You are on page 1of 15

 volume 22, no. 10 0.

Introduction
 july 2022
Unlike those drawing on misogynist ideology to punish
women for “stepping out of line”—for aspiring beyond
their place, as it were—the hostile enforcer of gender
conformity relies on the ideology of gender binarism to

The Logic of
insist that the gender non-conforming person is entitled
to no space, no place, no existential entitlement. There is
no place for the gender non-conforming person to retreat
and exist as such. Retreat—conformity to the gender bi-

Misandrogyny
nary—entails annihilation, non-existence. (Watson 2020,
240)

Lori Watson is here describing what she calls “misandrogyny.”1 This


paper gives an account of misandrogyny as a system of mechanisms
and centers attention on misandrogyny’s targets, not its perpetrators
or their psychologies. In these ways, the account is modeled after Kate
Manne’s account of misogyny in Down Girl.
Manne’s account centers attention on its targets rather than
its perpetrators, and it characterizes misogyny as systemic rather
than psychological. Rather than suppose that misogyny requires its
perpetrator(s) to loathe women, Manne proposes that misogyny is

Jeff M. Engelhardt the “‘law enforcement’ branch of a patriarchal order, which has the
overall function of policing and enforcing its overall ideology” (Manne
Dickinson College 2019, 63). The ideology that misogyny enforces is constituted by pa-
triarchal norms and expectations that call women to give feminine-
coded goods to men: “[B]y the lights of patriarchal ideology, a woman
is often expected to play the role of a man’s attentive, loving subor-
dinate” (ibid., 57). Feminine-coded goods include sex, attention, care,
epistemic deference, and sympathy. When women don’t provide these
©  2022  Jeff M. Engelhardt goods, the mechanisms of misogyny put them back in their patriarchal
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons
1. Watson acknowledges that the term is suboptimal in that it suggests that
Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 3.0 License. all gender non-conforming persons are committed to androgyny. The term,
<www.philosophersimprint.org/022010/> however, captures “the hostility, both interpersonal and structural, that gen-
der non-conforming persons face” (Watson 2020, 237). I follow Watson in
using the term for these reasons while rejecting “the implication that gender
non-conformity entails androgyny” (ibid., 237).


jeff m. engelhardt The Logic of Misandrogyny

place with hostility, threats, and violence (ibid., 47). Misogyny targets psychological dispositions that encourage targeting GNC folk for vio-
women because they are women in a man’s world (not in a man’s mind), lence, and that erase GNC folks from view.
and it maintains the patriarchal gender hierarchy by keeping women In the remainder of this section, I develop a few preliminary points
in their subordinate place in a man’s world. that put the analysis in context and address some questions. Sections
On the account of misandrogyny developed here, it is likewise a 1–3 describe three kinds of misandrogynistic mechanisms. I divide the
law enforcement branch of a patriarchal2 order, not a psychological mechanisms according to the different ways that they push GNC folk
disposition. Where misogyny enforces the patriarchal gender hierar- into nonexistence. Mechanisms of assignment push individual GNC folk
chy, misandrogyny is a system of mechanisms that together police and into one patriarchal gender role or the other—typically (but not al-
enforce the gender binary of a patriarchal order. The gender binary ways) the role associated with their sex assigned at birth. Mechanisms
is constituted by norms that preclude the existence of persons who of assimilation make it so that GNC folk can’t access basic necessities or
aren’t consistently “read” either as a man (and only a man) or as a other goods unless we cease to be GNC and assimilate into the gender
woman (and only a woman). Misandrogyny thus polices and enforc- binary. These mechanisms push GNC folk into some place, any place
es exactly the nonexistence of people who are neither women (only) in the gender binary.4 Mechanisms of annihilation aim to bring it about
nor men (only). I’ll use “gender non-conforming folks” or “GNC folks” that GNC folk are nonexistent. They push GNC folk out of literal, so-
to refer to these targets of misandrogyny. (I’ll elaborate on the term cial, legal, institutional, or epistemic existence. In describing mecha-
below.) Whereas misogyny targets women because they ought to be nisms of annihilation in section 3, I focus on mechanisms that target
subordinate according to dominant gender structures, misandrogyny GNC folk for literal, physical death. It would take separate papers to
targets GNC folks because they ought not to exist according to domi- fully develop the ideas of social, legal, institutional, and epistemic
nant gender structures.3 Whereas misogyny pushes women down into nonexistence, and I won’t attempt it here.
their subordinate place, misandrogyny pushes GNC folks out of exis-
tence—either by pushing its targets out of literal or social existence or 0.1 Preliminaries
by pushing them into binary gender positions. Who are GNC folk?
Giving this account of misandrogyny reveals the unity in a number I use “GNC folk” to refer to misandrogyny’s targets. A person is GNC
of processes that target GNC folks, thereby pointing to the workings in this sense just in case they are not consistently situated among pa-
of a system that polices and enforces the gender binary. Misandrogyny, triarchal norms as either a man (only) or a woman (only). Loosely,
like misogyny, is best understood as a system that targets people who “GNC folk” refers to everyone who isn’t either a man or a woman ac-
are distinctively positioned in a gendered system. Rather than focus cording to patriarchal norms. Patriarchal norms not only call for women
on the psychological motivations of those who perpetrate it, it’s bet- to give feminine-coded goods to men; they also determine whether
ter to uncover the systems that victimize GNC people, that cultivate one is (situated at a time and place as) a woman, a man, both, nei-
ther, etc. In making sense of this, it can help to think that there are
2. I intend to follow Manne’s use of “patriarchy” and its cognates, according to
which it refers, broadly, to a system of gender-based dominance that divides
4. These mechanisms do not necessarily push one to conform to the gender
persons into binary genders (men and women) and privileges men.
assigned at birth. They structure the world in ways that make various neces-
3. Thanks to a referee for this journal for suggesting the latter clause in this sities and resources unavailable unless one assimilates to the gender binary.
sentence. Section 2 clarifies this point further.

philosophers’ imprint –  2  – vol. 22, no. 10 (july 2022)


jeff m. engelhardt The Logic of Misandrogyny

two “levels” of patriarchal norms. The norms that Manne describes, people who do not and would not identify as gender non-conforming,
the norms that demand feminine-coded goods from women, are at and it excludes some people who would identify as non-binary, agen-
a “higher” level. The “lower-level” patriarchal norms determine how der, genderqueer, gender non-conforming, etc. It includes many (but
people are situated in that hierarchy (if they’re situated in it at all).5 not all) cis people, many (but not all) transpeople, and many (but not
For example, the lower-level norms in the contemporary United States all) people who identify as non-binary, GNC, genderqueer, etc.
make it so that (with a lot of qualifications and caveats) a skinny White That’s because my aim in the paper is to articulate a system that en-
person with shoulder-length hair is more likely to be read as a woman. forces patriarchal norms. What makes one a target of that enforcement
These lower-level norms determine which parts of human bodies mat- is how one is situated among patriarchal norms. Similarly, Manne’s ac-
ter to determining gender in which contexts,6 which behaviors are to count of misogyny is about how people are situated in hierarchical pa-
be read as relevant to gender and how, which clothes and accessories, triarchal norms and how they’re targeted by patriarchy’s mechanisms
which jobs, which kinds of friendship, etc. etc. ad nauseam (cf. Ásta of enforcement. On the analogous view offered here, misandrogyny
2011; Butler 1990; 1993). Some people are situated among these norms is about how people are situated in patriarchy’s gender binary norms
such that they are consistently taken to be gender-conforming women. and how they’re targeted by its mechanisms of enforcement. Self-iden-
Others are situated such that they are consistently taken to be gender- tification, chromosomes, and genitalia may affect how one is situated
conforming men. “GNC folk” refers to everyone else. among patriarchal norms, of course, and when they do, they will af-
There are three important points to keep in mind about how I’m fect whether one is GNC or not. So self-identification, chromosomes,
using “GNC folk” here. genitalia, gender presentation, etc. can affect whether one is GNC or
First, note that my characterization is based on how persons are sit- not on the characterization given here. But they matter only insofar as
uated among patriarchal norms—it is not based on self-identification, they affect one’s positioning among patriarchal norms.
chromosomes, or genitalia. For instance, if Ze identifies as gender- Second, keep in mind that one’s positioning among patriarchal
queer, then there’s a case to be made that Ze is genderqueer; but if Ze is norms is influenced by various ideologies, stereotypes, myths, and cul-
consistently situated among patriarchal norms as a man, then Ze is not tural tropes. As Robin Zheng (among others) has pointed out, races
in the extension of “GNC folk” as I’m characterizing it here. Similarly, are often “gendered,” so that “Asians as a racialized group are stereo-
if Chitra identifies as a cis woman, but she isn’t consistently situated as typed as feminine,” and “Blacks as a racialized group … are stereo-
a woman among patriarchal norms, and she isn’t consistently situated typed as masculine” (Zheng 2016, 405–6). Such stereotypes plausibly
as a man among patriarchal norms, then Chitra is GNC as I’m defining contribute to how one is gender-positioned in various institutions:
it here. Thus, ”GNC folk” as I characterize its extensionincludes many Angela Davis suggests that conceptions of femininity centering White-
ness led to Black and Indigenous American women being incarcerated
5. This level of norms is “lower” in the sense that it is prerequisite to the higher- in men’s prisons in the nineteenth century (Davis 2003, 72). Similarly,
level norms. The lower level sorts us into the gender binary, and then the
higher level establishes a hierarchical ordering of the two sorts. Thanks to a insofar as gender conceptions in the West often center wealthy, young,
referee for this journal for pushing me to clarify the higher/lower metaphor non-disabled, White, straight, cis people, they make it so that class,
here.
age, ability status, race, sexual orientation, and gender identity, among
6. For example: hair, chest, and shoulders in many contexts but perhaps not at
elite weight-lifting events; musculature in the hands but not the feet; hair on other things, affect how one is positioned among patriarchal gen-
faces, arms, legs, and chests, etc. der norms. Patriarchal norms interact with norms of classism, White

philosophers’ imprint –  3  – vol. 22, no. 10 (july 2022)


jeff m. engelhardt The Logic of Misandrogyny

supremacy, ableism, ageism, heterosexism, and others to determine settler-colonial White supremacy situates Indigenous American non-
whether or not one is GNC. binary gender systems and the non-binary persons in those systems as
Third, I said above that misandrogyny targets anyone who isn’t having some distinctively GNC-coded goods in some cases.
consistently read as either a woman only or a man only. That’s a con- That said, the account of misandrogyny given here doesn’t require
venient shorthand, but “read” has stronger psychological connotations that there be GNC-coded goods under patriarchy. The analogy turns
than is appropriate here. Being read as neither a man (only) nor a on the enforcement of patriarchal norms. Where misogyny enforces
woman (only) will often correlate with being a target of misandrogyny, the norms of the gender hierarchy, misandrogyny enforces the norms
but the basis for being a target of misandrogyny is how one is situated of the gender binary. Where misogyny polices and enforces women’s
among patriarchal norms, not how one is read (although of course the role in the gender hierarchy, misandrogyny polices and enforces the
two are strongly correlated). nonexistence of GNC folks in the gender binary. Misogyny pushes
women down into subordinate gender roles; misandrogyny pushes
Are there GNC-coded goods? GNC folk out of existence.
There seems to be an obvious disanalogy between misogyny on
Manne’s account and misandrogyny as I’ve described it. Misogyny If there aren’t GNC-coded goods, what are gender binary norms like?
targets women in order to police and enforce patriarchal norms that In my view, there are three broad kinds of patriarchal norms that get
call for women to give feminine-coded goods to men. Misandrogyny, enforced by three kinds of misandrogynistic mechanisms. I sketch
I’ve said, targets GNC folk in order to police and enforce norms that them here and return to them in the sections below. The relevant
constitute the gender binary. The most straightforward way to push norms are unified in that they call us to expect and endorse the non-
this analogy would be to say that there are GNC-coded goods and existence of GNC folk. They do this in different ways. In some cases,
patriarchal norms that call for GNC folk to give these goods to men they call us to conform to our assigned birth genders and to expect
(or perhaps men and women). But are there any GNC-coded goods? that others will do the same. In other cases, norms of the same kind
If patriarchal norms give no place to GNC folk, isn’t it dubious that call us to conform to one binary gender or another, if not to one’s birth
they also mark some goods as GNC-coded? Rather, there should be no assignment. Remove bodily hair to be a woman; don’t remove it to be
such marking under patriarchy. a man. Grow long hair to be a woman; don’t to be a man. Build upper
For the reasons just suggested, I’m going to proceed as though body musculature to be a man; diet to be a woman. And so on. These
there are no gender non-conforming-coded goods under patriarchy. norms call us to rid ourselves of features that would make us gender
(Which isn’t to say that there are no GNC-coded goods! Just that pa- non-conforming, whether the gender we conform to “matches” one’s
triarchy doesn’t recognize any.) But I think the question is worth tak- sex assigned at birth or not, and they call us to expect that others will
ing seriously. Although it’s useful to describe the “logic” of oppressive likewise render their gender non-conformity nonexistent. I call these
systems when we’re articulating them, there are good reasons to think “norms of assignment.”
that they can be self-contradictory. Women, for instance, are expected In addition, patriarchal norms call us to endorse and expect that
to be both sexually available and chaste. It is not out of the question every person is either a man or a woman, no one is both, and no one
that GNC folk may be normatively positioned as both nonexistent and is neither. These norms are evident in how readily we accept, for in-
givers of some goods. It is worth considering, for instance, whether stance, gender binary bathroom options. In taking it that it’s acceptable

philosophers’ imprint –  4  – vol. 22, no. 10 (july 2022)


jeff m. engelhardt The Logic of Misandrogyny

(under patriarchal norms) for a school or public space to have gender not rich, White, hetero, cis, or otherwise privileged, that’s not enough.
binary bathroom options, it’s accepted that everyone is either a man An intersectional analysis should also “theorize misogyny and other
or a woman and no one is neither. In accepting that there won’t be forms of oppression as structurally interdependent,” and discussion of
any men in women’s rooms and there won’t be any women in men’s examples should include substantive analyses of the roles that other
rooms, it’s accepted that no one is both a woman and a man. The same forms of oppression play (Berenstain 2019, 1367). Insofar as the pres-
considerations apply, mutatis mutandis, for gender segregated prisons, ent analysis is modeled on Manne’s, it is reasonable to ask whether the
schools, dormitories, sports, and shelters, and for gender-markings on account given here also fails to be intersectional.7
government identification, gender-marked school uniforms, and gen- This section gives reasons to think that the analysis in this paper
der-marked professional dress. These all evidence what I call “norms is intersectional. I’ll point to influential accounts of what makes an
of assimilation.” analysis intersectional and to parts of the present paper that exhibit
In some of the more jarring cases, patriarchal norms call us to en- the relevant intersectional-making features.
dorse and expect that GNC folk have no place in society. These ex- Kimberlé Crenshaw is most often credited with coining the term
pectations are plausibly entangled with the two kinds of norms noted “intersectionality.” Crenshaw makes the case that analyses of oppres-
above. Expecting that everyone will eradicate features that don’t con- sion in terms of just one “axis” or issue—racial oppression, say—tend
form to one of the two binary genders can have a hint of the expecta- to focus attention on the most privileged members of an oppressed
tion that if we don’t eradicate those features, then there will be no place group (e.g., class-privileged Black men, class-privileged cis White
for us: we will be socially unwanted, undeserving of attention and women) and obscure (or at least leave unanalyzed) the mechanisms
care, without standing in economic, educational, political, and social that target the most vulnerable (e.g., poor Black women). (See, e.g.,
spaces. And accepting that gender binary bathrooms accommodate all Crenshaw 1989, 151–152.) In order to avoid theorizing that further en-
persons can give us the impression that not only is there no place for trenches privilege and obscures vulnerability, we should offer analy-
GNC folk in society but that’s how it ought to be—there ought to be ses that acknowledge multiple axes of oppression and focus on those
no place for GNC folk. Similar expectations show up in how normal who are disadvantaged by multiple axes—those who are situated at
it feels to many people that GNC folk are marginalized economically, the intersections of multiple axes of oppression. Thus, I focus on those
legally, socially, and institutionally. I’m not convinced that there are who are situated at the intersections of multiple axes of oppression.
distinctive patriarchal norms that underwrite these expectations; they For each mechanism of misandrogyny described below, I provide ex-
may be grounded in the kinds of norms noted above. But there are amples illustrating the mechanism working in concert with other axes
distinctive mechanisms that aim to bring it about that GNC folk have of oppression.
no place in society; I call them “mechanisms of annihilation.” But as Berenstain points out, it’s not enough merely to give ex-
amples that focus on persons disadvantaged by multiple axes of op-
Is this analysis intersectional? pression; we should also provide substantive analyses of those other
Some commentators have criticized Manne’s account of misogyny on forms of oppression. Each section below includes substantive (but of
grounds that it fails to be intersectional. For instance, Nora Berenstain course brief) discussions of forms of oppression that intersect with
charges that while Manne “makes room” for insights about intersect-
ing oppressions and includes examples involving women who are 7. I’m grateful to a referee for this journal for pressing me on this point.

philosophers’ imprint –  5  – vol. 22, no. 10 (july 2022)


jeff m. engelhardt The Logic of Misandrogyny

misandrogyny. In discussing mechanisms of assignment, for instance, It would be fruitful to identify more interactions on the various
I appeal to Angela Davis’s analysis of how women’s prisons reinforce playing fields Hancock mentions, and perhaps it would help to con-
gender, race, and class hierarchies. The section on mechanisms of as- sider other accounts of intersectionality, but I hope this suffices for this
similation engages with analyses of the war on terror and colonialism. relatively short piece.
Section 3 discusses mechanisms of annihilation in conjunction with
analyses of transphobia, White ignorance, and settler colonialism. Misandrogyny and transphobia
One reason that intersectional analyses include substantive discus- Many GNC folk who are targets of misandrogyny are trans. According
sion of various forms of oppression is that, as Berenstain says, they to a common misconception, every trans person has a binary gender:
“theorize misogyny and other forms of oppression as structurally inter- they have had medical interventions to transition away from one to
dependent.” Patricia Hill Collins says intersectional analyses draw on “the other” binary gender. But this conception conflicts with one of the
the insight that race, class, gender, sexuality, etc. operate as “recipro- more influential definitions of “transgender” in trans studies, namely,
cally constructing phenomena” (Collins 2015, 2). Similarly, Vivian May that given by Susan Stryker: “any and all kinds of variation from gen-
says intersectionality approaches “systems of oppression as enmeshed der norms and expectations” (Stryker 2008, 19). (The common mis-
and mutually reinforcing” (May 2015, 3). Accordingly, this paper pres- conception, of course, illustrates the invisibility of GNC folk.) If we
ents misandrogyny as interdependent and mutually reinforcing with take “gender norms and expectations” in this definition to refer to pa-
patriarchy, White supremacy, colonialism, heterosexism, imperialism, triarchal norms and expectations, then it would seem that everyone
and other systems of oppression. In section 2, for instance, I make the who is GNC is also transgender and vice versa.8 This overlap suggests
case that mechanisms of assimilation are mutually reinforcing with co- a question: Why say that what I’m describing here is misandrogyny
lonialism, White supremacy, and the targeting of undocumented im- rather than transphobia?
migrants. Each section discusses interdependencies between specific Scholarly and popular usage most often take “transphobia” to refer
mechanisms of misandrogyny and various other forms of oppression. to psychological biases and negative attitudes that target transpeople.
Ange-Marie Hancock proposes that, among other things, intersec- Take, for instance, Talia Mae Bettcher’s use: “I use the term transphobia
tional analyses identify four “playing fields” upon which race, gender, not necessarily to imply the fear of transpeople, but simply any nega-
class, etc. interact: “the hegemonic (ideas, cultures, and ideologies), tive attitudes (hatred, loathing, rage, or moral indignation) harbored
structural (social institutions), disciplinary (bureaucratic hierarchies toward transpeople on the basis of our enactments of gender” (Bet-
and administrative practices), and interpersonal (routinized interac- tcher 2007, 46). As Bettcher notes, such attitudes likely “lie at the root
tions among individuals)” (Hancock 2007, 74). This paper identifies of much violence against transpeople” (ibid.). This, I take it, gives us
intersections in each of these playing fields: we saw above that vari- reason to maintain a use of “transphobia” that refers to negative psy-
ous ideologies interact in determining the extension of “GNC folk.” chological attitudes.
We’ll see below that misandrogyny interacts with White supremacy,
8. Keep in mind, however, that there may be cases in which a person identifies
colonialism, and sexism on the structural playing field, with White su- as trans but is consistently situated among patriarchal norms as a woman
premacy and the war on terror on the disciplinary playing field, and only or a man only; in this case, I take it that the person is trans by virtue of
their self-identity, but they are not GNC on my definition because they are
with racialized social power, White conceptions of queerness, trans- not positioned among patriarchal gender norms and expectations as neither
phobia, homophobia, and racism in interpersonal interactions. a man only nor a woman only.

philosophers’ imprint –  6  – vol. 22, no. 10 (july 2022)


jeff m. engelhardt The Logic of Misandrogyny

This does not imply (and I don’t take Bettcher to be saying) that 1. Assignment
there aren’t systems of mechanisms—in addition to individual psycho- Norms of assignment call us to rid ourselves of features that would
logical attitudes—that target transpeople for violence. There are. In my make us gender non-conforming and to expect that others will do the
view, these mechanisms overlap considerably with the mechanisms same. Mechanisms of assignment enforce these norms. They enforce
of misandrogyny. Mechanisms of misandrogyny target anyone who the placelessness of GNC folk by assigning each of us to a specific
doesn’t conform to the gender binary, i.e., GNC folk. Many transpeo- position in the gender binary.
ple are GNC folk and vice versa. Accordingly, the mechanisms I de- We’re subject to mechanisms of assignment at least from birth. In
scribe here overlap considerably with mechanisms that target trans many hospitals in the United States and Europe, patriarchal gender
folk. But rather than repurpose the term “transphobia” to refer to these norms dictate that a newborn’s gender is fully determined by their
mechanisms, it is preferable to retain the term that refers to negative genitalia and hormones—these are the only features available to situ-
psychological attitudes toward transpeople. It’s important to have a ate a newborn among patriarchal gender norms. Consequently, patri-
term with that referent. Moreover, Lori Watson has introduced the archal norms don’t distinguish between a person who is intersex and
term “misandrogyny” for the purpose of referring to mechanisms that one who is gender non-conforming at this stage of life; intersex new-
target gender-non-conforming people. Since the term “transphobia” borns are often situated as gender non-conforming, and as such, they
is already in use for a different important purpose, and since “misan- are subject to mechanisms of misandrogyny. Their bodies are made to
drogyny” is already used to refer to mechanisms that target GNC folk, conform to the gender binary through sex assignment, surgeries, and
I use misandrogyny for that same purpose here, and I refrain from re- hormone treatments.
purposing “transphobia.” As Anne Fausto-Sterling (among others) has described, it is shock-
In addition, as a dominant binary trans narrative has emerged, it ingly common for practitioners to perform medical interventions on
may be that patriarchal norms that situate binary transpeople qua trans intersex newborns, altering their bodies so that they conform to the
have emerged as well, and these may be accompanied by distinctive gender binary. Upon the birth of a child whose genitalia are “either/
mechanisms of enforcement. An adequate account of transphobia as or, neither/both,” as Fausto-Sterling puts it, “the attending physician
a system of mechanisms should determine whether these possibilities … consults a pediatric endocrinologist and a surgeon, and they de-
are actual at present. That’s not my aim here. Consequently, the ac- clare a state of medical emergency” (Fausto-Sterling 2000, 45). They
count here would plausibly be inadequate as an account of systems of tell the parents that they can and will “identify the ‘true’ sex that lies
transphobia, and I discourage readers from thinking of it as one. underneath the surface condition” (ibid., 50). Once they do, they’ll use
So much for preliminaries. In the following sections, I’ve divided hormonal and surgical treatments to alter the child’s body to conform
the mechanisms that enforce misandrogyny into three kinds. I suspect to the gender assignment. As research shows and as intersex activ-
there are more, though, and I wouldn’t be surprised if there are better ists point out, such medical interventions are plausible violations of
ways to classify the mechanisms. I propose the following as a point of patient agency and likely contribute to later psychological distress
departure. (Ferrara and Casper 2018, 3). In addition, in order to maintain the pre-
sumed “naturalness” of the binary gender position to which a child has
been assigned, many parents and physicians don’t tell the child about

philosophers’ imprint –  7  – vol. 22, no. 10 (july 2022)


jeff m. engelhardt The Logic of Misandrogyny

the medical interventions they’ve undergone. Monica Casper reports Adult conversation often involves subtle mechanisms of assign-
that when she was the executive director of the Intersex Society of ment. Z Nicolazzo describes cases in which Black non-binary trans
North America (ISNA), “she was told repeatedly by activists that learn- students are pushed into binary gender assignments by subtle dismiss-
ing they were lied to by their parents and physicians was ‘far worse’ als from predominantly White queer student groups. These dismiss-
than any physical alteration to their bodies, although these too were als tend to characterize the Black non-binary students as not “trans
seen as damaging” (ibid., 3). enough,” leveraging racialized social power to police what is and isn’t
Throughout life, one is routinely punished for gender non-confor- “trans enough,” and illustrating the dominant conception of queerness
mity in ways that push one into a gender assignment. These punish- as White queerness (Nicolazzo 2016, 8–10; Logie and Rwigema 2014;
ments range from everyday gender policing to violent attacks. Every- cf. Clarke 2019, 911). One case focuses on Silvia, a Black non-binary
day gender policing includes bullying, taunts, nudges, and corrections trans college student who identifies as agender and multiply disabled,
whenever one steps out of gender conformity. In these cases, one is and who uses “she/her/hers” pronouns. Silvia is talking to a binary
often read as a failed or unruly man or woman (cf. Watson 2020, 240). trans man in the mostly White student group TransActions, which fo-
Bullying and taunts target one for being a failure; nudges and correc- cuses on trans issues and gender activism. As Silvia describes a date
tions aim to help one overcome one’s gender failures. Bullying and she’s been on, the other student says, “This conversation really proves
taunts for gender non-conformity are likely familiar from most readers’ that I’m not a woman” (Nicolazzo 2016, 10). The implication is that
personal experiences—as recipients, witnesses, and/or bullies. It’s lit- Silvia is a woman, and the differences between the speaker and Silvia
tle surprise that gender non-conforming children and adults are more revealed in the story suffice to establish that the speaker is not a wom-
likely to be targeted for bullying, harassment, and name-calling than an.9 But Silvia isn’t a woman either. She’s agender. Nonetheless, when
gender-conforming peers (Clarke 2019, 910). she tried to describe aspects of her life to a predominantly White trans
Nudges and corrections often come from parents, teachers, coach- group, she was subtly pushed to interpret her experiences as those of
es, and friends. Children who wear the “wrong” clothes, play with a cis woman. Prima facie, binary gender norms and racial norms that
the wrong toys, play the wrong sports, play too aggressively or too position queerness as White conspired to preclude the possibility of
passively, speak in the wrong ways, walk in the wrong ways, etc. etc. Silvia’s being Black, trans, and non-binary. When she tried, she was as-
are often thereby situated among patriarchal norms as gender non- signed to cis womanhood by her White peers’ subtle dismissals—dis-
conforming. They are then subject to mechanisms of assignment that missals deriving their power partly from mutually reinforcing mecha-
push them back into a gender assignment by disapproving looks or nisms of misandrogyny, White supremacy, and ableism.
remarks; by having toys, activities, or clothes hidden or taken away, Because these mechanisms push us into being either a man (and
by pressure to join gender-conforming activities, sports, friend groups, not a woman) or a woman (and not a man), they often differ in how
and so on. Meanwhile, teens and adults, especially those read as AFAB they push us: the ways they push one to be a man differ from the ways
(assigned female at birth), might receive humiliating nudges or cor- they push one to be a woman. This is manifest when mechanisms
rections that push them toward their perceived gender assignment: 9. If it helps, you can think of Silvia’s conversation in terms of Mary Kate Mc-
advice on makeup, clothes, hair styles, social passivity, etc. or for those Gowan’s conversational exercitives. Silvia’s peer makes a conversational move
that is “fair play” only if Silvia is a woman. If no one objects, then it is sub-
read as AMAB (assigned male at birth), exhortations to be more ag- sequently permissible in the conversation to take it that Silvia is a woman
gressive, dominant, muscular, etc. (McGowan 2009).

philosophers’ imprint –  8  – vol. 22, no. 10 (july 2022)


jeff m. engelhardt The Logic of Misandrogyny

of assignment are violent. Katherine A. Rimes and colleagues (2019) in women’s prisons was to encourage and ingrain ‘appropriate’ gen-
compared victimization experiences of non-binary and binary trans der roles, such as vocational training in cooking, sewing and cleaning”
youth according to sex assigned at birth. They found that AFAB study (1996, 95; cited in Davis 2003, 71). As institutionalized mechanisms of
participants, both binary and non-binary, were more likely than non- assignment, such regimes pushed AFAB persons into binary feminine
binary and binary AMAB (assigned male at birth) participants to expe- gender roles.
rience sexual abuse. Rape and sexual abuse push one into a woman’s In addition, by pushing “fallen women” into training that empha-
patriarchal position by extracting feminine-coded goods. They “make” sized domestic labor, women’s prisons reinforced gender, race, and
their targets women by forcing a “failed woman” or a “disobedient class hierarchies. They prepared more affluent women for domestic
woman” into the patriarchal feminine sexual role (Rimes et al. 2019, lives of financial dependence on husbands, and they “steered poor
237). Meanwhile, when mechanisms of assignment violently push one women (and especially Black women) into ‘free world’ jobs in domes-
into a man’s role, they often aim to provoke one into enacting patriar- tic service” (Davis 2003, 70). Moreover, since Black and Indigenous
chal masculinity. They try to goad the target into violence, dominat- American women were often segregated from incarcerated White
ing others, or sexual abuse of women. This may explain why Rimes women, sentenced to men’s prisons, or exposed to the convict lease
and colleagues found that AMAB study participants, both binary and system, these “feminized” women’s prisons reflected and reinforced
non-binary, were more likely than non-binary and binary AFAB par- conceptions of femininity that center Whiteness (ibid., 72).
ticipants to experience physical assault (ibid., 237). Although mechanisms of assignment often push GNC folk into
Much work on early women’s prisons reveals both (i) how they their assumed birth assignment, they don’t always enforce conformity
enforced the gender binary and (ii) how misandrogyny can be mutu- with one’s birth assignment; they enforce conformity to the binary,
ally reinforcing with misogyny, White supremacy, and class domina- whether one is pushed to conform to one’s birth assignment or to the
tion. Angela Davis characterizes AFAB convicts in a way that resem- so-called opposite gender. Dean Spade describes how medical institu-
bles Lori Watson’s remark that presumed AFAB GNC folk are seen as tions enforce and stabilize the gender binary by making conformity
“failed women”: “According to dominant views [during the nineteenth to binary gender norms and dominant binary trans narratives pre-
century], women convicts were irrevocably fallen women. … [F]emale requisite for access to gender-affirming surgeries or hormones. “The
criminals were seen as having transgressed fundamental moral prin- ‘successful’ daily performance of normative gender is a requirement
ciples of womanhood” (2003, 70). Prison reformers didn’t challenge for receiving authorization for body alteration” (Spade 2006, 319). In
the idea that women convicts were fallen women but that they were some cases, one is expected to “live in the new gender role … for 1 to
beyond redemption. As a path to redemption, reformers proposed 2 years in order to experience life in the new role and develop appro-
prisons that would push criminalized AFAB persons to assimilate to priate role behaviors” (Shore 1984, 277). In most cases, one must ac-
White, middle-class domestic roles. Reporting on a prison described quire letters from two mental health experts and document persistent
by Elizabeth Gurley Flynn, Davis says their regimes were “based on gender dysphoria.10 Take these points in the context of surgeries that
the assumption that ‘criminal’ women could be rehabilitated by as- 10. One is often also required to rehearse a dominant narrative according to
similating correct womanly behaviors—that is, by becoming experts in which one identified with “the opposite gender” from a young age. As Spade
points out, this both (i) reinforces the invisibility of non-binary transpeople
domesticity—especially cooking, cleaning, and sewing” (ibid., 63). As and (ii) makes it seem as though only people who have identified with “the
Joanne Belknap put it, “[A]n important role of the reform movement opposite gender” from a young age experience gender dysphoria in a way

philosophers’ imprint –  9  – vol. 22, no. 10 (july 2022)


jeff m. engelhardt The Logic of Misandrogyny

affirm the genders of cis women or men: breast augmentation, plastic dormitories, sports, prisons, shelters, and recovery centers are com-
surgery, hair implants, and so on. As Spade points out, one doesn’t mon. They organize physical, institutional, legal, and social space in
need letters from two psychiatrists or to live “as a small-nosed woman” ways that make appropriate places for people who are men (and not
for years before being granted access to rhinoplasty (Spade 2006, 315). women) and appropriate places for people who are women (and not
There are no restrictions on medical interventions that contribute to men). If you are both or neither, then patriarchal gender segregation
gender conformity, and they are often covered by medical insurance organizes the world such that there is no place for you. If you want to
(Spade 2011, 148–149). But similar interventions are denied unless or use the bathroom, live in a dormitory, play a sport, or access a shelter
until it’s proved that they won’t contribute to gender non-conformity. for homelessness, addiction, or to escape abuse, then you will often
In these cases, mechanisms of assignment punish GNC folk and push have to assimilate into the gender binary; this means you must stop
us into gender conformity by inhibiting access to medical services and being both/neither, conceal your gender non-conformity, or let oth-
making gender conformity a necessary precondition for treatment. ers overlook it. If you are incarcerated or sent to a gender segregated
school, shelter, or care facility, you will be presumed to be (only) a
2. Assimilation man or (only) a woman. Gender segregated spaces serve to enforce
Mechanisms of assimilation push GNC folk into the gender binary by the nonexistence of GNC folk and push us into the gender binary.
making basic necessities and goods available only to persons who as- More and less official gender binary markers also push us to assim-
similate to some binary gender. Whereas mechanisms of assignment ilate. Government identifications and applications for jobs, schools,
push us into some assigned place in the gender binary—usually the scholarships, etc. often require one to choose a binary gender. (At
gender associated with one’s presumed birth assignment—mecha- present, seventeen countries, eighteen US states, and the District of
nisms of assimilation push us to be somewhere, anywhere in the gender Columbia allow non-binary gender designations on at least some of-
binary. Mechanisms of assignment enforce the placelessness of GNC ficial documents.) Many schools that aren’t gender segregated have
folk by assigning individual people into binary gender roles; mecha- gender-marking uniforms. If Ze is neither a boy nor a girl or both a
nisms of assimilation enforce the same by pushing GNC folk to assimi- boy and a girl, then there is no appropriate uniform for Ze to wear. It
late into physical, institutional, legal, and social spaces that allow only is currently legal for employers to prescribe sex-differentiated dress
for binary gender roles. Mechanisms of assignment push triangular codes (Clarke 2019, 978), and, in any case, “professional attire” is often
(oval, rectangular, trapezoidal, etc.) blocks into round holes or square relative to the wearer’s presumed binary gender. If one is neither/both,
holes. Mechanisms of assimilation produce lids (for buckets of blocks) then one is less likely to be read as “professional” during interviews or
that have only round and square holes. other formal interactions for jobs, schools, scholarships, court hear-
Readers are likely aware that the organization of physical, insti- ings, etc. Gender-coded identification, dress, and customs exclude
tutional, legal, and social space is such that there is often no place GNC folk and reinforce our placelessness.
for GNC folk qua GNC. Gender segregated bathrooms, schools, Things have improved in some cases—some universities, airports,
worth taking seriously. Consequently, when any person P experiences dis- shopping malls, restaurants, etc. have all gender or single-occupancy
comfort with their assigned gender role (as most people do), the dominant bathrooms, for instance, and there are ongoing attempts to recognize
narrative tells us to ask whether P identified with “the opposite gender” from
a young age or not. If so, then P is binary trans. If not, then P is not trans at all
and should “remain” in their assigned binary gender role.

philosophers’ imprint –  10  – vol. 22, no. 10 (july 2022)


jeff m. engelhardt The Logic of Misandrogyny

non-binary genders on US passports.11 But the fact remains that pa- a target for mechanisms of assimilation. Moreover, the ways that she
triarchal gender binary norms call for accommodations that exclude has been assimilated in different cases combine to make for another
GNC folk. Where they do, mechanisms of assimilation make it so that violation of patriarchal gender norms. Binary gender norms preclude
there is no place for us unless we assimilate to some binary gender. the possibility of persons who are “M” in some cases and “F” in oth-
As Lori Watson puts it, we must “adopt a gender or fail to have a so- ers, and yet this is what her records show. Consequently, those who
cial existence” (Watson 2020, 240). Assimilating to the gender binary consult her records in the light of patriarchal gender norms may target
is necessary not only for accessing resources but for having a social her for further exclusion, marginalization, or violence. This includes
existence at all. If you fail to satisfy binary gender norms, you won’t employers who do background checks or who require documentation
have a social identity, and you won’t be recognized as intelligibly hu- that confirms information on one’s job application; it includes police,
man (cf. ibid.). Mechanisms of assimilation structure the world so that officials checking documents for travel, and bureaucrats involved in
social standing, respect, recognition, and moral worth are distributed processing applications for other official documents. As Spade points
in ways that exclude GNC folk.12 out, in the context of the war on terror, when such discrepancies show
When mechanisms of assimilation push GNC folk into the gender up in the gender records of persons already subject to increased sur-
binary, they sometimes push a single individual into different binary veillance—thanks to their race or immigration status—it can make
positions in different cases; when they do, they are especially punitive, them a target for interrogation, detention, and violence (Spade 2011,
and they often reinforce (and are reinforced by) other mechanisms of 146). Similarly, in the case of Black, Brown, and Indigenous persons
oppression. Dean Spade gives an example. already targeted for incarceration and violence by state systems, dis-
crepancies in one’s gender records offer an occasion for incarceration
[F]or example, one person born in New York and living in
and state violence.
New York might have a birth certificate she cannot change
The dangers of “inconsistent” records have increased as the United
from “M” to “F” because she has not had genital surgery; a
States has increasingly targeted undocumented immigrants. In ef-
driver’s license that correctly reflects “F” because she got
forts to identify undocumented immigrants, US government agencies
a doctor’s letter; Social Security records that say “M” be-
that collect identifying data now regularly compare their data looking
cause she cannot produce evidence of surgery; a name
for “mismatched” information on individuals. (Previously, data had
change order that shows her new feminine name; and a
been shared only during specific investigations.) When they find it,
Medicaid card that reads “F” because the agency had no
they might threaten to revoke the individual’s driver’s license, pres-
official policy and the clerk felt the name change order
sure their employer to rectify the “discrepancy,” etc. (Spade 2011, 151).
and driver’s license were sufficient. (Spade 2011, 145)
These new policies expose immigrants and anyone whose gender re-
Whether this person identifies as binary or non-binary, she is situated cords “conflict” to harassment and exploitation by employers, violence
among patriarchal norms as gender non-conforming, and thus she is from police or ICE, and loss of access to government services and ben-
efits. Here, misandrogyny facilitates surveillance of undocumented
11. See H.R. 5962 for federal legislation that would allow a non-binary gender
identification. immigrants while the targeting of undocumented immigrants for ha-
12. Thanks to a referee for this journal for suggesting that I expand on this point rassment, exploitation, and violence exposes GNC folk to the same.
in this way.

philosophers’ imprint –  11  – vol. 22, no. 10 (july 2022)


jeff m. engelhardt The Logic of Misandrogyny

Mechanisms of assimilation have played significant roles in colo- plausibly helped reinforce binary gender norms and mechanisms of
nialism. Colonial efforts to assimilate Indigenous peoples, for instance, misandrogyny.14
often included enforcing binary gender norms on communities that
had recognized non-binary genders for generations (see, e.g., Mor- 3. Annihilation
gensen 2010, 111–116). Moreover, Indigenous violations of binary Mechanisms of annihilation aim to bring it about that GNC folk are non-
gender norms were often taken as justification for forced assimila- existent. They push GNC folk out of literal, social, legal, institutional,
tion. Mark Rifkin shows how “policies aimed at assimilating Indians or epistemic existence. If mechanisms of assignment push triangu-
… figured Indian cultures as other than heteronormative in order to lar (oval, rectangular, trapezoidal, etc.) blocks into square and round
reinvent and assimilate them as straight, private property-owning, holes and mechanisms of assimilation produce systems that have only
married citizens.”13 Andrea Smith has argued that sexual violence and round and square holes, then mechanisms of annihilation discard, dis-
“the imposition of European gender relationships on Native commu- count, and destroy blocks that aren’t round or square.
nities” even enabled European colonization of Native peoples (Smith Readers are probably already aware that fatal violence against trans
2005, 139). Ifi Amadiume describes how, prior to colonialism, the gen- and gender non-conforming people is rampant. According to numbers
der system of the Nnobi society in southeastern Nigeria allowed for compiled by Transrespect Versus Transphobia Worldwide, at least 350
what Amadiume calls “male daughters” and “female husbands.” But trans and gender non-conforming people were murdered from the
under colonialism, the institutional and social structures supporting beginning of October 2019 to the end of September 2020; dispropor-
these gender positions were condemned, abandoned, and reinter- tionately many were Black women or women of color, sex workers,
preted in order to assimilate the culture to the patriarchal gender bi- migrants, and/or poor. Although many of us mourn these murders
nary (Amadiume 1987, 123). In these cases and others, mechanisms of annually on Trans Day of Remembrance, patriarchal norms that call
assignment, assimilation, and annihilation work in concert to serve for the nonexistence of GNC folk often position them as justified—it’s
the purposes of colonialism. Cultures that recognize more than two supposed to be that we don’t exist. In recounting the 2008 murder of
genders or that allow more gender non-conformity were forced to re- Latisha King, Gayle Salamon makes the case that “in many instances
organize themselves to fit the patriarchal gender binary. Individuals of violence against gender-nonconforming people and transpeople …
who were non-binary were subject to mechanisms of assignment— violence justifies itself by characterizing non-normative gender as it-
“gendered and sexual reeducation” (Morgensen 2010, 114). Individuals self a violent act of aggression and reading the expression of gender
and communities who didn’t assimilate were subject to mechanisms identity as itself a sexual act” (Salamon 2018, 5). The defense in the Lati-
of annihilation (ibid., 111–117; Smith 2005, 178). The mechanisms of sha King murder trial pursued a “gay panic” defense, in which a man
misandrogyny in these cases conjoined with racist, religious, and Eu- presumed to be straight claims that he was thrown into a panic by a
rocentric ideologies to enact and justify genocide and exploitation. gay man’s sexual advances and thereby led to allegedly justified vio-
Meanwhile, the need to legitimize colonial genocide and exploitation lence. Salamon attended the trial and reports that the defense team of-
fered “no evidence of explicitly sexual aggression on Larry’s [Latisha’s]
part,” but that instead, “no sexual provocation was required because
13. Schneider 2007, 606–607, referring to Rifkin 2006. Cited in Morgensen 2010,
108. 14. Thanks to a referee for this journal for pointing this out.

philosophers’ imprint –  12  – vol. 22, no. 10 (july 2022)


jeff m. engelhardt The Logic of Misandrogyny

Larry’s feminine gender was already a panic inducing provocation” (ibid. 5, slurs. When she arrived at the hospital, some doctors refused to treat
emphasis in original). According to the logic of a gay panic defense, a her and some assumed she was HIV+. She died about an hour after
man seeks to exculpate himself from violence by appealing to the re- arriving at the ER.
vulsion and rage of being the object of a gay sexual advance. On these As noted above, intersex newborns are often positioned as GNC
lawyers’ extension of that defense, an AMAB person’s mere expres- folk at birth and targeted by mechanisms of assignment. Intersex fe-
sion of a feminine gender is similarly threatening and similarly an ex- tuses, meanwhile, are often targeted by mechanisms of annihilation.
cuse for violence. Their case, in short, was that Latisha’s mere gender Kwon Chan Jeon and colleagues report on the regularity with which
non-conformity justified her being the target of violence. The violence intersex fetuses are targeted for termination (Jeon et al. 2012).
justifies itself, as Salamon says. Talia Mae Bettcher describes much the As noted in the previous section, mechanisms of annihilation are
same in the murder of Gwen Araujo and her murderers’ appeal to a often mutually reinforcing with colonial oppression. Scott Lauria Mor-
“trans panic defense” (Bettcher 2007, 44). gensen points out that “[c]olonists interpreted diverse practices of
The case of Latisha King illustrates one intersection of mechanisms gender and sexuality as signs of a general primitivity among Native
of annihilation and mechanisms of White supremacy. Latisha King peoples. Over time, they … framed Native peoples as queer populations
was biracial and identified as Black; in one pretrial hearing, a gang marked for death” (Morgensen 2010, 106, emphasis added). He reports,
expert testified that her murderer, Brandon McInerney, was affiliated for instance, that when European-descended explorers encountered
with a White supremacist group (Salamon 2018, 39–40). One would non-binary Indigenous peoples in North America, their response was
expect these facts to inform public understanding of the murder and less often to single out the non-binary individuals for violence and
subsequent trial. But media reporting and the trial focused on King’s more often to subject their communities to “military attack, contain-
gender non-conformity (ibid., 25–37). The press seemed to ignore the ment, or removal” (ibid., 113). In conjunction with settler colonialism
relevance of White supremacist violence to the murder. On the one and racism, mechanisms of annihilation targeted entire communities
hand, the focus on King’s gender non-conformity—rather than on her for nonexistence.
murderer’s White supremacy—bolsters Salamon’s claim that accord- In addition to taking away the physical lives of GNC folk, mecha-
ing to patriarchal norms, King’s own gender expression was the cause nisms of annihilation also target us for social, legal, institutional, and
and justification of the murder. On the other hand, the refusal to ac- epistemic nonexistence. One would like a precise definition for each
knowledge the role that White supremacy might have played in the of these “kinds of nonexistence,” but I won’t provide any here. None-
murder is plausibly a consequence of what Charles Mills calls “White theless, I take the general idea to be relatively straightforward: when
ignorance,” wherein epistemic norms warped by a White supremacist mechanisms of annihilation aren’t literally destroying GNC folk, they
political system call knowers to ignore the causes and consequences serve to marginalize us to such a degree that we have no social, legal,
of racial oppression (see Mills 1997; 2007; see also Medina 2012 35) institutional, or epistemic standing. As Lori Watson says:
Mechanisms of annihilation are also manifest in medical neglect,
Gender non-conforming persons … are perceived as oc-
abortion of intersex fetuses, and genocide. In August 1995, Tyra Hunt-
cupying a space of contradiction: human and not intel-
er was in a car accident that left her badly injured; when EMTs arrived
ligibly human. Their bodies and self-presentation do not
and uncovered her genitalia, they stopped treating her for 5–7 crucial
fit within the schema of intelligible humanity. Normative
minutes while they made transphobic jokes and used racist and sexist

philosophers’ imprint –  13  – vol. 22, no. 10 (july 2022)


jeff m. engelhardt The Logic of Misandrogyny

notions of humanity carry with them the gender binary. Belknap, J. 1996. The Invisible Woman: Gender, Crime, and Justice. Bel-
One is never simply a human. They are a kind of human, mont, CA: Wadsworth.
a man, a woman, a member of a racial group, and so on. Berenstain, N. 2019. Down Girl: The Logic of Misogyny by Kate Manne.
(Watson 2020, 240) Mind 128(512): 1360–1371.
Bettcher, T. M. 2007. Evil deceivers and make-believers: On transpho-
When we’re situated among patriarchal norms as “not intelligibly hu-
bic violence and the politics of illusion. Hypatia 22(3): 43–65.
man,” we don’t have social, legal, institutional, or epistemic standing.
Bohrer, A. J. 2019. Marxism and Intersectionality: Race, Gender, Class and
The mechanisms that enforce those norms see to it.
Sexuality under Contemporary Capitalism. Bielefeld: Transcript Verlag.
4. Conclusion Butler, J. 1990. Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion of Identity.
New York: Routledge.
Misandrogyny is a system of mechanisms that—together with other
———. 1993. Bodies That Matter. New York: Routledge.
systems of oppression—enforces the norms that constitute the patriar-
Clarke, J. A. 2019. They, them, and theirs. Harvard Law Review 132(3):
chal gender binary. According to those norms, everyone is either only
894–991.
a man or only a woman; GNC folk don’t exist. Misandrogyny enforces
Collins, P. H. 2015. Intersectionality’s definitional dilemmas. Annual
this nonexistence by (i) assigning GNC folk to a binary gender and
Review of Sociology 41: 1–20.
punishing non-conformity to that gender, (ii) assimilating GNC folk
Crenshaw, K. W. 1989. Demarginalizing the intersection of race and
and cultures into the binary gender system, and (iii) eliminating GNC
sex: A black feminist critique of antidiscrimination doctrine, femi-
folk and cultures. Although much has been written on gender policing,
nist theory and antiracist politics. University of Chicago Legal Forum
binary gender norms, transphobia, and other topics related to misan-
1989(1): 139–167.
drogyny, we also need to appreciate that misandrogyny is a system
Davis, A. 2003. Are Prisons Obsolete? New York: Seven Stories Press.
of mechanisms that punishes those who violate binary gender norms.
Fausto-Sterling, A. 2000. Sexing the Body: Gender Politics and the Con-
Future work should elaborate further on how misandrogyny intersects
struction of Sexuality. New York: Basic Books.
with other systems of oppression, including misogyny, transphobia,
Ferrara, M., and Casper, M. 2018. Genital alteration and intersex: a
White supremacy, ableism, classism, and settler colonialism; and it
critical analysis. Current Sexual Health Reports 10(2): 1–6.
should spell out how mechanisms of annihilation bring about social,
Hancock, A.-M. 2007. When multiplication doesn’t equal quick addi-
legal, institutional, and epistemic nonexistence.
tion: Examining intersectionality as a research paradigm. Perspec-
References tives on Politics 5(1): 63–79.
Jeon, C. J., L. Chen, and P. Goodson. 2012. Decision to abort after a
Amadiume, I. 1987. Male Daughters, Female Husbands: Gender and Sex in
prenatal diagnosis of sex chromosome abnormality: A systematic
an African Society. London: Zed Books.
review of the literature. Genetics in Medicine 14(1): 27–38.
Ásta Kristjana Sveinsdóttir. 2011. The metaphysics of sex and gender.
Logie, C. H., and Rwigema, M.-J. 2014. “The normative idea of queer
In Feminist Metaphysics: Explorations in the Ontology of Sex, Gender
is a white person.” Understanding perceptions of white privilege
and the Self, Charlotte Witt (ed.), 47–66. New York: Springer.
among lesbian, bisexual, and queer women of color in Toronto,
Canada. Journal of Lesbian Studies 18(2): 174–191.

philosophers’ imprint –  14  – vol. 22, no. 10 (july 2022)


jeff m. engelhardt The Logic of Misandrogyny

Manne, K. 2019. Down Girl: The Logic of Misogyny. New York: Oxford Spade, D. 2006. Mutilating gender. In The Transgender Studies Reader,
University Press. Susan Stryker and Stephen Whittle (eds.), 315–332. New York:
May, V. 2015. Pursuing Intersectionality, Unsettling Dominant Imaginaries. Routledge.
New York: Routledge. ———. 2011. Normal Life: Administrative Violence, Critical Trans Politics and
McGowan, M. K. 2009. Oppressive speech. Australasian Journal of Phi- the Limits of Law. Brooklyn, NY: South End Press.
losophy 87(3): 389–407. Stryker, S. 2008. Transgender History. Berkeley, CA: Seal Press.
Medina, J. 2012. The Epistemology of Resistance. Oxford: Oxford Univer- Watson, L. 2020. Gender policing: comments on Down Girl. Philosophy
sity Press. and Phenomenological Research 101(1): 236–241.
Mills, C. 1997. The Racial Contract. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Zheng, R. 2016. Why yellow fever isn’t flattering: A case against ra-
—2007. White ignorance. In Race and Epistemologies of Ignorance, Tuana, cial fetishes. Journal of the American Philosophical Association 2(3):
N. & Sullivan, S. (eds), SUNY Press, pp. 11–38. 400–419.
Morgensen, S.L. 2010. Settler homonationalism: Theorizing settler co-
lonialism within queer modernities. GLQ: A Journal of Lesbian and
Gay Studies 16(1–2): 105–131.
Nicolazzo, Z. 2016. “It’s a hard line to walk”: Black non-binary trans*
collegians’ perspectives on passing, realness, and trans*-norma-
tivity. International Journal of Qualitative Studies in Education 29(9):
1173–1188.
Rifkin, M. 2006. Romancing kinship: A queer reading of Indian edu-
cation and Zitkala-Sa’s American Indian Stories. GLQ: A Journal of
Lesbian and Gay Studies 12(1): 27–59.
Rimes, K.A., N. Goodship, G. Ussher, D. Baker, and E. West. 2019. Non-
binary and binary transgender youth: Comparison of mental health,
self-harm, suicidality, substance use and victimization experiences.
International Journal of Transgenderism 20(2–3): 230–240.
Salamon, G. 2018. The Life and Death of Latisha King: A Critical Phenom-
enology of Transphobia. New York: New York University Press.
Schneider, B. 2007. Oklahobo: Following Craig Womack’s American
Indian and queer studies. South Atlantic Quarterly 106(3): 599–613.
Shore, E. 1984. The former transsexual: A case study. Archives of Sexual
Behavior 13: 277–285.
Smith, A. 2005. Conquest: Sexual Violence and American Indian Genocide.
Cambridge, MA: South End Press.

philosophers’ imprint –  15  – vol. 22, no. 10 (july 2022)

You might also like