You are on page 1of 17

PREDICATE COGNITION IN SEMANTICS

AGNES BR. SIMBOLON

2121150064

UNIVERSITAS KRISTEN INDONESIA

JAKARTA

JUNE 17, 2023


INTRODUCTION
simplified scientific models, some of which
Cognition is defined as ‘the mental action
have been developed using studies in
or process of acquiring knowledge and
rodents and non-human primates. These
understanding through thought, experience,
studies help us better understand certain
and the senses.’ At Cambridge Cognition we
parts of our cognition, such as how we learn
look at it as the mental processes relating to
language and have also been the basis for
the input and storage of information and
many breakthroughs in treatments for
how that information is then used to guide
common disorders of cognition such as
your behavior. It is the ability to perceive
Alzheimer’s disease.
and react, process and understand, store and
retrieve information, make decisions, and Cognition fundamentally controls our
produce appropriate responses. The modern thoughts and behaviors, which are regulated
word ‘cognition’ has its roots back to Latin, by discrete brain circuits underpinned by
‘cognoscere’ which is to ‘get to know’. With several neurotransmitter systems. Several
that in mind, cognitive functioning is brain chemicals play major roles in
therefore critical for day-to-day life, regulating cognitive processes; including
governing our thoughts and actions. We dopamine, noradrenaline (norepinephrine),
need cognition to help us understand serotonin, acetylcholine, glutamate, and
information about the world around us and GABA. To better understand what drives
interact safely with our environment, as the certain behaviors, in both healthy and
sensory information we receive is vast and diseased states, it is important to consider
complicated: cognition is needed to distill all cognition and the underlying neurobiology
this information down to its essentials. that underpins these behaviors. Our distinct
cognitive functions arise because of
Cognition has a physical basis in the brain
processes occurring within certain parts of
with over 100 billion nerve cells in a healthy
our brain, but only some of these, end up
human brain. Each of these can have up to
entering our conscious awareness.
10,000 connections with other nerve cells
called neurons. All of this makes it an This chapter discusses meaning as it is
incredibly complicated organ. To begin to viewed in cognitive linguistics. The term
understand the brain we sometimes rely on “cognitive linguistics” will be used here as a
cover term to refer to several related semantics is a separate module within the
theories, such as Cognitive Grammar, linguistic model, next to “cognitive syntax”,
(Radical) Construction Grammar, “cognitive morphology”, “cognitive
Conceptual Metaphor Theory, etc. that each pragmatics”, etc. However, cognitive
has its specifics, but essentially adheres to linguistics does not adopt a modular view of
the same general cognitive functional, language: all structures in language, ranging
usage-based perspective on language. One from morphemes to words to syntactic
of the basic tenets of these cognitive theories patterns, are considered inherently
is that language does not constitute a meaningful and as being of the same kind,
separate innate faculty of mind (cf. i.e. symbolic form-meaning pairings, called
Langacker 1987: 13). Undeniably, human “symbolic units” (Langacker’s Cognitive
beings have an innate (i.e. genetically Grammar) or “constructions” (Construction
determined) predisposition that allows them Grammar). More specifically, grammar is
to learn language; however, the full defined as a structured inventory of such
articulation of the linguistic system depends form-meaning pairs. For lexical items and
on experiential factors (physiological as well morphemes, assuming such a form-meaning
as cultural) and cognitive abilities that are pair is quite uncontroversial, as it goes back
not unique to language. Nor is it necessarily to de Saussure’s basic insight on the
so that grammatical structure, at a very arbitrariness of the link between the
abstract level, is innate and (thus) universal. significant (signifier) and the signifié
The innate, universal nature of grammar (signified). However, de Saussure and later
(which is an empirical question rather than (mainstream) linguistic theories (of which
the theoretical a priori which it often is taken generative linguistics is the most salient
to be, cf. also Tomasello 1995 or Levinson representative) held the view that idiomatic
2003a) is not an issue that is relevant to the constructions notwithstanding, the meaning
current chapter, but grammar’s interaction of compositional structures, such as in
with experiential factors and cognitive polymorphemic words or syntactic
abilities is at the heart of what “cognitive structures, is not arbitrary since it is
semantics” is. derivable from the meanings of the parts. In
other words, speakers know how to figure
The term “cognitive semantics” is
out the meaning of compositional words
somewhat misleading, as it may suggest that
such as woodstove or windmill based on (i) short, any linguistic unit, be it a morpheme,
the meaning of the parts (wood and stove, a lexical item, or a larger (grammatical)
wind and mill) and (ii) the meaning(s) of the pattern, is a symbolic unit linking a
N-N compounds in English. particular form to a particular meaning
The cognitive definition of grammar as an (which Langacker calls the semantic pole).
inventory of form-meaning pairs goes There will be differences between the
against such a view, saying not only those semantic structure of lexical items, which
grammatical patterns are inherently will be more content-specific, and that of
meaningful, but also that the existence of a more syntactic patterns (such as the
more general pattern (a “rule”) does not ditransitive construction, the caused-motion
exclude storage of instances of these construction, or the setting construction: see
patterns with their (possibly particular) Chapter 24) which will have a more
meaning. Langacker has called this the schematic meaning. In cognitive linguistics,
rule/list fallacy: it is not necessarily so that meaning is defined as conceptualization:
because something is regular or computable, “Semantic structure is conceptualization
it is not, or cannot be, stored. Quite the tailored to the specifics of linguistic
contrary; it turns out that full convention. Semantic analysis, therefore,
compositionality is rare and that speakers requires the explicit characterization of
store much more than is often assumed, conceptual structure” (Langacker 1987: 99).
including such compositional structures, At first sight, the cognitive view may not
some of which may be partially filled with seem to be fundamentally different from
specific lexical items (e.g. Jackendoff’s other theories which consider meanings to
(2008) constructional idioms, such as an N be concepts or conceptual representations.
of a man or N by N), whereas others are In cognitive grammar, grammatical
fully schematic (e.g. the ditransitive oppositions like that between nouns and
construction, such as Maarten gave Nick a verbs also receive a semantic definition
book). While in other models, the latter involving profile and base; for example, the
would be considered as the products of a verb kill and the noun killing are both
grammatical rule devoid of meaning, in characterized concerning the same base, but
cognitive linguistics they, too, would be each imposes a different profile: the noun
considered as inherently meaningful. In profiles a thing (a region in one domain)
whereas, being a relational predicate, the basis for Metaphor Theory (and later
verb profiles a temporal sequence of Blending Theory, cf. Fauconnier (1994),
interconnections between entities. The Coulson and Oakley (2001)), is probably the
grammatical difference relates to our publication that popularised the idea of the
cognitive capacity for conceptual reification, cognitive nature of (particularly) metaphor
i.e. our ability to conceive of an array of which is said to structure the way we talk,
temporal states as a single unified (abstract) think and act, an idea that had, however, an
entity. As Lakoff and Johnson (1980) have important precedent in an article from 1954
shown, such conceptual reification underlies by the philosopher Max Black.
much of our metaphorical thinking, as we In cognitive linguistics, the difference
treat non-discrete abstract entities as if they between metaphor and metonymy is
are discrete and tangible. For example, typically defined in two ways.
conceptualizing events, which in the real
world may not always have a clear First, the underlying mechanisms are
beginning and end, as entities with clear different: metaphor builds on (perceived)
boundaries allow us to qualify them, taking similarity where one entity is said to be
or thinking about different aspects just as we understood in terms of another (e.g.
would examine different aspects of a ARGUMENT IS WAR, LOVE IS A
concrete object. JOURNEY, CHANGE IS MOTION,
ANGER IS HEAT IN A CONTAINER,
etc.). Metonymy, in contrast, is defined in
METAPHOR AND METONYMY terms of reference, where one entity is used
to refer to another, usually because it is

In cognitive (lexical) semantics, metaphor (conceptually) contiguous to it. Physical

and metonymy play a major role in contiguity motivates the metonymy

structuring underlying the use of a door in walking

principles in the semantic category. through the door (the aperture in the wall)

Importantly, these are not seen as purely versus painting the door (the board covering

linguistic relations, but as conceptual that aperture), or between the container and

principles. Lakoff and Johnson’s (1980) contained (e.g. drinking a glass of beer).

book Metaphors We Live By, which laid the Conceptual contiguity could be argued to be
the motivation for the metonymy the speaker to select a different contextually
POSSESSOR-POSSESSED as the two need salient concept profile in a domain or
not be physically contiguous. domain matrix than the one usually
symbolized by the word” (Croft and Cruse
The second difference between metaphor 2004: 48). Such shifts are often motivated
and metonymy that is often invoked (which because one is focusing on a particular
follows logically from the preceding) is that aspect in a given context; for example, if I
metaphor concerns a mapping across say I see there are some new faces in class
different domains (or, more accurately, today, I am using faces metonymically as it
frames), whereas metonymy implies a shift is part of a person that allows me to
within the same domain. For example, the recognize them (or not, in this case).
meanings of kill in the uses kill a human Similarly, a helping hand focuses on the part
being and kill life on the planet can be seen of the body that we stereotypically use when
as metonymically related, involving a shift helping others. In an earlier study on the
of an instance (a living being) to the larger verb abort (Lemmens 1998: 211ff), I pointed
process (life) yet the relationship is not out that ideological reasons may also
metaphorical since they are both still motivate metonymical shifts: pro-lifers will
characterized vis-à-vis the domain of killing typically focus on the end-point and thus say
proper. Usage such as kill the peace process abort a baby/child whereas pro-choicers
is, however, metaphorical, as it is no longer often downplay this aspect and use fetus or
the domain of taking away a life that is at zygote. While the difference between
issue. Notice that the same metonymical metaphor and metonymy will mostly be
shift of profile as in the source domain is clear enough, the latter example shows that
possible here as well, e.g. Under economic this may not be so. Even if pregnancy and
pressure, Ford decided to kill the production fetus/baby can be argued to be
of the car (process) vs. Under economic metonymically related, aborting a pregnancy
pressure, Ford decided to kill the car could equally be regarded as a metaphor
(product). since it is an instantiation of aborting a
process (a metaphorical usage), just like
A metonymy can thus be defined as a shift aborting a mission or aborting a takeoff. The
of profile within the domain: “the ability of criterion of domain boundary crossing that is
often used in cognitive linguistics may not typically selected from a quite constrained
be so helpful either, given the difficulty of class (see, however, Capelle (2005: 46ff;
defining what a domain is (see, for instance, 453ff) for an interesting discussion). In
Clausner and Croft (1999) on this issue); it Construction Grammar, this phenomenon is
seems that the decision of boundary crossing called coercion; cf. Michaelis (2004, 2006),
is often post hoc, i.e. after one has already Goldberg (2006). Also, the semantics of
decided that usage is metaphorical. But even these expressions is to some extent idiomatic
then, such a decision may not always be (i.e. more than just the sum of the meaning
easy to make. of the parts), as they invariably mean that
the action expressed by the verb (working,
CONSTRUCTIONAL laughing, crying, etc.) is done to a high

SEMANTICS degree or even to some excess. In other


words, the construction incorporates a
particular evaluative (affective) judgment
The discussion has focused on lexical
that can be paraphrased as “do X intensively
meaning; it will be recalled that in cognitive
or excessively”. In addition, the object NP is
linguistics also grammatical structures are
not licensed by the verb as one cannot say
considered as inherently meaningful. Given
*he sang his heart or *he worked his head;
the more general nature of these
in other words, it is the entire construction
constructions, their semantic structure will
with the particle that allows for the
be considered to be more general or, in the
integration of an object NP, thereby
more technical terms introduced above, to
overruling the verb’s typical intransitive
be more schematic. The cognitive principle
nature Just like lexical categories, these
driving the schematization is the same, viz.
expressions can be seen as building a
that of analogy. Let us illustrate that with
schematic network where analogy and
one of Jackendoff’s pet examples of
schematization are the structuring principles.
constructional idioms, the [V one’s X PRT]
Two of the obvious schematizations concern
construction, as instantiated by expressions
the possessive pronoun and the body part
such as work one’s head off, sing one’s
where usages such as He worked his ass off
heart out, or cry one’s eyes. Jackendoff
and They worked their heads off are both
correctly points out that these expressions
are idiomatic, as the NP and particle are
regarded as instantiations of the more particular (highly schematic) meaning. For
schematic structure <NPi> work <POSSi example, given the close association
> <BODY PART> off. between singing and (possibly effortful)
breathing, singing one’s lungs out is quite
interpretable as doing intensive singing;
similarly, given the conventional link
between singing and the expression of
emotions, singing one’s heart out is fairly
transparent given the metonymy of heart as
a seat for the emotions. However, to say sing
one’s arms out/off is quite difficult (if not
impossible) to interpret, given the absence
The above discussion has focused on a of any transparent link between arms and
particular constructional idiom, or rather a singing. Surely, repeated use might lead to
family of related idioms, that can be semantic bleaching which is what has
captured under the general schema V one’s happened to V one’s {head/ ass off} where
X PRT; one might argue that this could still the choice of verb no longer seems to be
be regarded as a supra-lexical unit rather constrained by the body part. This takes us
than a grammatical structure (see Chapter back to salience within the category: some
24). While indeed the V one’s X PRT instantiations turn out to be more salient
construction remains somewhat more (more prototypical instances) than others.
specific in some respects, it should be clear Notice that here also the meaning of the
that a similar analysis can be suggested for construction may change the meaning of the
more general grammatical patterns, such as verb that occurs in it (a case of coercion).
the Ditransitive construction, e.g. John gave For example, the verb break is a lexical
Mary a book, the Caused Motion causative referring to a change of state
construction (e.g. She put the book on the where motion is backgrounded (if
table) or the Intransitive motion construction considered part of the verb’s meaning at all),
(e.g. He went into the room). These are also yet it saliently refers to a motion event in
considered symbolic form-meaning pairs She broke the eggs into the bowl (caused
where a particular form is paired with a motion) or in the sun broke through the
clouds (see Lemmens (2006b) for some This point fits with modularity-based
discussion of these uses of break and other accounts of perception and was fittingly
lexical causatives). The meaning of the made by Fodor in his discussion of input
construction also guides the interpretation of modules as “subsidiary systems” that must
novel verbs; if one were to say of the author “provide the central machine with
of the present chapter that He immersed into information about the world; information
the room, it will be clear, thanks to the expressed by mental symbols in whatever
meaning of the Intransitive Motion format cognitive processes demand of the
construction, that the verb refers to a representations that they apply to” (Fodor,
particular manner of motion even if it may 1983, p. 40). Similarly, Mandelbaum argues
not be clear what that manner is (nor would that the outputs of modular perceptual
we care to specify that here). systems ought to be conceptualized to
In its ambition to prove that such “actually guide action by entering into other
grammatical schemas are also meaningful, cognitive processes” (2018, p. 271). It is an
the cognitive linguistic literature (especially underemphasized explanatory virtue of
in Construction Grammar) may have modularity that it allows for a system to be
overemphasized the quest for, or the distinctly perceptual (in virtue of its
existence of, highly schematic constructions modularity) while outputting representations
that unify all the members of the category. that are immediately consumable by
However, as with lexical semantic cognition (in virtue of their format).
categories, it need not be the case that such Modularity-based versions of conceptualism
high-level schemas exist; in fact, some thereby avoid full-fledged versions of the
recent studies (see, among others, Perek “interface problem” in interactions between
(2015), Lemmens and Perek (2009)) show perception, cognition, and action (Burnston,
that it may be more accurate to pitch the 2017b; Butterfill & Sinagaglia, 2014;
constructional generalizations at a lower Mylopoulos & Pacherie, 2017; Shepherd,
level. 2018; 2019).
However, perception is older than cognition.
One might object that our perceptual
systems evolved from creatures who lacked
cognition, therefore there was no
CONCEPTUALISM
evolutionary pressure for concepts to figure modularity-based conceptualists can be
in perception. In what follows, I’ll sketch a pluralists about perceptual representation
version of conceptualism that posits (Quilty-Dunn, 2019b). As long as some
concepts in perception independently of significant component of perception is
stimulus-independent cognitive abilities. I’ll conceptual and feeds immediately into
argue not only those adult humans have cognition, there is room for other perceptual
conceptually structured perceptual representations to have other formats with
representations, but also that these other functional advantages. For example,
conceptual outputs of perception constitute a perhaps iconic representations allow for
natural representational kind found in richer, messier content to be encoded in
children and animals alike. Perceptual object perception, while sparse conceptual
representations function to segment out representations provide neatly packaged
particulars, track them, and predicate categorizations to central cognition. I will
features of them, including conceptual first argue against stimulus independence as
categories. These object representations a constitutive condition on conceptuality
constitute an evolutionarily ancient and (Prinz, 2002, p. 197; Beck, 2018; Burge,
developmentally early source of predicate- 2010b; Camp, 2009) in favor of a Cartesian
argument propositional structure that is view that concepts are simply
useful for (1) tracking individuals, (2) representations of a certain sort that, in
subsuming them under categories, and (3) principle, require no particular mental
distinguishing reference-guiding elements abilities for their instantiation in human and
from pure attributions. These structures can animal minds (Fodor, 2004). I’ll then use
function as evidential inputs to inferential empirical evidence to argue that perceptual
processes in creatures that have the requisite object representations are conceptualized
inferential abilities. propositional structures that develop (and
It is fully compatible with this modularity- likely evolved) before creatures’ abilities to
based conceptualism that some perceptual use them in inference. The resulting picture
processes output representations in preserves much of the letter—if not exactly
nonconceptual (e.g., iconic) formats. Instead the spirit—of traditional conceptualism.
of insisting on conceptual structure as a I will discuss two forms of stimulus-
transcendental epistemological requirement, independent use: re-combinability and
logical inference. However, I propose to This formulation runs into a
grant in general that there is some notion of counterexample: perception-based
stimulus (in)dependence that’s coherent demonstrative thought, which is stimulus-
enough to figure in a candidate condition on dependent but cognitive (Beck, 2018, pp.
concept possession. What matters for 328–329). Beck’s way of responding to this
present purposes is the following claim: A counterexample is to add the condition
concepts are the sorts of mental phenomena that every element of a representation must
that can only occur in creatures that can be stimulus-dependent for the representation
deploy them independently of what their (and the process that produces it) to be
transducers are doing at the moment. It is perceptual (2018, p. 330). Since
not entirely clear how we ought to demonstrative thoughts have concepts as
understand stimulus dependence. Lots of elements—e.g., the concept red is the
mental activity might happen to be prompted predicative element in the thought that is red
by a pattern of stimulation and happen to —and concepts are redeployed able
end when stimulation ends, but this wide net elsewhere, demonstrative thoughts fail this
might capture a messy variety of mentation additional criterion. However, this additional
rather than a natural kind. One could criterion simply rules out the possibility of
reasonably demand well-defined, testable deploying concepts in perceptual systems by
characterizations of stimulation and fiat. It seems like a largely empirical
dependence thereupon, and difficulties will question of whether humans can deploy
surely arise in trying to provide them (see concepts perceptually (Jacobson & Putnam,
Beck (2018) for careful discussion of the 2016; Mandelbaum, 2018). Our theories
details). shouldn’t build on the impossibility of this
I’ll also put aside a particularly strong form scenario to avoid counterexamples.
of the claim at issue. Beck (2018) argues One available move for Beck’s view would
that perception and cognition are be to distinguish states and processes:
distinguished using stimulus independence: concepts are stimulus-independent states,
a state/process is but they can be deployed via stimulus-
perceptual if it is stimulus-dependent and dependent perceptual processes. On this
cognitive if stimulus-independent. relaxed condition, however, perception-
based demonstrative thoughts again
represent a counterexample. Thus, Beck’s thinkable thoughts (e.g., Chomsky,1986).
version of the stimulus-dependence criterion The requirement of recomb inability has
faces a dilemma: avoid demonstrative roots in Evans’ Generality Constraint: “If a
thought as a counterexample but render subject can be credited with the thought that
perceptual deployment of concepts a is F, then he must have the conceptual
impossible by Viator allow for the resources for entertaining the thought that an
perceptual deployment of concepts but isG, for every property of being Gof which
succumb to the counterexample. My main he has a conception” (1982, p. 104). The
target is not the thesis that perception should Generality Constraint is regularly taken as a
be analyzed in terms of stimulus constitutive condition on concept
dependence, but instead, the hypothesis that possession.
having concepts constitutively requires the
ability to use them in a stimulus-independent
way—call that hypothesis stimulus- OBJECTS, PREDICATION, AND
independence. THE SYNTAX OF PERCEPTION
It’s compatible with stimulus independence
that perception is constituted by something
In the context of language and cognitive
completely unrelated, such as proprietary
processes, "objects," "prediction," and "the
representational formats or modularity. It’s
syntax of perception" are all relevant
even compatible with this hypothesis (so
concepts. Let's break them down:
stated) that concepts could be deployed via
stimulus-dependent processes. As long as a Objects: In language and perception, objects
creature with the concept of red can deploy refer to entities or things that can be
that concept independently of stimulation, perceived or conceptualized. They can be
the creature might have some stimulus- concrete physical entities, such as a book or
dependent means of deploying it as well. a chair, or abstract entities, such as love or
The striking creativity and freedom of justice. Objects are typically referred to
human thought suggest that concepts are the using nouns or noun phrases in a sentence.
sorts of mental states that can be freely Prediction: Prediction is a fundamental
recombined into novel structures, forming aspect of language that involves making
the finite basis of indefinitely many statements or attributing properties to
objects. It is the process of using a predicate perception, and "the sound of birds singing"
(verb or verb phrase) to describe or provide is the object of perception.
information about an object. Predicates can
In summary, objects are the entities or things
express actions, states, or qualities of objects
being referred to, predication is the process
and are used to form complete sentences.
of describing or attributing properties to
For example: objects using predicates, and the syntax of
perception involves the grammatical
"The cat is sleeping." Here, "is sleeping" is
structures used to express sensory
the predicate that describes the action/state
experiences or perceptions in language.
of the object "the cat."
It’s important to distinguish prediction as an
"She is intelligent." In this sentence, "is
aspect of content (a structural feature of a
intelligent" is the predicate attributing the
proposition) and as an aspect of the format.
quality of intelligence to the object "she."
One might argue that a picture expresses
The Syntax of Perception: The syntax of predication in that its content predicates a
perception refers to the grammatical and property of some individual, but the
syntactic structures used to express predicate-argument structure is not explicit
perception or sensory experiences in in the structure of the vehicle (i.e., its
language. It involves describing what one format). Minimally, the predicate-argument
sees, hears, smells, tastes, or feels. structure requires that “some sort of
Perception-related sentences typically functional relation among syntactic
involve verbs or verb phrases that indicate constituent’s maps onto some sort of logical
the sensory experience, and objects that or metaphysical relation among the semantic
represent the things being perceived. values of those constituents” (Camp, 2007,

For example: p. 157). In a sentence like ‘This is a fish’,


“the syntactic relation of function
"I see a beautiful sunset." Here, "see" is the
application mirrors a metaphysical relation
perception verb, and "a beautiful sunset" is
of instantiation” (ibid.); the constituent
the object being perceived.
‘This’ corresponds to the individual, ‘fish’
"He heard the sound of birds singing." In corresponds to the property fish, and the
this sentence, "heard" represents the syntactic relation between them functions to
express the instantiation of fish by the predicted if the hammer were a constituent
individual. This sort of structure is a of the POR.
canonical example of predicate-argument
structure (where ‘fish’ functions as predicate
and ‘This’ as argument). Furthermore, at CONCLUSION
least some of the constituents of PORs This paper has provided a sketch of one
behave like ordinary predicative concepts form conceptualism might take that is
that denote categories like a hammer. grounded in perceptual, developmental, and
Explaining results such as Gordon and comparative psychology. In this sketch, our
Irwin’s (1996; 2000) and Jordan et al. most primitive capacities to track and
(2010)) (discussed above) requires positing enumerate objects employ conceptualized
discursive representations of categories like propositional structures. These structures
a hammer in PORs that (i) represent kinds later come to constitute a form of perceptual
independently of low-level features, (ii) evidence based on which we draw
transcend individual sensory modalities, and inferences about the perceptible world.
(iii) are mapped to lexical items. These Conceptuality is not constitutively
features are characteristic of concepts like a dependent on stimulus-independent
hammer. A salient alternative explanation is cognitive abilities but rather provides a
that the initial pre-viewed feature (e.g., representational basis out of which those
‘hammer’) simply triggers associations with abilities grow.
other features such as related word forms,
If one were pushed to summarize cognitive
images, and sounds. In that case, wordforms
semantics in several keywords, some proper
like ‘hammer’ should activate associated
candidates would be conceptualization
wordforms like ‘nail’. But while those
(which entails encyclopedic), construal (the
associations are triggered, they do not yield
cognitive capacity to conceptualize
any object-specific benefit (Gordon & Irwin,
experience in alternate ways), image
1996). Instead, the object-specific benefit is
schemas (schematic patterns of bodily
limited to information that falls under the
experience), and prototype-structured
concept of the hammer (e.g., the sound and
categorization. These principles are not
appearance of hammers), just as would be
restricted to lexical items, but underlie
linguistic structures at all levels, ranging
from morphemes, lexical items, and semi- Language learning relies on both innate
open idioms to semantically highly predispositions and experiential and
schematic grammatical patterns. cognitive abilities. Cognitive semantics
considers all linguistic structures as
The conclusion provided discusses various
inherently meaningful. Grammar is defined
aspects of cognitive semantics, including the
as a structured inventory of form-meaning
role of cognition in language and the
pairs, including morphemes, lexical items,
relationship between meaning and grammar.
and syntactic patterns. The cognitive view
Here is a summary of the main points
challenges the notion that compositional
covered in the text: Cognition is the mental
structures have purely derived meanings. It
process of acquiring knowledge and
suggests that speakers also store instances of
understanding through thought, experience,
compositional structures with their specific
and the senses. It is essential for perceiving,
meanings. Metaphors and metonymy are
processing, and understanding information,
fundamental cognitive processes that
making decisions, and producing
structure semantic categories. Metaphor
appropriate responses.
involves understanding one entity in terms
The brain is the physical basis of cognition, of another based on perceived similarity,
with billions of nerve cells and complex while metonymy involves using one entity
connections between them. Studies in to refer to another based on conceptual
rodents and non-human primates have contiguity. Metaphor involves mapping
contributed to our understanding of across different domains or frames, while
cognition and its disorders. Cognition is metonymy implies a shift within the same
controlled by discrete brain circuits domain. Metonymy can be motivated by
regulated by neurotransmitter systems. physical or conceptual contiguity, and it
Several brain chemicals, such as dopamine, allows speakers to focus on specific aspects
noradrenaline, serotonin, acetylcholine, in a given context. Cognitive linguistics
glutamate, and GABA, play important roles considers grammatical structures as
in cognitive processes. inherently meaningful. Constructional

Meaning in cognitive linguistics is viewed idioms, such as "work one's head off" or

as a product of cognitive processes rather "sing one's heart out," are viewed as

than a separate innate faculty of the mind. idiomatic expressions with both lexical and
grammatical constraints. Schematization and
analogy are driving principles in the
formation of more general grammatical
patterns. These patterns incorporate
evaluative or affective judgments and allow
for the integration of specific lexical items.
Overall, the text introduces cognitive
semantics, highlighting the role of cognition
in language and the interconnectedness of
meaning and grammar.
REFERENCE

Lemmens, Maarten 1998. Lexical Perspectives on Transitivity and Ergativity. Causative


Constructions in English. [Current Issues in Linguistic Theory 166]. Amsterdam and
Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Lemmens, Maarten 2002. The semantic network of Dutch zitten, staan, and liggen, In John
Newman (ed.) The Linguistics of Sitting, Standing, and Lying. Amsterdam and Philadelphia:
John Benjamins, 103–139.
Lemmens, Maarten 2006a. Caused posture: experiential patterns emerging from corpus
research. In A. Stefanowitsch and S. Gries (eds) Corpora in Cognitive Linguistics. Corpus-Based
Approaches to Syntax and Lexis. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter, 261–296.
Michaelis, Laura A. 2006. Construction grammar. In K. Brown (ed.) The Encyclopedia of
Language and Linguistics, Second edition, Volume 3. Oxford: Elsevier, 73–84.
Newman, John (ed.) 2002. The Linguistics of Sitting, Standing, and Lying. Amsterdam and
Philadelphia: John Benjamins
Bays, P. M., Wu, E. Y., & Husain, M. (2011). Storage and binding of object features in visual
working memory.
Neuropsychologia, 49(6), 1622–1631. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2010.12.023
Beck, J. (2012). The generality constraint and the structure of thought. Mind, 121(483), 563–
600. https://doi.org/10.1093/mind/fzs077
Beck, J. (2018). Marking the perception-cognition boundary: The criterion of stimulus
dependence. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 96(2), 319–334.
https://doi.org/10.1080/00048402.2017.1329329
Beck, J. (2019). Perception is analog: The argument from Weber’s Law. Journal of Philosophy,
116(6), 319–349. https://doi.org/10.5840/jphil2019116621
Fodor, J. A. (2007). The revenge of the given. In B. McLaughlin & J. Cohen (Eds.),
Contemporary debates in philosophy of mind (pp. 105–116). Oxford: Blackwell. Fodor, J. A., &
Pylyshyn, Z. (1988). Connectionism and cognitive architecture: A critical analysis. Cognition,
28, 3–71. https://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/2103.003.0002

You might also like