You are on page 1of 17

What is a Begriffsschrift?

Author(s): Jonathan Barnes


Source: Dialectica, Vol. 56, No. 1 (2002), pp. 65-80
Published by: Wiley
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/42971468
Accessed: 11-03-2016 20:46 UTC

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/
info/about/policies/terms.jsp

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content
in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship.
For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Wiley is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Dialectica.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 130.113.111.210 on Fri, 11 Mar 2016 20:46:46 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
What is a Begriffsschrift?
Jonathan Barnes*

Abstract

Before Frege, the term 'Begriťfsschrifť was used to indicate (i) a language the expressions of
which adequately represent the structure of the judgements or concepts which they signify, and
(ii) a language the written signs of which designate ideas rather than sounds. In 1879 Frege fol-
lows (i). Later he adopts (ii) - and with it the Aristotelian theory of language in which it is
embedded.

In 1882 Frege published a short paper on the scientific justification for a


Begriffsschrift.1 Language, he observed, is a thing of beauty and a joy etc; but
natural languages lay snares for the scientist: they contain dangerous ambi-
guities, they encourage vagueness, they cut logical corners - in brief, they suf-
fer from such grave and such chronic maladies that they are unfit for scien-
tific purposes. Since science cannot rest dumb, a new language must be
invented - and that is the task which Frege had undertaken in Begriffsschrift.
An ingenuous reader will wonder whether Frege's heroic remedy is appro-
priate to the mundane complaints which he diagnoses (and which he was by
no means the first to diagnose): amputation for chilblains. Elsewhere, to be
sure, Frege identified more virulent diseases, and his therapy is not as violent
as it may appear. But I am concerned with the nature, not with the appropri-
ateness of the therapy. And this - in its most general terms - is clear. We must
design a new language. German will not do, nor will French; nor even Eng-
lish. Frege thus belongs to a tradition which goes back to Leibniz and beyond,
and which in the nineteenth century had produced such genial fantasies as
Esperanto (which is still alive), and Volopiik (which was invented in the year

f Université de Genève, jonathan.barnes@lettres.unige.ch


The term 'Begriffsschrift' is a common noun, not a proper name (though it is also
sometimes used as a proper name for Frege's monograph). The phrase 'the Begriffsschrift',
which scholars often use to designate Frege's new language, must be taken as elliptical for
'Frege's Begriffsschrift'.

Dialéctica Vol. 56, N° 1 (2002), pp. 65-80

This content downloaded from 130.113.111.210 on Fri, 11 Mar 2016 20:46:46 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
66 Jonathan Barnes

of Begriffsschrift), and Latino sine flexione (in which Peano sometimes wrote
and sometimes lectured), and - how can I resist it? - La langue bleue or
Bolak.2
To be sure, Frege's new language did not have the aspirations of Bolak.
Most artificial languages were supposed to possess the power and flexibility
of a natural language: you can write verse in Volopiik, you can make love in
Latino sine flexione. Their pretensions are social and political: like the flags by
which ships communicate, they are supranational; a Frenchman and a German
will chat with one another in Bolak - and had Bismarck and Napoleon so chat-
ted, the Franco-Prussian War might have been prevented. Nor was Leibniz less
optimistic: once his universal language is adopted, science will march forward
and men will quarrel no more - all will be resolved in a calculemus?
Frege's language had a more modest aim and a more restricted scope: it
was to be a language of science (and in the first instance of arithmetic); it was
to be capable of expressing all that a scientist might want (in his scientific
moments) to express - and nothing more. Just as a microscope is superior to
an eye for certain scientific purposes and useless for most of the ends of every-
day life, so Frege's new language is superior to German in the study or in the
laboratory and perfectly out of place in the salon or the boudoir. (The inept
comparison with a microscope was perhaps a nod to Emst Abbe.4)
I have heard it denied that Frege was out to create a new language: he
speaks in that vein - but surely it is a rhetorical exaggeration, a façon de par-
ler ? Well, you might decide that something in which you cannot write a billet
doux or tell a joke does not deserve the name of language. But if Frege did not
invent a language, what did he invent? Two possible answers to the question
must be scouted.
First, Frege did not invent a code or a notation - he and Sam Morse were
not in the same line of business. A Morse formula - a certain sequence of dots
and dashes - is a funny way of writing or sounding an English (or German or
French) expression. You understand the formula only when you know which
English (or German or French) expression it encodes. A Fregean formula is
not like that: in order to understand a Fregean formula you do not have to find
some corresponding English formula - no more than, in order to understand
a German formula, you have to discover a corresponding English formula.

! For a history of these things see Couturat and Léau, 1907; for Leibniz' contributions
see Trendelenburg, 1867; Knecht, 1981.
3 See esp. Leibniz, 1673 (quoted in Trendelenburg, 1867, pp. 32-37). - The calculemus
occurs in a note printed in Leibniz, 1 890, p. 200.
4 Or was it taken from Leibniz? See Leibniz, 1673, p. 241 (cited by Trendelenburg,
1867, pp. 36-37).

This content downloaded from 130.113.111.210 on Fri, 11 Mar 2016 20:46:46 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
What is a Begriffsschrift? 67

Secondly, Frege did not invent an adjunct or supplement to natural lan-


guage. All the sciences have their jargon - and the arts ape them. Jargon is not
a substitute for English: it is a superaddition to English. A scientist will write
English afforced. Frege's invention is not like that. Consider the following
sequence of signs, three of them Fregean and three English:
T Frege is French

The sequence is strictly comparable to:


It is not the case that Frege französisch ist.

The two sequences are not sentences, they are not well-formed, they belong
to no language: they are macaroni. (To be sure, they are intelligible enough;
but then plenty of nonsense is perfectly intelligible.)
Frege's invention, as the title of Begriffsschrift proclaims, is 'modelled on
the formular language of arithmetic'. To what language does the following
sequence of signs belong?
2 + 4 = 6.

To English? Is it not a brief way of writing

Two plus four make six?

If so, then had this paper been written in German, the sequence would have
abbreviated a German sentence; and in general, one and the same sequence of
symbols will belong to an indefinitely large number of languages - and, by a
felicitous coincidence, will express the very same thought in each of the lan-
guages to which it belongs. According to Frege, the sequence
2+4=6

does not belong to English or to German or to any natural language: it belongs


to lingua arithmetica, to the formular language of arithmetic. Frege's view has
its own oddities; but I suppose that he is right. If we may call lingua arith-
metica a language, then we may call Frege's invention a language.
However that may be, let us return to the essay of 1882. Once we have
decided that science requires a new language,
the question now arises whether signs for the ear or signs for the eye deserve preference,
(p. 52)

That is to say, should the new language be a written language or a spoken lan-
guage?
Frege offers three reasons in favour of preferring - for scientific purposes
- what he calls 'signs for the eye'. First, visible signs are more sharply defined
than audible signs: they are less prone to be confused with one another - ink

This content downloaded from 130.113.111.210 on Fri, 11 Mar 2016 20:46:46 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
68 Jonathan Barnes

is less labile than noise. Secondly, visible signs endure longer than audible
signs: you may look back to the top of the page or turn back to the start of the
chapter - ink fades less fast than noise. Thirdly, visible signs are made on a
two-dimensional surface, so that their vertical as well as their horizontal order
may be made to carry significance: audible signs occupy one dimension, the
before and after of time.
The three reasons are repeated, in almost the same words, in the paper on
Peano's Begriffsschrift which Frege published in 1896.5 He presumably
thought that they were good reasons; and so they are: that is to say, they advert
to certain contingent facts which give to writing - in certain contexts and for
certain ends - an advantage over speech. But if Frege's reasons are unexcep-
tionable, the question to which they are addressed is queer.
Should the new language be spoken or written? shall we choose signs for
the eyes or signs for the ears? Well, why think that we must choose the one or
the other? why not have both?6 When an improbable student assures me that
he has mastered a new language over the vacation, I do not ask him whether
it was a written or a spoken language; for I suppose that languages - most ordi-
nary languages - are both written and spoken. Frege asks us to pick either A
or B, and he urges the advantages of A; but we might plausibly complain that
he has suppressed the most enticing option - the conjunctive option of both A
and B. And a reason for preferring A to B is no reason for preferring A to both
A and B.

Frege did not overlook the conjunctive option. He did not suppose that
most languages are both written and spoken. He supposed that most languages
are spoken. The supposition was a commonplace, and ancient.
At the beginning of his de Interpretatione Aristotle observes that
items in the voice are symbols of passions in the soul, and written items of items in the
voice. (16a3-4)

That is to say, the written expressions of a language represent or stand for cer-
tain spoken expressions, just as the spoken expressions of a language repre-
sent or stand for certain psychological states or events. This thesis is one ele-
ment in the semantic theory which commentators read into the opening
paragraph of the de Interpretatione. The theory invokes 'written items', or
inscriptions; 'items in the voice', or utterances; 'passions in the soul', which
later Aristotelians generally identified as thoughts or concepts; and things.

3 The second of the three reasons is found in Trendelenburg, 1867, p. 2 (who adds that
written signs are readily transportable).
6 'The signs <of the universal language> must be not only visible but also audible'
(Trendelenburg, 1867, p. 22).

This content downloaded from 130.113.111.210 on Fri, 11 Mar 2016 20:46:46 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
What is a Begriffsschrift? 69

Inscriptions stand for utterances; utterances stand for thoughts; thoughts


resemble things. Suppose that Frege receives a letter which begins with the
inscription 'Dear Frege' : what must he do in order to understand it? First he
must determine which sound the inscription 'Frege' represents. Then he must
search his soul for the thought or concept which that sound represents. Finally
he must scout around in the world for a thing which the thought resembles.
With a bit of luck, he will hit upon himself.
The only part of this theory which concerns me here is the element which
connects inscriptions to utterances. I shall call this the Aristotelian thesis. I had
supposed that the thesis had long been exploded. But here is a passage from a
recent number of the Times Literary Supplement :

Modern Greek is a living reality that linguists can study directly, without the mediation of
writing. The written traces of the Greek language are just that, traces of linguistic realities,
not the realities themselves. (11.9.98: p. 22)

Aristotelianism dies hard.


The Aristotelian thesis was accepted by Frege. This is plain from various
casual remarks. Thus in 'Der Gedanke' we find the following brief exchange:
What do we call a sentence [Satz]? - A sequence of sounds [Lauten]. (1918/19, p. 60)

A sentence is not a sequence of expressions, whether written or spoken,


inscribable or utterable: a sentence is a sequence of sounds. Frege states this
as an uncontroversial truth. It is a consequence and a reflection of the Aris-
totelian thesis.

The thesis also finds explicit recognition both early and late in Frege's oeu-
vre. The longer of the two unpublished pieces on Boole's logic, which Frege
wrote in 1880, observes that a Begriffsschrift

differs from a word-language [Wortsprache] in an extrinsic way inasmuch as it is directed


at the eye rather than at the ear. This is indeed also true of a word- script [Wortschrift]; but
since a word-script simply imitates a word-language, it scarcely comes any closer to a
Begriffsschrift - indeed, it is even farther removed from one inasmuch as it consists of signs
of signs rather than of signs of things.7

A 'word-language' is a language-like German or English - whose signs con-


sist of words rather than of formulae; and a 'word-script' is the written ver-
sion of, or the inscriptional notation for a word-language. The word-script
merely 'imitates' the language: the inscriptions are not the linguistic realities
themselves, and the signs which Frege's printer has inscribed on the page are
'signs of signs', they are signs of utterances.

7 1880, pp. 13-14. - The phrase 'signs of signs' occurs, in a similar context, in
Humboldt, 1826, p. 1 1 1. No doubt it was a common formula.

This content downloaded from 130.113.111.210 on Fri, 11 Mar 2016 20:46:46 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
70 Jonathan Barnes

Here, then, we have the Aristotelian thesis presented in all its simplicity -
and presented as a commonplace. The thesis returns, near the end of Frege's
life, in a qualified version:
A sentence which a writer inscribes is in the first place a recipe for the construction of a
spoken sentence in a language in which the sequence of sounds serves as a sign for the
expression of a sense. Hence at first there is only a mediated connexion between written
signs and an expressed sense. Once this connexion is established we can regard the written
or printed sentence as an immediate expression of a thought, hence as a sentence in the
proper sense of the word. (1923+, p. 280)

The Aristotelian thesis is here said to hold only 'in the first place': at first, I
must look for the sound associated with the inscription and then hunt the sense
associated with the sound; but as I get used to the game, I may learn to look
directly for the sense on seeing the inscription. The Aristotelian thesis is mod-
ified, but not abandoned.
A language is a system of significant expressions. I shall say that a lan-
guage is Aristotelian if it is a system of significant sounds. A theory of mean-
ing for an Aristotelian language will make reference to utterances, it will pro-
duce theorems of the form

Utterance U means such and such.

An Aristotelian language may, to be sure, make use of a written notation. In


that case, there will be orthographical rules of the form

Inscription I represents utterance U.

But the addition of a notation is an optional extra; and it will have no effect
on the semantic theory of the language.
According to the Aristotelian thesis, natural languages are Aristotelian lan-
guages.8
Whether or not the Aristotelian thesis is true, it is easy to conceive of the
contrary of an Aristotelian language, of an 'anti-Aristotelian' language. An
anti-Aristotelian language is a system of significant inscriptions. A theory of
meaning for an anti- Aristotelian language will produce theorems of the form
Inscription I means such and such.

An anti-Aristotelian language may, to be sure, make use of a spoken notation.


In that case, there will be phonetic rules of the form

8 That is to say, most natural languages are Aristotelian: the Aristotelian thesis purports
to be a law of sublunar nature; and, like all such laws, it holds not universally but for the most
part.

This content downloaded from 130.113.111.210 on Fri, 11 Mar 2016 20:46:46 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
What is a Begriffsschrift? 71

Utterance U represents inscription I.

But the addition of a sound-system is an optional extra; and it will have no


effect on the semantic theory of the language.9
Frege's new language is anti-Aristotelian: it is a language for the eyes and
not for the ears. As far as I know, Frege never troubled to add a sound-system
to his language. (Peano did - but unhappily.10)
Frege's new language is anti-Aristotelian. Why call it a Begriffsschrift?
You might have guessed that the German compound would have been uncon-
genial to Frege, at least insofar as its first part carries an allusion to concepts.
Thus Schröder, falsely affirming that Frege had developed a logic of judge-
ments and not a logic of terms or concepts, suggested that 'Urteilsschrift'
would have been a more apposite label." Forty years later, Frege remarked:
I do not start from concepts and put together a thought or a judgement from them: rather, I
get to the parts of a thought by splitting up the thought. Here my Begriffsschrift differs from
similar creations by Leibniz and his followers - despite its name, which was not perhaps
felicitously chosen by me. (1919, p. 273.)

Judgement is prior to concept, Urteil to Begriff - and so the name 'Begriffs-


schrifť may seem infelicitous. Frege's reason for disliking the name is not
Schroder's reason; but the implication is the same - a better term for the new
language might have been 'Urteilsschrift'.
Then why did Frege call his new language a Begriffsschrift rather than an
Urteilsschrift?
The term 'Begriffsschrift' was not a Fregean neologism. Scholars refer to
Adolf Trendelenburg. In the introductory pages of a long piece entitled 'Über
Leibnizens Entwurf einer allgemeinen Charakteristik' he says:
The human mind, which owes so much to signs, has here recognized the possibility of elab-
orating signs still further inasmuch as, instead of the words already present in the language,
it brings sign and thing, the form of the sign and the content of the concept, into direct con-
tact, and devises signs which represent as separated or conjoined the characteristics which
are separated or conjoined in the concepts. Science has, in certain areas and for its own rea-
sons, already produced the first beginnings of such a Begriffsschrift...

9 The terms 'Aristotelian' and 4 anti- Aristotelian' are contraries, not contradictories:
there may, in principle, be languages which are 'neutral', neither Aristotelian nor anti-
Aristotelian. The semantic theory for such a language will produce theorems of the form
Expression E means such and such.
Where an expression is neither an inscription nor an utterance (or else it is one or the other,
indifferently). I suppose that natural languages are, in this sense, neutral; but I have no room
to explore the matter.
10 Letter to Frege, 14.10.96, in Frege, 1976, pp. 188-189.
11 In his review of Begriffsschrift - known to me from Bynum, 1972, p. 224 n.§.

This content downloaded from 130.113.111.210 on Fri, 11 Mar 2016 20:46:46 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
72 Jonathan Barnes

Such a manner of designation ... will be, in contrast to word-signs which are more or less
indifferent to the content of the ideas, a characteristic language of concepts, and, in con-
trast to the particular languages of different peoples, a universal language of things.12

Frege had probably read this text before he published Begriffsschrifi.


For in the Preface he refers to Leibniz and to his conception of 'a univer-
sal characteristic, a calculus philosophicus or ratiocinatory' and he attaches a
note:

On this see Trendelenburg, Historische Beiträge zur Philosophie, 3rd volume. (1879, p. V, n.*)

Frege is alluding to a paragraph which occurs a couple of pages after the pas-
sage I have just quoted. Presumably he read the essay from the beginning; and
it seems likely that he read it to the end.13
Trendelenburg's paper was first published in the Abhandlungen of the
Berlin Academy for 1855. The word 'Begriffsschrift' had made its Academy
début some thirty years earlier. The Abhandlungen for 1826 print an address
which Wilhelm von Humboldt gave in 1824 under the title: 'Über die Buch-
stabenschrift und ihren Zusammenhang mit dem Sprachbau'. Having distin-
guished different forms and functions of linguistic signs, Humboldt declares
that

The individuality of words, in every one of which there is always something more than
merely its logical definition, is so attached to sound that this immediately awakens in the
soul their peculiar effects. A sign which strives after the concept and neglects the sound can
express this only imperfectly. A system of such signs merely reproduces the bare concepts
of the outer and inner world; but language is meant to contain this world itself, changed, to
be sure, into thought-signs but nonetheless in the whole plenitude of its rich, colourful and
living multiplicity.
But there never has been, and there never can be, a Begriffsschrift which is modelled purely
on concepts and which has not been profoundly influenced by the words, contained in deter-
minate sounds, of the language for which it was invented. . . . The undeniable advantage of
a Begriffsschrift - the fact that it can be understood by people of different languages - does
not outweigh the disadvantages which it brings in from other sides.14

In a later paper Humboldt remarks that 'a script represents either concepts or
sounds [Töne], it is either an idea-script or a sound-script [Ideenschrift oder
Lautschrift]' . A page later he uses 'Begriffsschrift' as a synonym for 'Ideen-

12 Trendelenburg, 1867, pp. 3-4. - This passage contains the only occurrence of the word
'Begriffsschrift' in Trendelenburg's paper.
13 Heinrich Scholz was apparently the first scholar to point to the use of the word
4 Begriffsschrift' in Trendelenburg: see Frege, 1977, p. 115. On Frege's reading of
Trendelenburg see Sluga, 1980, pp. 48-52. See also above, n.4; and note e.g. the phrase 'noth-
ing is left to guesswork' in Trendelenburg, 1867, p. 45, and Frege, 1879, p. 3.
14 1826, pp. 112-113. (So far as I know, this passage was first brought to the attention of
Fregean scholarship by Thiel, 1995, p. 20).

This content downloaded from 130.113.111.210 on Fri, 11 Mar 2016 20:46:46 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
What is a Begriffsschrift? 73

schrift'.15 Humboldt's theories do not concern me here: what matters is that


he uses the word 'Begriffsschrift', and uses it to designate a script which con-
sists of signs for concepts rather than of signs for sounds.
Humboldt was an admirer, and a correspondent of Jean-François Cham-
pollion, the French linguist and Egyptologist.16 On the first page of the Letter
to M. Darier, published in 1822, Champollion introduced his study of the
'hieratic' and the 'demotic' Egyptian scripts by declaring:
I shall dare ... to hope that I have succeeded in proving that these two kinds of script are,
each of them, not alphabetic - as has generally been supposed - but rather ideographic , like
the hieroglyphs themselves; that is to say, they depict the ideas and not the sounds of a lan-
guage. (1822, p. 1)

The French adjective is 'idéographique' (and the italics are Champollion's). A


script is ideographic inasmuch as it consists of signs for ideas rather than of
signs for sounds.
According to Champollion, the signs of an ideographic script 'depict the
ideas and not the sounds of a language [peignant les idées et non les sons d'une
langue]'. He tacitly alludes to some celebrated French verses. Leibniz refers
to the same lines in a letter to Gallois, dating from 1677. He says of his uni-
versal language that
its true use would be to paint not words - as M. de Brebeuf says - but thoughts [peindre
non pas la parole ... mais les pensées], and to speak to the understanding rather than to the
eyes.17

Frege quoted this text in his essay on Boole (1880, p. 14).


15 1838, pp. 39-40 - but in practice he prefers 'Ideenschrift' to 'Begriffsschrifť; and for
a collateral adjective he uses 4 ideographisch' and not 'begriffsschriftlich' (e.g. pp. 86, 93, 99,
101, 102).
16 See esp. Humboldt, 1828, p. 145 n.*; cf. 1838, pp. 56-57, 78-106; Hartleben, 1909, 1,
pp. 144-166; 332. - Alexander von Humboldt was a friend and patron of Champollion (and
finally one of his pall-bearers: Hartleben, 1906, II, p. 528). On 8 March 1823 he sent from
Paris to his 'cher Bill' a parcel of books including 'l'essai curieux de Champollion sur les
hiéroglyphes phonétiques' (Humboldt, 1880, p. 115 - Hartleben, 1906, I, p. 442, states that,
before its publication on 5 November, a proof-copy of the Letter to M. Dacie r had been rushed
to an impatient Humboldt in Berlin; but he cites no source). In a letter of May 1824 to Welcker,
Humboldt explained how the essay happily reached him in time to be used for his address to
the Academy (Humboldt, 1859, pp. 116-117): in gratitude, he had dispatched a box of scarabs
and a copy of his address to Champollion (Hartleben, 1909, 1, p. 146, n.l).
17 In Leibniz, 1987, p. 229; cf. the reference in 'Nova algebrae promotio' to what de
scriptura eleganter dixit poeta Gallus (Leibniz, 1863, p. 160). Georges du Brébeuf's translation
of Lucan's Pharsalia appeared in 1654/5. The pertinent lines are these ('luy' refers to Cadmus
who introduced the alphabet into Greece):
C'est de luy que nous vient cet art ingenieux
De peindre la parole & de parler aux yeux,
Et par des traits diuers de figures tracées
Donner de la couleur & du corps aux pensées.
See Knecht, 1981, p. 181; and esp. Starobinski, 1990, who documents the renown of the quat-
rain.

This content downloaded from 130.113.111.210 on Fri, 11 Mar 2016 20:46:46 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
74 Jonathan Barnes

The genial metaphor dates from the 1650s: the idea behind it is older. Sir
Thomas Browne:

Certainly of all men that suffered from the confusion of Babel, the ¿Egyptians found the
best evasion; for, though words were confounded, they invented a language of things, and
spake unto each other by common notions in Nature, whereby they discoursed in silence,
and were intuitively understood from the theory of their Expresses. (1646, p. 419)

('the theory of their Expresses': the observation of their written signs.) And
my Lord Bacon, having duly cited the de Interpretatione for the Aristotelian
thesis, adds:

And we understand further that it is the use of China and the kingdoms of the high Levant
to write in Characters Real, which express neither letters nor words in gross, but Things or
Notions ... (1605, p. 121)

He then adduces the better known example of the Egyptian hieroglyphs.


The line stretches back to antiquity. Here is Plotinus:

The Egyptian sages ... do not use written signs which set out phrases and sentences, they
do not use marks which imitate sounds and utterances of propositions; rather, they write
pictures, and inscribe one picture for each thing. ( Enneads V viii 6)

The Egyptian sages were masters of a sacred language; their script depicted
things, not sounds; theirs was a Bilderschrift or picture-script - and a Bilder-
schrift is a kind of Begriffsschrift, a sort of ideography.
Not everyone shared the enthusiasm of Browne, or of Plotinus, for the the-
ory of expresses;18 but the hieroglyphs were recognized, from antiquity, as an
exception to the natural rule that languages are Aristotelian. Champollion
characterized such anti-Aristotelian languages by way of the word 'idéo-
graphique'. Humboldt used 'ideographisch' in the same sense; and for a noun
he employed 'Ideenschrift' - and also 'Begriffsschrift' (which perhaps was his
own invention).
As for Frege, in the essay on Boole he implies that the signs of a Begriffs-
schrift are 'signs of things [Sache]' (1880, p. 14). A sentence in 'Berechtigung'
is more explicit:
The formula-language of arithmetic is a Begriffsschrift since it expresses things [die Sache]
immediately, without the mediation of the sound. (1882, p. 54)

And in 1904, insisting on the need for a special 'mathematical language',


Frege says that a Begriffsschrift would be best suited to that end - that is, a

18 Picture-scripts, to some eyes, were out-moded and out-classed by syllabaries and


alphabets; and the letter-script was judged 4the most perfect type of script, since it analyses
words into their simplest parts and hence makes do with the smallest number of signs' (Kjrug,
1832, I, p. 357, s.v. 'Bilderschrift'). Note that in this article words are explicitly said to be
'articulated sounds [Töne]'.

This content downloaded from 130.113.111.210 on Fri, 11 Mar 2016 20:46:46 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
What is a Begriffsschrift? 75

system of rules in accordance with which you may express thoughts immedi-
ately without the mediation of sound, by written or printed signs (p. 666).
That is to say, Frege uses the word 'Begriffsschrift' in pretty much its stan-
dard German sense.19
I say 'pretty much' for two reasons. First, an ideography expresses ideas
or concepts, a Fregean Begriffsschrift does not. Rather, the expressions of a
Fregean Begriffsschrift express 'things' (in 1880 and 1882) or 'thoughts' (in
1904); and no doubt we should say - though I do not think that Frege himself
ever said so - that the signs of a Fregean Begriffsschrift express senses. Now
senses are not concepts but objects. This is no trifling fact about Frege's
semantic ideas, and it might be taken to induce a significant difference
between Frege's Begriffsschrift and a Champollionic ideography.
Secondly, an ideography is a script: a Fregean Begriffsschrift is a language.
Hieroglyphics is not a language: it is a way of writing Egyptian. The Fregean
Begriffsschrift is not a way of writing German: it is a language. Nor should it
be thought that a Begriffsschrift is simply a language whose script is ideo-
graphic. If a language is a Begriffsschrift, then its script is ideographic - that
much is an evidence. But if the script of a language is ideographic, it does not
follow that the language is a Begriffsschrift; for from the fact that the script
of a language is ideographic, nothing follows about the semantic status of any
spoken utterances.
Frege's use of the term 'Begriffsschrift' does not, for these two reasons,
coincide with the Champollionic use of 'idéographie' - or with Humboldt's
use of 'Begriffsschrift'. Nonetheless, you might reasonably believe that the
differences are less important than the similarities. Frege's use of the term to
designate a language rather than a script is readily intelligible. Frege implic-
itly corrects Champollion's false, 'Aristotelian', notion that linguistic signs
signify ideas or thoughts. But at bottom Champollion and Frege agree; for the
essential feature alike of an ideography and of a Fregean Begriffsschrift is the
fact that inscriptions are immediate bearers of sense.
Then why did Frege call his new language a Begriffsschrift? He called it
so because it was an anti-Aristotelian language - because it was a Begriffs-
schrift.

This answer is comfortingly banal; and it carries a moral: the correct Eng-
lish translation of Frege's word 'Begriffsschrift' is 'ideography'. The first
reported occurrence of any member of the ideographic family dates from 1823
- in an anonymous review of Champollion's Letter to M. Datier:
" Frege lectured on his Begriffsschrift almost every year of his academic life. It is natu-
ral to guess that each time he will have explained what the word 'Begriffsschrifť meant - but
Camap's notes (Frege, 1996) record no such explanation.

This content downloaded from 130.113.111.210 on Fri, 11 Mar 2016 20:46:46 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
76 Jonathan Barnes

In the course of his ten years' lucubrations, he has produced two Memoirs to prove, that
neither the hieratic or sacerdotal, nor the demotic or vulgar, writing is alphabetical, (as, he
says, was generally thought,) but ideographic , like the pure hieroglyphics; that is to say,
that they are, like the latter, the signs or pictures of ideas, and not the representation of
sounds. But neither is this a discovery due to M. Champollion, nor are his results quite cor-
rect.20

The English 'ideography' has the same origin as the German 'Begriffsschrift'.
Jourdain used 'ideography' for 'Begriffsschrift' in his 1912 paper on Frege:
he used it without explanation, as though it were evidently the correct trans-
lation; and Frege offered no objection.21 Yet few anglophone scholars now
speak of Frege's ideography. Some use 'concept script' or 'concept writing'
or 'conceptual notation' or the like; many treat the German 'Begriffsschrift'
as an English word (as I have myself done in the preceding pages). The Eng-
lish formulas attempt to do justice to the two parts of the German compound.
But they are ugly; they are false to the German (as well use 'railway court' for
'Bahnhof'); and they are scarcely intelligible ('concept script' has no dis-
cernible sense - unless you know that it is meant as a counter for 'Begriffs-
schrift'). As to 'Begriffsschrift' as an English word, I am all in favour of lin-
guistic imports - but why import what you grow at home? 'Ideography' is the
English for 'Begriffsschrift'.
So much for the moral. I return to the comfortingly banal thesis - which
does not tell the whole truth. For I have hitherto suppressed the earliest text in
which Frege says anything about the word 'Begriffsschrift':

In the expressions <of the new language> everything is omitted which has no significance
for inference . In § 3 I have designated as conceptual content the only thing which interests
me ... Hence the name 'Begriffsschrift'. (1879, p. IV)

The only sort of content or meaning possessed by the expressions of the new
language will be the sort of content or meaning which is pertinent to inference.
Frege will dub this sort of meaning 'conceptual content', 'begriffliche Inhalt'.
Hence 'Begriffsschrift' is an appropriate appellation for the new language. A
language is a Begriffsschrift if and only if the only content which its expres-
sions possess is conceptual content.

20 anon, 1823, p. 189. - With the last sentence cf. Humboldt, 1880, p. 116: 'Mr. Young,
who is nice about questions of literary property, admires the work of Champollion but claims
that it does no more than extend his own ideas'. For the story of the decipherment, and the jeal-
ousies and intrigues which surrounded it, see Hartleben, 1906, 1, pp. 345-500.
21 On the first page of his article Jourdain speaks of 'the " Begriffsschrifť"; in a footnote
to the same page he uses 'this ideography'; and thereafter he always uses 'ideography', except
that the title of Frege's monograph remains in German. For the comments which Frege sent to
Jourdain before the publication of the article - and which Jourdain largely incorporated into
the published version - see Frege, 1983, pp. 116-124.

This content downloaded from 130.113.111.210 on Fri, 11 Mar 2016 20:46:46 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
What is a Begriffsschrift? 77

This is a clear explanation - clear, I mean, to the extent that the notion of
conceptual content is clear. Yet it is not only different from the Champollionic
explanation which Frege was to offer a year or so later - it is not even equiv-
alent to that explanation. For it is plain that an ideography, in Champollion's
sense, need not be restricted to the expression of conceptual content (Egypt-
ian hieroglyphics was a colourful script); nor, conversely, is there any reason
why the restriction to conceptual content should be the exclusive property of
ideographies.
It is evident why the explanation which Frege offered in 1879 was later
replaced: the phrase 'conceptual content', on which it is based, was soon repu-
diated by its inventor. But how did Frege hit upon the Champollionic expla-
nation as a replacement? And why did he offer the 1879 explanation in the
first place? I have nothing to say on the former question: perhaps Frege looked
up the term 'Begriffsschrift' in a dictionary, perhaps he came across the word
in a book he was reading, perhaps it was a topic of conversation at one of Ernst
Abbe's intellectual soirées.22 In any event, he must have been peculiarly
pleased to find that he could redefine the term in a manner which both did jus-
tice to German usage and fitted his new language to a T.
Whence came the 1879 explanation? Trendelenburg offers no explicit def-
inition of the word 'Begriffsschrift'. But his text gives a hint. It does not hint
at the Champollionic explanation - on the contrary, the signs of a Begriffs-
schrift 'must be not only visible but also audible'.23 Rather, the text suggests
something like this: a Begriffsschrift is a language in which the form and struc-
ture of the signs, uttered or written, correspond to the structure and form of
the ideas which they present. This is certainly not identical with Frege's 1879
explanation; and it is certainly less than pellucid. But it is easy enough to imag-
ine how Frege might have arrived at his explanation on the basis of what he
found in Trendelenburg. It does not follow, but it is an economical supposi-
tion, that Frege did indeed take the term 'Begriffsschrift' from Trendelenburg.
Then whence came Trendelenburg's un-Champollionic notion? (It is clear
that he did not invent it.) I have not hit upon any earlier and pertinent use of
'Begriffsschrift'; but the word was surely calqued on 'idéographie' (or per-
haps on 'Ideographie') - and about the family to which that term belongs there
is a little more to be said.24
In his philosophical Handwörterbuch, the first edition of which was done
in 1 827, Wilhelm Traugott Krug explains that

" On which see Auerbach, 1918, pp. 162-163.


" See above, n.6
:4I owe the following references to Thiel, 1995, p. 20.

This content downloaded from 130.113.111.210 on Fri, 11 Mar 2016 20:46:46 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
78 Jonathan Barnes

idéographies ... is the art ... of expressing ideas - the word here signifies, quite generally,
all common representations or concepts - by means of a script intelligible to all men.

And an ideography may be termed a pasigraphy if


it is a truly universal language (a lingua characteristica universalis), i.e. a script which
expresses, in a universally intelligible fashion, not only concepts but also all connexions
and relations, and further all their possible modes of combination in judgements or propo-
sitions. (1832, II, pp. 500-501)

Krug refers to Leibniz, among many others, as a practitioner of idiographics.


In Carl Friedrich Hindenburg's commentary on Bürmann's fragmentary
Essai de caractéristique combinatoire , the German noun 'Ideographie' - and
the verb 'ideographiren' - are found; and Bürmann himself uses the noun in
a letter to Hindenburg: Chinese, he says, is an 'imperfect ideography'.25 In the
French Essai, Bürmann uses 'idéographie' or 'idéographie universelle'. Nei-
ther Hindenburg nor Bürmann offers a definition - each takes the terminology
to be familiar. But Bürmann describes an ideography as 'an unmediated script
[écriture immédiate] for the sciences of the geometer and of the philosophical
grammarian' (1803, p. 1). It is plain that a script is 'unmediated' if its signs
signify ideas and not sounds - if it is an ideography in Champollion's sense.
(But Bürmann also, and inconsistently, talks of 'a universal ideography which
is mediately and unmediatedly speakable' (p. 4).) The word 'idéographie'
surely existed before 1803.26 I do not know who invented it.
These texts indicate that the notion of an ideography contained three ele-
ments. First, an ideography is a universal language, a language intelligible (in
principle) to all men regardless of their nationality. (Krug contrasts ideogra-
phy with idiography.) Secondly, an ideography is a language the written signs
of which designate ideas rather than sounds. Thirdly, an ideography is a 'car-
acteristic', a language the expressions of which adequately represent the struc-
ture of the judgements or the concepts which they signify.
These three elements are logically independent of one another; but they
were closely associated in the minds of several proponents of ideographies,
and in particular the first element was thought to be closely connected to the

"See Hindenburg, 1803, pp. 132, 143; and p. 144 for the letter from Bürmann. -
Hindenburg (1741-1808) was a mathematician best known for his work in combinatorial
mathematics. He was a professor at Leipzig - first of philosophy and then of physics. -
Bürmann was a professor at the Handelsakademie in Mannheim. I do not know if his Essai , of
which Hindenburg prints fragments, was ever completed; but in 1807 he published a
Programme de la Pangraphie, partie fondamentale de la caractéristique syntactique, système
de notation universelle déduit d'éléments simples, méthodiquement combinés. The Deutsches
biographisches Archiv gives him no dates and no forenames; but perhaps he is to be identified
with the mathematician Heinrich Bürmann, who died in 1817.
26 French historical dictionaries, which cite Champollion as the first to use any word
from the ideographical family, must be corrected.

This content downloaded from 130.113.111.210 on Fri, 11 Mar 2016 20:46:46 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
What is a Begriffsschrift? 79

third. I am not sure whether the word 'idéographie' was implicitly defined by
the conjunction of the three elements, or whether one, or two, of the elements
were taken to constitute the definition and the others, or the other, construed
as a corollary. But since the three elements are distinct, it would make for clar-
ity to speak of three separate notions of what an ideography is, of three senses
of the term 'ideography'.
What is all this to Frege? Well, the first of the three notions has nothing to
do with his conception of a Begriffsschrift. The second notion corresponds to
what I have called the Champollionic explanation; and it thus matches Frege's
revised account of what a Begriffsschrift is. The third notion answers to Tren-
delenburg's conception, and hence lies behind Frege's 1879 account of the
matter. Frege called his new language a Begriffsschrift because it was a
Begriffsschrift; but in 1879 it was a Begriffsschrift in one sense - and in quite
another thereafter.27

References

Anon. 1823. review of Champollion, 1822. The Quarterly Review 28: 188-196.
Auerbach, F. 1918. Ernst Abbe: sein Leben , sein Wirken , seine Persönlichkeit . Grosse Männer
5. Leipzig.
Bacon, F. 1605. Of the Advancement of Learning. In J. M. Robertson (ed.), The Philosophical
Works of Francis Bacon , London, 1905.
Browne, T. 1646. Pseudodoxia Epidemica. Ed. R. Robbins, Oxford, 1981.
Bürmann, H. 1803. Essai de caractéristique combinatoire. In Hindenburg, 1803.
Bynum, T.W. 1972. Gottlob Frege: Conceptual Notation and related articles. Oxford.
Champollion, J.-F. 1822. Lettre à M. Dacier, secrétaire perpétuel de V Académie Royale des
Inscriptions et Belles-lettres, relative à l'alphabet des hiéroglyphes phonétiques employés
par les Egyptiens pour inscrire sur leurs monuments les titres, les noms, et les surnoms des
souverains grecs et romains. Paris.
Couturat, L. and Léau, L. 1907. Histoire de la langue universelle. Paris. (2nd edition.)
Frege, G. 1879. Begriffsschrift. Halle. [Reprinted in Frege, 1977.1
- . 1880. Booles rechnende Logik und die Begriffsschrift. In Frege, 1983.
- . 1882. Über die wissenschaftliche Berechtigung einer Begriffsschrift. Zeitschrift für
Philosophie und philosophische Kritik 81: 48-56. [Reprinted in Frege, 1977.1
- . 1896. Uber die Begriffsschrift des Herrn Peano und meine eigene. Berichte über die Ver-
handlungen der königlich sächsischen Gesellschaft der Wissenschaften zu Leipzig , math.-
phys. Kl. 48: 361-378. [Reprinted in Frege, 1967.1
- . 1904. Was ist eine Funktion? In Festschrift Ludwig Boltzmann , Leipzig, 1904. [Reprinted
in Frege, 1967.]
- . 1918/19. Der Gedanke. Beiträge zur Philosophie des deutschen Idealismus 1: 58-77.
[Reprinted in Frege, 1967.]
- . 1919. [Aufzeichnungen für Ludwig Darmstaedter]. In Frege, 1983.
- . 1923+. Logische Allgemeinheit. In Frege, 1983.
- . 1967. Kleine Schriften , ed. I. Angelelli. Darmstadt.
- . 1976. Wissenschaftlicher Briefwechsel, edd. G. Gabriel, H. Hermes, F. Kambartel, C. Thiel,
and A. Veraart. Hamburg.

27 Several questions posed at Bonn enabled me to improve this paper. I am particularly


grateful to Corine Besson, who discussed many Fregean issues with me; and to Curzio Chiesa,
to whose generosity I owe the references in n.17. My greatest debt is to Maddalena Bonelli,
who winkled out texts of which I had not heard.

This content downloaded from 130.113.111.210 on Fri, 11 Mar 2016 20:46:46 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
80 Jonathan Barnes

- . 1977. Begriffsschrift und andere Aufsätze, ed. I.Angelelli. Darmstadt. (3rd edition.)
- . 1983. Nachgelassene Schriften , edd. H. Hermes, F. Kambartel, and F. Kaulbach. Hamburg.
(2nd edition.)
- . 1996. Vorlesungen über Begriffsschrift. History of Philosophy of Logic 17: 1-48.
Hartleben, H. 1906. Champollion : sein Leben und sein Werk. Berlin.
- . 1909. Lettres de Champollion le Jeune. Bibliothèque égyptologue 30. Paris.
H INDENBURG, C.F. 1803. Über combinatorische Analysis und Dérivations-Calcul. Leipzig.
Humboldt, A. von. 1880. Briefe an seinen Bruder Wilhelm , ed. the family von Humboldt in
Ottmachau. Stuttgart.
Humboldt, W. von. 1826. Über die Buchstabenschrift und ihren Zusammenhang mit der
Sprachbau. Abhandlungen der historisch-philologischen Klasse der königlichen Akademie
der Wissenschaften zu Berlin aus dem Jahre 1824. Berlin. 161-188. [Reprinted in Hum-
boldt, 1906.1
- . 1828. Über vier Aegyptische, löwenköpfige Bildsäulen in den hiesigen Königlichen
Antikensammlungen. Abhandlungen der historisch-philologischen Klasse der königlichen
Akademie der Wissenschaften zu Berlin aus dem Jahre 1825. Berlin. 145-168.
- . 1838. Über den Zusammenhang der Schrift mit der Sprache. In Humboldt, 1906: 31-106.
- . 1859. Briefe an FG. Welcker, ed. R. Haym. Berlin.
- . 1906. Werke , vol V, ed. A. Leitzmann. Berlin.
Jourdain, P. E.B. 1912. The Development of the Theories of Mathematical Logic and the Prin-
ciples of Mathematics: Gottlob Frege. Quarterly Journal of Pure and Applied Mathemat-
ics 43: 237-269. [Reprinted in Frege, 1983.1
Knecht, H.H. 1981. La logique chez Leibniz : essai sur le rationalisme baroque. Lausanne.
Krug, W.T. 1832. Allgemeines Handwörterbuch der philosophischen Wissenschaften. Leipzig.
(2nd edition.)
Leibniz, G.W. 1673. Letter to Henry Oldenburg. In Leibniz, 1926.
- . 1677. Letter to Jean Gallois. In Leibniz, 1987.
- . 1863. Mathematische Schriften, VII, ed. C. I. Gerhardt. Halle.
- . 1 890. Die philosophischen Schriften, VII, ed. C.I.Gerhardt. Berlin.
- . 1926. Sämtliche Schriften und Briefe, II.l. Darmstadt.
- . 1987. Sämtliche Schriften und Briefe, III.2. Berlin.
Sluga, H. 1980. Gottlob Frege. London.
Starobinski, J. 1990. Les pérégrinations de Cadmus. In his edition of Rousseau, Essai sur
l'origine des langues. Paris.
Thiel, C. 1995. 'Nichts aufs Gerathewohl und aus Neuerungssucht': Die Begriffsschrift 1879
und 1893. In I. Max and W. Stelzner (edd), Logik und Mathematik: F rege- Kolloquium Jena
1993. Perspektiven der Analytischen Philosophie 5. Berlin.
Trendelenburg, A. 1867. Über Leibnizens Entwurf einer allgemeinen Charakteristik. In his
Historische Beiträge zur Philosophie. Berlin. III: 1-47.

This content downloaded from 130.113.111.210 on Fri, 11 Mar 2016 20:46:46 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

You might also like