You are on page 1of 24

PL15CH21-GrzymalaBusse ARI 18 April 2012 8:29

ANNUAL
REVIEWS Further Why Comparative Politics
Click here for quick links to
Annual Reviews content online,
including:
Should Take Religion
• Other articles in this volume
• Top cited articles
• Top downloaded articles
(More) Seriously
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2012.15:421-442. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org

• Our comprehensive search


Anna Grzymala-Busse
Department of Political Science, University of Michigan, Ann Arbor, Michigan 48109;
by King's College - London on 09/02/13. For personal use only.

email: abusse@umich.edu

Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2012. 15:421–42 Keywords


The Annual Review of Political Science is online at religious doctrine, ethnicity, the nation-state, institutions, political
polisci.annualreviews.org
economy of religion
This article’s doi:
10.1146/annurev-polisci-033110-130442 Abstract
Copyright  c 2012 by Annual Reviews. The study of religion holds great promise for the study of identity,
All rights reserved
institutional origins, the state, and the strategies of institutional actors in
1094-2939/12/0615-0421$20.00 comparative politics. Doctrinal differences translate into distinct patterns of
state institutions, economic performance, and policy preferences. Religious
attachments affect voting and popular mobilization. Churches can become
powerful institutional players that lobby, influence policy, and form effective
coalitions with both secular and denominational partners. Finally, natural
religious monopolies and (conversely) resolutely secular countries show
how churches have played a central role in the struggle of nations and states.
The relationship is thus mutual: religion influences political attitudes and
institutions, and politics affects religious practice and political activity.

421
PL15CH21-GrzymalaBusse ARI 18 April 2012 8:29

INTRODUCTION
Comparative politics, and especially the study of institutional origins and organizational actors,
has much to gain from a serious consideration of faith, doctrine, and religious hierarchies. First,
for scholars of ethnicity and identity, religion presents new analytical challenges. Unlike other
attributes, many religious identities are not fungible, or easily altered, and conversion costs do
not simply follow from the distance traveled. Even small doctrinal differences can become insur-
mountable, making religious identities uniquely costly to change. Second, in the development of
institutions and policy, these doctrinal differences translate into distinct configurations of secular
institutions. Organized religion also exerts an outsized influence on policy making: although the
vast majority of even very religious electorates want churches to stay out of politics, churches in
many democracies influence policy in domains ranging from abortion to education to the wel-
fare state.1 Third, scholars of the state can learn about the conditions under which state action
depresses religiosity or generates strong religious attachments, allowing natural monopolies to
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2012.15:421-442. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org

arise. Examining the role of religion also invites us to disaggregate the nation-state: at various
times, the state has opposed the nation, and the latter found a powerful ally in religious leaders
and organizations.
by King's College - London on 09/02/13. For personal use only.

This review article seeks to show why comparative politics needs to take religion more seriously.
To do so, it first focuses on the political importance of religious identity and doctrine. It then
examines the impact of religious hierarchies and doctrine on politics, in areas as varied as voting,
welfare-state configurations, and public policy. Finally, it examines how politics affects religion,
as well as the resulting political economy of religion, reviewed brilliantly in this journal by Gill
(2001). This literature has both brought rigor and overturned conventional wisdom in precisely
specifying how competition, rather than state support, can generate a vibrant religious scene.
Throughout this discussion, religion is defined as a public and collective belief system that
structures the relationship of the individual to the divine and the supernatural. It often implies
particular practices and behavioral constraints, a moral code, and a division between the sacred and
the secular. These attributes both reinforce the belief in the divine and distinguish one religion
from another. Because it is public and collective, religion and its claims continually come up against
politics, and vice versa. Because it is a belief system that cannot be disconfirmed, the claims of reli-
gion on politics can be absolute and irrefutable (but also open to symbolic, as opposed to material,
concessions; see Atran et al. 2007). Several other distinctions are analytically salient: between re-
ligion as an identity and as an ideology, among the different measures of religiosity (participation,
faith, affiliation) and its intensity, and above all, among different doctrines, or specific professed
beliefs about the sacred. Because much of the comparative literature has focused on Christianity
and politics, this review only briefly mentions works on Islam and other religions. It also focuses
on comparative politics; for a recent review of religion in global politics, see Philpott (2009).

THE POWER OF RELIGION?


To examine the mutual constitution of religion and politics, we first need to take religion seriously.
First, how is religion different from other identities, such as ethnicity, class, or nation? Are these
simply fungible, or is there something unique about religion? Second, if religion matters, how and

1
Surveys of 57 European and Latin American countries show that an average of 71% respondents did not want religious
authorities to influence politics, 78% did not want influence on the vote, and 71% did not want influence on the governments.
The lowest percentage of respondents within any one country was 51% (Grzymala-Busse 2010, World Values Surveys 1999–
2004, and the International Social Survey Programme, 1999–2009).

422 Grzymala-Busse
PL15CH21-GrzymalaBusse ARI 18 April 2012 8:29

when do religious doctrines make a difference? Political science has viewed religious identities
and doctrines as labels, functionally fungible but holding little substantive content of interest to
scholarship. As a result, numbers and distance have mattered more than content: we care more
about the prevalence of a given identity or religion, and assume that conversion costs are in direct
proportion to the distance traveled from the original identity or set of beliefs. Social scientists
have either empirically ignored or undertheorized the differences between and within Islam,
Catholicism, Protestant Christianity, Judaism, etc.—yet it is often these doctrinal differences that
matter the most, not only to the adherents and practitioners of these religions, but to the causal
impact religion has on politics.

Religion as a Unique Identity?


If religion can serve as both ideology and identity, are its claims unique? For many scholars,
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2012.15:421-442. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org

especially those working in the fields of ethnicity and ethnic politics, they are not. Prominent
analyses of ethnicity view religion as one dimension of ethnic cleavages, which can fall along lines
of race, religion, language, caste, tribe, etc. (Chandra 2004, Posner 2005, Bellin 2008). In these
by King's College - London on 09/02/13. For personal use only.

accounts, the import of identity lies not in the “passions it inspires or the traditions it embodies”
but in the “information it conveys about the expected behavior of other political actors” (Posner
2005, p. 104). Posner goes perhaps the farthest here, arguing that “all of the identities in a person’s
repertoire are equally important components of who they understand themselves to be” (2005,
p. 138). The emphasis is on both religion as one of many potential criteria for membership in
ethnic groups (see Chandra 2012) and the analytical and empirical fungibility of these attributes.
Language, tribe, religion, or race can all be “activated,” and none are intrinsically more compelling
than others in this perspective.
What could make religion different from other markers of identity? It is not its communal
nature, its ability to define interests, or its conferral of meaning on human endeavor: ethnicity,
nation, and language have that in common. But there are differences of both degree and kind.
First, religions make transnational claims across enormous populations: they are probably the
largest unit to which individuals claim loyalty. Islam, for example, claims roughly 1.5 billion
adherents, or roughly 22% of the world’s population, making it bigger than the most populous
nation (China has 1.3 billion citizens). Christianity claims more than 2 billion, or 33% of the
world’s population. These religions transcend national boundaries and have made claims about
authority that challenge nation-state boundaries (the resurrection of the Caliphate, or the Vatican’s
transcending secular state jurisdictions). Even though national religious traditions often differ,
even within the same international denomination, religion is unique in the implicit alternative it
offers to secular organization of state boundaries, both because religion transcends secular borders
and because it offers an alternative set of principles by which to organize life. This has meant that
transnational religious authority can undermine and threaten existing forms of the state, as it
already did in early modern Europe (Nexon 2009).
Second, religion is an unusually demanding identity. Some religions make claims about every
aspect of their adherents’ lives, ranging from their political views to dress codes and dietary
restrictions to where they may work, live, or travel. Beyond these quantitative differences, however,
“religion is concerned with the supernatural; everything else is secondary” (Stark & Finke 2000,
p. 90). The consequent fear of damnation or exclusion may “enable religious organizations to exert
on their members pressure unimaginable in most secular organizations” (Wald et al. 2005, p. 132).
Above all, religious identities (and, more precisely, religious practice) uniquely offer the promise
of supernatural goods, of salvation and nirvana. As a result, these identities may not be as pliable
as ethnic ones are often claimed to be: abandoning a given religion may mean eternal damnation.

www.annualreviews.org • Comparative Politics and Religion 423


PL15CH21-GrzymalaBusse ARI 18 April 2012 8:29

Ironically, in the eyes of would-be religious persecutors, other people’s religions are shallow, errant,
and fraudulent and can easily be changed. In fact, they must be changed; forcing conversion is the
only way to save souls and remove a source of spiritual pollution. Thus, persecutors see violence as
a justifiable and rational policy, despite the apparent absurdity of trying to force different religious
beliefs on someone by violence.2
Third, precisely because the stakes are so high and involve eternal reward and punishment,
religion can also withstand secular onslaught that would eradicate other communal identities.
Religious organizations are much harder to repress than are unions, newspapers, political groups,
or student organizations (Sahliyeh 1990, p. 13). Decentralized religions are especially difficult to
suppress: it would be difficult to eliminate all the clergy or places of worship in predominantly
Protestant or Muslim countries. The clergy often have little to lose. For them, the costs of par-
ticipation, even in risky and costly communal mobilization, are dwarfed by the costs of inaction,
since by inaction they stand to lose their congregations. This may be why the more public the
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2012.15:421-442. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org

protest of local clergy under communism, the greater their communal authority and legitimacy
(Wittenberg 2006).
These quantitative and qualitative differences mean that religion may be a unique form of
by King's College - London on 09/02/13. For personal use only.

identity, and we should avoid simply treating it like any other fungible marker. At the very least,
the transnational claims of religion and the intensity of its demands on its followers suggest that we
need to take these variables into account when examining the political implications of individual
and collective identities. This is especially the case because religion interacts with and reinforces
other identities: ethnic religious groups are extremely vigorous (Putnam & Campbell 2010; for a
very different view, see Stark & Finke 2000). Its ideological cognates (doctrine), association with
entrenched institutions (hierarchies and networks of places of worship), and emphasis on collective
ritual make religion a potent reinforcer of other identities. The result is that many secular identities
may have latent religious components as well (Mitchell 2006, Trejo 2009).

Religions Are Not (Always) Fungible: Taking Doctrine Seriously


Doctrinal differences further differentiate one religious group from another. Doctrine is the set of
beliefs and indicated practices espoused by a given religious denomination. Doctrine thus struc-
tures both thought and practice. There are several aspects to doctrinal differences: for example,
religions differ in their “salvific merit,” which “connects the perceived probability of salvation
to a person’s lifetime activities” (McCleary & Barro 2006, p. 51). Some, like Catholicism or
Buddhism, score very highly. Others, like Calvinism, do not. Religions also have a “political the-
ology,” or “shared ideas about legitimate political authority” (Philpott 2007, p. 505), which affects
how the religious authorities view political regimes and policies and how they then mobilize
their faithful. Doctrines differ even within denominations. As Stepan (2000) points out, religions
are “multivocal”—Islam, Western Christianity, and Confucianism each contain multiple voices,
perspectives, political views, preferred practices, and emphases on different beliefs. To be an ac-
tively participating evangelical Protestant itself means a variety of activities and organizational
belongings.
Doctrinal differences have immediate political implications. As we will see in the next sec-
tion, they can foster different individual political views, secular state institutions, and economic

2
This point applies to Christianity more than Islam. Once the Islamic community was defined historically, its focus was
on making Muslims better Muslims rather than on conversion. I am grateful to David Smith and Pauline Jones Luong for
bringing up this distinction.

424 Grzymala-Busse
PL15CH21-GrzymalaBusse ARI 18 April 2012 8:29

outcomes. Differences and similarities in doctrine may also create distinct (and unexpected) po-
litical alliances and conflicts: for example, the evangelical–Catholic prolife coalition of the 1990s
in the United States, or the conflict between the autocrat/Islamicist disavowal of human rights
as “Western imperialism” and the Catholic Church, which opposed this assault on what it saw as
universal human values at the Vienna World Conference on Human Rights in June 1993 (Weigel
1999, p. 26). It is for this reason that scholars working with public opinion surveys such as the
General Social Survey (GSS) have begun to recategorize religious traditions (Steensland et al.
2000) to reflect the nominal differences in religious denominations (rather than simply placing
them on a fundamentalist–liberal spectrum), and to take account of the differences not only among
denominations, but also between affiliation and belief (Steensland et al. 2000).
There are also political implications to the internal organization of denominations that are
influenced by doctrine. Catholic hierarchies support and are supported by the need for mediation
between God and the believers, whereas the belief in an immediate and direct relationship between
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2012.15:421-442. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org

God and the faithful in some Protestant denominations supports a much flatter hierarchy with no
clear leadership or lines of authority. As a result, the political impact of Catholics and Protestants
may vary. The Catholic Church has insisted on the universality of its doctrine and its political
by King's College - London on 09/02/13. For personal use only.

relevance—and has both the experience and the organization to enforce these convictions (Martin
1999, p. 40). Evangelicals and other Protestants have long carried on traditions of separation of
church and state (and a suspicion of the corrupting influence of politics), speak with multiple voices
rather than an ideological monopoly, and have far less experience in holding secular power. The
structure of the religion thus shapes the degree and type of influence its members seek to exert on
politics.
A final implication of doctrinal differences is that only some religions are fungible—that is,
individuals can convert to another religion without paying significant theological or social costs.
Within American Protestantism, for example, it is relatively easy to change churches or denom-
inations, and “church shopping” is an accepted practice. Across non-Protestant denominations,
however, conversions become considerably more complicated (Bruce 2000). Even in the United
States, the religious market par excellence, where roughly 40% of Americans have switched from
their parents’ religion (Putnam & Campbell 2010, p. 137), it is enormously more difficult to switch
into or out of Orthodox Judaism or Mormonism than it is to switch among evangelical Protes-
tant denominations. Conversion costs can be high even if the ideological or doctrinal differences
involved are relatively small. In fact, as the tragic history of the Uniates, Orthodox–Catholic con-
flict, or Shia–Sunni–Sufi conflicts shows, conversion costs can be highest for closely proximate
denominations. Apostates (those who abandon a religious tradition) and heretics (those who adopt
unorthodox religious views) are the transgressors most heavily punished by religious bodies. This
further suggests that religious monopolies may reflect not state regulation but extreme social
pressures to remain within a given denomination.
At the same time, we cannot infer political preferences from doctrine alone. Doctrine interacts
with secular structures and pressures to produce distinct configurations of influence, institutions,
and policy (de Swaan 1988, p. 85). As the Fundamentalism Project shows, even the ostensibly
unchanging doctrines of fundamentalist sects are reworked and reinterpreted over time and across
groupings (Marty & Appleby 1991–1995), and the rise of fundamentalism is a backlash against
secular political developments and innovations as much as it is an expression of religious orthodoxy.
Similarly, the overrepresentation of Islam in civil wars has far more to do with elite religious
outbidding and the susceptibility of societies to such outbidding than to intrinsic qualities of Islam
(Toft 2007). The Taliban, Hamas, and Hezbollah, meanwhile, are such effective forces of violence
not only because of their religious beliefs, but also because of their resilient and cohesive structure,
focused as it is on enhancing team effort, preventing free riding and defection, and obtaining

www.annualreviews.org • Comparative Politics and Religion 425


PL15CH21-GrzymalaBusse ARI 18 April 2012 8:29

credible signals of commitment from its members (Berman 2009, Iannaccone & Berman 2006,
Berman & Laitin 2008). Doctrine is critical, but it does not act alone.
Similarly, there can be as much internal variation in preferences and strategies within a given
religious body as there is among denominations, as the various national strategies of the Roman
Catholic Church show (Warner 2000, Philpott 2007). Just as national churches may vary in their
doctrinal focus, shared doctrine does not presuppose the same political strategies or influence.
Primarily Catholic countries, from Poland to Italy to France, show very different patterns of
Catholic church behavior, emphases, and teaching. The American Conference of Bishops empha-
sized social justice and nuclear disarmament until the 1990s—while their counterparts in Ireland
fought the liberalization of divorce laws. Nor is there a single Catholic strategy: instead, church
tactics have varied over time and across countries, with different national versions of Catholicism
as a result.
Two significant implications for the study of identity and institutions follow from an attention to
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2012.15:421-442. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org

doctrine. First, the costs of switching religions can vary enormously, and not necessarily in direct
proportion to the actual doctrinal differences. Similarity does not imply fungibility, and some
identities are far more difficult to change than others. Second, doctrine matters as an ideology
by King's College - London on 09/02/13. For personal use only.

that serves to influence both institutional creation and individual behavior. Religion can thus
provide the mechanisms by which symbols, traditions, rituals, and myths influence social and
political interactions. This specification of mechanisms is critical for cultural accounts, which have
tended to underspecify mechanisms ( Johnson 2002, p. 227). Taking doctrine seriously allows us
to delineate the mechanisms of cultural influence, both by identifying which issues are relevant to
religious organizations and by suggesting how religious doctrine and its secular context interact.
If doctrinal differences affect political expectations, institutional configurations, religious po-
litical coalitions, and the fungibility of religion, then they need to be taken more seriously than
the current literature has done. Rather than a label that can be costlessly changed, denomination
is a stickier plaster that adheres, often painfully. Without an appreciation (at the least) of doctrinal
differences, or a serious effort to theorize them, the relationship between religious ideas and sec-
ular institutions, the variance in political strategies and effectiveness of different denominations,
and political coalitions among religious bodies become difficult to explain. In short, religion can
influence public policy, secular institutional configurations, and regime durability. In examining
this causal impact, we need to be sensitive both to the independent roles played by doctrine and
religious organization and to the interactions between religious convictions and the secular state.
The state can support or repress religion—but it is just as fundamentally shaped by religious
convictions, ideas, and popular mobilization.

HOW RELIGION AFFECTS POLITICS


How can comparative politics benefit from a serious consideration of religion and its role in
politics? Religion has had clear and significant, if not always intuitive, impacts in several domains.
This section discusses its influence on voting and political behavior; the power of religious bodies
as institutional players, lobbyists, and coalition partners; religion’s role in the origins of institutions
(and long-term political outcomes); the impact of religion on attitudes toward and policies of social
welfare; and its broad influence on regime type and durability.

Faith and Political Behavior


Religion influences political behavior in both directly shaping views on political issues (through
doctrinal affinities) and indirectly implying support for specific policies and regimes (through the

426 Grzymala-Busse
PL15CH21-GrzymalaBusse ARI 18 April 2012 8:29

organizational support and mobilization of religious authorities and institutions). Religion can
thus function not only as a source of communal loyalty and shared identity and understandings,
but also as a powerful ideology, a set of normative principles and claims about how the world ought
to function. Several analyses have accordingly focused on the role religion plays in determining
political attitudes and behavior on the individual level. For example, religious individuals are
more likely to be motivated to pay taxes and comply with tax regulations (Torgler 2006), and
religious countries appear to have lower crime rates (Hull 2000). Doctrinal differences matter here:
Protestants, for example, have a lower “tax morale” than other religious people, perhaps because
they view their success as based on effort and view the poor and unemployed as responsible for
their plight (Furnham 1983).
A long-standing tradition sees religion as important to voting behavior (Rose & Urwin 1969,
Lijphart 1979, Roemer 1998). Those who are religiously committed are more conservative in
their worldviews than the nonaffiliated or unbelieving (Hayes 1995). Beyond these general state-
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2012.15:421-442. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org

ments, however, the impact of religiosity on political views is not straightforward. Membership in
doctrinally very conservative denominations, such as fundamentalist Protestants, correlates with
partisanship, but only through particular issue positions: thus, religious beliefs affect issue posi-
by King's College - London on 09/02/13. For personal use only.

tions, which in turn produce partisan leanings ( Jelen 1993). The impact of religious affiliation on
political attitudes such as tolerance, however, is heavily dependent on the degree of commitment
or intensity of belief and practice (Beatty & Walter 1984). Within denominations, the growing
differentiation and fragmentation among American Protestants, for example, has meant that the
category of “Protestant” has lost analytical value even as doctrinal conservatives are increasingly
Republican, and a new cleavage based on religious commitment may be emerging (Layman 1997,
2001).
Although religious commitment matters for partisanship in the United States, its impact else-
where is far less clear. Conservative Christianity in the United States is associated with conservative
stances across domains of public policy. In contrast, otherwise conservative religious Europeans
hold more liberal attitudes on transnational issues such as European integration or foreign aid
than their secular neighbors (MacIver 1989). Similarly, Islamic piety pushes respondents toward
political conservatism more in secular societies, and less so in religious ones [where presumably
religiosity does not differentiate respondents as much as it would in a secular society (Tessler
2002)]. More broadly, support for political Islam does not presuppose antidemocratic attitudes:
in several cases, this relationship is either nonexistent or mediated by gender (Tessler 2002).
Here, in asking how religion influences political views, we need to better specify which aspect
of religion matters. “Religion” is frequently included in a battery of control variables in regressions
examining political behavior, along with educational attainment, age, race, and gender, without
regard for how belief, affiliation, or observance might matter. Moreover, belief, participation, and
belonging are three distinct dimensions of religiosity (Layman 1997, 2001 Eisenstein 2006, Jelen
& Wilcox 2002, Beatty & Walter 1984). Belief is an internalized and personal adherence to the
doctrine and to the sacred: the personal level and kind of faith, acceptance of church doctrine,
and relationship to the deity, the sacred, and religious teachings. Commitment, or participation,
is activity within the church(es): attending services, evangelizing, and meeting with other church
members. In many ways, this is a measure of the intensity of religiosity, or the degree to which
the believer is willing to sacrifice time and effort in the name of religion. Belonging, or affili-
ation, is a much weaker connection to a religion than participation: in many cases, it is simply
self-identification, or a nominal belonging to a given organized religion. Even though this may
be the weakest indicator of personal religiosity, it “traditionally has been the only religious vari-
able in studies of political behavior” (Layman 1997, p. 289). It is often unclear which of these
specifications might be the most important in a given study and why. Yet, as we will see, one

www.annualreviews.org • Comparative Politics and Religion 427


PL15CH21-GrzymalaBusse ARI 18 April 2012 8:29

important approach (the political economy of religion) focuses on participation whereas another
(demand-side explanations) focuses on belief. Their findings conflict, but this may be simply a
function of the specifications chosen. Just as importantly, “religion” interacts with other salient
factors. As the studies above suggest, the impact of religious beliefs or belonging is likely to be
mediated by the intensity of observance or commitment.

Religious Authorities as Political Players


Religious organizations are political actors who engage in alliances, support specific political
formations, and structure social and political cleavages. In medieval and early modern Europe,
churches legitimated monarchical rule in Europe (and often acted as a competing source of political
authority and power). Religion was thus never far from the rise of the state. In one particularly
nuanced argument, religious denominations influenced the regime types that arose in early modern
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2012.15:421-442. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org

Europe: where Calvinist insurgents could rely on strong traditions of representative government,
constitutionalism was preserved. Conversely, where such a movement or traditions were lacking,
absolutism prevailed (Gorski 2003).
by King's College - London on 09/02/13. For personal use only.

In the modern era, religious authorities readily became involved in democratic politics. The po-
litical activities of churches and the coalitions they form have influenced the formation of political
party systems and the maintenance of governments (Kalyvas 1996, Warner 2000). The fundamen-
tal cleavages driving the formation of parties and broader political conflict were between church
and state, as the secular state wrested control over education, poverty relief, and legitimation from
religious authorities. This is the familiar story of the formation of long-lasting political cleavages
in European politics (Lipset & Rokkan 1967, Rokkan 1981). More recently, however, this story
has been elaborated to show how clerical–anticlerical divides brought together disparate secular
politicians in some countries, such as France, and why parties of Catholic religious defense had
an ambivalent relationship to democratization, thanks partly to the church authorities’ suspicion
of popular democracy (Gould 1999, Ertman 2009, Van Kersbergen & Manow 2009). Again, the
doctrine and hierarchical structure of Catholicism influenced its political role and prescriptions.
Religious authorities founded political movements and political parties, as the story of Christian
Democracy in Europe and Turkish Islamic parties shows (Kalyvas 1996, Altinordu 2010). Thus,
the Roman Catholic Church inadvertently fomented the rise of Christian Democratic parties
in Western Europe.The Roman Catholic Church attempted to stave off a liberal challenge in
nineteenth-century Europe by lending its support to lay Catholic movements—only to see them
acquire an autonomous life of their own and transform themselves into Christian Democratic
parties that were only tenuously connected to the Church (Kalyvas 1996). These parties had both
an uneasy and fundamental relationship to the Church, gaining organizational autonomy and
retaining doctrinal affinities (van Kersbergen 1994, Kalyvas & van Kersbergen 2010, Grzymala-
Busse 2011).
Moreover, churches act strategically to form coalitions and influence policy. Subsequently,
these Christian Democratic parties were but one potential coalition partner for the Church in
Europe as it sought to form political alliances with incumbent parties, exchanging government
policy concessions for electoral mobilization by the Church on behalf of the parties (Warner
2000). The Roman Catholic Church after World War II acted to prevent communist rule in Italy
and other countries, and it formed coalitions with right-wing governing parties that exchanged
policy concessions for considerable political support and electoral mobilization that would ben-
efit the right-wing incumbents. Here, if we think of the Church as an interest group, then sev-
eral considerations influence whether it will form an alliance with a political party, such as the

428 Grzymala-Busse
PL15CH21-GrzymalaBusse ARI 18 April 2012 8:29

extent to which it can obtain its goals elsewhere, the costs of supplying its own politicians, the
stability and popularity of the ally, and the “core competencies” of the Church (Warner 2000,
p. 30). In exchange for policy concessions, the Church can provide access to its organizational re-
sources, reputation, training of campaign staff, voter education, votes, and financing (Warner 2000,
p. 29).
What is less clear from this scholarship is the portability of the findings outside of the immediate
context. Although these studies carefully acknowledge both the cross-country differences and the
possibility of internal factions within the churches, they tend to focus on the Roman Catholic
Church, which may be uniquely suited to act (and be studied) as a unitary political actor, being
“renowned for its centralization, bureaucratization, and hierarchical organization” (Bellin 2008,
p. 326). It is less clear whether the more decentralized Protestant churches or other religious
traditions are cohesive as institutional players, or agile as economic firms, to the extent that the
medieval Roman Catholic Church was (Ekelund et al. 1996).
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2012.15:421-442. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org

Churches also lobby legislatures and set the political agenda. They can select and increase
the salience of issues and lead voters to evaluate politicians according to criteria they set out—
framing and priming, respectively (Scheufele 2000). Critically, popular religiosity appears to be a
by King's College - London on 09/02/13. For personal use only.

necessary condition for religions to influence politics—but popular demand for religious influence
on politics is not. Churches have framed policy debates and obtained their preferred policies even
when popular majorities overwhelmingly disapprove of church influence on voting and policy
making (Grzymala-Busse 2010). Here, the churches’ doctrinal preferences interact with their
moral authority and institutional access. As a result, we see variation in policy outcomes across
similarly Catholic countries, in domains such as abortion, gay rights, stem cell research, and
education (Minkenberg 2002, 2003). For example, abortion is restricted to saving the life of the
mother in Ireland and Poland but is available freely in ostensibly Catholic Italy and Croatia.
Similar variation can be observed in Latin America (Htun 2003, Hagopian 2009).
In examining how churches act as institutional players, at least two notes of caution apply. First,
as noted above, only some religious organizations have the capacity to act as unitary institutional
players, and even those need to satisfy additional conditions: “religious groups must come to
consider political action as a sacred obligation, draw on various internal resources to prosecute
that action, and confront a political environment that may hinder such efforts” (Wald et al. 2005,
p. 140). In other words, they need to hold grievances, obtain organizational capacity, and encounter
favorable political opportunity structures that offer influential secular allies.
Second, if religious organizations make doctrinal demands, only some societies and polities
will be responsive. The demand for religion may vary at the national, not just individual, level:
in effect, some countries’ “intercept” or “baseline” religiosity is higher or lower than others’, and
we should explain that difference, rather than focusing only on the variance around the mean.
We thus need a richer account of the social and political resonance of religion: both its ability to
retain adherents in spite of their disapproval of church political activity and its ability to forge a
variety of political alliances to obtain policy goods. One hypothesis might be that some societies,
despite their disapproval of church political activity, are more receptive to religious framing of
politics owing to long-standing fusion of religious and national identities. In many cases where
religion has been fused with nationalism, secular nationalism is replaced with new loyalties and
motives for conflict that are more compelling and less negotiable than secular nationalist ones
alone ( Juergensmeyer 1993, 2008). Where the churches had earlier protected the nation against
either a repressive domestic state or a hostile colonial power, for example, they gained the moral
authority that subsequently translated into policy success; and as we will see, such protection may
also lead to durable and high popular religiosity.

www.annualreviews.org • Comparative Politics and Religion 429


PL15CH21-GrzymalaBusse ARI 18 April 2012 8:29

Religion and Institutional Origins


Religion—and the denominational differences in doctrine that bring with them specific ideas and
norms regarding appropriate institutional solutions—can influence both the choice of institutions
and the long-term outcomes. Woodberry’s (2011) analyses of the impact of Protestant mission-
aries go the farthest. He argues that Protestant churches and missionaries (and their Catholic
counterparts where they faced Protestant competition) promoted mass literacy, printing, and
the rise of several institutions. They developed civil society, both directly and in response to
their missionary efforts; they fostered rule of law, by mobilizing white colonial settlers (the
more independent the missionaries from sponsor states, the more they could speak out against
injustices and demand reform); and they minimized market regulation, e.g., by advocating
the breaking of monopolies and opposing forced labor. Education, in turn, spurred social
mobility, opportunities for women, and long-term health improvements, among other favorable
outcomes. In a more moderate articulation of this thesis, Protestantism facilitates democracy:
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2012.15:421-442. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org

the doctrine encourages individual conscience, with the Bible as key authority rather than priests
or religious authorities, and its tenets “tend towards separation and independence from ancient
church structures and traditions as well as political authorities” (Woodberry & Shah 2004
by King's College - London on 09/02/13. For personal use only.

p. 48).
Specific institutional legacies are further laid at the hands of religion. Schooling has been a
central issue in the relationship between church and state. Both actors are in effect “taking an
option on the future by ensuring the control of education of children and adolescents” (Rémond
1999, p. 147). The gradual wresting of education from the church into the secular state’s hands
has been a signal process in the development of the state (De Swaan 1988)—and here again, de-
nominational differences played a considerable role in determining how these processes unfolded.
More recently, elements of doctrinal teaching, such as subsidiarity and transnational identities in
Catholic doctrine, have informed the organization and development of institutions such as the
European Union (whose founders, including Robert Schuman and Konrad Adenauer, were all
committed Roman Catholics).
Dominant religious doctrines shaped would-be state institutions even before the state was
founded. Lutheran, Calvinist, and Catholic doctrines each view the source of poverty differently
and see its moral import in distinctive ways. Accordingly, each church imposed different regimes of
poverty assistance in early modern Europe: integration, punitive work, and exclusion, respectively
(Kahl 2005, 2007). These distinctions do not map directly onto Esping-Andersen’s (1990) famous
typology of welfare regimes. As a result, several outstanding puzzles in the study of the welfare
state are resolved: for example, why the United States and United Kingdom hold individuals
responsible for their own poverty, whereas Scandinavian countries and Germany view poverty
relief as a social responsibility. Conversely, in several countries where traditional class- and party-
based accounts of the welfare state would lead us to predict sparse provisions for women and
children, we see instead a strong, progressive role for the state in family policy. The underlying
reason was church–state conflict in the nineteenth century, won by the secular liberal forces of
the nation-state (Morgan 2009).
Doctrinal differences play a critical role not only in the choice of secular state institutions
but also in religion’s broader relationship to the nation-state. Protestant free and reformed
churches have held a strongly antistate position, whereas Lutheran and Orthodox state churches
either “never questioned the prerogative of the central state in social policy and education”
(van Kersbergen & Manow 2009, p. 4) or actively embraced the state as a provider of resources
and a close partner. In contrast, the Catholic Church in the nineteenth century fought liberal
efforts to build modern nation-states, but it supported democratization efforts and ensured social

430 Grzymala-Busse
PL15CH21-GrzymalaBusse ARI 18 April 2012 8:29

peace in the twentieth-century transitions to democracy in Southern and Eastern Europe. Critical
to explaining this variation are doctrinal differences, both across religions and across time.

Religion’s Impact on Political Economy


Historically, welfare regimes, unemployment patterns, and educational expenditures have been
linked to doctrinal differences (Castles 1994, Kahl 2005, van Kersbergen & Manow 2009). A new
literature emphasizes religion’s impact on the political economy of the welfare state. Religion
here affects political economy in two ways. First, the conflict between church and state over
poverty relief has led to distinct patterns of subsequent welfare-state structure and provisions. In
turn, welfare-state provisions depress religious observance and participation, as state provisions
substitute for church amenities (Gill & Lundsgaarde 2004). This relationship may also explain
why some of the greatest political conflict in church–state relations occurred over the provision
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2012.15:421-442. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org

of welfare services, such as education, hospitals, and poverty relief.


Second, religious electorates are less likely to support welfare-state provisions, presumably
confident in religious institutions’ capacity to protect individuals from the vicissitudes of economic
by King's College - London on 09/02/13. For personal use only.

downturns (Scheve & Stasavage 2006, Dehejia et al. 2007). More religious individuals prefer lower
levels of social insurance, because religion substitutes for the state as a source of insurance against
adverse life events (Scheve & Stasavage 2006). Some religions emphasize the value of hard work
and individualism, leading their adherents to oppose welfare programs that decouple work and
reward (Benabou & Tirole 2006). Where religious charities can substitute for the welfare state, it
is feasible for poor religious voters to oppose the welfare state (Huber & Stanig 2009).
Exemplifying this recent turn in political economy, De la O & Rodden 2008 argue that religion
distracts voters from voting in their class interests by acting as a cross-cutting cleavage. The more
the poor attend church, the more likely they are to vote against Left parties. What is less clear is the
adjudication between the two hypothesized mechanisms. It may be the case that religious beliefs
substitute for economic preferences; for poor religious voters, the psychic benefits of religion act
as a substitute for the welfare state. Alternatively, religious beliefs may distract from economic
preferences by creating a second issue dimension that proves more compelling. The uncertainty
persists partly because the observable implications of each hypothesis are empirically difficult to
disentangle, and partly because the two are logically compatible with each other.
More broadly, some forms of religiosity may depress economic growth whereas others may
stimulate it (McCleary & Barro 2006). Religious participation (church attendance) is associated
with a decrease in rates of economic growth, but some religious beliefs, such as belief in hell,
heaven, and an afterlife, tend to increase economic growth by promoting behavioral changes on
the individual level (Barro & McCleary 2003). In one version of the argument, higher productivity
signals salvation; this is true for those individuals who believe in predestination, as Calvinists do,
and for whom economic wealth and productivity is not a way of earning grace but a way of demon-
strating it. In another pathway, individuals work harder and more efficiently in order to secure
salvation and earn grace, as in the Catholic tradition and several Protestant ones. Intriguingly,
government involvement in religion is actually linked to economic modernization in another study
(Fox 2006).
One potential problem with these analyses, of course, is that religious doctrine, political insti-
tutions, and economic outcomes influence each other. It may very well be, for example, that the
provision of certain types of welfare goods or identity mobilization makes individuals more likely
to choose a specific denomination (Chesnut 2003, Trejo 2009). Yet these endogeneity problems
can be ameliorated (if not eliminated) through the use of experimental methods or instrumental
variables. In a particularly compelling example, Becker & Woessman (2009) find that the economic

www.annualreviews.org • Comparative Politics and Religion 431


PL15CH21-GrzymalaBusse ARI 18 April 2012 8:29

prosperity of Protestant regions is due not to a particular work ethic, as Max Weber argued, but
to higher stock of human capital: specifically, literacy. Higher literacy, in turn, is a direct result of
Lutheran doctrinal emphasis on reading the Bible for oneself. Becker & Woessman use distance
to Wittenberg, the heart of Lutheranism, as an instrument for Protestantism that is not related
to either education or economic development, and find that Protestantism has a strong effect on
literacy.

Religion and Regimes


Religious bodies can legitimate and lend support to secular regimes—or conversely, withdraw that
support and oppose particular secular incumbents and governing structures. Churches and regimes
thus mutually influence and constitute each other’s development and strategies. For example,
where the Catholic Church faced competition from Protestant denominations in Latin America,
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2012.15:421-442. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org

it was more willing to support indigenous popular movements for democracy (Gill 1998) and to
promote secular ethnic mobilization (Trejo 2009). Even if the assumption that the poor demand a
church that opposes autocracy is “empirically questionable” (Philpott 2007, p. 512), the argument
by King's College - London on 09/02/13. For personal use only.

at its core shows how competition (itself influenced by state regulation) leads religious bodies to
adopt political stances that then affect their own standing in societies and vis-à-vis governments.
In settings as varied as Poland, the Philippines, Spain, and Brazil, Roman Catholic churches
used a variety of tactics to oppose authoritarian regimes: mobilizing popular support, protecting
the opposition, withdrawing previous public support for the incumbent, or developing a liberation
theology that led local priests and bishops to oppose authoritarianism in the name of human rights
and social justice (Gill 1998, Ramet 1998, Philpott 2004). In these efforts, the churches “have shown
a remarkable ability to mobilize collective action, including political protest” (Gill 2001, p. 118).
By the same token, secular regimes influence religious strategies. For example, Philpott (2007)
argues that integrationism—the fusion of state prerogatives given to a particular religion and that
religion’s claims on the state—is the reason why Islam may preclude democratization. Ironically,
this is not because of an inherent antidemocratic stance within Islamic doctrine—though au-
thoritarian regimes have justified themselves in Islamic terms, as in Iran, Saudi Arabia, Sudan, and
Afghanistan under the Taliban—but instead because the authoritarian regimes in Islamic countries
have often been rigidly secular, outlawing Islamic movements and prompting a “correspondingly
undemocratic posture in Islamic movements that have arisen to oppose them” (Philpott 2007,
p. 516, see also Iannaccone & Berman 2006). Here, the repression of religion leads the religion
to adopt a particular political stance.
Critically, the ramifications of various types of church–state integration do not simply follow
from the level of integration. Democracy can coexist with integration. For example, we do not
see a strict separation of church and state even in Western Europe, long held up as a model of
secularization and democracy—yet democratic practice has not suffered (Stepan 2000; see also
Monsma & Soper 1997). Although government intervention in religion is lower in democracies
than in nondemocracies, few states separate religion and politics fully, and democracies exhibit
a wide range of (non)separation (Fox 2006). Attitudes toward publicly visible religion also vary
among democracies, a diversity Kuru (2007) attributes to historical ideational struggles. “Twin
tolerations,” or the mutual respect and nonintervention of the state and the religious institution,
matter considerably more for democratic practice than a rigid separation of the two spheres (which
is unobtainable in practice) (Stepan 2000). What is less clear is whether this autonomy determines
the church’s attitude to democracy and its public opposition to authoritarian rule, or whether more
prosaic factors, such as competition with other denominations, are just as important in fostering
church support for democratic regimes (Gill 1998) and indigenous rights (Trejo 2009).

432 Grzymala-Busse
PL15CH21-GrzymalaBusse ARI 18 April 2012 8:29

In short, religion matters, not just because its adherents are committed to it, but because
the ideas, identities, and cultural mechanisms it entails continue to shape political life. Religious
doctrines and denominations remain sources of ideology and identity, policy pressure, social
mobilization, and political influence. As a result, religious organizations and beliefs shape both
political behavior and institutional configurations.

Sustaining Influence?
Is this influence of religion waning? Modernity has not undermined the importance of religion,
despite the predictions of advocates of secularization, ranging from Durkheim to Weber to their
followers. The political implications of religion remain both clear and enormous (Sahliyeh 1990,
Appleby 2000, Burleigh 2007). But some scholars argue that the meaning of religion has changed,
in that the sacred and secular have become differentiated (Casanova 1994, Casanova 2006, Taylor
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2012.15:421-442. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org

2007). In these interpretations, religious belief and doctrine have become privatized, rather than
acting as “grand legitimators, responsible for integrating and regulating society as a whole” (Gorski
& Altinordu 2008, p. 58). Indeed, the differentiation of the sacred and secular allows us to examine
by King's College - London on 09/02/13. For personal use only.

how the two can influence each other. Other scholars have argued that secularization proceeds,
but in very specific contexts that maximize social and economic security (Bruce 2000, Norris &
Inglehart 2004). Few, however, claim that religion is disappearing from the global political stage.
Moreover, organized religion and the secular state are in constant interaction, if not conflict.
There are certainly grounds for such conflict: “Persons in authority generally seek the means
of preserving their power. For religious authority, this may often mean reaching out for the
assistance of the state, as religious groups typically lack the backing of coercive power. Overlapping
authority between state and religious leaders may also cause conflict. . .religious leaders may use
their institutional position to challenge unpopular governments as a means of preserving their
authority or credibility among parishioners” (Gill 1998, p. 120). Once religion is introduced into
politics, it becomes very difficult to disinvite it: “not only do its absolutist criteria clash with the
politics of compromise, but religion tends to be emotionally ‘hot’ and accompanied by its own
experts who are frequently difficult to control. . .very few state officials relish publicly opposing
religious considerations once they have been activated” (Demerath 1991, p. 30).
One conclusion that emerges from these discussions is that God is most certainly not dead—
and S/He remains politically (and economically) active. Religious loyalties continue to structure
political thought and action. By paying greater attention to religion and religious doctrine, com-
parative politics thus stands to gain insight into political behavior, the origins of institutions, the
importance of churches as institutional players, and the role of doctrine and religious ideas in
social and political interactions.

HOW POLITICS INFLUENCES RELIGION: THE POLITICAL


ECONOMY OF RELIGION
Even as religion has structured institutions and political behavior, we continue to observe con-
siderable variation both in the intensity of religious practice and belief and in their subsequent
impact on politics. Poland is very different from the Czech Republic, and Ireland, even after the
recent Church scandals, is far more religious than France. Accordingly, public policy in Poland
and Ireland is far more influenced by Catholic Church preferences than in the resolutely secular
Czech Republic or France.
These differences beg the question of the political determinants of religion itself. Why
are some countries, groups, and individuals so much more religious (as measured by belief,

www.annualreviews.org • Comparative Politics and Religion 433


PL15CH21-GrzymalaBusse ARI 18 April 2012 8:29

observance, and belonging) than others? Many states have attempted to harness religion, to sanc-
tion some beliefs and not others, and to regulate, control, and coerce religious denominations into
supporting particular political options. Such attempts took on a great variety of forms and levels
of intensity, even across countries with ostensibly the same state ideology and regime type (such
as the communist one-party states) (Ramet 1998).
The impact of such state attempts to control religion has led to the flowering of a “political
economy of religion” (see Gill 2001 and Clark 2010 for stimulating and concise overviews). In
a quest to provide the micro foundations of religious behavior, these approaches focus on the
regulatory environment: how states favor a particular religion over others, and what impact such
regulation has on religions’ ability to meet consumers’ preference heterogeneity.
To summarize, where the religious market can freely offer diverse alternatives to heteroge-
neous religious beliefs and preferences, rates of religious participation and denominational affili-
ation increase (Chaves & Cann 1992, Finke & Stark 1992, Stark & Iannaccone 1994, Iannaccone
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2012.15:421-442. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org

1998, Gill 2001, Clark 2010). Competition among religions drives them to better meet consumer
“demand,” and consequently to increase innovation and efficiency. Religious pluralism thus breeds
religious fervor. In contrast, where the state regulates religious markets by financially or politically
by King's College - London on 09/02/13. For personal use only.

supporting a state religion, the levels of religious pluralism and participation decrease. Specifically,
where costs of market entry are high and the state favors particular religions, religious participa-
tion drops. These differences in regulation explain why only some countries have succumbed to
secularism, most notably those that extend state privileges to established religions, as in Northwest
Europe.
The regulation of religious markets is said to depress participation for several reasons.
Consumers have no control over the quantity or quality of the religious goods provided; state
interests are unlikely to converge with consumer preferences; one publicly sponsored religion
can never provide variety of religious choices demanded by diverse individuals; and finally,
even if religious alternatives arise, individuals are already bound to the inefficient state religion
(Iannaccone 1991, Chaves & Cann 1992). Two implications follow. First, as both
Tocqueville and Marx noted, “it was the caesaropapist embrace of throne and altar under abso-
lutism that perhaps more than anything else determined the decline of church religion in Europe”
(Casanova 1994, p. 29). Second, given the heterogeneity of religious preferences, some argue that
“the only means of enforcing a religious monopoly is by government fiat” (Gill 2001). Religious
monopolies cannot occur “naturally,” in the absence of state mandate (Stark 1992, Gill 2001).
Instead, in one account, insecure leaders faced with a dominant religion enforce a monopoly;
where several religious minorities are equally powerful, rulers will favor low state regulation
(Gill 2008).
This compelling and provocative approach changed the terms of the debate. It suggested that
the more competitive the religious market, the more likely we are to see the demand for di-
verse religious offerings met, and thus, greater religious observance. Where religions face more
competition, they put in greater effort to attract consumers, and the result is greater religious
participation. In this framework, attempts by organized religion to influence politics are an al-
ternative supplied in the religious market (for those consumers who prefer an activist religion)
and/or a way of gaining greater market share by diversifying the portfolio of outreach strategies.
State support that ensures a privileged position for the church may also be the result of political
influence by the church, as was the case with the Russian Orthodox Church (Knox 2005).
Yet, as powerful as they are, these accounts leave several areas to be clarified. The dragon
of “secularism” that the scholars of religious markets have been slaying is in fact a paper tiger:
the radical prediction that religion is doomed to extinction (Wallace 1966) is not representative
of the broader scholarship on secularization. Indeed, a conceptualization of “secularization” as a

434 Grzymala-Busse
PL15CH21-GrzymalaBusse ARI 18 April 2012 8:29

wholesale turn away from religious faith and participation had not been adopted generally and has
been disavowed by the scholarship (see the valuable discussion by Gorski & Altinordu 2008). It
is hardly surprising that religion continues to flourish if no theory predicted its demise. Further,
political economy approaches conceptualize religiosity as participation rather than as belief. Yet
there are participants who do not believe and believers who do not participate (Huber 2005,
Davie 1990). As a result, finding a vibrant religious marketplace with many participants does
not preclude tenuous individual connections to faith (one indicator of secularization). Thus, the
“churn” generated by conversions and moving from one church to another is a sign of a healthy
religious marketplace—but it can also indicate weak commitment to a particular religion.
Some pointed criticisms can be levied against the religious markets approach. First and fore-
most, monopolies flourish, and newly liberalized markets do not undergo a religious upsurge.
Stark argues that “to the extent that only one faith is available without risk of sanctions, religious
apathy and indifference will be high. That is, if the market is inherently segmented whenever
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2012.15:421-442. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org

the religious economy tends toward monopoly, substantial demand must go unsatisfied and many
consumers will withhold their patronage” (Stark 1992, p. 262). Yet Ireland, Malta, and Poland are
all naturally occurring monopolies, ones that survived despite state efforts to undermine them.
by King's College - London on 09/02/13. For personal use only.

Stark & Finke (2000) then argue that conflict can act as a substitute for competition, that “reli-
gious firms can generate high levels of participation to the extent that the firms serve as primary
organizational vehicles for social conflict” (Stark & Finke 2000, p. 202). But what are the micro
foundations here, and why would social conflict create religious vibrancy? This proposition has
been used to explain the high levels of observance in Catholic Poland—yet Croatia and Lithuania,
both of which faced similar levels of social conflict, show lower levels of religiosity (Froese & Pfaff
2001, p. 490). Jenkins (2007, p. 50) warns against confusing causes with consequences: “perhaps the
religious monopoly just means that people have not felt the need to set up rival religious bodies.”
A more compelling explanation for the existence of “natural monopolies” is that where fixed costs
are large—i.e., where people view alternative religions as close substitutes—monopolies can arise
without state intervention (Barro & McCleary 2005). It is not the case that monopolies cannot
occur “naturally” (Gill 2001).
Second, the absence of regulation, or the liberalization of religious markets, does not result
in the predicted religious upsurge. This is partly because the political economy approach does
not conceptually differentiate between regulation as repression and regulation as subsidy. “State
regulation” is almost inevitably measured as the state support for a given church but not as the
active repression of other denominations (for an important exception, see Grim & Finke 2007). Yet
state support for one religion is not the same as the suppression of others. Unless the state coerces
society into supporting a given religion, or tries to eliminate alternative religions, it is not clear
how privileging one religion suppresses the demand (and, more importantly for the theory, the
exercise of that demand) for other religions.
If we are interested in the constraints on religious participation, then our subject is not
states privileging one religion over others but rather states preventing others from arising. Anti-
proselytizing laws, for example, explicitly and directly constrain religious participation in ways
that subsidizing a dominant religion does not. This is especially the case because state support
for a given religion actually frees up potential consumers for other denominations: it makes the
state-favored religion less popular. After all, even in countries with established churches, disaf-
fected believers are free to move to other denominations, as in nineteenth-century England with
its flourishing of nonconformist sects [from 1840 to 1960, sects outnumbered the Anglican popu-
lation in several regions of England ( Jenkins 2007, p. 51)]. As a result, this account fails to explain
why state support for one religion would mean that other denominations fail to attract adherents
or sacralize politics.

www.annualreviews.org • Comparative Politics and Religion 435


PL15CH21-GrzymalaBusse ARI 18 April 2012 8:29

Conversely, why does the absence of regulation not result in greater observance? The political
economy of religion has difficulties in explaining the low rates of religiosity in states with no state
support for a particular religion, such as France, the Czech Republic, or Estonia. In these free
markets, we should see high rates of observance, if the assumptions of high and heterogeneous
demand for religion hold. Why do we not see religious entrepreneurs move in and the rates
of religious observance go up accordingly? If the assumption of a universal and varied need for
religion is true, then “the sacred should have returned. . .where secularization had gone the furthest
and the absence of religion created the greatest need. Accordingly, we should have witnessed
religious revivals in highly secularized societies such as Sweden, England, France, Uruguay, and
Russia. Yet the public resurgence of religion took place in places such as Poland, the United States,
Brazil, Nicaragua, and Iran, all places which can hardly be characterized as secularized wastelands”
(Casanova 1994, pp. 224–25).
The answer given by the political economy of religion is that previous state support for a given
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2012.15:421-442. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org

religion prevents current conversions to other religions in a liberalized market (Iannaccone 1994).
But this is having it both ways: if state-supported religions are so inefficient in satisfying con-
sumer demand, how could they bind adherents so successfully? Either people seek new religious
by King's College - London on 09/02/13. For personal use only.

alternatives (in which case nominal state support for one denomination should have little effect
on consumers turning to other denominations) or they do not, in which case the key assumption
of heterogeneity of religious preferences and their intensity is violated. Put differently, the re-
lationship of the political economy of religion to history—and the determinism of the past—is
contradictory. On the one hand, believers are said to freely move between religions. On the other
hand, actions taken in the past (i.e., state support for a religious monopoly) prevent them from
doing so. This literature, in short, has some difficulty addressing the conditions, and the costs, of
joining or leaving denominations.
More broadly, without a clearer appreciation of doctrine (other than as a strict practice) or how it
matters, the political economy literature operates within unacknowledged boundary conditions of
American Protestantism. The political economy approach argues that reaffiliation (change within
a religious tradition) is much less costly and more frequent than conversion (change of religious
traditions) (Stark & Finke 2000, p. 114). Yet this is true for American Protestants far more than
for other denominations, or other religious markets. If anything, as noted above, the punishments
meted out to apostates and heretics in many religious traditions suggest that the closer the chosen
alternative, the higher the cost paid by the convert. Indeed, assuming fungibility leads to the
conclusion that markets are a “natural state”—but where products (religious or otherwise) are
highly differentiated, oligopolies are a common outcome.
Finally, political economy accounts of religion face several empirical anomalies that they dis-
miss or simply misconstrue. Catholic countries are excluded from consideration, “having yielded
sufficiently deviant results to require separate consideration” (Stark & Finke 2000, p. 237). Catholi-
cism is said to be more vibrant because (a) low-level clergy are supported entirely by donations, so
they have to be entrepreneurial; (b) Catholicism is not subject to intervention by secular govern-
ments; and (c) the religion is international in character (Stark & Finke 2000, p. 243). The first two
of these statements are untrue; the third is ad hoc. It is also not the case that the diversity of reli-
gious orders in Catholicism reconciles monopoly status with vibrancy (Finke & Wittberg 2000):
religious orders are not the laity, by definition, so it is not clear how they channel popular diversity
of religious preferences, especially given that several orders (such as the Jesuits) were set up by the
Catholic hierarchy to enforce doctrinal orthodoxy. Free market conditions for competing Islamic
groups are said to explain the vibrancy of Islamic monopolies (Stark & Finke 2000, p. 249), a
statement many Iranians or Saudis would find puzzling, to say the least. In the end, a meta-review
of 24 studies found little relationship between pluralism and participation, with mixed results for

436 Grzymala-Busse
PL15CH21-GrzymalaBusse ARI 18 April 2012 8:29

state regulation (Chaves & Gorski 2001; see also Olson 1999 and Voas et al. 2002 for a pointed
methodological critique).
Along with the literature on the origins and patterns of religious belief (Atran 2002, Sloan
Wilson 2002, Dennett 2006), these market analogies assume a high, heterogeneous, and inelastic
demand for religion. In the political economy literature, societies have similar levels of demand
for religion (and varied preferences regarding the type of religion), and religions are fungible:
individuals can change their religious commitments easily, irrespective of the religious alterna-
tives on offer. These explanations do not examine why some individuals and, by extension, some
societies may be more or less receptive to religious mobilization and belief. Yet empirical test-
ing of the political economy models shows that there is significant demand-side variation across
religious markets (Montgomery 2003). And, if such variation in the demand for religion exists,
then the differences in religious participation can be the result not of supply-side competition
and offerings, but of demand-side forces, contrary to the explanations in the political economy of
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2012.15:421-442. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org

religion.
One such demand-side model argues that insecurity—material, economic, psychological, and
political—explains why people turn to religion, and by extension, why some societies are more
by King's College - London on 09/02/13. For personal use only.

religious than others (Norris & Inglehart 2004). One implication here is that countries undergoing
massive transitions and upheavals, such as the collapse of communism in East Central Europe,
ought to turn to religion. Given religion’s traditional concern with morality, such constituencies
should be especially receptive to religious incursion into public policy issues framed as “moral.” As
one observer of the American political scene noted, “morality policy politics may be more prevalent
where fundamental religious principles are the foundation for political debate” (Mooney 2001,
p. 16). Yet the insecurity and uncertainty that followed the fall of (secular!) communism has not
resulted in an increase in religious observance or belief anywhere in the postcommunist region; in
fact, where we observe change, it is in the opposite direction. As with the political economy of
religion, the fundamental problem with the demand-side approach is that structural conditions are
held responsible for behavior—but when market structures or levels of security change, behavior
does not.
One potential solution is to develop a richer account of the state. As noted above, political
economy accounts view the state as a market regulator that privileges certain religions over others.
Yet state repression can make national martyrs out of religious bodies, creating both powerful
attachment to monopoly religions and popular resonance to their claims. We thus need a more
nuanced view of the state and its roles, including both support for and oppression of religion.
More fundamentally, we cannot take for granted the “nation-state” as a coherent entity: the state
may oppose the nation-building project (as it did in colonial and communist regimes), or state
can be established when no coherent national identity yet exists. Religion can then become a
protector of the nation, as it did in Ireland and Poland. The close alignment of religious and
national identities then catalyzes religiosity and provides resonance to subsequent political claims
by religious authorities. In short, the alliance between nation and religion matters for church
vitality—and earlier hostile state regulation (as oppression) actually strengthens it.
As a result, natural monopolies not only exist— they can flourish, if sustained by the intertwining
of nationalism and religious belief. These monopolies have roots not in state regulation but in
the historical relationship between nation and church, and the fusion of national and religious
identities, as in Poland and Ireland (Breuilly 1993, Ramet 1998, Martin 2005). Levels of both
participation and belief are high, given the church’s nurturing and the double bind of betraying
the nation by leaving the religion. Conversely, where the church is perceived to have earlier
opposed the nation, even the absence of regulation will not result in greater religiosity, as in the
Czech Republic and France.

www.annualreviews.org • Comparative Politics and Religion 437


PL15CH21-GrzymalaBusse ARI 18 April 2012 8:29

Movement between religions is no longer seen as devoid of transaction costs. Instead, the costs
of conversion will vary directly with the degree of fusion between religion and nation. Where the
fusion is tight, apostasy or conversion can be perceived as betraying the nation: “heresy becomes
a national definition of treachery” (Martin 2005, p. 131). National identity and community ties
also mean that individuals may disagree with church teachings and with church political activity,
yet remain loyal to the faith itself. As a result, extensive objections to church political activity
coexist with high religiosity. This dynamic is clearest in Catholic churches, but it is also visible in
Protestant denominations (Hertzke 1988, p. 147). Above all, churches can now enter the political
arena and find that their claims resonate both with society and with secular politicians. Offending
religious sensibilities blurs into national treason, and politicians are anxious about offending a
powerful societal actor. Secular elites fear electoral backlash and increased costs of governing that
would come with church opposition, and their risk aversion is exacerbated by the information
asymmetries between elites and voters.
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2012.15:421-442. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org

CONCLUSION
by King's College - London on 09/02/13. For personal use only.

The study of religion and comparative politics holds great promise for the study of identity,
institutional origins, the state, and the strategies of institutional actors. The critical implications
go far beyond the study of religion itself, as we have seen. Religious attachments affect voting and
popular mobilization. Churches can become powerful institutional players that lobby, influence
policy, and form effective coalitions with both secular and denominational partners. Doctrinal
differences translate into distinct patterns of state institutions, economic performance, and policy
preferences. And finally, natural religious monopolies and conversely, resolutely secular countries,
show how churches played a central role in the struggle of nations and states.
As we examine these patterns of the mutual influence of the sacred and the secular, the study
of religion invites us to take doctrine seriously, both as a source of unique identity and as a
powerful demarcation of institutional preferences. Failure to do so blinds us to the differences in
the resulting institutional configurations, to the very high costs paid by those who travel only a
short distance from their original identity, and to the peculiar coalitions (and lack thereof) that
result when religion enters politics, and vice versa.

DISCLOSURE STATEMENT
The author is not aware of any affiliations, memberships, funding, or financial holdings that might
be perceived as affecting the objectivity of this review.

ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
I am grateful to Pauline Jones Luong, Ignacio Sánchez-Cuenca, David T. Smith, and Margit
Tavits for their valuable comments.

LITERATURE CITED
Altinordu A. 2010. The politicization of religion: political Catholicism and political Islam in comparative
perspective. Polit. Soc. 38(4):517–51
Appleby S. 2000. The Ambivalence of the Sacred: Religion, Violence, and Reconciliation. New York: HarperCollins
Atran S. 2002. In Gods We Trust. New York: Oxford Univ. Press
Atran S, Axelrod R, Davis R. 2007. Sacred barriers to conflict resolution. Science 317:1039–40

438 Grzymala-Busse
PL15CH21-GrzymalaBusse ARI 18 April 2012 8:29

Barro R, McCleary R. 2003. Religion and economic growth across countries. Am. Sociol. Rev. 68:760–81
Barro R, McCleary R. 2005. Which countries have state religions? Q. J. Econ. 120(4):1331–70
Beatty K, Walter O. 1984. Religious preference and practice: reevaluating their impact on political tolerance.
Public Opin. Q. 48(1):318–29
Becker S, Woessman L. 2009. Was Weber wrong? A human capital theory of Protestant economic history.
Q. J. Econ. 124(2):531–96
Bellin E. 2008. Faith in politics: new trends in the study of religion and politics. World Polit. 60(2):315–47
Benabou R, Tirole J. 2006. Belief in a just world and redistributive politics. Q. J. Econ. 121(2):699–746
Berger P. 1999. The Desecularization of the World. Washington, DC: Eerdmans/Ethic and Public Policy Center
Berman E. 2009. Radical, Religious, and Violent. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Berman E, Laitin D. 2008. Religion, terrorism and public goods: testing the club model. J. Public Econ.
92(10–11):1942–67
Breuilly J. 1993. Nationalism and the State. Manchester, UK: Manchester Univ. Press
Bruce S. 2000. The supply-side model of religion: the Nordic and Baltic states. J. Sci. Stud. Relig. 39(1):32–46
Burleigh M. 2007. Sacred Causes. New York: HarperCollins
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2012.15:421-442. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org

Casanova J. 1994. Public Religions in the Modern World. Chicago: Univ. Chicago Press
Casanova J. 2006. Religion, European secular identities, and European integration. In Religion in an Expanding
Europe, ed. T Byrnes, P Katzenstein, pp. 65–92. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge Univ. Press
by King's College - London on 09/02/13. For personal use only.

Castles F. 1994. On religion and public policy: Does Catholicism make a difference? Eur. J. Polit. Res. 25(1):19–
40
Chandra K. 2004. Why Ethnic Parties Suceed. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge Univ. Press
Chandra K, ed. 2012. Constructivist theories of ethnic politics. Unpublished manuscript, Dep. Polit. Sci.
New York Univ.
Chaves M, Cann D. 1992. Regulation, pluralism, and religious market structure. Ration. Soc. 4(3):272–90
Chaves M, Gorski P. 2001. Religous pluralism and religious participation. Annu. Rev. Sociol. 27:261–81
Chesnut A. 2003. Competitive Spirits: Latin America’s New Religious Economy. New York: Oxford Univ. Press
Clark WR. 2010. Toward a political economy of religion? Polit. Econ. 12(1):2–10
Davie G. 1990. Believing without belonging: Is this the future of religion in Britain? Soc. Compass 37(4):455–69
Demerath NJ. 1991. Religious capital and capital religions: cross-cultural and non-legal factors in the separa-
tion of church and state. Daedalus 120(3):21–40
de Swaan A. 1988. In Care of the State: Health Care, Education and Welfare in Europe and the USA in the Modern
Era. New York: Oxford Univ. Press
Dehejia R, DeLeire T, Luttmer E. 2007. Insuring consumption and happiness through religious organizations.
J. Public Econ. 91:259–79
De La O AL, Rodden J. 2008. Does religion distract the poor? Income and issue voting around the world.
Comp. Polit. Stud. 41(4/5):437–76
Dennett D. 2006. Breaking the Spell: Religion as a Natural Phenomenon. New York: Viking
Eisenstein M. 2006. Rethinking the relationship between religion and political tolerance in the US. Polit.
Behav. 28:327–48
Ekelund R, Hebert R, Tollison R, Anderson G, Davidson A. 1996. Sacred Trust: The Medieval Church as an
Economic Firm. New York: Oxford Univ. Press
Ertman T. 2009. Western European party systems and the religious cleavage. In Religion, Class Coalitions, and
Welfare States, ed. K van Kersbergen, P Manow, pp. 39–55. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge Univ. Press
Esping-Andersen G. 1990. The Three Worlds of Welfare Capitalism. Princeton, NJ: Princeton Univ. Press
Finke R, Stark R. 1992. The Churching of America: Winners and Losers in Our Religious Economy. New Brunswick,
NJ: Rutgers Univ. Press
Finke R, Wittberg P. 2000. Organizational revival from within: explaining revivalism and reform in the Roman
Catholic Church. J. Sci. Stud. Relig. 39(2):154–70
Fox J. 2006. World separation of religion and state into the 21st century. Comp. Polit. Stud. 39:537–69
Froese P, Pfaff S. 2001. Replete and desolate markets: Poland, East Germany, and the new religious paradigm.
Soc. Forces 80(2):481–507
Furnham A. 1983. The Protestant work ethic, human values, and attitudes toward taxation. J. Econ. Psychol.
3:113–28

www.annualreviews.org • Comparative Politics and Religion 439


PL15CH21-GrzymalaBusse ARI 18 April 2012 8:29

Gill A. 1998. Rendering Unto Caesar: The Catholic Church and the State in Latin America. Chicago: Univ. Chicago
Press
Gill A. 2001. Religion and comparative politics. Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 4:117–38
Gill A. 2008. The Political Origins of Religious Liberty. New York: Cambridge Univ. Press
Gill A, Lundsgaarde E. 2004. State welfare spending and religiosity: a cross-national analysis. Rationality Soc.
16(4):399–436
Gorski PS. 2003. The Disciplinary Revolution: Calvinism and the Rise of the State in Early Modern Europe. Chicago:
Univ. Chicago Press
Gorski P, Altinordu A. 2008. After secularization? Annu. Rev. Sociol. 14:55–85
Gould A. 1999. The Origins of Liberal Dominance. Ann Arbor: Univ. Mich. Press
Grim B, Finke R. 2007. Religious persecution in cross-national context: clashing civilizations or regulated
economies? Am. Sociol. Rev. 72:633–58
Grzymala-Busse A. 2010. The sacralization of politics in Europe and beyond. Unpublished manuscript, Dep. Polit.
Sci., Univ. Mich.
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2012.15:421-442. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org

Grzymala-Busse A. 2011. Why there is (almost) no Christian Democracy in post-communist Europe.


Party Polit. Epub ahead of print. doi:10.1177/1354068811407596
Hagopian F, ed. 2009. Religious Pluralism, Democracy, and the Cahtolic Church in Latin America. South Bend,
by King's College - London on 09/02/13. For personal use only.

IN: Univ. Notre Dame Press


Hayes B. 1995. The impact of religious identification on political attitudes: an international comparison.
Sociol. Relig. 56(2):177–94
Hertzke A. 1988. Representing God in Washington: the Role of Religious Lobbies in the American Polity. Knoxville:
Univ. Tenn. Press
Htun M. 2003. Sex and the State. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge Univ. Press
Huber J. 2005. Religious belief, religious participation, and social policy attitudes across countries. Unpublished
manuscript, Dep. Polit. Sci., Columbia Univ.
Huber J, Stanig P. 2009. Church-state separation and redistribution. Presented at Annu. Meet. Assoc. Sci. Stud.
Relig., Econ., and Culture. Arlington, VA
Hull B. 2000. Religion still matters. J. Econ. 26:35–48
Iannaccone LR. 1991. The consequences of religious market structure: Adam Smith and the economics of
religion. Rationality Soc. 3(2):156–77
Iannaccone LR. 1994. Why strict churches are strong. Am. J. Sociol. 99(5):1180–21
Iannaccone LR. 1998. An introduction to the economics of religion. J. Econ. Lit. 1465–96
Iannaccone LR, Berman E. 2006. Religious extremism: the good, the bad, and the deadly. Public Choice
128(1):109–29
Jelen T. 1993. The political consequences of religious group attitudes. J. Polit. 55(1):178–90
Jelen T, Wilcox C. 2002. Religion and Politics in Comparative Perspective. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge Univ.
Press
Jenkins P. 2007. The Next Christendom: The Rise of Global Christianity. New York: Oxford Univ. Press
Johnson J. 2002. How conceptual problems migrate: rational choice, interpretation, and the hazards of
pluralism. Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 5:223–48
Juergensmeyer M. 1993. The New Cold War? Religious Nationalism Confronts the Secular State. Berkeley: Univ.
Calif. Press
Juergensmeyer M. 2008. Global Rebellion: Religious Challenges to the Secular State. Berkeley: Univ. Calif. Press
Kahl S. 2005. The religious roots of modern poverty policy: Catholic, Lutheran, and reformed Protestant
traditions compared. Arch. Europ. Sociol XLVI(1):91–126
Kahl S. 2007. Saving the poor: how religion shapes welfare-to-work policy in Europe and the United States.
Unpublished manuscript, Dep. Polit. Sci., Yale Univ.
Kalyvas S. 1996. The Rise of Christian Democracy in Europe. Ithaca, NY: Cornell Univ. Press
Kalyvas S, van Kersbergen K. 2010. Christian Democracy. Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 13:183–209
Knox Z. 2005. Russian Society and the Orthodox Church: Religion in Russia after Communism. London: Routledge
Kuru A. 2007. Passive and assertive secularism. World Polit. 59:568–94
Layman G. 1997. Religion and political behavior in the United States. Public Opin. Q. 61(2):288–316

440 Grzymala-Busse
PL15CH21-GrzymalaBusse ARI 18 April 2012 8:29

Layman G. 2001. The Great Divide: Religious and Cultural Conflict in American Party Politics. New York:
Columbia Univ. Press
Lijphart A. 1979. Religious versus linguistic versus class voting: the “crucial experiment” of comparing Belgium,
Canada, South Africa and Switzerland. Am. Polit. Sci. Rev. 73:442–57
Lipset S, Rokkan S, eds. 1967. Party Systems and Voter Alignments: Cross National Perspectives. New York: Free
Press
MacIver MA. 1989. Religious politicization among Western European mass publics. In Religious Politics in
Global and Comparative Perspective, ed. WH Swatos, pp. 111–30. New York: Greenwood
Martin D. 1999. The evangelical Protestant upsurge and its political implications. See Berger 1999, pp. 19–36
Martin D. 2005. On Secularization; Towards a Revised General Theory. Aldershot, UK: Ashgate
Marty M, Appleby S, eds. 1991. Fundamentalisms Observed. Chicago: Univ. Chicago Press
McCleary R, Barro R. 2006. Religion and economy. J. Econ. Perspect. 20(2):49–72
Minkenberg M. 2002. Religion and public policy: institutional, cultural, and political impact on the shaping
of abortion policies in Western democracies. Comp. Polit. Stud. 35(2):221–47
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2012.15:421-442. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org

Minkenberg M. 2003. The policy impact of church-state relations: family policy and abortion in Britain,
France, and Germany. West Eur. Polit. 26(1):195–217
Mitchell C. 2006. The religious content of ethnic identities. Sociology 40:1135–52
by King's College - London on 09/02/13. For personal use only.

Monsma S, Soper C. 1997. The Challenge of Pluralism. New York: Rowman & Littlefield
Montgomery J. 2003. A formalization and test of the religious economies model. Am. Sociol. Rev. 68(5):782–809
Morgan K. 2009. The religious foundations of work-family policies in Western Europe. See van Kersbergen
& Manow 2009, pp. 56–90
Mooney C, ed. 2001. The Public Clash of Private Values. New York: Seven Bridges
Nexon D. 2009. The Struggle for Power in Early Modern Europe: Religious Conflict, Dynastic Empires, and Inter-
national Change. Princeton, NJ: Princeton Univ. Press
Norris P, Inglehart R. 2004. Sacred and Secular: Religion and Politics Worldwide. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
Univ. Press
Olson D. 1999. Religious pluralism and US church membership: a reassessment. Sociol. Relig. 60(2):149–73
Philpott D. 2004. The Catholic wave. J. Democracy 15:32–46
Philpott D. 2007. Explaining the political ambivalence of religion. Am. Polit. Sci. Rev. 101(3):505–25
Philpott D. 2009. Has the study of global politics found religion? Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 12:183–202
Posner D. 2005. Institutions and Ethnic Politics in Africa. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge Univ. Press
Putnam R, Campbell D. 2010. American Grace. New York: Simon & Schuster
Ramet S. 1998. Nihil Obstat: Religion, Politics, and Social Change in East-Central Europe and Russia. Durham,
NC: Duke Univ. Press
Rémond R. 1999. Religion and Society in Modern Europe. Oxford, UK: Blackwell
Roemer J. 1998. Why the poor do not expropriate the rich: an old argument in new garb. J. Public Econ.
70:399–424
Rokkan S. 1981. Territories, nations, parties: toward a geoeconomic-geopolitical model for the explanation
of variations within Western Europe. In From National Development to Global Community, ed. R Merritt,
B Russett, pp. 70–95. London: Allen & Unwin
Rose R, Urwin D. 1969. Social cohesion, political parties and strains in regimes. Comp. Polit. Stud. 2(1):7–67
Sahliyeh E, ed. 1990. Religious Resurgence and Politics in the Contemporary World. Albany, NY: SUNY Press
Scheve K, Stasavage J. 2006. Religion and preferences for social insurance. Q. J. Polit. Sci. 1:255–86
Scheufele D. 2000. Agenda-setting, priming, and framing revisited: another look at cognitive effects of political
communication. Mass Commun. Soc. 3(2&3):297–316
Sloan Wilson D. 2002. Darwin’s Cathedral. Chicago: Univ. Chicago Press
Stark R. 1992. Do Catholic societies really exist? Rationality Soc. 4(3):261–71
Stark R, Finke R. 2000. Acts of Faith: Explaining the Human Side of Religion. Berkeley: Univ. Calif. Press
Stark R, Iannaccone L. 1994. A supply-side reinterpretation of the “secularization” of Europe. J. Sci. Stud.
Relig. 33(3):230–52
Steensland B, Park J, Regnerus M, Robinson L, Wilcox WB, Woodberry R. 2000. The measure of American
religion: toward improving the state of the art. Soc. Forces 79(1):291–318

www.annualreviews.org • Comparative Politics and Religion 441


PL15CH21-GrzymalaBusse ARI 18 April 2012 8:29

Stepan A. 2000. Religion, democracy, and the ‘twin tolerations’. J. Democracy 11(4):37–57
Taylor C. 2007. A Secular Age. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
Tessler M. 2002. Islam and democracy in the Middle East. Comp. Polit. 34(3):337–54
Toft M. 2007. Getting religion? The puzzling case of Islam and civil war. Int. Sec. 30(Spring):97–131
Torgler B. 2006. The importance of faith: tax morale and religiosity. J. Econ. Behav. Organ. 61:81–109
Trejo G. 2009. Religious competition and ethnic mobilization in Latin America: why the Catholic Church
promotes indigenous movements in Mexico. Am. Polit. Sci. Rev. 103(3):323–42
van Kersbergen K. 1994. The distinctiveness of Christian Democracy. In Christian Democracy in Europe, ed.
D Hanley, pp. 31–47. London: Pinter
van Kersbergen K, Manow P, eds. 2009. Religion, Class Coalitions, and Welfare States. Cambridge, UK:
Cambridge Univ. Press
Voas D, Crockett A, Olson D. 2002. Religious pluralism and participation: why previous research is wrong.
Am. Sociol. Rev. 67(2):212–30
Wald K, Silverman A, Fridy K. 2005. Making sense of religion in political life. Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 8:121–43
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2012.15:421-442. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org

Wallace AFC. 1966. Religion: An Anthropological View. New York: Random House
Warner C. 2000. Confessions of an Interest Group. Princeton, NJ: Princeton Univ. Press
Weigel G. 1999. Roman Catholicism in the age of John Paul II. See Berger 1999, pp. 37–49
by King's College - London on 09/02/13. For personal use only.

Wittenberg J. 2006. Crucibles of Political Loyalty. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge Univ. Press
Woodberry R. 2011. Religion and the spread of human capital and political institutions. In The Oxford Handbook
of the Economics of Religion, ed. R McCleary, pp. 111–131. New York: Oxford Univ. Press
Woodberry R, Shah T. 2004. The pioneering Protestants. J. Democracy 15(2):47–61

442 Grzymala-Busse
PL15-frontmatter ARI 20 April 2012 12:16

Annual Review of
Political Science
Contents Volume 15, 2012

A Conversation with Kenneth Waltz


Kenneth Waltz and James Fearon p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p 1
How (and Why) Is This Time Different? The Politics of Economic
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2012.15:421-442. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org

Crisis in Western Europe and the United States


Jonas Pontusson and Damian Raess p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p13
by King's College - London on 09/02/13. For personal use only.

The Consequences of the Internet for Politics


Henry Farrell p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p35
What (If Anything) Does East Asia Tell Us About International
Relations Theory?
Alastair Iain Johnston p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p53
Using Roll Call Estimates to Test Models of Politics
Joshua D. Clinton p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p79
Global Civil Society: The Progress of Post-Westphalian Politics
John S. Dryzek p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p 101
Global Distributive Justice: Why Political Philosophy Needs
Political Science
Michael Blake p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p 121
Varieties of Capitalism: Trajectories of Liberalization and the New
Politics of Social Solidarity
Kathleen Thelen p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p 137
Domestic Explanations of International Relations
Bruce Bueno de Mesquita and Alastair Smith p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p 161
Electoral Accountability: Recent Theoretical and Empirical Work
Scott Ashworth p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p 183
International Influences on Elections in New Multiparty States
Judith G. Kelley p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p 203
Formal Models of International Institutions
Michael J. Gilligan and Leslie Johns p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p 221

v
PL15-frontmatter ARI 20 April 2012 12:16

In From the Cold: Institutions and Causal Inference


in Postcommunist Studies
Timothy Frye p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p 245
International Regimes for Human Rights
Emilie M. Hafner-Burton p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p 265
Is Health Politics Different?
Daniel Carpenter p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p 287
LGBT Politics and American Political Development
Richard M. Valelly p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p 313
Policy Makes Mass Politics
Andrea Louise Campbell p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p 333
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2012.15:421-442. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org

Formal Models of Bureaucracy


Sean Gailmard and John W. Patty p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p 353
by King's College - London on 09/02/13. For personal use only.

Studying Organizational Advocacy and Influence: Reexamining


Interest Group Research
Marie Hojnacki, David C. Kimball, Frank R. Baumgartner, Jeffrey M. Berry,
and Beth L. Leech p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p 379
Causes and Electoral Consequences of Party Policy Shifts in
Multiparty Elections: Theoretical Results and Empirical Evidence
James Adams p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p 401
Why Comparative Politics Should Take Religion (More) Seriously
Anna Grzymala-Busse p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p 421
Geographic Information Systems and the Spatial Dimensions
of American Politics
Wendy K. Tam Cho and James G. Gimpel p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p 443
Richardson in the Information Age: Geographic Information Systems
and Spatial Data in International Studies
Kristian Skrede Gleditsch and Nils B. Weidmann p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p 461

Indexes

Cumulative Index of Contributing Authors, Volumes 11–15 p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p 483


Cumulative Index of Chapter Titles, Volumes 11–15 p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p 485

Errata

An online log of corrections to Annual Review of Political Science articles may be found
at http://polisci.annualreviews.org/

vi Contents

You might also like