.
in Moralität und Sittlichkeit, edited by W. Kühlmann, 26. Struggle for Recognition, p. 166. The qualifier ʻpossiblyʼ
Suhrkamp, Frankfurt am Main, 1986, pp. 189, 187. is here significant. As we shall see, Honneth has yet to
13. This condition is not reducible to what Habermas calls formulate a coherent account of the relation between an
ʻpersonalityʼ, since, according to Honneth, it requires interests model of conflict and a ʻrecognition-theoreticʼ
that social structures are arranged in such a way that model. See Peter Osborne, ʻA Paradigm too Far?ʼ, RP
individuals possess the necessary degree of self-respect 80, pp. 34-7.
to be able to engage in dialogue as free and equal part- 27. Ibid., p. 163.
ners. 28. Ibid., pp. 166–7, 163.
14. ʻDiskursethik und implizites Gerechtigkeitskonzeptʼ, 29. Ibid., pp. 171–8.
p. 191. 30. Ibid., p. 175.
15. This has become a familiar refrain in Habermas criti- 31. A. Honneth, ed., Pathologien des Sozialen: Die Auf-
cism. See, in particular, Stanley Aronowitz, The Crisis in gaben der Sozialphilosophie, Fischer Verlag, Frankfurt
Historical Materialism, University of Minnesota Press, am Main, 1994, pp. 49–51.
Minneapolis, 1981, pp. 58–68; Hans-Ernst Schiller, 32. Ibid., pp. 28ff.
ʻHabermas und die Kritische Theorieʼ, in G. Bolte, ed., 33. ʻThe Social Dynamics of Disrespectʼ, p. 266.
Unkritische Theorie: Gegen Habermas, zu Klampen, 34. In this regard, see the debate between Honneth and
Lüneburg, 1989; Ben Agger, The Discourse of Domina- Critchley in Radical Philosophy 89, May-June 1998,
tion, Northwestern University Press, Evanston IL, 1992, pp. 27–39.
ch. 10. 35. See Critique of Power, ch. 3. It is evident that the ca-
16. Reprinted in Jürgen Habermas, Theory and Practice, pacity of ideology to reach immediately into the in-
trans. J. Viertel, Beacon Press, Boston MA, 1973. stinctual structure of individuals is also presupposed in
17. ʻWork and Instrumental Actionʼ, trans. M.G. Ash, New Marcuseʼs One-Dimensional Man, Beacon Press, Boston
German Critique 26, 1982, pp. 52–3. MA, 1964. Hence, ʻfalse needsʼ are described as a form
18. E.P. Thompson, The Making of the English Working of ʻintrojectionʼ producing the ʻimmediate identificationʼ
Class, Vintage, New York, 1966; Barrington Moore, In- of the individual with society (p. 10).
justice: The Social Bases of Obedience and Revolt, M.E. 36. See Learning to Labour, Saxon House, Westmead, 1977,
Sharpe, White Plains NY, 1978. In the essay in question, ch. 8. In his Common Culture (Westview Press, Boulder
however, Honneth draws more directly on the findings CO, 1990), Paul Willis outlines the process of what
of industrial sociology. he calls ʻsymbolic workʼ, which is based on the pre-
19. ʻThe Social Dynamics of Disrespectʼ, p. 266. In effect, sumption that the cultural commodities supplied by the
this might be understood as a ʻmiddle wayʼ between commercial culture industry are not consumed passively
Marcuseʼs discernment of the liberatory potential of by duped individuals, but are used as catalysts for an
work through its erotization, and Habermasʼs exclusion active process of symbolic creativity. See especially,
of work from the sphere of emancipatory praxis alto- Common Culture, pp.17ff. If Willis is right, then clearly
gether. Although agreeing with Habermas that Marcuseʼs Adornoʼs account of how the culture industry enforces
idea of the transformation of work into ʻplayʼ is unten- a false integration is insufficient as it stands.
able, Honneth wants work to be open to normative cri- 37. Paul Willisʼs claim was that the anti-school culture of
tique. On Marcuseʼs view of work, see Uri Zilbersheid, working-class boys itself pushes them towards com-
Die Marxsche Idee der Aufhebung der Arbeit und ihre pliance with structures of domination through its valor-
Rezeption bei Fromm und Marcuse, P. Lang, Frankfurt izing of patriarchy and its devaluing of mental labour
am Main, 1986. See also Ben Agger, The Discourse of as ʻfeminineʼ. Angela McRobbie argued that the same
Domination, chs 10 and 11. complicity of culture with social control can be seen
20. ʻMoral Consciousness and Class Dominationʼ, in Axel in the construction of an ʻideology of romanceʼ among
Honneth, The Fragmented World of the Social, State working-class girls, which valorizes marriage, family
University of New York Press, Albany NY, 1995, pp. life and beauty. See her ʻWorking Class Girls and the
205–19. Culture of Femininityʼ, in Women Studies Group, ed.,
21. ʻThe Social Dynamics of Disrespectʼ, p. 261. Women Take Issue, Hutchinson, London, 1978.
22. See Jürgen Habermas, Moral Consciousness and Com- 38. In his In Search of Respect: Selling Crack in El Barrio,
municative Action, trans. Lenhardt and Nicholsen, MIT Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1995, p. 8.
Press, Cambridge MA, 1990, p. 207. This technocratic 39. Bourgoisʼs study traces the contours of a form of ʻstreet-
solution has been justly criticized by Honneth. See his defined dignityʼ developed in conditions of immense
ʻThe Other of Justice: Habermas and the Ethical Chal- structural oppression tinged with racism among young
lenge of Postmodernismʼ, trans. J. Farrell, in The Cam- Puerto Ricans in East Harlem. The same logic, whereby
bridge Companion to Habermas, Cambridge University social exclusion plus racism produces a cultural form
Press, Cambridge, 1995, p. 305. centred upon an outright rejection of dominant, white
23. Ludwig Siep, ʻThe Struggle for Recognition: Hegelʼs middle-class norms is analysed in Herman Tertiltʼs study

Radical Philosophy 94 (March/April 1999) 17


of a young Turkish gang in Frankfurt am Main, Ger- view Press, Boulder CO, 1995, p. 249).
many (Turkish Power Boys, Suhrkamp, Frankfurt am 48. Struggle for Recognition, p. 178.
Main, 1996). These studies demonstrate convincingly 49. Other theorists working within this framework are Iris
how cultural forms can block the move from oppression Marion Young, Justice and the Politics of Difference,
to resistance by redefining self-respect through a rejec- Princeton University Press, Princeton NJ, 1990; and
tion tout court of the norms of the wider society and its Charles Taylor, Multiculturalism and the ʻPolitics of
dominant groups. Recognitionʼ, Princeton University Press, Princeton NJ,
40. ʻThe Social Dynamics of Disrespectʼ, p. 269. 1992.
41. Wendy Brown, States of Injury: Power and Freedom in 50. See Wendy Brownʼs insightful critique of identity poli-
Late Modernity, Princeton University Press, Princeton tics in States of Injury, chs 2 and 3.
NJ, 1995, p. 59. 51. Theodor W. Adorno, ʻSocietyʼ, trans. F. Jameson, in
42. See Judith Butlerʼs essay ʻMerely Culturalʼ, in New Left S. Bronner and D. Kellner, eds, Critical Theory and
Review 227, 1998, pp. 33–44. Society, Routledge, London, 1989, pp. 271, 274.
43. Struggle for Recognition, p. 164; also, p. 162: ʻThe 52. My argument here was prompted by the suggestions of
forms of recognition associated with rights and social Peter Dews on an earlier draft of this paper.
esteem … represent a moral context for societal conflict, 53. Alexander García Düttman, Zwischen den Kulturen,
if only because they rely on socially generalized criteria Suhrkamp, Frankfurt am Main, 1997, p. 10. See also
in order to functionʼ (my emphasis). his ʻThe Culture of Polemic: Misrecognizing Recogni-
44. This point can also be said to apply to the practice of tionʼ, Radical Philosophy 81, January–February 1997,
ʻconsciousness-raisingʼ in early Second Wave feminism, pp. 27–34.
which would otherwise seem to be a form of oppositional 54. See Judith Butler, Excitable Speech: A Politics of the
group formation to which Honnethʼs model of collective Performative, Routledge, London and New York, 1997,
resistance corresponds quite closely. Consciousness-rais- pp. 24–8. Butler is, however, rightly critical of the to-
ing deliberately set out to ignore, or deny, the dominant talizing implications of Althusserʼs reading of inter-
conceptions of equality and impartial respect, devel- pellation.
oping a standpoint of partiality centred on womenʼs 55. That Honneth does read claims to recognition as identity
experience. Thus the important task was to break free claims is strongly suggested by the explicit reference to
from the ideological neutrality of liberal personhood, ʻidentity claimsʼ as constitutve of Hegelʼs account of
which disguised a masculine world-view. See Jeffrey social struggle, in Struggle for Recognition, p. 23.
Gauthier, Hegel and Feminist Social Criticism, SUNY 56. See Nancy Fraserʼs distinction between ʻaffirmativeʼ
Press, Albany NY, 1997, ch. 4. and ʻtransformativeʼ recognition in her Justice Inter-
45. Struggle for Recognition, p. 163. ruptus, Routledge, London and New York, 1997, pp.
46. Lois Weis stresses the tendency to stick with individu- 23ff. See also García Düttman, Zwischen den Kulturen,
alistic/private solutions rather than collective action and pp. 107–24.
collective struggle in her account of the emerging femi- 57. See Brown, States of Injury, p. 27.
nist identity of working-class girls. The girls in Weisʼs 58. See her Transformations: Recollective Imagination and
study, although developing an identity which seemingly Sexual Difference, Routledge, London and New York,
points towards the need for collective resistance, ʻare not 1993, p. 142.
conscious of their shared political sexual class identity 59. Administering Civil Society: Towards a Theory of State
even though the glimmerings of such consciousness are Power, Macmillan and St. Martins Press, London and
thereʼ. Weis stresses that it is only through seeing their New York, 1996, pp. 69, 111, 163–4. Central to Neo-
problems as shared and as needing collective action that cleousʼs account is a critique of the idea that the work-
these girls could truly press for substantive change. See ing class was already fully formed before the state
Lois Weis, Working Class Without Work: High School ʻactedʼ upon it. Thus the very idea of the ʻmakingʼ of
Students in a De-industrializing Economy, Routledge, the English working class necessitates an account of
New York, 1990, p. 206. its constitution, throught its subsumption by power and
47. Jay MacLeod, in his study of two groups of working- dominant social interests (ibid., pp. 105–7).
class youths in the USA, provides an excellent account 60. Ibid., pp. 69, 140ff.
of how the ʻachievement ideologyʼ and the rhetoric of 61. See Judith Butler, Bodies that Matter, Routledge, Lon-
equality of opportunity effectively block collective in- don and New York, 1993, pp. 225–6.
sight into the constraining structural forces bearing upon 62. Negative Dialectics, trans. E.B. Ashton, Continuum,
working-class youths as a group and produces instead a New York, 1973, pp. 52, 160–61 (translation altered).
feeling of personal responsibility. Arguing against Paul 63. See, for example, the recent essay ʻAnerkennung und
Willisʼs optimism about the possibility of ʻpenetrationsʼ moralische Verpflichtungʼ, in Zeitschrift für philoso-
of liberal ideology, MacLeod suggests: ʻinsightful opin- phische Forschung 51, 1997, p. 38.
ions are of little use in isolation; there needs to be an 64. See his ʻRecht und Anerkennungʼ, in Selbstbehauptung
ideological perspective and a cultural context in which und Anerkennung, edited by H. Girndt, Academia Ver-
their insights can be applied that leads to positive and lag, Sankt Augustin, 1990, especially pp. 172ff.
potentially transformative rituals, symbols, territories 65. See his Zwischen den Kulturen, pp. 117–18.
and political strategiesʼ (Ainʼt No Makinʼ It: Aspirations 66. Negative Dialectics, pp. 33, 20 (translation altered).
and Attainment in a Low Income Neighbourhood, West-

18 Radical Philosophy 94 (March/April 1999)

You might also like