You are on page 1of 12

See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.

net/publication/242458737

STRUCTURE FOR COORDINATION Part I

Article · January 1998

CITATIONS READS
83 2,749

1 author:

Ljiljana Progovac
Wayne State University
81 PUBLICATIONS   1,388 CITATIONS   

SEE PROFILE

Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:

A Critical Introduction to Language Evolution (Springer book) View project

All content following this page was uploaded by Ljiljana Progovac on 22 August 2014.

The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file.


State-of-the-Article Glot International, Volume 3, Issue 7, September 1998 3

this out to me). The data show that anaphoric epithets

STRUCTURE FOR COORDINATION can function as bound variables (14), but since they
obey Condition C, this is only possible if the QP in an
A-bar position, but not its trace in an A-position, c-

Part I commands the epithet at LF. Otherwise, (15) would be


grammatical:
(14)
John criticized every senatori in private while praising the
bastardi in public.

by Ljiljana Progovac (15)


*Billi expected that the bastardi would win.

The ungrammaticality of (16) below would follow


Capturing the structure of coordination has long posed a challenge for any theory of syntax. Given the systematic and
from some version of the Leftness Condition (see
pervasive nature of coordination cross-linguistically, it has become clear that the degree of success of any theory of
Chomsky 1973, Higginbotham 1980), as also pointed
language structure largely depends on how successful it is in integrating coordination. The recent years have seen a
out in Munn (1993):
significant progress: numerous sophisticated analyses of coordination have been advanced, and a wealth of new data
has been uncovered. The riddle of coordination is on the verge of being resolved. (16)
Part I of this paper introduces the representative data relevant for determining the structure for coordination *Hisi dog and everyi man went to mow a meadow.
(section 1), and provides a survey of the analyses of coordination that do not treat conjunctions as heads of This leaves us with no evidence for c-command
conjunction phrases (section 2). Part II, to appear in Glot International 3,8 (see box), provides a survey of those between conjuncts.
analyses of coordination that do treat conjunctions as heads of conjunction phrases (section 3), as well as the In addition, cross-linguistic data on binding and
extensive Bibliography. negative concord reinforce the conclusion that there
is no evidence that the first conjunct c-commands the
second (for more details and arguments, see Progov-
1. Representative Data c-commands the second: ac 1996, 1997, to appear a).
1.0. Introductory words A reflexive pronoun in the second conjunct
(8)
This section introduces the data generally Johni’s dog and hei/himi went for a walk. cannot be bound by the first conjunct. This is most
considered in developing a theory of coordination. It readily observed in languages with possessive reflex-
(9)
includes not only some well-known data concerning ives, as illustrated for Serbo-Croatian in (17), but is
*He/himi and Johni’s dog went for a walk.
coordination, such as asymmetries among conjuncts, also obvious in English (18), (see Collins 1988a,b and
but also some less-known data, such as repetition of However, the same effect is observed even across Munn 1993).
conjunctions in front of each conjunct, as well as sentences, where Principle C cannot be invoked,
some old data that have been reanalyzed and re- since structural relations such as c-command operate (17)
*Jovani i svojai z¦ ena su stigli.
thought, such as the (lack of) c-command effects only within sentence boundaries:
*John and self ’s wife are arrived
among conjuncts. In order to keep this paper finite in (10) *“John and self ’s wife have arrived”
size, the intricacies of Gapping, Right Node Raising, *Hei finally arrived. Johni’s dog went for a walk.
(18)
and VP-Ellipsis will not be discussed here in any
It must be then that some other, possibly pragmatic, *Either Johni or a picture of himselfi will suffice.
detail; the reader is referred to Johnson (1996).
principle is responsible for the ungrammaticality of Likewise, a negative word in the first conjunct
1.1. Asymmetry: Ross’ effects (10). This same principle, whatever it is, can then cannot license a negative polarity item any in the
Ross (1967) concluded that the second conjunct also account for the ungrammaticality of (9). second (19). (For conditions on polarity licensing and
forms a unit with the conjunction, but not the first Given the additional data below, it seems that negative concord, see e.g. Ladusaw 1980 and Zanutti-
conjunct, based on the following contrasts: we not only can, but must, attribute (9) to something ni 1991). In fact, one is required to use two negatives,
other than Principle C. If principle C were operative as in (20), where the use of two negatives does not
(1) between conjuncts, it would render (11) and (12)
John left, and he didn’t even say good-bye.
result in a dialectal/negative concord use. For (21)
below equally ungrammatical. (11), however, is and (22), in which c-command uncontroversially
(2) perfectly grammatical, while (12) is marginal and obtains, exactly the opposite is true: the negative
John left. And he didn’t even say good-bye. marked, at best. word licenses the polarity item in (21), and the use of
(3) (11) another negative word in (22) results in a dialectal/
*John left and. He didn’t even say good-bye. John and John’s wife are certainly invited. negative concord usage:
Collins (1988a,b) and Munn (1993) discuss the (12) (19)
following contrasts that illustrate that extraposition ?*John certainly likes John’s wife. *He chased nobody and/or any dogs.
is possible of the last conjunct and conjunction, but Another type of argument for c-command comes from (20)
not of the first conjunct and conjunction, which fact bound pronouns. The possibility of binding a pronoun He chased nobody and no dogs.
supports Ross’ conclusion: in (13) may look like an argument for c-command (21)
(4) between conjuncts. However, this can only be an Nobody chased any dogs.
John read a book yesterday, and the newspapers. argument that every c-commands his at LF, since (22)
(5) quantifiers are subject to the rule of Quantifier %Nobody chased no dogs.
*John read the newspapers yesterday, the book and. Raising (QR) (May 1977):
There may exist alternative explanations for each of
In addition, Zoerner (1995) points out that ‘etc(etera)’ (13) the effects discussed above. For negation, one can
is used to replace the last conjunct(s) and the con- Everyi man and hisi dog went to mow a meadow.
argue that the negative feature needs to raise out of
(Munn 1993)
junction, establishing the two as a constituent. the coordination phrase (see Zanuttini 1991 and
(6)
The proposal that the pronoun is c-commanded by QP Haegeman and Zanuttini 1991), but that such raising
I bought jam, bread, etc. at LF, rather than the trace of QP, is supported by the is blocked by CSC (Coordinate Structure Constraint),
data discussed in Hornstein and Weinberg (1990) which prohibits movement out of coordinated phras-
(7)
(thanks to Marc Authier and Lisa Reed for pointing es in general (see section 1.10). For binding, one can
*I bought jam, bread, and etc.

These data seem to stand on a firm ground, and have


been widely exploited in the GB literature as evi-
This is the first State-of-the-Article that appears in two installments (we thought it fit the subject matter).
dence for a hierarchical organization of the &P
Here is the full table of contents of both Part I and Part II of Ljiljana Progovac’s Structure for coordination.
(Conjunction Phrase), as will be seen below.

1.2. Is there c-command? Part I (this month) Part II (next month)


The literature that adopts a hierarchical ap-
proach to coordination assumes or argues that the 1. Representative data 3. Conjunction as a head
first conjunct in VO languages (including English) c- 1.0. Introductory words 3.0. Introductory words
commands the rest of coordination. Of course, this 1.1. Asymmetry: Ross’ effects 3.1. Conjunction Phrase (&P) with recursive comple-
would constitute the strongest possible argument for 1.2. Is there c-command ment
hierarchy. However, such a c-command relationship 1.3. Subcategorization 3.2. Conjunction Phrase (&P) with recursive specifi-
is not a necessary consequence of a hierarchical 1.4. Agreement er
organization of the coordination phrase, as will 1.5. Conjunction doubling 3.3. Conjuncts as adjuncts
become clear in the later discussion. 1.6. Chaotic Case 3.4. Conjunction: Head without a phrase
The question is, then, whether the first conjunct 1.7. Coordination of Likes Constraint
1.8. Conjunction adverbs 4. Concluding remarks
c-commands the rest of coordination or not. The
1.9. Coordinate Structure Constraint
answer seems to be ‘no,’ since the arguments for c-
command are at best ambivalent. The rest of the Appendix: “Economy of conjunction marking” and
2. Conjunction as non-head adjunction
section reviews these arguments.
2.0. Introductory words
Collins (1988a,b) and Munn (1993) attempt to 2.1. Multi-headedness
capture the contrasts below by invoking Principle C, The Coordination Bibliography
2.2. Multi-dimensional analyses
which is only possible if the first conjunct
State-of-the-Article Glot International, Volume 3, Issue 7, September 1998 4

argue that the conjuncts do not satisfy the condition mother’ and ‘children’ in (33), suggesting that what- including the first. (This differs from the process
on co-argumenthood and that this leads to ungram- ever the hierarchical relation between ‘mother’ and found in English of repeating only the intermediate
maticality (see e.g. Hellan (1988) and Reinhart and ‘three children’ is in (34), it cannot be the same as the conjunctions.) Conjunction Doubling is available in
Reuland (1993)). At the very least, then, one can say one in (33). French, Italian, Japanese, Serbo-Croatian (SC), and
that there is no evidence for c-command between This is not the whole story, however. In various other languages (see Payne 1985 for more languag-
conjuncts. However, given that Principle C also does language, including English, singular agreement can es), but not in English:
not hold between conjuncts (see the contrast between be selected even with conjunction phrases, under
(43) French (Kayne 1994):
(11) and (12)), a stronger conclusion suggests itself: certain circumstances. In the following examples Jean connait et Paul et Michel.
conjuncts do not c-command each other. Thus, a from English, the first conjunct alone is responsible Jean knows and Paul and Michel
theory of coordination from which this conclusion for the choice of agreement on the verb (see (35) and “Jean knows both Paul and Michel.”
follows is to be preferred. (36)), which case is reminiscent of (34) above, and not (44) Italian:
There is only an apparent tension between the of (33): Sono arrivati (e) Anna, (e) Roberto, e Laura.
data that point to a hierarchy (section 1.1.) and the are arrived and Anna and Roberto and Laura
(35)
data that point to the conclusion that there is no c- “Anna (and) Roberto and Laura have arrived.”
There is /??are [a man and three children] at the front door.
command among conjuncts, as will be seen below. (45) Serbo-Croatian:
(36)
(I) Marija, (i) Milan, i Petar studiraju lingvistiku.
There *is/are [three children and a man] at the front door.
1.3. Subcategorization and Mary and Milan and Peter study linguistics
The question of subcategorization is relevant for Agreement with the first conjunct is only possible if “Mary (and) Milan and Peter are students of linguistics.”
coordination in two different ways: (i) first, the the subject &P is preceded by the verb. Camacho (46) English:
question arises whether or not all conjuncts have to (1997, 85) states that, if a language has alternative *And Mary and Peter study linguistics.
satisfy the subcategorization requirements of the word orders, agreement with one conjunct, or partial
As illustrated with comma placement for Serbo-
head by which they are governed; (ii) second, if a agreement, will occur with non-canonical word order.
Croatian and Italian examples, phonological cues
coordination phrase dominates conjuncts, it is not The same preverbal/postverbal asymmetries arise in
(pauses) suggest that each conjunction forms a unit
clear how such a phrase can satisfy the subcategori- many other languages, as reported for Arabic, Irish,
with the immediately following conjunct in VO
zation requirement of a head that selects an NP, for Portuguese, and Russian (see McCloskey and Hale
languages. No other comma patterns are possible, as
example. Related to this question is also the question 1984, McCloskey 1986, 1989, van Oirsouw 1987,
given below:
of conjoinability of different categories. If a coordina- Munn 1993, 1996, Benmamoun (1992), Aoun, Ben-
tion phrase hosts an NP, a PP and/or an AP, as in mamoun and Sportiche (1994), Babyonyshev 1996, (47) Serbo-Croatian:
1997, etc.). The following Arabic examples illustrate *I, Marija i Milan i Petar studiraju lingvistiku.
(23)/(24) below, what features will such a coordina-
tion phrase have? that first conjunct agreement is possible, but that it (48) Italian:
only occurs in post-verbal positions: *Sono arrivati e, Anna e Roberto e Laura.
(23)
Pat has become [a banker] and [very conservative]. (37) Interestingly and importantly, head final languages,
(Sag et al. 1985) el-walad we-l-banaat gataluu el-bisse such as Japanese, double their conjunctions to the
the-boy and-the-girls killed-3PL/MASC the-cat right, as illustrated below (see Kuno 1973, Kayne
(24)
“The boy and the girls killed the cat.”
Robin is [ugly], [a dolt] and [of no help]. (Zoerner 1995) 1994, Zoerner 1995). This provides a powerful argu-
(38) ment for treating conjunctions as heads (see section
Different analyses offer different solutions to this el-banaat we-l-walad gataluu el-bisse 3, Part II). This is so because conjunctions show the
problem, as will be made clear in sections 2 and 3. the-girls and-the-boy killed-3PL/MASC the-cat
same order with respect to conjuncts that (other)
As far as the first question goes, the data sug-
(39) heads show with respect to their complements.
gest that not all the phrases have to satisfy the gatal el-walad we-l-banaat el-bisse
subcategorization requirements of the governing killed-SG/MASC the-boy and-the-girls the-cat (49) Japanese:
head, as the following examples illustrate (see [Robin-to Kim-to Terry-to]-ga
(40) [Robin-and Kim-and Terry-and-CASE
Gazdar et al. 1985): gatalen el-banaat we-l-walad el-bisse
(25) killed-PL/FEM the-girls and-the-boy the-cat Since the Conjunction Doubling strategy is available
Pat was annoyed by [the children’s noise] and [that their crosslinguistically, a theory of coordination that can
Some analyses of coordination, such as Munn (1993),
parents did nothing to stop it]. accommodate these data is to be preferred.
capitalize on this set of data to argue that the first
(26) conjunct is what the &P adjoins to, but that the first
You can depend on [my assistant] and [that he will be on time]. 1.6. Chaotic Case
conjunct is not really the part of this &P (see section
Recent accounts have started to make use of
(27) 3.3., Part II). While this analysis accommodates the
*Pat was annoyed by [that their parents did nothing to stop the
unexpected Case assignment in coordination phras-
data with first conjunct agreement, it has to say
noise] and [the children]. es, most notably Zoerner (1995) and Johannessen
something special about plural agreement with two
(1998). It is well-known that coordination phrases in
(28) singular conjuncts, as in (31), for example.
English tolerate accusative Case assignment to
*You can depend on [that my assistant will be on time] and [his Babyonyshev (1997) offers an interesting analy-
intelligence]. subjects, and nominative Case assignment to objects,
sis of this variation, based on the agreement pattern
as illustrated below. The examples also show that a
(29) in Russian, where preverbal &P necessarily triggers
mixture of nominative and accusative Cases is
*Pat was annoyed by that their parents did nothing to stop it. plural agreement, while postverbal subjects optional-
possible in a single coordination phrase.
(30) ly occur with agreement with the first conjunct only:
*You can depend on that he will be on time. (50) Subjects:
(41) Them and us are going to the game together.
V komnatu vošli/vošla/*vošel/*vošlo molodaja z¦ enšc¦ina
The above contrasts seem to illustrate that only the (Stahlke 1984, 360, quoted in Johannessen 1998)
into room entered-pl./sg.f/sg.m/sg.n young woman-f-nom
first conjunct has to satisfy the subcategorization i malen’kij mal’c¦ ik. (51)
requirements of the preposition, while the second and little boy-m-nom She and him will drive to the movies.
conjunct can sometimes, under certain circumstanc- ‘Into the room entered a young woman and a small boy.’ (Schwartz, B.D. 1985, 165, quoted in Johannessen 1998)
es, get “a free ride.” All other things being equal, that (42) (52) Objects:
analysis of coordination is to be preferred from which Molodaja z¦ enšc¦ ina i malen’kij mal’c¦ ik All debts are cleared between you and I.
these data follow. young woman-f-nom and little boy-m-nom (Shakespeare, Merchant of Venice, quoted in Johannessen 1998)
vošli/*vošla/*vošel/*vošlo v komnatu.
entered-pl./sg.f/sg.m/sg.n into room (53)
1.4. Agreement I really wanted my mother to live with my husband, Michael
The agreement considerations point to poten- She proposes an analysis which captures, straightfor- and I.
tially conflicting conclusions. On the one hand, wardly, the asymmetry between pre-verbal and post- (Evening Standard, 30 June 1992, 16, quoted in Johannessen
agreement is normally established in such a way 1998)
verbal agreement, based on the common assumption
that both conjuncts are taken into account, as if that the subject has to check its features in TP. The Johannessen (1998) offers data from 32 languages
the structure were symmetrical (31). This is in preverbal subject is overtly moved to TP for this demonstrating that the phenomenon is widespread
contrast to a clearly asymmetrical case, given in purpose. On the other hand, the postverbal subject and systematic. For her, (50) would be the case of
(32): checks its features covertly (at LF). The features of the EBC (Extraordinary Balanced Coordination), in
(31) postverbal subject, if it is a &P, either move as a whole, which both conjuncts receive unexpected Case; in
A man and three children ?*is/are at the front door. resulting in plural agreement, or only the features of contrast, (51) would be a case of UC (Unbalanced
the first conjunct move to TP, resulting in singular Coordination), in which only one conjunct receives
(32)
A man with three children is/*? are at the front door. agreement. unexpected Case. She establishes the following
If Babyonyshev’s analysis is on the right track, correlation (1998, 55):
Similarly, in the contrast below, conjuncts in (33) are then it has the following two implications for the
interpreted as thematically parallel, as opposed to (54) Johannessen’s Correlation
structure of coordination: (i) the first conjunct is “There is a very strong correlation between, on the one hand,
the two NPs in (34), which are clearly hierarchically hierarchically higher than the rest of &P; otherwise, the order of verb+object, and on the other, that of normal
arranged: there would be no asymmetry with respect to which conjunct+deviant conjunct (usually the same as that between
conjunct can check its features in TP; (ii) first conjunct conjunction+deviant conjunct).”
(33)
A mother and three children arrived late on purpose. agreement data can be captured even if the first Out of 12 OV languages (Amharic, Burushaski,
conjunct is the part of &P. Eastern Mari, Hopi, Japanese, Latin, Qafar, Sidaa-
(34)
A mother with three children arrived late on purpose. mu Afo, Swahili, Tamil, Turkic, Yagnobi), 11 have the
1.5. Conjunction Doubling deviant UC conjunct in the first position (excluding
While in (34) the agentive intention “on purpose” is By Conjunction Doubling I will refer to the Yagnobi); out of 14 VO-languages, all have the
ascribed only to ‘a mother,’ it is ascribed to both ‘a repetition of the conjunction in front of all conjuncts,
State-of-the-Article Glot International, Volume 3, Issue 7, September 1998 5

deviant UC conjunct in the second position (Czech, (67) 1.9. Coordinate Structure Constraint (CSC)
English, Fulfulde, Ga, Italian, Norwegian, Old Bobby is the man [who was defeated by Billie Jean] and [who Based on the data like (83–85), Ross (1967: 98–
beat Margaret].
Hebrew, Old Irish, Old Norse, Palestinian Arabic, 99) formulates the constraint in (86). (83) illustrates
Serbo-Croatian, Slovene, Tokelauan, Welsh). In her (68) that extraction of a conjunct is unacceptable, while
sample, there are six languages whose word order is *Bobby is the man [defeated by Billie Jean] and [who beat (84) illustrates that extraction out of a conjunct is
Margaret].
mixed or unclear (Afrikaans, Dutch, Estonian, unacceptable. Both contrast with the acceptable (85),
German, Homeric Greek, Vedic), and which do not However, just as purely semantic formulations have where extraction is not out of a coordination phrase.
conform to the correlation. Since English is a VO systematic counterexamples, so do purely syntactic (83)
language, it follows from (54) that the deviant con- approaches, as well as Schachter’s formulation in *Which surgeon did Kim date t and a lawyer?
junct in Unbalanced Coordination will necessarily be (66). The examples below involve successful coordi-
(84)
the second conjunct. nation of syntactically unlike categories: *Which surgeon did Kim date friends of t and a lawyer?
On the other hand, it follows from Zoerner’s
(69) (85)
(1995) generalization in (55) that deviant Case in the Pat has become a banker and very conservative.
first conjunct is grammatical in English (56–57), as Which surgeon did Kim date (friends of)?
(Sag et al. 1985)
long as all non-final conjuncts share it. (58) and (59) (86) Coordinate Structure Constraint (CSC)
(70) “In a coordinate structure, no conjunct may be moved, nor may
are claimed by Zoerner to be ungrammatical because
Robin is ugly, a dolt and of no help. (Zoerner 1995) any element contained in a conjunct be moved out of that
non-final conjuncts do not share the same Case, as
(71) conjunct.”
required by (55):
Robin considers Kim completely evil, a total witch, and beyond
(55) Zoerner’s Generalization
Extraction out of conjuncts is allowed only if it
salvation. (Zoerner 1995)
All non-final conjuncts must have identical Case. applies Across-the-Board (ATB), as in:
(72)
(56) [NP Robin’s help] and [CP that (s)he gave it so willingly] (87)
?Him, her and I all left. delighted Kim. (Zoerner 1995) Which surgeon did Kim date friends of and enemies of?

(57) (73) On the other hand, Lakoff (1986) argued that CSC is
Robin saw he, she and me. Robin realized [CP that the sky was falling] and [NP the gravity falsified by a range of data, and concluded that it
of the situation]. (Zoerner 1995) constitutes a wrong generalization (see also Gold-
(58)
*He, her and Robin (all) left. As will be discussed below, a theory based on the idea smith 1985, Zoerner 1995).
(59) that conjunctions are heads in the X’-schema (section (88)
*Him, she and Robin (all) left. 3, Part II) does not have anything to say about CLC How much can you drink t and still stay sober?
— the principle simply does not seem to have any-
The two analyses make different predictions. Johan- In defense of CSC, Postal (in press) argues that (88)
thing to do with the theory. Most of the proponents of
nessen’s analysis would be falsified by grammaticali- is not an instance of true coordination, but rather
such theories deny the existence of CLC. The status
ty of examples like (56, 57, 59, as well as by 60–63 that one of the conjuncts acts as an adjunct (see
of CLC may be more relevant in those theories of
below), while their grammaticality would follow from section 3.3, Part II, for adjunction analyses of coordi-
coordination that assume parallel structures, in
Zoerner’s analysis. In fact, since Zoerner draws a line nation). It is not the purpose of this paper to decide
which coordination involves a merger of two trees
only between final and non-final conjuncts, he pre- whether or not CSC is real. If it is real, one would
with identical structures (e.g. Goodall (1987), see
dicts grammaticality of any Case combination in two- expect that it follows from a more general principle,
section 2.2.). For this approach, examples like (74)
way conjunctions. On the other hand, Zoerner’s which subsumes other islands, such as Subjects,
below are still a problem (see Gazdar et al. 1985).
analysis would be falsified by grammaticality of Complex NP’s, etc. (see Ross 1967). There are various
(74) could not have been generated by a merger of
examples like (58) and (63), while the grammaticality analyses of islandhood, but attempts to provide a
two well-formed trees, given the ungrammaticality of
of (58) would follow from Johannessen’s analysis. (I unified account (e.g. Chomsky 1986) are only partly
(75):
report 60–63 below without a grammaticality judg- successful. While it is obvious that a successful
ment.) (74) analysis of islandhood would shed light on the struc-
You can depend on [my assistant] and [that he will be on time]. ture of islands, including coordination phrases, and
(60)
Him and I both left. (75) while it is also obvious that a successful analysis of
*You can depend on that he will be on time. the structure for coordination will shed light on the
(61) analysis of islandhood, this connection is not a trivial
Robin saw he and me. The contrast above is equally problematic for an
one, and, as far as I can see, has not been established
attempt to make CLC follow from an analysis in which
(62) yet.
All debts are cleared between I and him. conjuncts, rather than the conjunction(s), are (multi-
Adjunction analyses of coordination (section 3.3,
ple) heads of coordination (see section 2.1.).
(63) Part II) have claimed advantage on this issue since
While counterexamples do not necessarily falsify
I really wanted my mother to live with I, him, and Michael. they reduce CSC to Adjunct islandhood. However,
a theory, it seems safe to conclude that counterexam-
this cannot be a significant advantage given that
It may not be possible to determine a priori how the ples do indeed falsify a generalization that does not
there are islands other than adjuncts, and given that
data bend here. There are many factors that influence follow from a theory, which seems to be the case with
the nature of adjunct islandhood is not completely
native speaker judgments on these, including various CLC. The contrasts discussed above may be a result
understood either.
prescriptive rules. This may well be a case where of the interaction of the structure of coordination and
ultimately the theory will have to draw the line be- another principle of grammar (see Appendix, Part II,
tween grammaticality and acceptability. Not only can a 2. Conjunction as non-head
for an analysis that invokes an Economy principle:
prescriptive rule render a grammatical construction 2.0. Introductory words
Economy of Conjunction Marking).
unacceptable, but it can also render an otherwise Various analyses of coordination treat conjunc-
ungrammatical construction acceptable. (By ‘grammat- tion as a reflex/spell-out of a feature, rather than as
1.8. Conjunction adverbs
ical’ I mean generated by the rules of Grammar; by a head of a coordination phrase. One line of such
Collins (1988a,b) argues that certain adverbs
‘acceptable’ I mean judged acceptable by native speak- analyses treats conjuncts as heads of coordination
are associated with conjunctions, and that they
ers.) phrases, resulting in multi-headedness (section 2.1.),
modify the conjunction, as in the following exam-
One conclusion emerges, however: ‘deviant’ Case while another argues that conjuncts appear at
ples:
occurs in coordination phrases cross-linguistically, parallel levels/tiers of representation, and that there
(76) are no coordination phrases at the level of syntax
and is subject to regular cross-linguistic patterns. John and maybe Mary went to the store. (section 2.2.).
1.7. Coordination of Likes Constraint (CLC) (77)
Perhaps John, maybe Mary, and certainly Bill went to the 2.1. Multi-headedness
On the basis of contrasts like (64) and (65), store.
Chomsky (1957) concluded that syntactically differ- Some early attempts to integrate conjunction
ent categories cannot be conjoined, which constraint He provides arguments that these adverbs neither into the phrase structure resulted in the following
has been referred to as Coordination of Likes Con- modify the corresonding NPs, nor can they derive rules (Jackendoff 1977, Chomsky 1981):
straint (CLC); see also Williams’ (1978) “Law of from sentential paraphrases of coordinated NPs. For (89)
Coordination of Likes:” example, although (77) below is acceptable, (79) and NP → NP Conj NP
(80) are not:
(64) (90)
the scene [PP of the movie] and [PP of the play] (78) VP → VP Conj VP etc.
The treasurer, the president, and perhaps the CEO will get
(65) (91)
together tonight to hammer out an agreement.
*the scene [PP of the movie] and [CP that I wrote] XP → XP Conj XP
(79)
Schachter (1977: 90) strengthens the formulation of ??The treasurer and perhaps the president will get together
Basically, the assumed structure is as in (92) below:
the principle to require semantic, as well as syntac- tonight... (92)
tic, ‘likeness,’ as in (66). Schachter shows that just (80)
XP
purely semantic considerations do not suffice, since *Perhaps the president will get together tonight...
there is a contrast between (67) and (68) below, even
though they involve coordination of semantically If this is the correct analysis of the examples above, XP and XP and XP
equal functions. then it has two consequences for the structure of The consequences of this basic analysis of coordina-
coordination: first, it provides an additional argu- tion, with conjuncts as heads, have been explored by
(66) ment for the head status of coordination; second, it
“The constituents of a coordinate construction must belong to many, for example, Gazdar et al. 1985, Sag et al.
the same syntactic category and have the same semantic
requires that there be as many conjunctions as there 1985, Pullum and Zwicky 1986, Ingria 1990, and
functions.” are conjuncts, in order to capture the fact that each Pollard and Sag 1994. This approach can capture, in
can be modified, as in (77). a rather straigthforward way, our intuitive feeling
State-of-the-Article Glot International, Volume 3, Issue 7, September 1998 6

that coordination of two NPs is an NP, of two PPs is a (98) One problem for this approach is that, very
PP, etc. On the other hand, most of the data dis- [CP That Himmler appointed Heydrich] and [NP the often, the order of the conjuncts is not reversible, as
implications thereof] frightened many observers.
cussed in section 1. do not follow from this structure: illustrated in (108–111).
the structure predicts that conjuncts will each c- (99)
(108)
command the other (contra section 1.2.); that there Pat remembered [NP the appointment] and [CP that it was
John read the book and quickly.
will be no asymmetries of Ross’ type (contra section important to be on time].
(109)
1.1.); that there should be no Case variability (contra The reader is referred to Bayer (1996) for the reasons *John read quickly and the book.
section 1.6); etc. In addition, recent developments in against an ad hoc solution which proposes that
the theory of structure of phrases and sentences clauses as dominated by an NP in the above exam- (110)
point to the conclusion that structure involves binary You can depend on [my assistant] and [that he will be on time].
ples.
branching (see Kayne 1984, for example). If that is For examples like (96) and (97), Jacobson (1987) (111)
true, then (92) cannot be the correct representation proposes that the verb ‘be’ can be analyzed as select- *You can depend on that he will be on time and his intelligence.
of coordination. In addition to binary branching, ing a category PRED, which, in turn, can be re- A multi-dimensional analysis also does not predict
recent research has achieved yet another generaliza- written as AP, NP, PP. This solution is unsatisfactory any other asymmetries among conjuncts, which
tion which radically simplifies the conceptual system for two reasons: first, it conflates the distinction however occur, such as variability in Case and
of language: that any phrase is headed by a single between form and function; second, as pointed out in agreement assignment (sections 1.6. and 1.4.),
head, and that every head projects a phrase. If this is Bayer (1996), the verb ‘become’ (as illustrated in (95)) asymmetry in extraposition possibilities (sec-
true, then, again, the structure in (92) is not a possi- will have to re-write the feature PRED in a different tion 1.1.), etc. Moreover, as was pointed out for multi-
ble representation for coordination since in it, a way, since ‘become’ selects only a subset of categories headed analyses, conjunctions are analyzed as
single phrase XP can be headed by any number of selected by ‘be.’ elements that do not exist at the syntactic level, but
XPs. are rather just phonological reflexes of tree-mergers.
Lakoff and Peters (1969) have a different ver- (100)
Robin regards Kim as completely evil, (?as) a total witch, and In an analysis that involves tree-pasting, it is not at
sion of multi-headed conjunction structure: all clear why such markers of tree pasting would be
(??as) beyond salvation.
(93) necessary, let alone why they would show such
XP (101)
Robin regards Zoe as a woman, as rich and (?*as) in the lucky
intricate patterns of distribution, as illustrated in the
position of owing a castle. rest of this section, as well as in the Appendix, Part
XP XP XP II.
The particle ‘as’ seems rather comfortable with NPs As pointed out in section 1.8., Collins (1988a,b)
and APs, but not with PPs. The piece of data illus- argues that conjunctions can be modified by adverbs.
and XP and XP and XP trated above is not an argument against the exist- This would not be possible if conjunctions were not
ence of predication phrases, but seems to be a strong syntactically present. Next, as also pointed out by
Their proposal assumes that each conjunct is accom-
argument against the CLC itself. Even when the Collins, even the conjunction ‘and’ has a clear seman-
panied by an instance of a conjunction. All conjuncts
choice of coordinating likes is available, the grammar tic contribution, identifying a causal/temporal rela-
in (93) enjoy basically equal syntactic status. The
prefers not to use it. tionship between conjuncts, as in:
strucuture is still multi-headed, and multi-branch-
A multi-headed approach also does not have the
ing, but it enjoys some advantages over (92). It (112)
tools to deal with the examples of coordination of
predicts the possibility of conjunction doubling (as Bill drank the poison and died.
unlike categories, where their order cannot be re-
discussed in section 1.5.); it predicts that conjuncts
versed (see section 1.7.). (113)
will not c-command each other, as per conclusion in ?Bill died and drank the poison.
Another consequence of the approaches sketched
section 1.2.); it predicts that each conjunction can be
above is that the conjunction itself remains an (114)
modified by an adverb (see example (77) in section
element without a clear grammatical status: it is Bill died: he drank the poison.
1.8.); it predicts asymmetries noticed by Ross (see
neither a head, nor a phrase, nor a modifier.
section 1.1.). In fact, the proposals by Collins The oddity of (113) is not shared by the conjunction-
(1988a,b) and Progovac (1996,1997) are similar in less (114), which is perfectly acceptable. It must be,
2.2. Multidimensional analyses then, that the source of temporal/causal information
spirit, as will be discussed in section 3, Part II.
Goodall (1987, 20) sees coordination as a union in this case resides in the conjunction. This, of
In addition, this approach assumes that one and
of phrase markers, or as ‘pasting together,’ one on top course, can only be captured if the conjunction is
the same conjunction gets copied in a single coordi-
of the other, of two trees, with any identical nodes present at the syntactic and semantic levels of
nation phrase, deriving (93) from (94) below. The
merging together (see also Williams 1981, Goodall representation.
spirit of this analysis is adopted by Zoerner 1995
1993). For him, coordinated structures exist at
(section 3.1, Part II), who provides a syntactic mech-
parallel levels. Thus, the two sentences with identi-
anism for achieving the link between equivalents of
cal VPs, given in (102) and (103), merge, as illustrat-
(93) and (94).
ed in (104). The conjunction is inserted between the Murder Mystery Correction
(94) conjuncts during the PF process of linearization
[and XP XP XP] (105). To our regret, the last few lines of Chapter 4 of Chris
Tappan’s Murder Mystery in Glot International 3, 5
Any multi-headed analysis of coordination raises the (102) were inadvertently omitted. We print the last few
following question: since phrases inherit the features Jane saw Bill.
paragraphs here. We apologize to Chris Tappan and to
of their heads, what features would a multi-headed
(103) our readers.
phrase inherit in case the conjuncts are not of the Alice saw Bill.
same category, as in the examples below. The solu- “Were those his exact words?” Paul asked her,
tion proposed in Gazdar et al. (1985), for example, is (104)
Jane ignoring her last comment and before she could continue
that the feature(s) projected to the mother node saw Bill. her story.
Alice
would constitute the intersection of the features of “Something like that. ‘I think you don’t have
the daughter nodes (Head Feature Constraint). The (105) enough paper!’ ”
major categories are represented using combinations Jane and Alice saw Bill.
“And then what happened?”
of the binary features N and V, based on Chomsky This basic analysis is also adopted in Moltmann “So I go in and I was shocked to see that Nartin
1970. 1992, Grootveld (1993), te Velde (1996, 1997), etc. was angry as hell. I mean, I had not expected this
(95) The strongest appeal of this approach is the elegance because Bill had made that comment jokingly, and when
Pat became [NP a Republican] and [AP quite conservative]. with which it can capture Right Node Raising, as I had been there earlier, the atmosphere had been fine,
(Sag et al. 1985) illustrated in (106). The example (106) would derive they were sitting there like friends, no animosity. But
from (107), by pasting the relevant trees together: now, Nartin was fuming. ‘Did you hear what he said?!’
(96)
Robin is [AP ugly], [NP a dolt] and [PP of no help]. he asked me. I said, You mean that comment about the
(106) paper? ‘Yes!’ he says. ‘I could kill him for it!’ he said. ‘I
(Zoerner 1995)
John cooked, and Mary ate, the goulash.
could kill him for it,’ that were his exact words. I could
(97)
(107) hardly believe what I heard. Especially from Nartin.
Zoe is [NP a woman], [AP rich] and [PP in the lucky position of
John cooked And I mean, it was only about the paper in the printer!”
owing a castle]. (Johannessen 1990) the goulash
Mary ate “You said that they were talking about the reasons
However, it is often not obvious what these common This solution to Right Node Raising is clearly superi- why Nartin did not get the job when you were up there
features are, the issue taken in Johannessen 1998. She or to any approach that assumes a host of deletion earlier, right?”
points out that NP, AP and PP have no categorial rules. “Right.”
features in common, given that NPs are analyzed as This analysis also fares well with the conclusion “What did they say? What were they talking
[+N,–V], APs are [+N,+V], and PPs are [–N,–V]. Yet that conjuncts do not c-command each other: they about?”
they coordinate successfully in the above examples. “I don’t know, I wasn’t there for a long time, I
essentially do not see each other, since they are at
The problem cannot be just the lack of a good choice of walked in, and walked out again, right away.”
different levels. In addition, the approach does not
features. Note that N, P and A are the three out of four “So you did not catch anything?”
predict that only like elements can coordinate, since
major word level categories, excluding only V. It is “As far as I remember, Bill was telling Nartin what
the union of phrase markers can presumably occur
hard to imagine that there will be a categorial feature all the members of the committee had said. But I really
as long as the conjoined material is in the same did not pay very much attention.”
unifying the three, while excluding the V. It seems position.
equally difficult to find a feature common to clauses “Thanks a lot, Esperanza.” Paul said. “You have
Unfortunately, a multi-dimensional approach been a great help.”
and NPs, which also coordinate successfully (from faces problems with respect to other data, in addition
Bayer 1996): I think you don’t have enough paper, Paul thought.
to constituting a considerable enrichment of the They had to find Nartin. Right away.
theoretical apparatus. Where was James?
State-of-the-Article Glot International, Volume 3, Issue 8, October 1998 3

(120)

STRUCTURE FOR COORDINATION *Tom ’n Mary and Jim

(121)

Part II *Tom and Mary ’n Jim

Another advantage of Zoerner’s idea is that it


provides tools for differentiating sub-group coordi-
nation, for which examples above would be gram-

by Ljiljana Progovac matical. Thus, actually, if one adopts Zoerner’s


structure in (117) for examples (118) or (119), then
one can reserve the structure in (116) for sub-
group coordination, where Mary and Jim are
considered a sub-group, which coordinates with
Tom. This would correspond to the fact that
In Part I, which appeared in Glot International 3–7, I introduced the representative data relevant for determining the different conjunctions are possible with subgroup
structure for coordination. Part I also provided a survey of the analyses of coordination that do not treat conjunctions coordination, since there are two distinct &Ps:
as heads of conjunction phrases. Part II provides a survey of those analyses of coordination that do treat conjunctions
as heads of conjunction phrases. Part II also contains the extensive Bibliography. (122)
Tom and [Mary and Jim]

3. Conjunction as a head For Zoerner, in multiple coordination, a single & (123)


3.0. Introductory words projects more than one layer of &P structure, in Tom and [Mary ’n Jim]
The idea that conjunction is a head of a parallel to Larson’s (1988) VP shell proposal (this
(124)
phrase, typically the conjunction phrase (&P), has analysis of coordination was mentioned, but Tom ’n [Mary and Jim]
been explicitly proposed or explored by many, argued against, in Collins 1988a,b). Thus, only
including: Thiersch 1985, Munn 1987a, 1987b, one & is generated (as per Lakoff and Peters (125)
1992, 1993, Collins 1988a,b, Kolb and Thiersch 1969), the last one, while other & positions in Tom and [Mary or Jim]
1991, Woolford 1987, 1994, Kayne 1994, Johan- multiple coordination are filled by the head move-
nessen 1990, 1993a–c, 1996, 1998, Zoerner 1995, ment of the base-generated conjunction. The basic On the other hand, if (116) is the correct represen-
Camacho 1997, etc. This analysis, of course, representation for two-term coordination will be tation for a single coordination phrase, then it is
became more readily available only with the the same as Johannessen’s, the one in (115) above. not clear how to represent sub-group coordination
advent of the X’-theory, somewhere in the late Below is Zoerner’s analysis of three-term coordi- in a distinct way (see also Kayne’s analysis in
seventies. This basic analysis allows of various nation: section 3.3.). All other things being equal, it is
specific implementations: conjuncts can be specifi- desirable to have this ambiguity follow directly
ers and complements in a &P with recursive (117) from the structural representation.
complements (section 3.1); conjuncts can be speci- &P Johannessen/Zoerner type of structure seems
fiers and complements in a &Ps with recursive supported by the possibility to extrapose the
specifiers (3.2); conjuncts can be attached by Tom &’ highest &’, providing evidence for its constituency
adjunction (section 3.3); conjunctions can be (see Zoerner 1995):
treated as heads that do not project a &P (section & &P
3.4.). The rest of this section provides a brief (126)
I saw Tom yesterday, and Mary and Jim.
survey of these analyses.
e Mary &’
This analysis also predicts that each higher
3.1. Conjunction Phrase (&P) with recursive
& Jim conjunct c-commands any lower conjuncts, which
complement
prediction may be problematic for the proposal, if
I discuss in some detail two analyses of
the conclusion in section 1.2, Part I, is correct.
coordination that argue that conjuncts are specifi- and
This analysis has little to say about conjunction
ers and complements in &Ps, where the comple-
The movement of and to e is normally covert; if doubling, i.e. repetition of the conjunction in front
ment is recursive: Johannessen (1998) and
overt, the emphatic examples like (118) below will of every conjunct, including the first (section 1.5,
Zoerner (1995). These analyses are based on a
be generated (see Appendix for possible semantic Part I). Johannessen (1998) claims that such
host of previous papers, including: Thiersch 1985,
contribution of repeated conjunctions). The basic doubled conjunctions are adverbs, which claim, as
Munn 1987a, 1987b, 1992, Kolb and Thiersch
advantage of Zoerner’s proposal is that it predicts far as I can tell, will be hard to sustain.
1991, Johannessen 1990, 1993c, Grootveld 1992,
that one and the same form of the conjunction has Johannessen argues, to my mind convincing-
etc. Since the two analyses share many of the
to surface between conjuncts of the same coordi- ly, that the features of &P are inherited not only
consequences, I will discuss them in parallel.
nation phrase, as illustrated below for English from its head, &, but also from its specifier,
Johannessen (1998) argues that the non-final
(Zoerner 1995 also offers comparable Japanese through Spec/Head agreement. On the other
conjuncts are specifiers in a conjunction phrase,
data): hand, Zoerner argues that features of all con-
and that the final conjunct is a complement. This
juncts percolate to &P. Johannessen’s take on this
is illustrated in (115) for two-termed coordination,
(118) is theoretically superior: her proposal comes at no
and in (116) for three-termed coordination (note
Tom and Mary and Jim cost since Spec/Head agreement is already widely
that she uses CoP label for Coordination Phrase):
established as a mechanism for feature-sharing.
(119) On the other hand, allowing features of both
(115) Tom ’n Mary ’n Jim
&P complements and specifiers to percolate up to the

Tom &’

& Jim
This is Part II of Ljiljana Progovac’s State-of-the-Article Structure of coordination; Part I was published in
the previous issue of Glot International. Here is the full table of contents of both Part I and Part II:

and
Part I (last month) Part II (this month)
(116)
&P 1. Representative data 3. Conjunction as a head
1.0. Introductory words 3.0. Introductory words
Tom &’
1.1. Asymmetry: Ross’ effects 3.1. Conjunction Phrase (&P) with recursive
1.2. Is there c-command complement
1.3. Subcategorization 3.2. Conjunction Phrase (&P) with recursive
& &P2 1.4. Agreement specifier
1.5. Conjunction doubling 3.3. Conjuncts as adjuncts
Mary &2’ 1.6. Chaotic Case 3.4. Conjunction: Head without a phrase
1.7. Coordination of Likes Constraint
1.8. Conjunction adverbs 4. Concluding remarks
&2 Jim 1.9. Coordinate Structure Constraint
Appendix: “Economy of conjunction marking” and
and 2. Conjunction as non-head adjunction
2.0. Introductory words
Zoerner (1995) proposes a hierarchically similar 2.1. Multi-headedness A Coordination Bibliography
structure, although with an important difference. 2.2. Multi-dimensional analyses
State-of-the-Article Glot International, Volume 3, Issue 8, October 1998 4

phrasal node is a mechanism with no precedent in depending on whether the conjunction is endowed (132) (see also intonation patterns for other lan-
the theory. Johannessen’s proposal insures that a for particular Case assignment by a higher head, guages discussed in section 1.5.). This intonation
&P whose first conjunct is an NP has the features or whether default Case choice is available. On pattern is not captured by Johannessen’s or Zoern-
of an NP, as desired. The plural feature of the the other hand, non-final conjuncts will receive er’s analyses in which the intermediate conjunct
conjunction will have to come from the conjunc- their Case by spec-head agreement with the does not form a constituent with the preceding
tion itself. In addition, this analysis does not force moved conjunction, which Case need not necessar- conjunction. Also, the example (126) is captured
phrases of the same/similar type to coordinate. ily coincide with the Case of the final conjunct. even better in Collins’ approach, since extraposition
The strongest argument for her approach is its Because all non-final conjuncts receive Case targets a maximal projection in his framework,
ability to capture the otherwise problematic through the same mechanism, they all have to rather than X’ (this advantage is also there in
asymmetries discussed in section 1.7, Part I (see have the same Case. Thus, the prediction of Munn’s and Kayne’s analyses, section 3.3).
Gazdar et al. 1985): Zoerner’s analysis is that all non-final conjuncts The main reason why Collins proposes an
must have the same Case. equal number of &Ps and conjunctions is his
(127) On the other hand, Johannessen argues for a analysis of examples like (135) and (136), repeat-
You can depend on [my assistant] and [that he will be on time].
cut-off point between the initial conjunct versus ed from section 1.8, Part I:
non-initial conjuncts in VO languages. From her
(128)
Spec-Head agreement analysis it follows that the (135)
*You can depend on [that he will be on time].
John and maybe Mary went to the store.
first conjunct will not receive the deviant Case
Since only the features of the first conjunct will be unless all other conjuncts do.
(136)
shared by the &P, (127) is grammatical, and it is Going into the details of Case assignment Perhaps John, maybe Mary, and certainly Bill went to the
possible for the other conjunct to take the form developed by the two analyses for multiple-term store.
that is not selected by the preposition. (128) coordination is beyond the scope of this paper, as
shows that that-clauses are not selected by the well as the resolution of the inconsistencies in The basic argument is that one can have as many
preposition. On the other hand, it is harder for judging the data, as pointed out in section 1.6, conjunction adverbs as conjuncts. If, as Collins
Johannessen’s analysis to capture some gender Part I. However, the facts that standard Case can argues, these adverbs modify conjunctions, rather
resolutions that occur crosslinguistically, where be suspended with coordination at all, and that one than conjuncts, then it must be that each conjunct
both conjuncts are taken into account (see e.g. can predict which conjuncts will be deviant based is preceded by a conjunction, overt or covert. This
Corbett 1991, Bayer 1996). on word order, provide strong support for a head-of- analysis would also capture, rather elegantly, the
While Johannessen’s approach successfully coordination-phrase analysis of conjunctions. possibility to double conjunctions in front of the
treats examples like (127) and (128), it faces the first conjuncts, as in the Conjunction Doubling
opposite problem: how to exclude impossible cases 3.2. Conjunction Phrase (&P) with recursive strategy discussed in section 1.5, Part I.
of coordination (see section 1.7, Part I). Obviously, specifier However, the distribution of overt/covert con-
a separate principle would be needed, possibly an Collins (1988a,b) offers the following struc- junctions raises a problem. It is not clear why the
Economy principle introduced in the Appendix. In ture for coordination, in which each conjunct is a ultimate head of the highest &P should always be
any event, an approach that overgenerates can be complement in its own &P. empty, at least in English, while the most embed-
salvaged by identifying an independent principle ded conjunction should (always?) be overt (but see
at work, but an approach that rules out accepta- (131) Collins’ paper for comparing this situation to that of
&P complementizers surfacing in embedded, but not
ble examples is harder or impossible to salvage.
The X’-structure Johannessen and Zoerner main clauses). Johannessen’s analysis faces a
propose for coordination implies that the comple- &’ &P2 similar question. On the other hand, Zoerner’s
ment will precede the conjunction in verb-final analysis captures this elegantly. On his account, the
languages, as in (129). & Tom &2’ &P3 last conjunction is the only one generated; the rest
are the movement copies thereof. As pointed out in
(129) the previous section, Zoerner’s analysis also pro-
&2 Mary &3’ (too)
&P vides the tools for analyzing sub-group coordination
from single group coordination, while the analysis
(and) &3 Jim in (131) does not.
&’ Mary
It may be worth exploring an alternative to
Tom &
and (131), in which the (recursive) specifer will be to
the left, as in:
As opposed to the structure proposed by Johan-
and nessen or Zoerner discussed in the previous (137)
section, the location of recursion in (131) is in the &P
Both authors provide arguments that (129) is specifier position. Another difference is that the
correct, based on constituency tests which show specifier is to the right of &’, rather than to the &P2 &’
that indeed, in verb-final languages, the conjunc- left, as usually assumed for English. Yet another
tion forms a unit with the preceding, rather than difference concerns the number of &Ps projected
with the following conjunct. In addition, as pointed &P3 &2’ & Jim
per conjunct. According to (131), there are as
out in section 1.5, Part I, the conjunction doubling many &Ps as there are conjuncts. This differs
strategy in OV languages will repeat the conjunc- from Johannessen 1998, according to whom the &3’ &2 Mary and
tion following the last conjunct, rather than preced- number of &Ps is one fewer than the number of
ing the first, as expected under this analysis. Also, conjuncts. While for Zoerner, the number of &P &3 Tom (and)
the data that served as input for Johannessen’s projections is also one fewer than that of con-
generalization repeated below strongly suggests juncts, Zoerner assumes that all these projections This representation would capture the intonation
that a structural difference is involved: are only layers of structure projected by a single patterns in (132) rather straightforwardly, but will
conjunction. Collins specifically argues that each not be able to handle Zoerner’s extrapositon exam-
(130) Johannessen’s Correlation ple in (126), since the intermediate conjunct here
“There is a very strong correlation between, on the one hand,
&P is headed by a distinct conjunction.
the order of verb+object, and on the other, that of normal Collins does not explain why he wanted his does not form a constituent with the last (but see
conjunct+deviant conjunct (usually the same as that between specifiers to be to the right in (131), but I can see Kayne 1994 for an analysis of extraposition which
conjunction+deviant conjunct).” two reasons for this decision. First, this enables may be more consistent with the representation in
him to analyze ‘too’ as a specifier of &P. The basic (137) than the one in (131)). Since the ultimate
These consistent differences between head-initial distribution of ‘too’ is given below: head of &P is &, (137) also easily captures the fact
and head-final languages provide the strongest that it is & that has to be overt, rather than &2 or
support for the idea that conjunctions are heads of (132) &3 (this latter point is also true of Kayne’s analysis,
phrases: they follow the pattern of order and Tim, (and) Mary, and John, too, arrived on time. see section 3.3.) On the other hand, the alternative
constituency established for other (uncontrover- in (137) would not capture the placement of ‘too,’ as
sial) heads. One puzzle remains, however: the (133) (131) does rather ingeneously.
*Too Tim, Mary, and John arrived on time.
tendency for the conjunction to appear between Both (131) and (137) capture the Conjunction
conjuncts cross-linguistically, avoiding a peripher- (134) Doubling effects discussed in the previous sections.
al position, which tendency is not attested with *Tim, Mary, too, and John arrived on time. However, the two analyses make different hierar-
the verb (cf. e.g. SOV/VSO languages). chical predictions. While both predict that there is
As pointed out in section 1.6, Part I, Zoerner The second reason is Collins’ conclusion that the no strict c-command among conjuncts, (137) pre-
and Johannessen make different predictions with first conjunct m-commands the rest of the con- dicts that the following conjunct m-commands the
respect to deviant Case. Zoerner argues that the juncts, as will be discussed below. preceding one(s), while (131) predicts that the
conjunction assigns Case to its complement, the Apart from integrating the placement of ‘too,’ preceding conjunct m-commands the following ones.
final conjunct in VO languages, just like a prepo- this analysis, better than any other, captures the While Collins argues that indeed the first conjunct
sition or a verb would. The particular Case to be prosodic patterns. There is comma intonation after m-commands the second, but does not c-command
assigned will vary from language to language, each head-complement grouping, as evident from it, based on examples (8–9), section 1.2, Part I,
State-of-the-Article Glot International, Volume 3, Issue 8, October 1998 5

establishes that such contrasts are handled in a This analysis straightforwardly captures the fact The advantages of this structure are the follow-
way that does not invoke either c-command or that a &P involving NPs behaves like an NP, ing: it captures the lack of c-command among the
m-command. This issue deserves further attention. which fact must be somehow derived in the ap- conjuncts, as established in section 1.2, Part I; it
The lack of strict c-command among conjuncts is proaches in which both conjuncts are within &P. straightforwardly predicts the availability of
predicted by both of these analyses; if the conclu- This analysis also captures the extraposition facts conjunction doubling strategies, as in section 1.5,
sions of section 1.2. are correct, this remains their discussed in section 1.1. in a rather straightfor- Part I; it renders all conjuncts equal in status, in
important advantage. ward way, as successfully as Collins (section 3.2.). spite of the existence of hierarchy; it predicts
However, as they stand now, neither of the Case inconsistencies support this approach only deviance in Case assignment to conjuncts, since
two analyses is able to invoke the Spec/Head part-way. Johannessen’s Unbalanced Coordina- what receives Case directly is the (null) pronomi-
mechanism of feature sharing, which, to my mind, tion effects are predicted, since the deviant Case nal head. However, this approach faces the follow-
is the strongest achievement of Johannessen’s will appear on the second conjunct, if only on one ing problems: it generates several &Ps, where the
approach. Recall that Johannessen handles of the conjuncts. On the other hand, Johanessen’s presence of one is felt (contrast Zoerner’s analy-
subcategorization in a rather straightforward Extraordinary Balanced Coordination effects, sis); it predicts that the last two &Ps cannot
fashion: the features of the first conjunct, the where both conjuncts have deviant Case, are not extrapose as a unit, contrary to the data present-
specifier of &P, percolate up &P, by spec/head predicted at all. The proposal in (139) would ed in section 3.1., which seem to indicate that
agreement. Her analysis predicts, correctly, that disallow the first conjunct to receive deviant Case they do; while Extraordinary Balanced Coordina-
the first conjunct, but not necessarily the subse- marking, since it appears in exactly the same tion is not a problem for this approach, Unbal-
quent conjuncts, has to satisfy the subcategoriza- position in which a single-term NP would. Munn anced Coordination is: since the conjuncts here
tion features of the governing head (see examples (1993) captures first conjunct agreement data, enjoy the same status, asymmetries in Case-
(127) and (128), section 3.1.). although at the expense of losing a straightfor- assignment among conjuncts are not expected.
Notice that it would not work to say that &P ward explanation for regular agreement patterns
can be specified for more neutral features, render- (see section 1.4, Part I). It follows from this analy- 3.4. Conjunction: head without a phrase
ing it compatible with subcategorization require- sis that the first conjunct c-commands the follow- Camacho (1997) proposes an analysis of
ments of various heads, and that then semantics ing ones, for which Munn argues, although the coordination which treats conjunctions as heads,
decides what can appear inside this &P. The additional data discussed in section 1.2, Part I, but not as heads of &Ps. In an attempt to capture,
reason is that the reverse order of conjuncts in point to the contrary. Munn also addresses the at the same time, the status of a conjunction as a
examples like (127) is not possible: issue of conjunction repetition, as discussed in head, and its lack of relevant features, he propos-
section 1.5, Part I. His proposal is that the con- es the following analysis of coordinating subjects:
(138) junction raises at LF to adjoin to the NP in (139),
*You can depend on [that my assistant will be on time] and [his and that this movement can happen overtly in (142)
intelligence]. TP
some languages. One empirical problem with this
One way to keep Johannessen’s spec/head solution conclusion is that it fails to capture prosodic
requirements of repeated conjunctions, pointed Tom T’
would be to raise the first conjunct to the specifier
position in (137). Notice that this option is una- out in section 1.5, Part I.
vailable in (131). Even if moved, the first conjunct Kayne (1994) adopts the spirit of Munn’s T TP
would not c-command the following conjuncts, as analysis, but with one important difference. Since
desired, but it would be able to share its features his Antisymmetry approach prohibits adjunction and Mary T’
with the top &P in the same way in which this is to the right, Kayne assumes that initial conjuncts
achieved in Johannessen. However, this move- are adjoined to the conjunction phrase, formed
T VP
ment would raise further questions, such as the with the conjunction and the final conjunct (140).
position of ‘both/either’ in English, as well as the While in Munn’s analysis, the second conjuncts
are adjuncts to the first, in Kayne’s analysis the saw the movie
Conjunction Doubling strategy in other languag-
es. If the first conjunct is in Spec, then the expla- first conjuncts are adjuncts to the &P containing
the last conjunct. Like Zoerner’s (117), the structure in (142) as-
nation for the Conjunction Doubling strategy is sumes that a head can project more than one
lost. The position of ‘both/either’ is not directly a (140) layer of structure. Unlike the approaches outlined
problem for this approach, since their status is &P in sections 3.1–3.3, Camacho does not postulate
controversial. Although Collins suggests that they the existence of a &P, and allows conjunctions to
may be in the & position preceding the first head (the second layer of) any predicational
NP &P
conjunct, many assume that they are quantifier- projection. This approach seems to capture the bi-
like, and not conjunctions at all. sentential ring of examples with coordinated
Tom & &P2
subjects since it posits two TPs with two distinct
3.3. Conjuncts as adjuncts specifiers. The cameleon-like nature of a coordina-
The analyses discussed in this section share NP &P2
tion phrase follows, too: there is no coordination
with the previous analyses the assumption that phrase to begin with.
conjuncts head &Ps. They differ in that they treat Mary &2 NP One potential problem is that coordinated
at least some conjuncts as adjuncts. Munn (1993) elements are predicted not to form a constituent
proposes that the second conjunct right adjoins in this representation (i.e. Tom and Mary in
and Jim
(with its &P) to the first conjunct, while Kayne (142)), as pointed out and addressed in Camacho.
(1994) argues that the first conjunct left adjoins to Kayne’s structure is hierarchically parallel to the The constituency effects, such as agreement,
the &P containing the second conjunct. In addi- structure proposed in Johannessen, handling binding, pronominal replacement, etc., therefore
tion, Munn 1993 (for semantic representation) most of the data in the similar fashion. One must be captured in some other way, which puts
and Progovac 1996, 1997 (for syntactic represen- difference is that extraposition facts are handled this analysis at an important disadvantage.
tation) advance an analysis according to which in a more straightforward way by Kayne, since Another problem for this analysis is that the
every conjunct, in its &P, is adjoined to an ab- the extraposed material is indeed a full phrase conjunction turns out to be a head with exception-
stract phrase. (see also the comment on Collins’ and Munn’s al nature: first, it is a head which does not have a
According to Munn (1993), the first conjunct analyses in the previous sections). corresponding phrase, and, second, it is a head
appears in the regular position in which a single- There is yet another logical possibility for the which can appear in the head position of any
term phrase would, while any subsequent con- adjunction analysis of conjunction, i.e., to treat (predicational) projection. The trend in the recent
juncts are complements in the &Ps, adjoined to each conjunct as a complement in a &P, where research on coordination has been the opposite: to
the first conjunct (this analysis is mentioned but each &P is attached to an abstract head, the advance a theory that will render conjunctions
argued against in Collins 1988a,b). (Note that situation that resembles an appositive structure. unexceptional and comparable to other heads.
Munn uses the term BP, which stands for Boolean This was proposed in Munn (1993) as a semantic Camacho’s approach makes certain predic-
Phrase, instead of &P). representation for coordination and in Progovac tions with respect to deviant Case assignment.
(1996,1997) for syntactic representation. For example, both NPs in (142) are in a
(139)
NP
Spec/Head relationship with T, although the
(141)
DP
instantiations of T are different. It may be argued
that a conjunction in T is comparable to a non-
NP &P
finite element occupying T, which cannot assign
DP &P
nominative Case. This would predict that the first
Tom & NP conjunct can appear in some kind of default Case,
& Jim say either Accusative or Nominative. (Notice,
NP &P2 DP &P however, that this is in contradiction to Johannes-
and sen’s generalization in (130), which asserts that
Mary &2 NP DP &P & Mary the second, rather than first, conjunct will be
deviant in Case). For the second conjunct, Cama-
cho’s analysis proves too strong: since the second
and Jim (they) & Tom
State-of-the-Article Glot International, Volume 3, Issue 8, October 1998 6

conjunct is in the spec/head relationship with T, it (ix) (unrelated) events, one of fulfilling some obliga-
John, Mary and Peter brought a bottle of wine.
seems to have no choice but to appear in the tion or other, and the other of bringing wine. In
Nominative Case, although the Accusative seems contrast, (xiii) involves coordination of two verb
(x)
widely accepted in the second-conjunct subjects. John, and Mary, and Peter brought a bottle of wine. phrases (VPs). (xiii–b) is the most basic/economi-
cal form occuring: it is unspecified/ambiguous
4. Concluding remarks The contrast between (ix) and (x) indicates that between one event vs. two event readings. On the
While the theories of coordination are many the use of an extra conjunction affects the inter- other hand, (xiii–c) necessarily implies two
and various, the weight of evidence seems to push pretation in that it enforces the reading of three events: the event of fulfilling the obligation is
to the following general conclusions: (i) conjunc- separate events of wine-bringing (see discussion distinct from the event of bringing wine. An
tions are (functional) heads that head Coordina- below). (I am using ‘event’ here as a cover term for equivalent pattern is also attested in (xi).
tion Phrases (&Ps) cross-linguistically; (ii) the both states and events.) As a curious result of this otherwise precise
first conjunct (in VO languages) stands structur- Consider now the data in (xi–xiii). The con- pattern, the (b) examples, involving 1-coordina-
ally apart from the rest of the &P, including the structions differ with respect to whether or not tion, are always potentially ambiguous between
conjunction and the rest of conjuncts, although they require the overt use of ‘and’ for coordination one or two events, since they are only specified for
there is no clear evidence that the first conjunct c- purposes. Some coordinations can be conjunction- the number of participants — two. (Different
commands the rest of &P; (iii) the conjunction and less (paratactic/asyndetic), such as (xii–a); others contextual circumstances will favor one or the
the non-initial conjuncts (in VO languages) form a cannot, such as (xi–a) and (xiii–a). However, the other interpretation.) Zero- and 2-coordinations,
structural unit. data below are subject to a clear pattern, formu- on the other hand, are not ambiguous: the former,
It is worth emphasizing that, as far as I can lated in (xiv) as ‘Economy of Conjunction Mark- which are appositive in nature, imply one partici-
see, all the theories of coordination have contrib- ing.’ The basic claim of the principle is that every pant, and thus necessarily one event ((a) exam-
uted to the advancement of knowledge in the (overt) conjunction marker is costly in that it ples); the latter imply two events, and thus
area. Even if they were not the ones to propose necessarily increases the complexity of the event necessarily two participants ((c) examples).
any of the conclusions that will eventually sur- structure. The availability of the Economy Principle in
vive, and even if they argued against such conclu- (xiv) makes it possible to argue that adjunction of
sions, various analyses have provided invaluable (xi) certain adverbials/adjectivals is an instance of
insights, hypotheses, and data without which a. * Mary, Peter will bring a bottle of wine. zero-coordination, as in Progovac (in press; to
advancement would be impossible. b. Mary and Peter will bring a bottle of wine. appear b); (see also Haik (1985) and Williams
c. Both Mary and Peter will bring a bottle of wine.
(1990) who analyze adjuncts in parasitic gap
Appendix: ‘Economy of Conjunction (xii) constructions as conjuncts, thus unifying ATB
Marking’ and adjunction a. [S Mary fulfilled her obligation]; [S she brought a bottle of extraction with coordination and adjunction; but
In Progovac (in press; to appear b) I argue wine]. see Postal 1994 for criticism). Some modifications
that the effects of the CLC are created by an b. [S Mary fulfilled her obligation] and [S she brought a of (xiv) are necessary to accommodate adverbials/
bottle of wine].
Economy principle, which one can call ‘Economy c. * Both [S Mary fulfilled her obligation] and [S she brought adjectivals and their role in the event structure.
of Conjunction Marking.’ Roughly put, the princi- a bottle of wine]. Among other cross-linguistic curiosities, this move
ple prohibits the use of an overt conjunction may explain the overt occurrence of a conjunction
where the two phrases converge without such a (xiii) marker with what are normally treated as ad-
conjunction (unless an increase in the event a. * Mary [VP fulfilled her obligation]; [VP brought a bottle of juncts (see also section 3.4. for a discussion of
wine].
structure is available, as per discussion below). In b. Mary [VP fulfilled her obligation] and [VP brought a bottle these):
the following examples, (a) of each pair illustrates of wine].
an unacceptable instance of coordination; the (b) c. Mary both [VP fulfilled her obligation] and [VP brought a (xv)
bottle of wine]. John read the book and quickly.
example offers the reason: the conjunctionless
counterpart is available:
(xiv) Economy of Conjunction Marking This analysis is in consonance with, and draws
An extra (overt) conjunction marker signals an increase in the from, Davidson 1967 and subsequent extensions,
(i)
complexity of the event structure, according to the following
a. * John probably and unwillingly went to bed. (Gleitman
formula: such as Parsons 1980, 1990, Dowty 1989, Higgin-
1965) botham 1985, and Takahashi 1994, in which
Zero-coordination = one participant (one event necessarily):
b. John probably went to bed unwillingly.
(a) examples adverbials are analyzed as predicates of events,
1-coordination = two participants (one or two events): which coordinate with the main predicate.
(ii) (b) examples
a. ?* John ate with his mother and with good appetite. 2-coordination = two participants/two events: (c) examples This is, of course, the direction opposite to the
(Gleitman 1965) (The number of participants above refers to the number of one taken in section 3.3., where conjuncts are
b. John ate with his mother, with good appetite. conjuncts that are separate participants in the event(s).) analyzed as adjuncts. It is not accidental that
(iii) there have been attempts to bring conjunction
a. * the book [that I read] and [about the war]. For example, (xii) involves coordination of clauses. and adjunction under the same umbrella: both are
b. the book that I read about the war The use of an overt conjunction in (xii–b) increas- recursive, and both seem deficient without the
es the complexity of the event structure: while other. For example, adjunction is the only opera-
(iv) (xii–a) implies one event (bringing wine), which
a. * I sat [on the couch] and [with fever].
tion that creates a phrase without a head. If
b. I sat on the couch with fever.
(same) event is also described as fulfilling an treated as coordination, adjunction phrases would
obligation, (xii–b) is unspecified/ambiguous be- be headed by zero coordination heads.
On the other hand, examples of acceptable coordi- tween implying one event (as in (xii–a)) or two
nation in (a) below do not normally have accepta-
ble counterparts without coordination (on the
relevant reading), whether they are ‘alike’ or not, A Coordination Bibliography
as given in (b):

(v)
Abbot, Barbara (1976). Right Node Raising as a tions in Syntax and Processing: Studies in
a. the scene [PP of the movie] and [PP of the play]
b. * the scene [PP of the movie] [PP of the play] Test for Constituenthood. Linguistic Inquiry Russian and Japanese. Doctoral Dissertation,
7: 639–642. MIT.
(vi) Abney, Steve (1987). The English Noun Phrase in Babyonyshev, Maria (1997). Covert Feature
a. Bobby is the man [CP who was defeated by Billie Jean] its Sentential Aspect. Doctoral Dissertation, Checking and Conjunction Agreement in
and [CP who beat Margaret].
b. * Bobby is the man [CP who was defeated by Billie Jean]
MIT. Russian. Paper presented at 1997 Formal
[CP who beat Margaret]. Aissen, Judith (1989). Comitative Agreement in Approaches to Slavic Linguistics (FASL),
Tzotzil. In Papers on the Plural Pronoun University of Connecticut, Storrs.
(vii) Construction and Comitative Coordination, Bahloul, Maher, and Wayne Harbert (1992).
a. Pat has become [NP a banker] and [AP very conservative].
SRC (Syntax Research Center)–89–02, 17–24, Agreement Asymmetries in Arabic. In M.
b. * Pat has become [NP a banker] [AP very conservative].
Cowell College, University of California, Kural and L. Moritz, (eds.), Proceedings of
(viii) Santa Cruz. WCCFL XI, Stanford: CSLI.
a. Pat was annoyed by [NP the children’s noise] and [CP that Aissen, Judith (1989). Agreement Controllers and Bayer, Samuel (1988). Weak Connectivity Revisit-
their parents did nothing to stop it. Tzotzil Comitatives. Language 65: 510–536. ed: A Syntactic Approach. Paper presented at
b. * Pat was annoyed by [NP the children’s noise] [CP that their
parents did nothing to stop it]. Aoun, Joseph and Elabbas Benmamoun (1996). the Annual Meeting of the Linguistic Society
Agreement, Coordination and Gapping. of America, New Orleans, LA.
The advantage of adopting this principle is that it Manuscript, University of California, Los Bayer, Samuel, and Mark Johnson (1995). Fea-
captures not only the effects ascribed to CLC, but Angeles. tures and Agreement. Proceedings of the
also its counterexamples (see (vii) and (viii)). The Aoun, Joseph, Elabbas Benmamoun, and Domin- Association for Computational Linguistics,
principle is also independently motivated and has ique Sportiche (1994). Agreement, Word 70–76.
a wider coverage than CLC; for example, it cap- Order, and Conjunction in some varieties of Bayer, Samuel (1996). The Coordination of Unlike
tures the use of repeated conjunctions for a single Arabic. Linguistic Inquiry 25.2: 195–220. Categories. Language 72.3: 579–616.
coordination, as in (x) below. Babyonyshev, Maria (1996). Structural Connec- Benmamoun, Elabbas (1992). Functional and
State-of-the-Article Glot International, Volume 3, Issue 8, October 1998 7

Inflectional Morphology: Problems of Projec- Deirdre Wheeler, (eds.), Categorial Grammars Houtman, Joop (1994). Coordination and Constit-
tion, Representation and Derivation. Doctoral and Natural Language Structures, 153–197. uency. A Study in Categorial Grammar.
Dissertation, University of Southern Califor- Dordrecht: Reidel. Doctoral Dissertation, University of Gronin-
nia, Los Angeles. Dowty, David D. (1989). On the Semantic Content gen.
Bennis, Hans (1986). Gaps and Dummies. Dor- of the Notion of ‘Thematic Role.’ In Gennaro Hudson, Richard (1976). Conjunction Reduction,
drecht: Foris. Chierchia, Barbara H. Partee and Raymond Gapping, and Right-Node Raising. Language
Bennis, Hans and Teun Hoekstra (1985). Gaps Turner (eds.), Properties, Types and Meaning 52: 535–562.
and Parasitic Gaps. The Linguistic Review 4: II, 69–129. Hudson, Richard (1982). Incomplete Conjuncts.
29–87. Dougherty, Ray C. (1970). A grammar of coordi- Linguistic Inquiry 13: 547–550.
Borsley, Robert D (1994). In Defense of Coordinate nate conjoined structures. Language 46.4: Hudson, Richard (1988). Coordination and Gram-
Structures. Linguistic Analysis 24.3: 218–246. 850–898. matical Relations. Journal of Linguistics 24:
Boškovic¢, Z¦ eljko (1997). Coordination, Object Dyla, Stefan (1984). Across-the-Board Dependen- 303–342.
Shift, and V-Movement. Linguistic Inquiry cies and Case in Polish. Linguistic Inquiry 15: Hudson, Richard (1989). Gapping and Grammati-
28.2: 357–365. 701–705. cal Relations. Linguistics 25: 57–94.
Bowers, John (1993). The Syntax of Predication. Dyla, Stefan (1988). Quasi-comitative Coordina- Hurford, James R. (1974). Exclusive or inclusive
Linguistic Inquiry 24.4: 591–656. tion in Polish. Linguistics 26: 383–414. disjunction. Foundations of Language 11:
Burton, Strang and Jane Grimshaw (1992). Coor- Eisenberg, Peter (1973). A Note on Identity of 409–411.
dination and VP-Internal Subjects. Linguistic Constituents. Linguistic Inquiry 4: 417–420. Ingria, Robert (1995). The Limits of Unification.
Inquiry 23.2: 305–313. Franks, Steven (1993). On Parallelism in Across- Proceedings of Association for Computational
Camacho, José (1996). Comitative Coordination in the-Board Dependencies. Linguistic Inquiry Linguistics, 194–204.
Spanish. In C. Parodi, D. Quicoli, M. Saltarel- 24: 509–529. Jackendoff, Ray (1972). Gapping and Related
liand M.L. Zubizaretta, (eds.), Aspects of Gazdar, Gerald (1981). Unbounded Dependencies Rules. Linguistic Inquiry 2: 21–35.
Romance Linguistics: Selected Papers from and Coordinate Structure. Linguistic Inquiry Jackendoff, Ray (1977). X’ Syntax. Cambridge,
the Linguistics Symposium on Romance 12: 155–184. Mass: MIT Press.
Languages XXIV, Washington, D.C.: George- Gazdar, Gerald, Ewan Klein, Geoffrey Pullum, Jacobson, Pauline (1987). Review of Generalized
town University Press. and Ivan Sag (1985). Generalized Phrase Phrase Structure Grammar, by Gerald
Camacho, José Antonio (1997). The Syntax of NP Structure Grammar. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Gazdar. Linguistics and Philosophy 10:
Coordination. Doctoral Dissertation, Univer- Gazdar, Gerald, Geoffrey K. Pullum, Ivan A. Sag, 389−426.
sity of Southern California, Los Angeles. and Thomas Wasow (1982). Coordination and Jayaseelan, K.A (1990). Incomplete VP Deletion
Camacho, José (1998). How Similar are Con- Transformational Grammar, Linguistic In- and Gapping. Linguistic Analysis 20: 64–81.
juncts? Paper presented at the 28th Linguis- quiry 13.4: 663–676. Johannessen, Janne Bondi (1993a). A Configura-
tic Symposium on Romance Languages George, L. M (1980). Analogical Generalizations of tional Theory of Coordination. In D. Adger
(LSRL), The Pennsylvania State University. Natural Language Syntax. Doctoral Disserta- and C.S. Rhys, (eds.), Working Papers 8,
Camacho, José and Liliana Sánchez (1996). Three tion, MIT. Centre for Cognitive Science, Edinburgh
Types of Conjunction. In Proceedings of NELS Gleitman, Lila (1965). Coordinating Conjunctions University, Edinburgh.
26. University of Massachusetts at Amherst: in English. Language 41: 260–293. Johannessen, Janne Bondi (1993b). Coordination.
GLSA. Goldsmith, John (1985). A Principled Exception to A Minimalist Approach. Doctoral Disserta-
Chametzky, Robert (1987). Coordination and the the Coordinate Structure Constraint. In tion, University of Oslo.
Organization of Grammar. Doctoral Disserta- Chicago Linguistic Society, 21: 133–143. Johannessen, Janne Bondi (1993c). Coordinate-
tion, University of Chicago. Goodall, Grant (1987). Parallel Structures in alpha and unbalanced Coordination. In
Chomsky, Noam (1957). Syntactic Structures. The Syntax: Coordination, Causatives and Re- Andreas Kathol and M. Bernstein, (eds.),
Hague: Mouton. structuring. Cambridge: Cambridge Universi- Proceedings of the 10th ESCOL, 153–162,
Chomsky, Noam (1973). Conditions on Transfor- ty Press. Cornell University, Ithaca, N.Y.
mations. In Steven Anderson and Paul Kipar- Green, Georgia M (1973). The Lexical Expression Johannessen, Janne Bondi (1996). Partial Agree-
sky, (eds.), A Festschrift for Morris Halle, New of Emphatic Conjunction: Theoretical Impli- ment and Coordination. Linguistic Inquiry
York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston. cations. Foundations of Language 10: 27.4: 661–676.
Chomsky, Noam (1981). Lectures on Government 197−248. Johannessen, Janne Bondi (1998). Coordination.
and Binding. Foris: Dordrecht. Grootveld, Marjan (1992). On the Representation In Press. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Chomsky, Noam (1986). Barriers. Cambridge, of Coordination. In R. Bok-Bennemma and R. Johnson, Kyle (1996). When Verb Phrases Go
Mass.: MIT Press. van Hout, (eds.), Linguistics in the Nether- Missing. Glot International 2.5: 3–9.
Chomsky, Noam (1995). The Minimalist Program. lands 1992, 61–73, Amsterdam: John Ben- Josefsson, G (1991). Pseudocoordination — A
Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. jamins. VP+VP Coordination. Working Papers in
Collins, Chris (1988a). Part 1. Conjunction Ad- Grootveld, Marjan (1994). Parsing Coordination Scandinavian Syntax 47: 130–156.
verbs. Manuscript, MIT. Generatively. Doctoral Dissertation, Kaplan, Jeff (1984). Obligatory ‘Too’ in English.
Collins, Chris (1988b). Part 2. Alternative Analy- HIL/Leiden University. Language 60: 510–518.
ses of Conjunction. Manuscript, MIT. Grosu, Alex (1981). Should There Be a (Restrict- Kaplan, Ron, and John Maxwell (1988). Constitu-
Collins, Chris (1994). Economy of Derivation and ed) Rule of Conjunction Reduction? Linguistic ent Coordination in Lexical-Functional Gram-
the Generalized Proper Binding Condition. Inquiry 12: 149–150. mar. Proceedings of COLING 1988, 303–305.
Linguistic Inquiry 25: 45–61. Haegeman, Liliane and Raffaella Zanuttini Kayne, Richard S. (1984). Connectedness and
Corbett, Greville (1991). Gender. Cambridge (1991). Negative Heads and the NEG Criteri- Binary Branching. Dordrecht: Foris.
University Press. on. The Linguistic Review 8: 233–253. Kayne, Richard S. (1994). The Antisymmetry of
Cowper, Elizabeth (1985). Parasitic Gaps, Co- Haik, Isabelle (1985). The Syntax of Operators. Syntax. Cambridge: MIT Press.
ordinate Structures and the Subjacency Doctoral Dissertation, MIT. Kershaw, Paul (1992). Conjunction and Case-
Condition. Proceedings of NELS 15: 75–86. Hellan, Lars (1988). Anaphora in Norwegian and Assignment: A Parameter. Paper presented at
GLSA, University of Massachusetts, Amherst. the Theory of Grammar. Dordrecht: Foris. the Second Language Research Forum, Uni-
Cremers, Crit (1993). On Parsing Coordination Higgins, Roger (1973). On J. Emonds’ Analysis of versity of Minnesota.
Categorially. Doctoral Dissertation, HIL/ Extraposition. In: John Kimball, (ed.), Syntax Kolb, Hans-Peter, and Craig Thiersch (1991).
Leiden University. and Semantics 2, 149–195, New York: Aca- Levels and Empty Categories in a Principles
Culicover, Peter W. and Ray Jackendoff (1997). demic Press. and Parameters Approach to parsing. In
Semantic Subordination despite Syntactic Higginbotham, James (1985). On Semantics. Hubert Haider and Klaus Netter, (eds.),
Coordination. Linguistic Inquiry 28.2: Linguistic Inquiry 16: 547–593. Representation and derivation in the Theory
195−217. Higginbotham, James (1980). Pronouns and of Grammar, 251–302, Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Davidson, Donald (1967). The Logical Form of Bound Variables. Linguistic Inquiry 11: Korhonen, Riitta (1993). Buts about Conjunctions.
Action Sentences. In Nicholas Rescher, (ed.), 679−708. A Syntactic Study of Conjunction expressions
The Logic of Decision and Action. Pittsburgh: Hoeksema, Jack (1983). Plurality and Conjunc- in Finnish. Doctoral Dissertation. Studia
University of Pittsburgh Press, 81–95. tion. In Alice G.B. ter Meulen, (ed.), Studies Fennica Linguistica 4.
Depuydt, Leo (1993). Conjunction, Contiguity, in Model theoretic Semantics (GRASS 1), Koutsoudas, Andreas (1971). Gapping, Conjunc-
Contingency: On Relationships between 63−83, Dordrecht: Foris. tion Reduction, and Identity of Deletion.
Events in the Egyptian and Coptic Verbal Hoeksema, Jack (1987). The Semantics of non- Foundations of Language 7: 337–386.
Systems. New York and Oxford: Oxford Uni- Boolean and. Journal of Semantics 6: 19–40. Kuno, Susumu (1973). The Structure of the Japa-
versity Press. Hohle, T. (1990). Assumptions about Asymmetric nese Language. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Dik, Simon C (1968). Coordination: Its Implica- Coordination. In J. Mascaró and M. Nespor Kuno, Susumu (1976). Gapping: A Functional
tions for the Theory of General Linguistics. (eds.), GLOW Essays for Henk Van Riemsdijk, Analysis. Linguistic Inquiry 7: 300–318.
Amsterdam: North Holland. Dordrecht: Foris. Ladusaw, William A. (1980). Polarity Sensitivity as
Dowty, David (1988). Type Raising, Functional Hornstein, Norbert and Amy Weinberg (1990). Inherent Scope Relations. New York: Garland.
Composition, and Non-Constituent Coordina- The Necessity of LF. The Linguisic Review 7: Ladusaw, William A. (1989). Group Reference and
tion. In Richard Oehrle, Emmon Bach and 129–167. the Plural Pronoun Construction. In Papers
State-of-the-Article Glot International, Volume 3, Issue 8, October 1998 8

on the Plural Pronoun Construction and Paper, McGill University. Laurence Horn and Yasuhiko Kato, (eds.),
Comitative Coordination, SRC (Syntax Re- Munn, Alan (1992). A Null Operator Analysis of Studies in Negation and Polarity. Oxford
search Center)-89–02, 1–7, Cowell College, ATB Gaps. The Linguistic Review 9: 1–26. University Press.
University of California, Santa Cruz. Munn, Alan (1993). Topics in the Syntax and Progovac, Ljiljana. To appear b. Conjunction
Lakoff, George (1986). Frame Semantic Control of Semantics of Coordinate Structures. Doctoral Doubling and Avoid Conjunction. In Mila
the Coordinate Structure Constraint. In Anne dissertation, University of Maryland. Dimitrova-Vulchanova and M. Lars Hellan,
M. Farley, Peter T. Farley, and Karl-Erik Munn, Alan (1996). First Conjunct Agreement (eds.), Topics in South Slavic Syntax, Amster-
McCullough, (eds.), Papers form the Chicago without Government: A Reply to Aoun, Ben- dam: John Benjamins.
Linguistic Society 22, Part 2, The Parasession mamoun and Sportiche. Manuscript, Michi- Pullum, Geoff, and Arnold Zwicky (1986). Phono-
on Pragmatics and Grammatical Theory, gan State University. logical Resolution of Syntactic Feature Con-
152−167. Na, Younghee and Geoffrey J. Huck (1992). On flict. Language 62: 751–73.
Lakoff, George and Stanley Peters (1969). Phrasal Extracting from Asymmetrical Structures. In Pulte, William (1971). Gapping and Word Order in
Conjunction and Symmetric Predicates. In Diane Brentari, Gary N. Larson and Lynn A. Quechua. In CLS 7, 193–197, Chicago.
David A. Reibel and Sanford A. Schane, (eds.), MacLeod, (eds.), The Joy of Grammar, Quine, W.V (1966). The Ways of Paradox and
Modern studies in English: Readings in 251−274. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. Other Essays. New York: Random House.
Transformational Grammar, pp. 113–142, Neijt, Anneke (1979). Gapping: A Contribution to Radford, Andrew (1988). Transformational Gram-
Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey. Sentence Grammar. Dordrecht: Foris. mar. Cambridge University Press.
Lakoff, Robin (1971). If ’s, And’s and But’s about Oehrle, Richard (1990). Categorial Frameworks, Reinhart, Tanya and Eric Reuland (1993). Reflex-
Conjunction. In J. Fillmore and T. Langen- Coordination, and Extraction. In Aaron L. ivity. Linguistic Inquiry 24: 657–720.
doen, (eds.), Studies in Linguistics Semantics, Halpern, (ed.), Proceedings of West Coast Roberts, Taylor (1997). The Optimal Second
115–149, New York: Holt, Reinhart & Win- Conference on Formal Linguistics 9, 411–425, Position in Pashto. In Geert Booij and Jeroen
ston. Stanford Linguistics Association, CSLI, van de Weijer, (eds.), Phonology in Progress —
Lang, Ewald (1984). The Semantics of Coordina- Stanford, California. Progress in Phonology, 367–401. [HIL
tion. SLCS 9. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. Oehrle, Richard (1992). Dynamic Categorial Phonology Papers III.] The Hague: Holland
Larson, Richard K. (1985). On the Syntax of Grammar. In Robert Levine, (ed.),Formal Academic Graphics.
Disjunction Scope. Natural Language and Grammar: Theory and Implementation, Ross, John R. (1967). Constraints on Variables in
Linguistic Theory 3: 217–264. 79−128, Oxford and New York: Oxford Univer- Syntax. Doctoral Dissertation, MIT. Pub-
Larson, Richard (1988). On the Double Object sity Press. lished as Infinite Syntax, Norwood, N.J.:
Construction. Linguistic Inquiry 19: 335–391. van Oirsouw, Robert (1980). Deletion Processes in Ablex, 1986.
Lasersohn, Peter (1995). Plurality, Conjunction Coordinate Structures in English. Doctoral Ross, John R. (1970). Gapping and the Order of
and Events. Dordrecht: Kluwer. Dissertation, University of Cambridge. Constituents. In Manfred M. Bierwisch and
Levine, Robert D. (1985). Right Node (Non)- van Oirsouw, Robert (1982). Gazdar on Coordina- Karl Erich Heidolph, (eds.), Progress in
Raising. Linguistic Inquiry 16: 492–497. tion and Constituents. Linguistic Inquiry 13: Linguistics, 249–259. The Hague: Mouton.
Liu, Jian and Alain Peyraube (1994). History of 553–557. Rosser, J. Barkley (1953). Logic for Mathemati-
some Coordinative Conjunctions in Chinese. van Oirsouw, Robert (1987). The Syntax of Coordi- cians. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Journal of Chinese Linguistics 22: 1–24. nation. New York: Croom Helm. Rothstein, Susan (1991). Heads, Projections and
Maling, Joan (1972). On ‘Gapping and the Order of Parsons, Terence (1980). Modifiers and Quantifi- Category Determination. In Katherine Leffel
Constituents.’ Linguistic Inquiry 3: 101–108. ers in Natural Language. Canadian Journal and Denis Bouchard, (eds.), Views on Phrase
May, Robert C. (1977). The Grammar of Quantifi- of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume VI, pp Structure, Dordrecht: Kluwer.
cation. Doctoral Dissertation, MIT. 29–60. Sag, Ivan A (1982). Coordination, Extraction, and
McCawley, James D. (1987). Some Additional Parsons, Terence (1990). Events in the Semantics Generalized Phrase Structure Grammar.
Evidence for Discontinuity. In Geoffrey J. of English: A Study in Subatomic Semantics. Linguistic Inquiry 13: 329–336.
Huck and Almerindo E. Ojeda, (eds.), Syntax Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. Sag, Ivan, Gerald Gazdar, Thomas Wasow and
and Semantics 20, Discontinuous Constituen- Partee, Barbara and M. Rooth (1983). Generalized Steven Weisler (1985). Coordination and How
cy, New York: Academic Press. Conjunction and Type Ambiguity. In R. to Distinguish Categories. Natural Language
McCawley, James D. (1968). The Role of Seman- Bäuerle, Christoph Schwarze, and Arnim von and Linguistic Theory 3: 117–171.
tics in Grammar. In Emmon Bach and Robert Stechow, (eds.), Meaning, Use and the Inter- Sánchez-López, C. (1995). On the Distributive
T. Harms, (eds.), Universals in Linguistic pretation of Language, 362–383, Berlin: Reading of Coordinate Phrases. Probus 7.2:
Theory, 125–169, New York: Holt, Reinhart Walter De Gruyter. 181–196.
and Winston. Payne, John R. (1985). Complex Phrases and Sarkar, Anoop, and Aravind Joshi (1996). Coordi-
McCloskey, James (1986). Inflection and Conjunc- Complex Sentences. In Timothy Shopen, (ed.), nation in Tree-Adjoining Grammars: Formali-
tion in Modern Irish. Natural Language and Language Typology and Syntactic Description, zation and Implementation. COLING 1996,
Linguistic Theory 4: 245–281. 3–41. Cambridge: Cambridge University 610–615, Copenhagen.
McCloskey, James (1989). A Note on Agreement Press. Sarkar, Anoop (1997). Separating Dependency
and Coordination in Old Irish. In Sandra Pelletier, Francis Jeffry (1977). Or. Theoretical from Constituency in a Tree Rewriting Sys-
Chung and Jorge Hankamer, (eds.), A Fest- Linguistics 4.1/2: 61–74. tem. Proceedings of the Fifth Meeting on
schrift for William Shipley, 105–114, Syntax Pitha, Petr (1986). Four (Simple) Remarks on Mathematics of Language, Saarbruecken,
Research Center, University of California, Coordination. In Jacob L. Mey, (ed.), Lan- Germany.
Santa Cruz. guage andDiscourse: Text and Protest. A Schachter, Paul (1977). Constraints on Coordina-
McCloskey, James and Kenneth Hale (1984). On Festschrift for Petr Sgall, Amsterdam: Ben- tion. Language 53: 86–103.
the Syntax of Person-Number Inflection in jamins. Schein, Barry (1993). Plurals and Events. Cam-
Modern Irish. Natural Language and Lin- Postal, Paul (1993a). The Status of the Coordinate bridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
guistic Theory 1: 487–533. Structure Constraint. Manuscript, New York Schmerling, Susan (1975). Assymetric Conjunc-
McNally, Louise (1993). Comitative Coordination: University, New York. tion and Rules of Conversation. In Peter Cole
A Case Study in Group Formation. Natural Postal, Paul (1993b). Parasitic Gaps and the and Jerry L. Morgan, (eds.), Syntax and
Language and Linguistic Theory 11: 347–379. Across-the-Board Phenomenon. Linguistic Semantics 3: Speech Acts, 211–231, New York,
McNally, Louise (1992). VP Coordination and the Inquiry 24.4: 735–754. Academic Press.
VP-Internal Subject Hypothesis. Linguistic Postal, Paul (1994). Parasitic and Pseudoparasitic Schwartz, Bonnie D. (1985). Case and Conjunc-
Inquiry 23.2: 336–341. Gaps Linguistic Inquiry 25.1: 63–117. tion. Southern California Occasional Papers
Mithun, Marianne (1988). The Grammaticaliza- Postal, Paul In Press. Three Investigations of in Linguistics 10, 161–186.
tion of Coordination. In John Haiman and Extraction. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press. Schwartz, Linda (1988a). Asymmetric Feature
Sandra A. Thompson, (eds.), Clause Combin- Progovac, Ljiljana (1996). (And) Coordination, and Distribution in ‘Pronominal Coordinations.’ In
ing in Grammar and Discourse, 331–360, Coordination. Paper presented at the LSA Michael Barlow and Charles A. Ferguson,
Amsterdam: John Benjamins. Annual Meeting, San Diego. (eds.), Agreement in Natural Language, 237–
Moltmann, Frederike (1992). On the Interpreta- Progovac, Ljiljana (1997). Slavic and the Struc- 249. Palo Alto: CSLI.
tion of Three-Dimensional Syntactic Trees. ture for Coordination. In Martina Lindseth Schwartz, Linda (1988b). Conditions for Verb-
Proceedings of SALT II. and Steven Franks, (eds.), Proceedings of Coded Coordinations. In Michael Hammond,
Morrill, Glynn (1994). Type Logical Grammar: 1996 Formal Approaches to Slavic Linguistics Edith A. Moravcsik and Jessica R. Wirth,
Categorial Logic of Signs. Dordrecht: Kluwer. (FASL), 207–224, Ann Arbor: Michigan Slavic (eds.), Studies in Syntactic Typology, 53–73.
Muadz, H. (1991). A Planar Theory of Coordina- Publications. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
tion. Doctoral dissertation, University of Progovac, Ljiljana. In Press. Avoid Conjunction, Schwartz, Linda (1989a). Thematic Linking in
Arizona, Tucson. Adjunction, and Coordination of Likes Con- Hausa Asymmetric Coordination. Studies in
Munn, Alan (1987a). Coordinate Structure and X- straint. Proceedings of 1997 Formal Ap- African Linguistics 20.1: 29–62.
bar Theory. McGill Working Papers in Lin- proaches to Slavic Linguistics (FASL). Ann Schwartz, Linda (1989b). Asymmetrical Syntax
guistics 4: 121–140. Arbor: Michigan Slavic Publications. and Symmetrical Morphology in African
Munn, Alan (1987b). Coordinate Structures, X-bar Progovac, Ljiljana. To appear a. Coordination, Languages. In Paul Newman and Robert
Theory and Parasitic Gaps, Honors Research C-command, and “Logophoric” N-words. In Botne (eds.), Current Approaches to African
State-of-the-Article Glot International, Volume 3, Issue 8, October 1998 9

Linguistics 5: 21–33. Dordrecht: Foris. Advertisement


Siegel, M (1984). Gapping and Interpretation.
Linguistic Inquiry 15: 523–530. Netherlands The Netherlands Graduate School of Linguistics is a graduate school in
Sjoblom, Todd (1980). Coordination. Doctoral Graduate which four major research institutes of linguistics in the Netherlands joined
Dissertation, MIT.
Stahlke, Herbert (1984). Independent and Clitic
: LOT School of
Linguistics
forces: CLS, IFOTT, HIL and UiL OTS.

Pronouns in English. In Papers from Chicago The LOT International Series aims at publishing disserations reporting on
Landelijke Onderzoekschool Taalwetenschap
Linguistic Society, 358–364. research carried out in the Netherlands Graduate School of Linguistics LOT.
Steedman, Mark (1985). Dependency and Coordi- Occasionally, other monographs or edited volumes will be published in this
nation in the Grammar of Dutch and English. series as well. LOT comprises the majority of the linguistic research carried
Language 61.3: 523–568. out in the Netherlands, reflecting virtually every field in linguistics.
Steedman, Mark (1989). Constituency and Coordi- The Institute for Functional Research into Language and Language Use
nation in a Combinatory Grammar. In Mark IFOTT (IFOTT) is an inter-university institute of the Universities of Amsterdam
R. Baltin and Anthony S. Kroch, (eds.), Alter- and Leiden, and the Vrije University of Amsterdam, whose characteristic is a
native Conceptions of Phrase Structure, 201– functional approach to language and language use.
231. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Steedman, Mark (1990). Gapping as Constituent
Coordination. Linguistics and Philosophy 13:
207–263.
Takahashi, Daiko (1994). Minimality of Move-
ment. Doctoral Dissertation, University of
Connecticut, Storrs.
Thiersch, Craig (1985). VP and Scrambling in the
German Mittelfeld. Manuscript, University of
Connecticut and University of Koln.
te Velde, John R (1996). Coordination and An-
tisymmetry Theory: Some Evidence from Paul Boersma
Germanic. American Journal of Germanic
Linguistics and Literatures 8.2: 135–175. Functional phonology
te Velde, John R (1997). Deriving Conjoined XPs: Formalizing the interactions
A Minimal Deletion Approach. In Werner
Abraham and Elly van Gelderen, (eds.), between articulatory and
German: Syntactic Problems — Problematic perceptual drives
Syntax, 231–258, Tübingen: Max Niemeyer.
de Vries, Gertrud (1992). On Coordination and
Ellipsis. Doctoral Dissertation, Tilburg Uni- Inge Genee In Functional phonology, Paul Boersma develops a
versity. theory that seeks to explain and describe the
Watson, Richard (1966). Clause to Sentence Sentential data of the languages of the world from general
capabilities of human motor behaviour and
Gradations in Pacoh. Lingua 16: 166–188.
Wesche, Brigit (1995). Symmetric Coordination.
Complementation in a perception. By separating the roles of the
An Alternative Theory of Phrase Structure.
Tübingen: Max Niemeyer.
Functional Grammar of articulation and the audition of speech sounds, it
predicts and clarifies generalizations about the
Wilder, Chris (1994). Coordination, ATB and Irish organization of human speech, and solves
several outstanding controversial phonological
Ellipsis. In C. Jan Wouter Zwart, (ed.), Mini-
malism and Kayne’s Asymmetry Hypothesis. issues.
Groninger Arbeiten zur Germanistischen Inge Genee studied Dutch and General Linguis- Providing a synthesis between the “phonetic”
Linguistik 37, 291–329, Groningen. tics at the University of Amsterdam, where she and “phonological” standpoints, the theory of
Wilder, Chris (1995). Some Properties of Ellipsis subsequently worked as a research assistant. She functional phonology expresses explanatory
in Coordination. Geneva Generative Working studied and later taught Celtic at the University functional principles like the minimization of
Papers ii/2: 23–61. Also in Artemis Alexiadou of Utrecht. In 1996/7 she was a lecturer in Lin- articulatory effort and the minimization of
and T. Alan Hall, (eds.), Studies on Universal guistics in York, England. She now lives with her perceptual confusion directly in a descriptive
Grammar and Typological Variation, Amster- family in Canada. formal grammar, and offers a typologically and
dam, John Benjamins. Sentential complementation in a functional grammar empirically adequate alternative to generative
Williams, Edwin (1978). Across the Board Rule of Irish offers a corpus-based description of this theories of autosegmental phonology and feature
Application. Linguistic Inquiry 9: 31–43. aspect of Irish syntax in three periods: Old geometry. The subjects covered in this book
Williams, Edwin (1981). Transformationless (700–900), Middle (900–1200) and Early Mod- include articulation and perception models,
Grammars. Linguistic Inquiry 12. ern Irish (1200–1600). The core of the study constraint-based accounts of phonetic
Williams, Edwin (1990). The ATB Theory of consists of a classification of Complement Taking implementation, the acquisition of articulatory
Parasitic Gaps. The Linguistic Review 6: Predicates, and describes correlations between and perceptual phonological feature values, an
265−279. formal and functional aspects of sentential com- algorithm for learning stochastic grammars, the
Woolford, Ellen (1987). An ECP Account of Con- plement constructions, with special attention to construction of phoneme inventories, circular
straints on Across-The-Board Extraction. the role played by sentential complementation in optimization in sound change, and a
Linguistic Inquiry 18: 166–171. the expression of modality. Nine different pa- determination of the fundamental principles that
Yi, Eun–Young (1994). Coordination and Clausal rameters of syntactic, semantic and pragmatic underlie the surface phenomena sometimes
Structure of Korean. Paper presented at the nature are shown to interact in producing the ascribed to the primitive phonological operations
9th International Conference on Korean formal variation found in each period. An analy- of spreading and the Obligatory Contour
Linguistics, University of London. sis of key historical developments discusses the Principle.
Zaenen, Annie and Lauri Kartunnen (1984). different factors which result in the proliferation This book will appeal to phonologists interested
Morphological Non-Distinciveness and Coor- of non-finite construction types at the expense of in the possibility that the grammar directly
dination. Eastern States Conference on Lin- finite ones. reflects common principles of efficient and
guistics, 309–320. This book is of interest to linguists working on effective communication, to phoneticians
Zanuttini, Raffaella (1991). Syntactic Properties of typology, subordination, modality and language interested in the idea that phonetic explanations
Sentential Negation: A Comparative Study of change. It is of special interest to anyone inter- can be expressed as constraint interactions in a
Romance Languages. Doctoral Dissertation, ested in Irish historical grammar and verbal formal grammar, and to any linguist interested in
University of Pennsylvania, Philadelphia. semantics. the innateness debate.
Zoerner, Ed (1994). Deriving the Distribution of
Conjunctions. Kansas Working Papers in
Linguistics 19: 214–234. 1998. ISBN 90-5569-050-3. xxii+488 pp. Indexed. Paperback. 1998. ISBN 90-5569-054-6. xii+494 pp. Indexed. Paperback.
Zoerner, Ed (1995). Coordination: The Syntax of
&P. Doctoral Dissertation, University of Price for individuals:
California, Irvine.
Zoerner, Ed (1995). Conjunction as a Case Fea-
NLG 66.00 (ex. 6% VAT where applicable, ex. P&P, only
when ordered directly from the publisher)
Holland Academic Graphics
[ s c i e n t i f i c [ d o c u m e n t ] p r o c e s s i n g ]
ture-Checker. Berkeley Linguistics Society Price for libraries and institutes:
P.O. Box 53292 e-mail: mail@hag.nl
NLG 99.00 (ex. 6% VAT where applicable, ex. P&P)
(BLS) 21. 2505 AG The Hague http: www.hag.nl
Postage and handling:
Zwart, C. Jan Wouter (1995). Review of Johannes- Netherlands, NLG 10.00 | Europe and the USA, NLG 12.50 The Netherlands fax: +31 70 4480177
sen, J.B.: Coordination. A Minimalist Ap- Rest of the world, NLG 17.50
proach. Glot International 1: 11–13.

View publication stats

You might also like